SUCCESSORS OF SINGULAR CARDINALS AND COLORING THEOREMS I TODD EISWORTH AND SAHARON SHELAH

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "SUCCESSORS OF SINGULAR CARDINALS AND COLORING THEOREMS I TODD EISWORTH AND SAHARON SHELAH"

Transcription

1 SUCCESSORS OF SINGULAR CARDINALS AND COLORING THEOREMS I TODD EISWORTH AND SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. We investigate the existence of strong colorings on successors of singular cardinals. This work continues Section 2 of [], but now our emphasis is on finding colorings of pairs of ordinals, rather than colorings of finite sets of ordinals.. Introduction The theme of this paper is that strong coloring theorems hold at successors of singular cardinals of uncountable cofinality, except possibly in the case where the singular cardinal is a limit of regular cardinals that are Jonsson in a strong sense. Our general framework is that λ = µ +, where µ is singular of uncountable cofinality. We will be searching for colorings of pairs of ordinals < λ that exhibit quite complicated behaviour. The following definition (taken from [2]) explains what complicated means in the previous sentence. Definition.. Let λ be an infinite cardinal, and suppose κ+θ µ λ. Pr (λ, µ, κ, θ) means that there is a symmetric two place function c from λ to κ such that if ξ < θ and for i < µ, α i,ζ : ζ < ξ is a strictly increasing sequence of ordinals < λ with all α i,ζ s distinct, then for every γ < κ there are i < j < µ such that (.) ζ < ξ and ζ 2 < ξ = c(α i,ζ, α i,ζ2 ) = γ. Just as in [], one of our main tools is a game that measures how Jonsson a given cardinal is. Recall that a cardinal λ is a Jonsson cardinal if for every c : [λ] <ω λ, we can find a subset I λ of cardinality λ such that the range of c I is a proper subset of λ. A reader seeking more background should investigate [4] and [3] in [5]. Date: October 6, Key words and phrases. Jonsson cardinals, coloring theorms, successors of singular cardinals. This is publication number 535 of the second author.

2 2 TODD EISWORTH AND SAHARON SHELAH Definition.2. Assume µ λ are cardinals, γ is an ordinal, n ω, and J is an ideal on λ. We define the game Gm n J [λ, µ, γ] as follows: A play lasts γ moves. In the α th move, the first player chooses a function F α : [λ] <n µ, and the second player responds by choosing (if possible) a subset A α λ such that A α β<α A β A α J + ran(f α [A α ] <n ) is a proper subset of µ. The second player loses if he has no legal move for some α < γ, and he wins otherwise. In the previous definition, if J = Jλ bd then we may omit it. Note that it causes no harm if we use a set E of cardinality λ instead of λ itself; in this case, we write Gm n J [E, µ, γ]. Note that λ is a Jonsson cardinal if and only if Player I does not have a winning strategy in the game Gm ω [λ, λ, ]. One may view the lack of a winning strategy for Player I in games of longer length as a strong version of Jonsson-ness or a weak version of measurability if λ is measurable, then Player II can make sure her moves are elements of some λ complete ultrafilter. The following claim investigates how the existence of winning strategies is affected by modifications to the game; the proof is left to the reader. Claim.3. () If µ µ and the first player has a winning strategy in Gm n J [λ, µ, γ], then she has a winning strategy in Gm n J[λ, µ, γ]. (2) Suppose we weaken the demand on the second player to (.2) ( ζ < λ)[ran(f α [A α \ ζ] <n ) is a proper subset of µ]. If cf(λ) γ and J Jλ bd, then the first player has a winning strategy in the revised game if and only if she has a winning strategy in the original game. (3) If J is γ complete, then the same applies to the case where we weaken the demand on the second player to (.3) ( Y J)[ran(F α [A α \ Y ] <n ) is a proper subset of µ]. (4) We can allow the second player to pass, i.e., to let A α = β<α A β (even if this is not a legal move) as long as we declare that the

