The Properly Efficient Bargaining Solutions

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "The Properly Efficient Bargaining Solutions"

Transcription

1 The Properly Efficient Bargaining Solutions By Jingang Zhao * Department of Economics Iowa State University 260 Heady Hall Ames, Iowa jingang@iastate.edu Fax: (515) Tel: (515) Abstract: This note is motivated by the similarity between multiobjective programming (MOP) and bargaining theory. It uses the known MOP concepts to establish two new bargaining results: (1) the efficiency of Kalai- Smorodinsky (KS) and Nash (NA) solutions for large classes of bargaining problems can be refined to the sharper concept of proper efficiency; (2) the independence of irrelevant alternatives (IIA) of NA solution in convex bargaining can be upgraded to strong IIA, which is a form of sensitivity analysis in MOP. These results show that bargaining theory and MOP can gain insights from each other. Keywords: Bargaining, multiobjective programming, proper efficiency Running Head: Properly Efficient Bargaining Solutions MAC Number: 90C29, 90D12. * my own. I would like to thank Rick Percy and David Schmeidler for valuable comments. All errors, of course, are

2 1. Introduction Multiobjective programming (MOP) and bargaining theory have been studied as two separate disciplines 1. In bargaining, a point is chosen from a utility set to increase players' payoffs; in MOP, a point is chosen from the feasible set to maximize a vector of functions. These two problems coincide when the objectives are players payoffs, therefore the two disciplines could gain insights from each other. By applying known concepts from MOP, this note establishes two new properties of bargaining solutions. First, it shows that efficiency in large classes of bargaining problems can be refined to the sharper concept of proper efficiency in MOP (Geoffrion, 1968): Nash and Kalai-Smorodinsky solutions both are properly efficient in large classes of bargaining problems. Second, bargaining axioms like monotonicity and independence of irrelevant alternatives can be understood as sensitivity analysis in MOP (i.e., how a solution changes when the environment changes). It shows that independence of irrelevant alternatives (IIA) of Nash solution (i.e., it remains unchanged when the feasible set shrinks) in convex bargaining can be upgraded to strong IIA, which allows both the feasible set and the disagreement-point to change. In addition, linear MOP leads to linear bargaining, whose solutions are alternative answers to the core-selection problem in coalitional TU (transferable utility) games. Finally, the duality theory in MOP leads to a dual result between the cost-sharing and surplus-sharing problems. It is the author s hope that the known bargaining axioms might be applied to MOP in the near future. The rest of the paper is organized as follows: Section 2 describes the problem. 1 For surveys, see Zeleny (1984) on MOP, Zhao (1991) and Oliveira and Ferreira (2000) on multiobjective games, and Thomson (1994) on bargaining. MOP is also called MOMP (multiobjective mathematical programming), MCDM (multiple criterion decision making), or Vector Max/Min. 2

3 Section 3 studies bargaining efficiency, Section 4 studies the strong IIA of Nash solution, and Section 5 studies linear bargaining and the duality between cost- and surplus-sharing problems. Section 6 concludes, and the appendix provides all proofs. 2. Description of the problem Let N = {1, 2,..., n} be a finite set of players. A utility bargaining problem is a pair (d, X) of a d-point and a feasible set satisfying: (i) d R n +, X Rn, X, and X is compact; (ii) d + x for all x X; and (iii) there is some x X such that x >>d. This 2 requires neither d X nor comprehensiveness (see Figures 1-2). (Figures 1 and 2 about here) Let U be the set of the above bargaining problems. A bargaining solution is a function g: U R n + such that g(d, X) X. Let e = (1,..., 1) be a vector of one's in Rn, Arg-Max {h(x) + x X} denote the set of optimal solutions for Max {h(x) x X}, and X * e = {x X {z X z>x}= } denote the efficient frontier of X. Definition 1: Given (d, X). (i) Its egalitarian solution is ES = d+λ E e, where λ E = Max {λ d+λe X}; (ii) its Kalai-Smorodinsky solution is KS = d+λ KS t KS, where λ KS = Max {λ d+λt KS X}, and t KS is its optimal direction; (iii) its Nash solution is NA = Arg-Max {Π(x j d j ) x X}; and (iv) its proportional solution is given by P = (1+λ P )d, where λ P = Max {λ (1+λ)d X}. The "optimal direction" t KS is defined by 2 The inequalities are defined as: d x d i x i, all i; d < x d x, d x; d << x d i < x i, all i. (d, X) is d-comprehensive if for any x X, and x y d, one has y X, see Thomson (1994). 3

4 (1) t i KS = t i KS (d, X) = Max {(x i-di) x X}, i = 1,, n. In other words, the i th component of t KS is the difference between i's maximum feasible payoff and his d-value di. As illustrated in Figure 1-a and Figure 2, the above solutions have a geometric interpretation (except the NA solution): one starts at the d-point, walks along an optimal direction (such as t KS ) towards the efficient frontier X * e, and stops at a solution on the frontier. Such a geometric intuition is also shared by algorithms like the gradient method in MOP and mathematical programming, which is examined in Section 4. A bargaining problem (d, X) is called a convex bargaining problem if X is a convex set. Axiomatic properties of the above solutions have been well established in convex bargaining: The NA solution is the only solution satisfying efficiency, symmetry, scale invariance, and IIA (Nash, 1950); the KS solution is the only solution satisfying efficiency, symmetry, scale invariance, and monotonicity (Kalai and Smorodinsky,1975) The proper efficiency of bargaining solutions A multiobjective programming problem is defined as: (2) MOP: Max F(x) = {f 1 (x);... ; f k (x)}; k > 1 x X ; where X is a non-empty feasible set in R n, and fi: X R, i =1,..., k, are the objective functions to 3 A solution z(d, X) satisfies: (1) Εfficiency if z X * E ; (2) Symmetry if z i(d, X) = z j (d, X) for i j when (d, X) is invariant under all permutations of N; (3) Scale invariance if z(t(d), T(X)) = T(z(d, X)) for any scale transformation T defined by T(x) = {a 1 x 1,, a n x n } and T(X) ={T(x) x X} for some a >>0; (4) IIA if z(d, X ) = z(d, X) for any X X and z(d, X) X ; (5) Monotonicity if z i (d, X) z i (d, X ) for any enlargement X of X in i s favor, where X ( X) is an enlargement of X in i s favor if tks i (d, X ) = Max{(x i-d i ) x X } > tks i j (d, X), and tks (d, X ) = 4

5 be maximized. A linear MOP problem has the following form: Max F(x) = Cx (3) LMOP: x X = {y R n + Ay b}; where C = C k n is a k n matrix. When C = I n n is the identity matrix, (3) is equivalent to a class of linear bargaining problems defined below: Definition 2: A linear bargaining problem is defined by (d; A, b) R n+mn+m, which is a utility bargaining problem (d, X) whose feasible set is given by (4) X = {x R n Ax b}, + where d is the earlier d-point, A = Α m n is an m n matrix, and b = b m 1 R m. A linear bargaining problem is clearly a convex bargaining problem. A bargaining problem (d, X) can now be treated as a MOP problem {F(x) = x x X} with an opportunity cost d: one picks a point x X trying to maximize each of the n objectives fi(x) = xi, and the objectives will take the low values fi(d) = di, all i, if no agreement is reached. Such a connection suggests that one discipline could shed light in better understanding the other. This section examines bargaining efficiency using the following efficiency results in MOP: Definition 3: (i) The weakly efficient, and efficient solutions for the MOP problem defined in (2) are: (5) X * we = {x X {y X F(y) >> F(x) } = }; (6) X * e = {x X {y X F(y) > F(x)} = }. (ii) (Geoffrion, 1968) An efficient solution x 0 is properly efficient if there is M>0 such that, for any i and x X with f i(x) > f i (x 0 ), there is a j i satisfying f j (x) < f j (x 0 ) and f i (x)-f i (x 0 ) f j (x 0 )-f j (x) M. tks j (d, X) for all j i. See Nash (1950), Kalai and Smorodinsky (1975). 5

6 Let the set of all properly efficient solutions be denoted as (7) X pe * = {x X x is a properly efficient solution of (2)}. (Figure 3 about here) It is straightforward to see X pe * X* e X we * (see Figure 3). If x 0 X is not weakly efficient, then there is x X satisfying F(x) >> F(x 0 ). If x 0 is not efficient, then there is x X satisfying F(x) > F(x 0 ). Finally, if x 0 is not properly efficient (like B and C in Figure 3), then for any M > 0, there is an i and x X with f i (x) > f i (x 0 ) such that [f i (x)-f i (x 0 )] > [f j (x 0 )-f j (x)]m for all j with f j (x 0 ) > f j (x). By letting M + and by the fact that there are only a finite number of objectives, one sees that a non-properly efficient solution implies the existence of some objective i * whose marginal gain can be made arbitrarily large relative to each of the marginal losses in all other objectives. By the above observation, the main weakness of a non-properly efficient solution is its extreme unfairness: The increase in one player s payoff can be made arbitrarily large relative to a small loss in another player's payoff. In finite allocation problems, the main difference between the two concepts is that an efficient solution allows one to get all and the remaining players all get zero, this unfair situation is ruled out by a properly efficient solution. An example of such nonproper efficiency is the two endpoints of the efficient frontier in a two-person surplus-sharing problem with risk-averse preference as shown in Figure 3. Similarly, a non-properly efficient bargaining outcome implies the existence of some player i* whose payoff can be increased by an arbitrarily large amount relative to small losses by other players. One would expect a good 6

7 bargaining solution to rule out non-properly efficient outcomes. This is indeed the case: the NA and KS solutions are properly efficient in large classes of bargaining problems defined below. Definition 4: (i) Given (d, X) and S N, let x S = {x i i S}. A feasible point x 0 X is called an S-efficient solution if it is an efficient solution for Max {F S (x) = x S x X}. (ii) A bargaining problem (d, X) is non-degenerate if for any S N and any S-efficient solution x, (x-d) µt KS for all µ (- <µ< ), where t KS is the optimal direction (1). (iii) (d, X) is a ball-shaped bargaining problem if (a) X is convex; (b) For any S N and any S-efficient solution x, one has x i = d i for all i S. The S-efficiency coincide with efficiency if S = N (see Dubey, 1986; Zhao, 1991). A ball-shaped bargaining problem is clearly non-degenerate (see Figure 4-a for a degenerate problem). Note that ball-shaped bargaining problem is a very large set of bargaining problems, it includes all problems satisfying comprehensiveness, it also includes all problems given by X = {x R n + x d, f(x) f(x 0 )} and x 0 >>d, where f is a convex and increasing function (see Claim 2 in the appendix for a proof). The efficient frontier in two player ball-shaped bargaining (i.e., n = 2) is a non-increasing and concave curve linking the lines x 2 = d 2 and x 1 = d 1. Therefore, surplus sharing problem defined by (10) in Section 5 is a ball-shaped problem (see Figure 2). (Figure 4 about here) Proposition 1: (i) the KS solution in non-degenerate and convex bargaining is the only solution satisfying proper efficiency, symmetry, scale invariance, and monotonicity; (ii) the NA solution is properly efficient in linear bargaining and in ball-shaped bargaining. Since proper efficiency is a property of MOP in which a convex feasible set is a basic assumption, it will be extremely difficult (likely impossible) to establish a properly efficient bargaining solution for non-convex problems. The difference between efficiency and proper 7

8 efficiency will become more significant if one pushes bargaining theory from the current riskneutral assumption to risk-averse (-seeking) assumptions (i.e., a player s payoff x i be replaced by a nonlinear concave (convex) utility function f i (x i )). 4. The strong IIA of Nash solution This section is based on the similarity between monotonicity in bargaining and sensitivity analysis in MOP: they both study how a solution will change in response to changes in primitive parameters. It shows that the NA solution in convex bargaining remains as a constant either the feasible set shrinks without losing the NA solution or the d-point moves towards the efficient frontier on the line connecting the original d-point and the NA solution. Given (d, X), t R n +, t 2 = Σ (t i) 2 =1, let U(t; d, X) be the set of bargaining problems (d', X') satisfying: (i) d' = d + µ t for some µ 0; and (ii) X' = {x X d' x }. Definition 5: Given a solution g = g(d, X) for (d, X), let t = (g-d)/ g-d. (i) g satisfies homogeneity if it satisfies strong individual rationality (SIR) and g(d', X') g(d, X) for all (d', X') U(t; d, X); (ii) g satisfies SIIA (strong independence of irrelevant alternatives) if it satisfies homogeneity and IIA. SIR means x>>d. It has been shown that SIR and IIA together imply efficiency (See Roth, 1977; Zhou, 1997). In ball-shaped bargaining problems, one can show that SIR plus IIA (or homogeneity plus weak efficiency or SIR plus weak efficiency) imply proper efficiency (see Claim 1 in the appendix). Proposition 2: In a convex bargaining problem (d, X), its NA solution is the only solution that satisfies scale invariance, SIIA, and symmetry. Note that homogeneity changes the d-point, IIA changes the feasible set, and SIIA 8

9 changes both the d-point and the feasible set. Therefore, g(d, X) satisfies SIIA if g(d', X') = g(d, X) for any (d', X') such that g(d, X) X' X, d' = d + µt >>d (0 µ µ 0 = g-d ), and x d' for all x X'. It remains to be seen if SIIA imply symmetry (or scale invariance). The appendix provides a non-trivial proof for the homogeneity of a NA solution in general convex bargaining problems. One surprising consequence of homogeneity arises from the KS solution. Since KS solution has the geometric intuition that it is obtained by walking along the optimal direction from the d-point towards the efficient frontier, one would expect it to satisfy homogeneity. However, as shown below, the KS solution does not satisfy homogeneity in a general convex problem (see Figure 4-b). Let d = (2, 1), X = {2 x 1 6, 1 x 2 4, x 1 +4x 2 18}, one gets t KS = (4, 3), KS = (5, 3.25). Note that the unit direction is t = (4/5, 3/5). For d = d + (5/4)t = (3, 1.75), X' = {x X d' x} = {3 x 1 6, 1.75 x , x 1 +4x 2 18}, KS = KS(d', X') = (57/11, 141/44) (5.2, 3.2) KS = (5, 3.25). Note that the KS solution satisfies a weak homogeneity defined below. Assume d X and let t and U(t; d, X) be as described in Definition 5. Then, the KS solution is a constant for all (d', X) such that d' = d + µ t (µ 0) and d' X. 5. Linear bargaining and the duality between cost-and surplus-sharing problems This section first discuss two remarks based on the similarity between linear MOP and linear bargaining. It then provides a preliminary result on the duality between cost-sharing and surplus-sharing problems, which suggests future research in the spirit of the duality theory in MOP. Consider the core selection problem for a coalitional TU game Γ = {N, v(. )}, where for each S N, v(s) is the payoff of S. A payoff vector is any x R n + giving x i ( 0) to player i. 9

10 An allocation of v(n) is any x R n + such that Σx i = v(n). Definition 6: The core of a game Γ = {N, v(. )} is given by (8) C(Γ) = {x R n + Σ i S x i v(s) for all S N, and Σx i = v(n)}. In other words, the core 4 is the set of all allocations of the grand coalition s payoff v(n) satisfying the coalitional rationality for all coalitions. Its selection problem is resolved by bargaining solutions given below: Remark 1: Given Γ= {N, v(. )}, assume C(Γ). Define a utility bargaining problem (d, X) by d i = v(i) for all i, and X = C(Γ). Then, any non-empty solution g(d, X) is a solution to the core selection problem. Similarly, core selection in coalitional NTU (non-transferable utility) games can alternatively be solved by solutions in non-linear bargaining. Two other classes of linear bargaining are of special interest: the rectangular bargaining problem and the surplus sharing problem. The feasible set of a rectangular bargaining problem is (9) X = {x R n + d x u}, which can be given as a vector (d, u) R 2n + (i) of the following Remark 2. such that d<<u, and its solutions are provided in part A surplus sharing (SS) problem is a vector (r; d) R n+1 + with r >Σ d i or (d, X) with (10) X = {x R n + x d, Σ x i r} = {x R n + Ax b}, where r is the joint return, d is the d-point, and the matrices are: 4 The core is dual to the base polyhedron of a set function. See Fujishige (1991) for references. 10

11 1 1 K 1 r d e 1 A = Α (n+1) n = K r, = b = b( n + 1) 1 = =. I K K K K d K 0 0 K 1 dn An SS problem represents situations like networks, where returns exhibit scale economies. A network provider i alone generates a revenue of d i, while full cooperation generates a joint return r >Σd i. Solutions of an SS problem are given in part (ii) of Remark 2 below. Remark 2: (I) The solutions of a rectangular problem (d, u) are: (i) KS = NA = u; (ii) the ES solution is efficient u-d = λe for some λ>0 ES = KS = NA = u; (iii) the P solution is efficient u = λd for some λ > 0 P = KS = NA = u. (II) The solutions of an SS problem (r; d) are: (11) ES = KS = NA = d + λ E e, λ E = λ KS = λ N = (r Σ d j) / n; (12) P = (1 + λ P ) d, λ P = (r / Σ d j) 1. The ES and P solutions might not exist (see Figure 1-b). In an SS problem, the uniform solution (or U solution with U i = U j ) might not exist, and the ES, KS and NA solutions always coincide (see Figure 2). Remark 3: Bargaining theory has grown without considering computation. It is nontrivial and useful in future works to design practical methods in finding the KS and other solutions (except NA) 5 in linear (non-linear) bargaining. In an SS problem (r; d), the unit optimal directions and travel distances for ES, KS, NA and P solutions are (see Figure 2): (13) ES= KS= NA= d+µ ES t ES, t ES = t KS = t NA = e/ n, µ ES = µ KS = µ NA = (r Σ d j)/ n; (14) P = d + µ p t p, t P = d / d, µ P = [(r/σd j ) 1] d. Finally, homogeneity and duality theory in MOP lead to a preliminary dual property of the 5 The NA solution can be solved by the known optimization methods. 11

12 SS problems 6. By homogeneity, a solution remains unchanged when the d-point moves along its optimal direction. What happens if the d-point of an SS problem moves beyond the efficient line along an optimal direction? One obtains a cost sharing (CS) problem, defined by an (n+1) vector (L; D) R n+1 + such that Σ D i > L, or a linear dual bargaining problem (D; Y) whose feasible set is (15) Y = {y R n + y D and Σ y i L}. Such CS problems arise from situations like carpooling or municipal cost-sharing (Young, 1985), where costs exhibit scale or scope economies: It costs a commuter D j to drive alone, while it costs only L < Σ D j if all commuters carpool in a single vehicle. Note the economic duality between the SS and CS problems: no player in an SS problem will accept a return less than his d-point, which is below the efficient line; while no player in a CS problem will pay a cost greater than his d-point, which is above the efficient line. Such relation is similar to the duality between Max- and Min-MOP s, which suggests the need to seek the general duality between CS and SS problems. The next proposition is a preliminary step forward along this line of future research. (Figure 5 about here) 6 This is related to the d-monotonicity (Thomson, 1987). Let e(i) be the direction of the i th axis (i.e., e j (i) = 1 if j = i, = 0 if j i). Given (d, X), let d' = d+λe(i) for some small λ > 0, then x(d, X) satisfies d-monotonicity if x i (d', X) x i (d, X), and strong d-monotonicity if x j (d', X) x j (d, X) for all j i. See Thomson (1987) for more discussions. A dual bargaining problem (D; Y) satisfies (see Zhao, 1999): (i) D R n +, Y Rn, Y, and Y is + compact; (ii) y D for all y Y; (iii) there is y Y such that y << D. Its KS and NA solutions are: y NA = Arg- Max {Π(D i -y i ) y Y}; y KS = D+λ KS t KS Y, where t KS is given by t i KS = Min {(y i-d i ) y Y} for all i, and λ KS = Max {λ D+λt KS Y}. 12

13 Proposition 3: Consider an SS problem (r; d) with Σ d i < r: (i) there is a unique CS problem (L'; D') such that y P (L'; D') = P(r; d) and µ ' P = µ P, where L '= r, and D'= (-1+2r/Σ d j)d; (ii) There exists a unique CS problem (L*; D*) such that y KS (L*; D*) = y NA (L*; D*) = y ES (L*; D*) = KS(r; d), µ * KS = µ * NA = µ * ES = µ KS, where (16) L*= r, and D*= d+(2(r Σ d j)/n)e. In other words, the P and ES solutions in a SS problem each defines a unique CS problem whose solution (and its optimal direction and travel distance) coincide with those in the original SS problem (see Figure 5). However, the reverse of Proposition 3 is not true, because the set of CS problems is larger than that of SS problems. 6. Concluding remarks This note has established, by applying concepts in MOP, two new properties of bargaining solutions: (i) the KS and NA solutions are properly efficient in large classes of convex bargaining problems; (ii) the NA solution satisfies strong IIA, which can be used to replace its efficiency and IIA, while the KS solution doesn t satisfy homogeneity. These results illustrate that new insights on bargaining can be obtained from MOP. From this perspective, this note provides more questions for future research than the above two results: it is non-trivial to find a practical algorithm for computing the KS and other solutions (except the NA solution), and it is challenging to establish general duality between cost- and surplus-sharing problems in the spirit of the duality theory in MOP. On the other hand, new insights on MOP might also be obtained from bargaining theory. For example, it is useful to check if the dual Vector-Min problem (i.e., dual to the Vector-Max problem for utility bargaining) can be interpreted as a bargaining problem, and it is useful to apply 13

14 the bargaining axioms (such as scale invariance or monotonicity) to the stability and the sensitivity analysis of MOP solutions. Appendix Before we prove Propositions 1 and 2, we first provide the following six claims. Recall that efficiency and scale invariance are summarized in Footnote 3. Claim 1 (Geoffrion, 1968): Consider the MOP (2), let X * e, X * pe, X * we be given in Definition 3, k + ={λ Rk + Σ λ j = 1} and k ++ ={λ Rk ++ Σλ j =1} denote the k-1 simplex and its relative interior. For each λ k +, let f λ (x) = Σ {λ jf j (x)}, and X * (λ) = Arg-Max {f λ (x) x X}= {x 0 X f λ (x 0 ) f λ (x), x X}. Suppose all f i (x) are continuous and concave, X is a convex and compact set, then U (A1) X we * = X * ( λ ), and λ k + U (A2) X pe * = X * ( λ ). λ k ++ Claim 2: If there is a convex and increasing function f(x) and x 0 >>d such that X = {x R n + x d, f(x) f(x 0 )}, then for any S N and S-efficient solution x 0, xi 0 = d i for all i S. Proof of Claim 2: By the convexity of f, X = {x R n + x d, f(x) f(x 0 )} is a convex set. Therefore, the MOP problem Max { F T (x) = x T x X} is a convex problem for any coalition T. Let x 0 = x(s) be an S-efficient solution for some S N. By Claim 1, it must be a solution of Max {Σ j S (λ j x j ) x X} for some λ S = {λ j j S}such that λ j 0 and Σ j S λ j = 1. Assume by way of contradiction that x i 0 > d i for some i S. Since f is increasing in all arguments, the value of Σ j S {λ j x0 j } can be increased by reducing xi 0 to d i and increasing any x j with λ j > 0, which 14

15 contradicts the optimality of the above maximization problem. Hence, x i 0 = d i for all i S. Q.E.D Claim 3: Homogeneity implies weak efficiency. Proof of Claim 3: Let (d, X) be a bargaining problem, and z = z(d, X) = d + µ 0 t be a solution satisfying homogeneity, where t = (z-d)/ z-d, µ 0 = z-d. Homogeneity leads to (A3) µ 0 = Max {µ d + µ t X}. Otherwise, if there is some µ > µ 0 such that d + µ t X, one sees that z(d', X') d + µ 0 t for d' = d + [µ 0 +(µ-µ 0 )/2] t, and X' = {x X x d' }. By (A3), z(d, X) X * we. Q.E.D Claim 4: (i) In ball-shaped bargaining, homogeneity implies proper efficiency. (ii) In convex bargaining, homogeneity and IIA imply efficiency. Proof of Claim 4: Part (i). Let (d, X) be a ball-shaped bargaining problem. By Claim 3, z(d, X) X we *, where z(d, X) is the same as in Claim 3. The MOP problem Max {F(x) = x x X} is clearly a convex problem. If z(d, X) X pe *, Claim 1 leads to (A4) z(d, X) X * (λ) = Arg-Max {f λ (x) x X} for some λ k +, with at least one i such that λ i = 0. Therefore, z(d, X) is an S-efficient solution for some S N and i S. By Definition 5, one has z i (d, X) = d i, which contradicts SIR or z i (d, X) > d i. Hence, z(d, X) X pe *. Part (ii) follows from Roth (1997) because homogeneity requires SIR. Q.E.D Claim 5: In a linear bargaining problem, the Nash solution satisfies homogeneity. Proof of Claim 5: Let X = {x R n + Ax b}, NA = Arg-Max{f(x,d)= Π(x i-d i ) x X} be the Nash solution. First observe that NA >> d (If NA i = d i for some i, then NA would not be 15

16 a solution of Max {Π(x i -d i ) x X}. Since f(x,d) is strictly quasi-concave and X is a linear convex set, the Nash solution is uniquely determined by the Kuhn-Tucker conditions: (A5.1) f - λ A 0, x ( f - λ A) = 0; Ax-b 0, λ (Ax-b) = 0; λ R m +, x Rn + ; where f(x,d)= { f/ x 1,, f/ x n }. Let J {1,, m} be the set of binding constraints, and A j be the j-th row of A. Then, for j J, λ j > 0 and A j x-b j = 0; and for j J, λ j = 0 and A j x- b j < 0. Since NA satisfies SIR and IIA, NA is the unique feasible x satisfying (A5.2) f - λ A = 0, λ j > 0 and A j x-b j = 0 for all j J. Now, let t = (NA-d)/ NA-d denote the characteristic direction of Nash solution, µ 0 = NA-d, d' = d + µt (0 µ µ 0 ), and X' = {x X d' x}, we need to show NA = NA(d, X) is identical to the new solution (A6) NA(d', X') = Arg-Max{f(x, d') x X'}. It follows from (A5) and f(na, d') = {Π i 1 (NA i - d' i ),, Π i n (NA i- d' i )} = {Π i 1 (NA i - d i ),, Π i n (NA i- d i )}[(µ 0 -µ)/ µ 0 ] (n-1) = [(µ 0 -µ)/ µ 0 ] (n-1) f(na, d) that NA = NA(d, X) satisfies the Kuhn-Tucker conditions (i.e., (A5.2)) for the new Max problem (A6). Since the new NA solution is uniquely determined by its Kuhn-Tucker conditions, one must have NA(d, X) = NA(d', X'). Q.E.D (Figure 6 about here) Claim 6: The Nash solution in a convex bargaining problem satisfies homogeneity. Proof of Claim 6: It follows from Berge s maximum principal and the uniqueness of the Nash solution that NA(d, X) is continuous in (d, X). Since the compact and convex feasible set X is the limit of a sequence of linear feasible sets (see Figure 6), NA(d, X) is the limit of a sequence of Nash solutions for linear bargaining. Therefore, NA(d, X) must satisfy homogeneity. Q.E.D 16

17 Proof of Proposition 1: Part (i). Suppose a solution g(d, X) satisfies proper efficiency, symmetry, scale invariance, and monotonicity. By X pe * X* e, one has g = KS (see Kalai and Smorodinsky, 1975). The symmetry, scale invariance and monotonicity of KS solution are shown in Kalai and Smorodinsky (1975), we therefore only need to show the proper efficiency. Suppose by way of contradiction that KS X pe *. By Claim 1 and the efficiency of KS solution, one has Therefore, one must have U KS X * e X we * = X * ( λ ), and KS X pe * = X * ( λ ). λ k + KS X * (λ) = Arg-Max {f λ (x) x X} U λ k ++ for some λ k +, with at least one i such that λ i = 0. By Claim 1, KS is S-efficient for some S N and i S, which contradicts the non-degeneracy. Hence, KS X * pe. Part (ii). In linear MOP, one has X pe * = X* e. The efficiency of NA solution therefore leads to its proper efficiency in linear bargaining. Now consider a ball-shaped bargaining (d, X). Similar to the proof of part (i), one can show that NA solution must be an S-efficient for some S N and i S. By Definition 4, NA i = d i, which contradicts the optimality of Max {Π(x i -d i ) x X}> 0. Hence, NA X * pe. Q.E.D Proof of Proposition 2: It follows form Claim 6 and Nash (1950) that Nash solution satisfies scale invariance, SIIA and symmetry. Since SIIA implies efficiency and IIA, any solution satisfying scale invariance, SIIA and symmetry must coincide with the Nash solution. Q.E.D Proof of Remark 2: Part (I) Given X = {x R n + d x u}, one can check that the optimal direction of KS solution is given by t KS = (u-d), which leads to KS = u. The rest of part (I) can be similarly proved by using the features of rectangular bargaining. Part (II) Given X = {x R n + x d, Σ x i r}, the optimal direction of KS solution is t KS = (r Σ d j)e, so KS = d + [(r Σ d j)/n] e. The rest of the proof is straightforward. Q.E.D 17

18 Proof of Proposition 3: We only prove part (ii). By D*= d+(2(r Σ d j)/n)e and L* = r, one has (Σ D * j L*) = (r Σ d j). Therefore, y ES (L*; D*) = D* ((Σ D * j L*)/n)e = d+((r Σ d j)/n)e = ES(r; d). The proof for y ES (L*; D*) = y KS (L*; D*) = y NA (L*; D*) is straightforward (see Zhao, 1999). The uniqueness follows from the requirement µ KS * = µ NA * = µ ES * = µ KS. The proof for part (i) is similar. Q.E.D REFERENCES C. Berge (1963), Topological Spaces. New York: Macmillan. P. Dubey (1986), Inefficiency of Nash Equilibria, Mathematics of Operations Research, Vol. 11, 1-8. S. Fujishige (1991), Submodular functions and optimization theory, Annals of Discrete Mathematics, No. 47. Amsterdam: North Holland. A. Geoffrion (1968), Proper efficiency and the theory of vector maximization. Journal of Math. Anal. and Appl., Vol. 22(3). E. Kalai and M. Smorodinsky (1975), Other solutions to Nash's bargaining problem, Econometrica, Vol. 43, J. Nash (1950), The bargaining problem, Econometrica, Vol. 18, S. Oliveira and P. Ferreira (2000), Bi-objective optimisation with multiple decisionmakers: a convex approach to attain majority solutions, Journal of the Operational Research Society, Vol. 51, A. Roth (1977), Individual rationality and Nash's solution to the bargaining problem, Mathematics of Operations Research, Vol. 2, W. Thomson (1987), Monotonicity of bargaining solutions with respect to disagreement point, Journal of Economic Theory, Vol. 42, W. Thomson (1994), Cooperative Models of Bargaining, Chapter 35 in Handbook of Game Theory, Edited by R. Aumann and S. Hart. Amsterdam: Elsevier Science 18

19 Publishers. M. Zeleny (1984), MCDM: past decade and future trends, Greenwich, Conn: JAI Press. H. P. Young (1985), Cost allocation, in Fair Allocation, H.P. Young, Ed., AMS Short Course Lecture Notes, Vol. 33. Providence: American Mathematical Society. J. Zhao (1991), The equilibria of multiple objective games, The International Journal of Game Theory, Vol. 20, J. Zhao (1999), Dual bargaining and the Talmud bankruptcy problem, Working Paper #99-05, Economics Department, Ohio State University. L. Zhou (1997), Nash bargaining theory and the revealed preference theory for non-convex problems, Econometrica, Vol. 65,

20 x 2 x 2 P u = KS = NA KS= NA ES X d= (d 1, d 2 ) d= (d 1, d 2 ) O Fig 1-a x 1 O Fig 1-b x 1 Figure 1. (a) Solutions in a rectangular bargaining problem, whose ES and P solutions are not efficient; (b) A linear bargaining problem whose ES, P and U solutions do not exist. x 2 P ES =KS= NA d = (d 1, d 2 ) x 1 +x 2 =r x 1 O Figure 2. Solutions in an SS problem (d; r), whose U solution does not exist, and whose ES, KS and NA solutions coincide. 20

21 x 2 Properly efficient set = Curve BC without the points B and C; Efficient set = Curve BC; Weakly efficient set = Curve AD. A B C D x 1 Figure 3. The difference between efficient and properly efficient solutions. x 2 x 2 KS= NA X 4 (6, 4) KS = (5, 3.25) (6, 3.75) KS ' = (5.2, 3.2) O d'= (3, 1.75) d= (d 1, d 2 ) 1 d = (2, 1 ) Fig 4-a x 1 2 Fig 4-b 4 6 x 1 O Figure 4. Counter examples. (a) An example of degenerate bargaining, where for S = (1) or (2), an S-efficient solution x coincides with the maximum vector; (b) A bargaining problem in which homogneity fails to hold in the KS solution. 21

22 x 2 x 2 (D', Y') D' D* (D*, Y*) P P (d, X ) d = (d 1, d 2 ) ES =KS = NA (d, X ) d = (d 1, d 2 ) x 1 +x 2 =r x 1 +x 2 =r O Fig 5-a x 1 O Fig 5-b x 1 Figure 5. (a) The P solution in an SS problem uniquely defines a CS problem with an identical P solution; (b) The ES (= NA = KS ) solution in an SS problem uniquely defines a CS problem with an identical ES (= NA = KS) solution. x 2 O d = (d 1, d 2 ) x 1 Figure 6. A feasible set in convex bargaining is a compact and convex set in R n, which can be approximated by a sequence of linear compact and convex sets. 22

Dual Bargaining and the Talmud Bankruptcy Problem

Dual Bargaining and the Talmud Bankruptcy Problem Dual Bargaining and the Talmud Bankruptcy Problem By Jingang Zhao * Revised January 2000 Department of Economics Ohio State University 1945 North High Street Columbus, OH 43210 1172 USA Zhao.18@Osu.Edu

More information

Cooperative bargaining: independence and monotonicity imply disagreement

Cooperative bargaining: independence and monotonicity imply disagreement Cooperative bargaining: independence and monotonicity imply disagreement Shiran Rachmilevitch September 23, 2012 Abstract A unique bargaining solution satisfies restricted monotonicity, independence of

More information

Bargaining Efficiency and the Repeated Prisoners Dilemma. Bhaskar Chakravorti* and John Conley**

Bargaining Efficiency and the Repeated Prisoners Dilemma. Bhaskar Chakravorti* and John Conley** Bargaining Efficiency and the Repeated Prisoners Dilemma Bhaskar Chakravorti* and John Conley** Published as: Bhaskar Chakravorti and John P. Conley (2004) Bargaining Efficiency and the repeated Prisoners

More information

The Core and Coalition Formation in an N-person Network Game *

The Core and Coalition Formation in an N-person Network Game * The Core and Coalition Formation in an N-person Network Game * By Jingang Zhao February 2008 Department of Economics University of Saskatchewan 9 Campus Drive Saskatoon, Saskatchewan CANADA S7N 5A5 Tel:

More information

The Interdisciplinary Center, Herzliya School of Economics Advanced Microeconomics Fall Bargaining The Axiomatic Approach

The Interdisciplinary Center, Herzliya School of Economics Advanced Microeconomics Fall Bargaining The Axiomatic Approach The Interdisciplinary Center, Herzliya School of Economics Advanced Microeconomics Fall 2011 Bargaining The Axiomatic Approach Bargaining problem Nash s (1950) work is the starting point for formal bargaining

More information

The Nash bargaining model

The Nash bargaining model Politecnico di Milano Definition of bargaining problem d is the disagreement point: d i is the utility of player i if an agreement is not reached C is the set of all possible (utility) outcomes: (u, v)

More information

Stagnation proofness and individually monotonic bargaining solutions. Jaume García-Segarra Miguel Ginés-Vilar 2013 / 04

Stagnation proofness and individually monotonic bargaining solutions. Jaume García-Segarra Miguel Ginés-Vilar 2013 / 04 Stagnation proofness and individually monotonic bargaining solutions Jaume García-Segarra Miguel Ginés-Vilar 2013 / 04 Stagnation proofness and individually monotonic bargaining solutions Jaume García-Segarra

More information

Nash Bargaining in Ordinal Environments

Nash Bargaining in Ordinal Environments Nash Bargaining in Ordinal Environments By Özgür Kıbrıs April 19, 2012 Abstract We analyze the implications of Nash s (1950) axioms in ordinal bargaining environments; there, the scale invariance axiom

More information

Game Theory. Bargaining Theory. ordi Massó. International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB)

Game Theory. Bargaining Theory. ordi Massó. International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB) Game Theory Bargaining Theory J International Doctorate in Economic Analysis (IDEA) Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona (UAB) (International Game Theory: Doctorate Bargainingin Theory Economic Analysis (IDEA)

More information

TWO-PERSON COOPERATIVE GAMES

TWO-PERSON COOPERATIVE GAMES TWO-PERSON COOPERATIVE GAMES Part II: The Axiomatic Approach J. Nash 1953 The Approach Rather than solve the two-person cooperative game by analyzing the bargaining process, one can attack the problem

More information

1 Axiomatic Bargaining Theory

1 Axiomatic Bargaining Theory 1 Axiomatic Bargaining Theory 1.1 Basic definitions What we have seen from all these examples, is that we take a bargaining situation and we can describe the utilities possibility set that arises from

More information

A Characterization of the Nash Bargaining Solution Published in Social Choice and Welfare, 19, , (2002)

A Characterization of the Nash Bargaining Solution Published in Social Choice and Welfare, 19, , (2002) A Characterization of the Nash Bargaining Solution Published in Social Choice and Welfare, 19, 811-823, (2002) Nir Dagan Oscar Volij Eyal Winter August 20, 2001 Abstract We characterize the Nash bargaining

More information

Randomized dictatorship and the Kalai-Smorodinsky bargaining solution

Randomized dictatorship and the Kalai-Smorodinsky bargaining solution Randomized dictatorship and the Kalai-Smorodinsky bargaining solution Shiran Rachmilevitch April 3, 2012 Abstract Randomized dictatorship, one of the simplest ways to solve bargaining situations, works

More information

ECONOMICS SERIES SWP 2009/16. Weakest Collective Rationality and the Nash Bargaining Solution. Nejat Anbarci and Ching-jen Sun

ECONOMICS SERIES SWP 2009/16. Weakest Collective Rationality and the Nash Bargaining Solution. Nejat Anbarci and Ching-jen Sun Faculty of Business and Law School of Accounting, Economics and Finance ECONOMICS SERIES SWP 2009/16 Weakest Collective Rationality and the Nash Bargaining Solution Nejat Anbarci and Ching-jen Sun The

More information

SANDWICH GAMES. July 9, 2014

SANDWICH GAMES. July 9, 2014 SANDWICH GAMES EHUD LEHRER AND ROEE TEPER July 9, 204 Abstract. The extension of set functions (or capacities) in a concave fashion, namely a concavification, is an important issue in decision theory and

More information

Lecture Notes on Bargaining

Lecture Notes on Bargaining Lecture Notes on Bargaining Levent Koçkesen 1 Axiomatic Bargaining and Nash Solution 1.1 Preliminaries The axiomatic theory of bargaining originated in a fundamental paper by Nash (1950, Econometrica).

More information

Rationality and solutions to nonconvex bargaining problems: rationalizability and Nash solutions 1

Rationality and solutions to nonconvex bargaining problems: rationalizability and Nash solutions 1 Rationality and solutions to nonconvex bargaining problems: rationalizability and Nash solutions 1 Yongsheng Xu Department of Economics Andrew Young School of Policy Studies Georgia State University, Atlanta,

More information

Axiomatic bargaining. theory

Axiomatic bargaining. theory Axiomatic bargaining theory Objective: To formulate and analyse reasonable criteria for dividing the gains or losses from a cooperative endeavour among several agents. We begin with a non-empty set of

More information

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7).

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). The axiomatic approach (OR 15) Nash s (1950) work is the starting point

More information

Unique Nash Implementation for a Class of Bargaining Solutions

Unique Nash Implementation for a Class of Bargaining Solutions Unique Nash Implementation for a Class of Bargaining Solutions Walter Trockel University of California, Los Angeles and Bielefeld University Mai 1999 Abstract The paper presents a method of supporting

More information

Mathematical Social Sciences

Mathematical Social Sciences Mathematical Social Sciences 61 (2011) 58 64 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Mathematical Social Sciences journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/econbase The Kalai Smorodinsky bargaining solution

More information

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 7: Supermodular Games

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 7: Supermodular Games 6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 7: Asu Ozdaglar MIT February 25, 2010 1 Introduction Outline Uniqueness of a Pure Nash Equilibrium for Continuous Games Reading: Rosen J.B., Existence

More information

Game Theory: Spring 2017

Game Theory: Spring 2017 Game Theory: Spring 2017 Ulle Endriss Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam Ulle Endriss 1 Plan for Today Today we are going to review solution concepts for coalitional

More information

AN ORDINAL SOLUTION TO BARGAINING PROBLEMS WITH MANY PLAYERS

AN ORDINAL SOLUTION TO BARGAINING PROBLEMS WITH MANY PLAYERS AN ORDINAL SOLUTION TO BARGAINING PROBLEMS WITH MANY PLAYERS ZVI SAFRA AND DOV SAMET Abstract. Shapley proved the existence of an ordinal, symmetric and efficient solution for three-player bargaining problems.

More information

Efficiency, Fairness and Competitiveness in Nash Bargaining Games

Efficiency, Fairness and Competitiveness in Nash Bargaining Games Efficiency, Fairness and Competitiveness in Nash Bargaining Games Deeparnab Chakrabarty, Gagan Goel 2, Vijay V. Vazirani 2, Lei Wang 2 and Changyuan Yu 3 Department of Combinatorics and Optimization, University

More information

ENCOURAGING THE GRAND COALITION IN CONVEX COOPERATIVE GAMES

ENCOURAGING THE GRAND COALITION IN CONVEX COOPERATIVE GAMES STUDIA UNIV. BABEŞ BOLYAI, MATHEMATICA, Volume LIV, Number 1, March 2009 ENCOURAGING THE GRAND COALITION IN CONVEX COOPERATIVE GAMES TITU ANDREESCU AND ZORAN ŠUNIĆ Abstract. A solution function for convex

More information

A Constructive Proof of the Nash Bargaining Solution

A Constructive Proof of the Nash Bargaining Solution Working Paper 14/0 /01 A Constructive Proof of the Nash Bargaining Solution Luís Carvalho ISCTE - Instituto Universitário de Lisboa BRU-IUL Unide-IUL) Av. Forças Armadas 1649-126 Lisbon-Portugal http://bru-unide.iscte.pt/

More information

Weighted values and the Core in NTU games

Weighted values and the Core in NTU games Weighted values and the Core in NTU games Koji Yokote August 4, 2014 Abstract The purpose of this paper is to extend the following result by Monderer et al. (1992): the set of weighted Shapley values includes

More information

5.2 A characterization of the nonemptiness of the core

5.2 A characterization of the nonemptiness of the core Computational Aspects of Game Theory Bertinoro Spring School Lecturer: Bruno Codenotti Lecture 5: The Core of Cooperative Games The core is by far the cooperative solution concept most used in Economic

More information

A generalization of the Egalitarian and the Kalai Smorodinsky bargaining solutions

A generalization of the Egalitarian and the Kalai Smorodinsky bargaining solutions Int J Game Theory 2018) 47:1169 1182 https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-018-0611-4 ORIGINAL PAPER A generalization of the Egalitarian and the Kalai Smorodinsky bargaining solutions Dominik Karos 1 Nozomu Muto

More information

Department of Economics

Department of Economics Department of Economics Two-stage Bargaining Solutions Paola Manzini and Marco Mariotti Working Paper No. 572 September 2006 ISSN 1473-0278 Two-stage bargaining solutions Paola Manzini and Marco Mariotti

More information

Mathematical Foundations -1- Constrained Optimization. Constrained Optimization. An intuitive approach 2. First Order Conditions (FOC) 7

Mathematical Foundations -1- Constrained Optimization. Constrained Optimization. An intuitive approach 2. First Order Conditions (FOC) 7 Mathematical Foundations -- Constrained Optimization Constrained Optimization An intuitive approach First Order Conditions (FOC) 7 Constraint qualifications 9 Formal statement of the FOC for a maximum

More information

Solutions without dummy axiom for TU cooperative games

Solutions without dummy axiom for TU cooperative games Solutions without dummy axiom for TU cooperative games L. Hernandez Lamoneda, R. Juarez, and F. Sanchez Sanchez October, 2007 Abstract In this paper we study an expression for all additive, symmetric and

More information

Background notes on bargaining

Background notes on bargaining ackground notes on bargaining Cooperative bargaining - bargaining theory related to game theory - nice book is Muthoo (1999) argaining theory with applications; - also, Dixit and Skeath's game theory text

More information

Optimality, Duality, Complementarity for Constrained Optimization

Optimality, Duality, Complementarity for Constrained Optimization Optimality, Duality, Complementarity for Constrained Optimization Stephen Wright University of Wisconsin-Madison May 2014 Wright (UW-Madison) Optimality, Duality, Complementarity May 2014 1 / 41 Linear

More information

Nash Demand Game and the Kalai-Smorodinsky Solution

Nash Demand Game and the Kalai-Smorodinsky Solution Florida International University FIU Digital Commons Economics Research Working Paper Series Department of Economics 8-9-2008 Nash Demand Game and the Kalai-Smorodinsky Solution Nejat Anbarci Department

More information

Col.lecció d Economia E13/301. Cooperative games with size-truncated information. F. Javier Martínez-de-Albéniz

Col.lecció d Economia E13/301. Cooperative games with size-truncated information. F. Javier Martínez-de-Albéniz Col.lecció d Economia E13/301 Cooperative games with size-truncated information F. Javier Martínez-de-Albéniz UB Economics Working Papers 2013/301 Cooperative games with size-truncated information Abstract:

More information

Incentives to form the grand coalition versus no incentive to split off from the grand coalition

Incentives to form the grand coalition versus no incentive to split off from the grand coalition Incentives to form the grand coalition versus no incentive to split off from the grand coalition Katsushige FUJIMOTO College of Symbiotic Systems Science, Fukushima University, 1 Kanayagawa Fukushima,

More information

Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College

Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College 2015 Course Overview 1. Bargaining 2. Hidden information and self-selection Optimal contracting with hidden information

More information

Game Theory Fall 2003

Game Theory Fall 2003 Game Theory Fall 2003 Problem Set 1 [1] In this problem (see FT Ex. 1.1) you are asked to play with arbitrary 2 2 games just to get used to the idea of equilibrium computation. Specifically, consider the

More information

Area I: Contract Theory Question (Econ 206)

Area I: Contract Theory Question (Econ 206) Theory Field Exam Winter 2011 Instructions You must complete two of the three areas (the areas being (I) contract theory, (II) game theory, and (III) psychology & economics). Be sure to indicate clearly

More information

Consistency, anonymity, and the core on the domain of convex games

Consistency, anonymity, and the core on the domain of convex games Consistency, anonymity, and the core on the domain of convex games Toru Hokari Yukihiko Funaki April 25, 2014 Abstract Peleg (1986) and Tadenuma (1992) provide two well-known axiomatic characterizations

More information

Multiagent Systems Motivation. Multiagent Systems Terminology Basics Shapley value Representation. 10.

Multiagent Systems Motivation. Multiagent Systems Terminology Basics Shapley value Representation. 10. Multiagent Systems July 2, 2014 10. Coalition Formation Multiagent Systems 10. Coalition Formation B. Nebel, C. Becker-Asano, S. Wöl Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg July 2, 2014 10.1 Motivation 10.2

More information

Almost Transferable Utility, Changes in Production Possibilities, and the Nash Bargaining and the Kalai-Smorodinsky Solutions

Almost Transferable Utility, Changes in Production Possibilities, and the Nash Bargaining and the Kalai-Smorodinsky Solutions Department Discussion Paper DDP0702 ISSN 1914-2838 Department of Economics Almost Transferable Utility, Changes in Production Possibilities, and the Nash Bargaining and the Kalai-Smorodinsky Solutions

More information

Bridging the gap between the Nash and Kalai-Smorodinsky bargaining solutions

Bridging the gap between the Nash and Kalai-Smorodinsky bargaining solutions Bridging the gap between the Nash and Kalai-Smorodinsky bargaining solutions Shiran Rachmilevitch July 9, 2013 Abstract Bargaining solutions that satisfy weak Pareto optimality, symmetry, and independence

More information

Axiomatic Foundations for Compromise Theory. John P. Conley* Richard McLean** and Simon Wilkie*** Revised: February 2014

Axiomatic Foundations for Compromise Theory. John P. Conley* Richard McLean** and Simon Wilkie*** Revised: February 2014 Axiomatic Foundations for Compromise Theory John P. Conley* Richard McLean** and Simon Wilkie*** Revised: February 2014 This is a much revised version of a manuscript of the same title that first appeared

More information

Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium

Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium Zeynel Harun Alioğulları Mehmet Barlo February, 2012 Abstract This study argues that Nash equilibria with less variations in players best responses are more appealing.

More information

Achieving Efficiency with Manipulative Bargainers

Achieving Efficiency with Manipulative Bargainers Achieving Efficiency with Manipulative Bargainers Juan Camilo Gómez Department of Economics Macalester College August 6, 005 Abstract: Two agents bargain over the allocation of a bundle of divisible commodities.

More information

Relative Benefit Equilibrating Bargaining Solution and the Ordinal Interpretation of Gauthier s Arbitration Scheme

Relative Benefit Equilibrating Bargaining Solution and the Ordinal Interpretation of Gauthier s Arbitration Scheme Relative Benefit Equilibrating Bargaining Solution and the Ordinal Interpretation of Gauthier s Arbitration Scheme Mantas Radzvilas July 2017 Abstract In 1986 David Gauthier proposed an arbitration scheme

More information

2.1 Definition and graphical representation for games with up to three players

2.1 Definition and graphical representation for games with up to three players Lecture 2 The Core Let us assume that we have a TU game (N, v) and that we want to form the grand coalition. We model cooperation between all the agents in N and we focus on the sharing problem: how to

More information

Game Theory. Greg Plaxton Theory in Programming Practice, Spring 2004 Department of Computer Science University of Texas at Austin

Game Theory. Greg Plaxton Theory in Programming Practice, Spring 2004 Department of Computer Science University of Texas at Austin Game Theory Greg Plaxton Theory in Programming Practice, Spring 2004 Department of Computer Science University of Texas at Austin Bimatrix Games We are given two real m n matrices A = (a ij ), B = (b ij

More information

On 1-convexity and nucleolus of co-insurance games

On 1-convexity and nucleolus of co-insurance games On 1-convexity and nucleolus of co-insurance games Theo Driessen, Vito Fragnelli, Ilya Katsev, Anna Khmelnitskaya Twente University, The Netherlands Universitá del Piemonte Orientale, Italy St. Petersburg

More information

CENTER FOR INTERNATIONAL ECONOMICS. Working Paper Series. Working Paper No On unication of solutions to the bargaining problem

CENTER FOR INTERNATIONAL ECONOMICS. Working Paper Series. Working Paper No On unication of solutions to the bargaining problem CENTER FOR INTERNATIONAL ECONOMICS Working Paper Series Working Paper No. 208-03 On unication of solutions to the bargaining problem Claus-Jochen Haake and Cheng-Zhong Qin May 208 ON UNIFICATION OF SOLUTIONS

More information

Nash Bargaining Theory with Non-Convexity and Unique Solution

Nash Bargaining Theory with Non-Convexity and Unique Solution Nash Bargaining Theory with Non-Convexity and Unique Solution Cheng-Zhong Qin y Shuzhong Shi z Guofu Tan x March 3, 2009 Abstract We characterize a class of bargaining problems allowing for non-convexity

More information

Nonlinear Programming (NLP)

Nonlinear Programming (NLP) Natalia Lazzati Mathematics for Economics (Part I) Note 6: Nonlinear Programming - Unconstrained Optimization Note 6 is based on de la Fuente (2000, Ch. 7), Madden (1986, Ch. 3 and 5) and Simon and Blume

More information

Mechanism Design: Basic Concepts

Mechanism Design: Basic Concepts Advanced Microeconomic Theory: Economics 521b Spring 2011 Juuso Välimäki Mechanism Design: Basic Concepts The setup is similar to that of a Bayesian game. The ingredients are: 1. Set of players, i {1,

More information

The B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics

The B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics The B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics Topics Volume 7, Issue 1 2007 Article 29 Asymmetric Nash Bargaining with Surprised Players Eran Hanany Rotem Gal Tel Aviv University, hananye@post.tau.ac.il Tel

More information

CORVINUS ECONOMICS WORKING PAPERS. Young's axiomatization of the Shapley value - a new proof. by Miklós Pintér CEWP 7/2015

CORVINUS ECONOMICS WORKING PAPERS. Young's axiomatization of the Shapley value - a new proof. by Miklós Pintér CEWP 7/2015 CORVINUS ECONOMICS WORKING PAPERS CEWP 7/2015 Young's axiomatization of the Shapley value - a new proof by Miklós Pintér http://unipub.lib.uni-corvinus.hu/1659 Young s axiomatization of the Shapley value

More information

CHAPTER 2: CONVEX SETS AND CONCAVE FUNCTIONS. W. Erwin Diewert January 31, 2008.

CHAPTER 2: CONVEX SETS AND CONCAVE FUNCTIONS. W. Erwin Diewert January 31, 2008. 1 ECONOMICS 594: LECTURE NOTES CHAPTER 2: CONVEX SETS AND CONCAVE FUNCTIONS W. Erwin Diewert January 31, 2008. 1. Introduction Many economic problems have the following structure: (i) a linear function

More information

On the Impact of Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives

On the Impact of Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives On the Impact of Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives by Bezalel Peleg, Peter Sudhölter and José M. Zarzuelo Discussion Papers on Business and Economics No. 6/2010 FURTHER INFORMATION Department of

More information

No-envy in Queueing Problems

No-envy in Queueing Problems No-envy in Queueing Problems Youngsub Chun School of Economics Seoul National University Seoul 151-742, Korea and Department of Economics University of Rochester Rochester, NY 14627, USA E-mail: ychun@plaza.snu.ac.kr

More information

Math 152: Applicable Mathematics and Computing

Math 152: Applicable Mathematics and Computing Math 152: Applicable Mathematics and Computing May 26, 2017 May 26, 2017 1 / 17 Announcements Homework 6 was posted on Wednesday, due next Wednesday. Last homework is Homework 7, posted next week (due

More information

The Core can be accessed in a Bounded Number of Steps

The Core can be accessed in a Bounded Number of Steps The Core can be accessed in a Bounded Number of Steps by László Á. KÓCZY Econometrics Center for Economic Studies Discussions Paper Series (DPS) 02.18 http://www.econ.kuleuven.be/ces/discussionpapers/default.htm

More information

BIPARTITE GRAPHS AND THE SHAPLEY VALUE

BIPARTITE GRAPHS AND THE SHAPLEY VALUE BIPARTITE GRAPHS AND THE SHAPLEY VALUE DIPJYOTI MAJUMDAR AND MANIPUSHPAK MITRA ABSTRACT. We provide a cooperative game-theoretic structure to analyze bipartite graphs where we have a set of employers and

More information

האוניברסיטה העברית בירושלים

האוניברסיטה העברית בירושלים האוניברסיטה העברית בירושלים THE HEBREW UNIVERSITY OF JERUSALEM TOWARDS A CHARACTERIZATION OF RATIONAL EXPECTATIONS by ITAI ARIELI Discussion Paper # 475 February 2008 מרכז לחקר הרציונליות CENTER FOR THE

More information

where u is the decision-maker s payoff function over her actions and S is the set of her feasible actions.

where u is the decision-maker s payoff function over her actions and S is the set of her feasible actions. Seminars on Mathematics for Economics and Finance Topic 3: Optimization - interior optima 1 Session: 11-12 Aug 2015 (Thu/Fri) 10:00am 1:00pm I. Optimization: introduction Decision-makers (e.g. consumers,

More information

Pure Strategy Equilibria in Symmetric Two-Player Zero-Sum Games

Pure Strategy Equilibria in Symmetric Two-Player Zero-Sum Games Pure Strategy Equilibria in Symmetric Two-Player Zero-Sum Games Peter Duersch Jörg Oechssler Burkhard C. Schipper November 22, 2010 Abstract We show that a symmetric two-player zero-sum game has a pure

More information

The Shapley Value. 1 Introduction

The Shapley Value. 1 Introduction 64 1 Introduction The purpose of this chapter is to present an important solution concept for cooperative games, due to Lloyd S. Shapley (Shapley (1953)). In the first part, we will be looking at the transferable

More information

NEGOTIATION-PROOF CORRELATED EQUILIBRIUM

NEGOTIATION-PROOF CORRELATED EQUILIBRIUM DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS UNIVERSITY OF CYPRUS NEGOTIATION-PROOF CORRELATED EQUILIBRIUM Nicholas Ziros Discussion Paper 14-2011 P.O. Box 20537, 1678 Nicosia, CYPRUS Tel.: +357-22893700, Fax: +357-22895028

More information

On the Non-Symmetric Nash and Kalai Smorodinsky Bargaining Solutions. Yigal Gerchak

On the Non-Symmetric Nash and Kalai Smorodinsky Bargaining Solutions. Yigal Gerchak Decision Making in Manufacturing and Services Vol. 9 2015 No. 1 pp. 55 61 On the Non-Symmetric Nash and Kalai Smorodinsky Bargaining Solutions Yigal Gerchak Abstract. Recently, in some negotiation application

More information

The general programming problem is the nonlinear programming problem where a given function is maximized subject to a set of inequality constraints.

The general programming problem is the nonlinear programming problem where a given function is maximized subject to a set of inequality constraints. 1 Optimization Mathematical programming refers to the basic mathematical problem of finding a maximum to a function, f, subject to some constraints. 1 In other words, the objective is to find a point,

More information

An Axiomatization of the Euclidean Compromise Solution

An Axiomatization of the Euclidean Compromise Solution An Axiomatization of the Euclidean Compromise Solution by M. Voorneveld, A. van den Nouweland y, and R. McLean z SSE/EFI Working Paper Series in Economics and Finance, No. 703; This version: October 13,

More information

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract Pure strategy dominance with quasiconcave utility functions Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam Abstract By a result of Pearce (1984), in a finite strategic form game, the set of a player's serially

More information

Motivating examples Introduction to algorithms Simplex algorithm. On a particular example General algorithm. Duality An application to game theory

Motivating examples Introduction to algorithms Simplex algorithm. On a particular example General algorithm. Duality An application to game theory Instructor: Shengyu Zhang 1 LP Motivating examples Introduction to algorithms Simplex algorithm On a particular example General algorithm Duality An application to game theory 2 Example 1: profit maximization

More information

Patience and Ultimatum in Bargaining

Patience and Ultimatum in Bargaining Patience and Ultimatum in Bargaining Björn Segendorff Department of Economics Stockholm School of Economics PO Box 6501 SE-113 83STOCKHOLM SWEDEN SSE/EFI Working Paper Series in Economics and Finance No

More information

A Parametric Simplex Algorithm for Linear Vector Optimization Problems

A Parametric Simplex Algorithm for Linear Vector Optimization Problems A Parametric Simplex Algorithm for Linear Vector Optimization Problems Birgit Rudloff Firdevs Ulus Robert Vanderbei July 9, 2015 Abstract In this paper, a parametric simplex algorithm for solving linear

More information

Lecture 5. The Dual Cone and Dual Problem

Lecture 5. The Dual Cone and Dual Problem IE 8534 1 Lecture 5. The Dual Cone and Dual Problem IE 8534 2 For a convex cone K, its dual cone is defined as K = {y x, y 0, x K}. The inner-product can be replaced by x T y if the coordinates of the

More information

An introductory example

An introductory example CS1 Lecture 9 An introductory example Suppose that a company that produces three products wishes to decide the level of production of each so as to maximize profits. Let x 1 be the amount of Product 1

More information

THE MINIMAL OVERLAP COST SHARING RULE

THE MINIMAL OVERLAP COST SHARING RULE THE MINIMAL OVERLAP COST SHARING RULE M. J. ALBIZURI*, J. C. SANTOS Abstract. In this paper we introduce a new cost sharing rule-the minimal overlap cost sharing rule-which is associated with the minimal

More information

Interval values for strategic games in which players cooperate

Interval values for strategic games in which players cooperate Interval values for strategic games in which players cooperate Luisa Carpente 1 Balbina Casas-Méndez 2 Ignacio García-Jurado 2 Anne van den Nouweland 3 September 22, 2005 Abstract In this paper we propose

More information

Lectures 6, 7 and part of 8

Lectures 6, 7 and part of 8 Lectures 6, 7 and part of 8 Uriel Feige April 26, May 3, May 10, 2015 1 Linear programming duality 1.1 The diet problem revisited Recall the diet problem from Lecture 1. There are n foods, m nutrients,

More information

SURPLUS SHARING WITH A TWO-STAGE MECHANISM. By Todd R. Kaplan and David Wettstein 1. Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel. 1.

SURPLUS SHARING WITH A TWO-STAGE MECHANISM. By Todd R. Kaplan and David Wettstein 1. Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel. 1. INTERNATIONAL ECONOMIC REVIEW Vol. 41, No. 2, May 2000 SURPLUS SHARING WITH A TWO-STAGE MECHANISM By Todd R. Kaplan and David Wettstein 1 Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel In this article we consider

More information

Network Calculus. A General Framework for Interference Management and Resource Allocation. Martin Schubert

Network Calculus. A General Framework for Interference Management and Resource Allocation. Martin Schubert Network Calculus A General Framework for Interference Management and Resource Allocation Martin Schubert Fraunhofer Institute for Telecommunications HHI, Berlin, Germany Fraunhofer German-Sino Lab for

More information

Introduction. 1 University of Pennsylvania, Wharton Finance Department, Steinberg Hall-Dietrich Hall, 3620

Introduction. 1 University of Pennsylvania, Wharton Finance Department, Steinberg Hall-Dietrich Hall, 3620 May 16, 2006 Philip Bond 1 Are cheap talk and hard evidence both needed in the courtroom? Abstract: In a recent paper, Bull and Watson (2004) present a formal model of verifiability in which cheap messages

More information

NOTES ON COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY AND THE CORE. 1. Introduction

NOTES ON COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY AND THE CORE. 1. Introduction NOTES ON COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY AND THE CORE SARA FROEHLICH 1. Introduction Cooperative game theory is fundamentally different from the types of games we have studied so far, which we will now refer to

More information

Economics Bulletin, 2012, Vol. 32 No. 1 pp Introduction. 2. The preliminaries

Economics Bulletin, 2012, Vol. 32 No. 1 pp Introduction. 2. The preliminaries 1. Introduction In this paper we reconsider the problem of axiomatizing scoring rules. Early results on this problem are due to Smith (1973) and Young (1975). They characterized social welfare and social

More information

Random Extensive Form Games and its Application to Bargaining

Random Extensive Form Games and its Application to Bargaining Random Extensive Form Games and its Application to Bargaining arxiv:1509.02337v1 [cs.gt] 8 Sep 2015 Itai Arieli, Yakov Babichenko October 9, 2018 Abstract We consider two-player random extensive form games

More information

UNDERGROUND LECTURE NOTES 1: Optimality Conditions for Constrained Optimization Problems

UNDERGROUND LECTURE NOTES 1: Optimality Conditions for Constrained Optimization Problems UNDERGROUND LECTURE NOTES 1: Optimality Conditions for Constrained Optimization Problems Robert M. Freund February 2016 c 2016 Massachusetts Institute of Technology. All rights reserved. 1 1 Introduction

More information

R u t c o r Research R e p o r t. Minimal and locally minimal games and game forms. 1. Endre Boros 2 Vladimir Gurvich 3 Kazuhisa Makino 4

R u t c o r Research R e p o r t. Minimal and locally minimal games and game forms. 1. Endre Boros 2 Vladimir Gurvich 3 Kazuhisa Makino 4 R u t c o r Research R e p o r t Minimal and locally minimal games and game forms. 1 Endre Boros 2 Vladimir Gurvich 3 Kazuhisa Makino 4 RRR 28-2008, October 2008 RUTCOR Rutgers Center for Operations Research

More information

Monotonic ɛ-equilibria in strongly symmetric games

Monotonic ɛ-equilibria in strongly symmetric games Monotonic ɛ-equilibria in strongly symmetric games Shiran Rachmilevitch April 22, 2016 Abstract ɛ-equilibrium allows for worse actions to be played with higher probability than better actions. I introduce

More information

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Emir Kamenica and Matthew Gentzkow University of Chicago June 2010 1 Persuasion mechanisms In this paper we study a particular game where Sender chooses a signal π whose

More information

Lecture 1: Entropy, convexity, and matrix scaling CSE 599S: Entropy optimality, Winter 2016 Instructor: James R. Lee Last updated: January 24, 2016

Lecture 1: Entropy, convexity, and matrix scaling CSE 599S: Entropy optimality, Winter 2016 Instructor: James R. Lee Last updated: January 24, 2016 Lecture 1: Entropy, convexity, and matrix scaling CSE 599S: Entropy optimality, Winter 2016 Instructor: James R. Lee Last updated: January 24, 2016 1 Entropy Since this course is about entropy maximization,

More information

Nash Bargaining Theory with Non-Convexity and Unique Solution

Nash Bargaining Theory with Non-Convexity and Unique Solution Nash Bargaining Theory with Non-Convexity and Unique Solution Cheng-Zhong Qin y Shuzhong Shi z Guofu Tan x August 17, 2009 Abstract We introduce log-convexity for bargaining problems. We show that the

More information

Computational Properties of Quasi-Strict Equilibrium

Computational Properties of Quasi-Strict Equilibrium Computational roperties of Quasi-Strict Equilibrium Felix Brandt and Felix Fischer Institut für Informatik, Universität München 80538 München, Germany {brandtf,fischerf}@tcs.ifi.lmu.de Abstract. This paper

More information

Computational Game Theory Spring Semester, 2005/6. Lecturer: Yishay Mansour Scribe: Ilan Cohen, Natan Rubin, Ophir Bleiberg*

Computational Game Theory Spring Semester, 2005/6. Lecturer: Yishay Mansour Scribe: Ilan Cohen, Natan Rubin, Ophir Bleiberg* Computational Game Theory Spring Semester, 2005/6 Lecture 5: 2-Player Zero Sum Games Lecturer: Yishay Mansour Scribe: Ilan Cohen, Natan Rubin, Ophir Bleiberg* 1 5.1 2-Player Zero Sum Games In this lecture

More information

Bargaining on a Non-Convex Domain

Bargaining on a Non-Convex Domain Faculty Working Paper 91-0104 330 B385 1991:104 COPY 2 Bargaining on a Non-Convex Domain John P. Conley Department of Economics Simon Wilkie Bell Communications Research > Bureau of Economic and Business

More information

Implementing the Nash Extension Bargaining Solution for Non-convex Problems. John P. Conley* and Simon Wilkie**

Implementing the Nash Extension Bargaining Solution for Non-convex Problems. John P. Conley* and Simon Wilkie** Implementing the Nash Extension Bargaining Solution for Non-convex Problems John P. Conley* and Simon Wilkie** Published as: John P. Conley and Simon Wilkie Implementing the Nash Extension Bargaining Solution

More information

Cooperative Games. Stéphane Airiau. Institute for Logic, Language & Computations (ILLC) University of Amsterdam

Cooperative Games. Stéphane Airiau. Institute for Logic, Language & Computations (ILLC) University of Amsterdam Cooperative Games Stéphane Airiau Institute for Logic, Language & Computations (ILLC) University of Amsterdam 12th European Agent Systems Summer School (EASSS 2010) Ecole Nationale Supérieure des Mines

More information

Volume 35, Issue 2. Cournot Equilibrium Uniqueness in Case of Concave Industry Revenue: a Simple Proof

Volume 35, Issue 2. Cournot Equilibrium Uniqueness in Case of Concave Industry Revenue: a Simple Proof Volume 35, Issue 2 Cournot Equilibrium Uniqueness in Case of Concave Industry Revenue: a Simple Proof Pierre von Mouche Wageningen Universiteit Federico Quartieri Universita degli studi di Napoli Federico

More information

Manipulation of Preferences and Relative Utilitarianism

Manipulation of Preferences and Relative Utilitarianism Games and Economic Behavior 37, 196 215 (2001) doi:10.1006/game.2000.0839, available online at http://www.idealibrary.com on Manipulation of Preferences and Relative Utilitarianism JoelSobel 1 Department

More information