3 COLORING THEOREMS 3 second player loses if the order type of the set of moves where he did not pass is < γ. (5) If Player I has a winning strategy in Gm n J[λ, µ, γ] for every µ < µ where µ is singular and γ > cf(µ ) is regular, then Player I has a winning strategy in Gm n J [λ, µ, γ]. We can weaken the requirement that γ is regular and instead require that cf(γ) > cf(µ ) and ω γ = γ. In Section 2 of [], the existence of winning strategies for Player I in variants of the game is investigated. We will prove one such result here; the reader should look in [] for others. Claim.4. If 2 χ < λ < ℶ (2 χ ) +(χ) then Player I has a winning strategy in Gm ω [λ, χ, (2 χ ) + ]. Proof. At a stage i, Player I will select a function F i : [λ] <ω χ coding the Skolem functions of some model M i. For the initial move, we let the model M 0 have universe λ, and include in our language all relations on λ and all functions from λ to λ of any finite arity that are first order definable in the structure H(λ + ),, < λ with the parameters χ and λ. + For subsequent moves, M i is an expansion of M 0 with universe λ that has all relations on λ and all functions from λ to λ of any finite arity that are first order definable in the structure H(λ + ),, < λ from the + parameters χ, λ, M 0, and A j : j < i. To obtain the function F i, we let Fn i : n < ω list the Skolem functions of M i in such a way that Fn i has m i(n) n places. Let h : ω ω be such that for all n, h(n) n and h ({n}) is infinite. We then define { Fh( u ) i (.4) F i (u) = ({α u : u α < m i(n)}) if this is < χ 0 otherwise The point of doing this is that whenever Player II chooses A i, we know that ran(f i [A i ] <ω ) will look like the result of intersecting an elementary submodel of M i with χ; in particular, this range will be closed under the functions from M i. Note that M 0 (and all expansions of it) has definable Skolem functions and so for any i and A λ, the Skolem hull of A in M i (denoted by Sk Mi (A)) is well defined. Let (F i, A i ) : i < (2 χ ) + be a play of the game in which Player I uses this strategy (with M i the model corresponding to F i ). For each i, define (.5) α i = min{α : Sk M0 (A i ) ℶ α (χ) > χ}.

4 4 TODD EISWORTH AND SAHARON SHELAH By the choice of M 0 and M i, clearly α(i) is a successor ordinal or a limit ordinal of cofinality χ +, and (.6) Sk M0 (A i ) ℶ αi (χ) 2 χ. Since A i A j for i > j, we know the sequence α i : i < (2 χ ) + is non decreasing. Furthermore, for each i we know (.7) α i < min{β : λ ℶ β (χ)} < (2 χ ) +. This means that the sequence α i : i < (2 χ ) + is eventually constant, say with value α. Let i be the least ordinal < (2 χ ) + such that α i = α for i i. Proposition.5. If i i < (2 χ ) +, then Sk M0 (A i+ ) ℶ α (χ) is a proper subset of Sk M0 (A i ) ℶ α (χ). Proof. Note that i, α, and ℶ α (χ) are all elements of M i+ as they are definable in H(λ + ),, < λ + from the parameters M 0 and A j : j i. Furthermore, (.8) γ := min{γ < λ : Sk M0 (A i ) γ = χ} is also definable in M i+ (and < (2 χ ) + ). Thus the language of M i+ includes a bijection between Sk M0 (A i ) γ and χ. If Player I has not won the game at this stage, after Player I selects A i+ we will be able to find an ordinal β < χ such that β / ran(f i+ [A i+ ] <ω ). By definition of h, we know β := h (β) is an element of Sk M0 (A i ) ℶ α (χ). However, β is not an element of Sk Mi+ (A i+ ) since F i+ codes the Skolem functions of M i+, the range of F i+ [A i+ ] <ω is Sk Mi+ (A i+ ) χ. Since Sk Mi+ (A i+ ) is closed under h, this contradicts our choice of β. Since Sk M0 (A i+ ) Sk Mi+ (A i+ ), we have established the proposition. Note that the preceding proposition finishes the proof of the claim if play of the game continues for all (2 χ ) + steps, then Sk M0 (A i ) ℶ α (χ) : i < (2 χ ) + is a strictly decreasing family of subsets of Sk M0 (A i ), contradicting (.6). 2. Club guessing technology In this section, we prove that if λ = µ +, where µ is singular, then under certain circumstances we can find a complicated library of colorings of smaller cardinals. In the next section, we will use this library of colorings to get a complicated coloring of λ. The basics of club guessing are explained in [4], but we will take a few minutes to recall some of the definitions.

5 COLORING THEOREMS 5 Let us recall that if S is a stationary subset of λ, then an S club system is a sequence C = C δ : δ S such that for (limit) δ S, C δ is closed unbounded in δ. In this section, we will be concerned with the case where λ is the successor of a singular cardinal, i.e., λ = µ + where cf(µ) < µ. In this context, if C is an S club system, then for δ S we define an ideal J b[µ] δ γ < δ, on C δ by A J b[µ] δ if and only if A C δ, and for some θ < µ and β A nacc(c δ ) [β < γ or cf(β) < θ]. Note that it is a bit easier to understand the definition of J b[µ] δ by looking at the contrapositive a subset A of C δ is large, i.e., not in, if and only if A nacc(c δ ) is cofinal in δ, and the cofinalities of members of any end segment of A nacc(c δ ) are unbounded below µ. J b[µ] δ Claim 2.. Let λ = µ +, where µ is a singular cardinal of cofinality κ < µ. Let S λ be stationary, and assume that sup{cf(δ) : δ S} = µ < µ. Let C be an S club system, and for each δ S, let J δ be the ideal J b[µ] δ. Let κ i : i < κ be a non decreasing sequence of cardinals such that (2.) κ = i<κ κ i µ, and let γ < µ. Assume we are given a λ club system ē and a sequence of ideals Ī = I α : α < λ such that () I α is an ideal on e α extending J bd e α (2) if δ S, then for each i < κ, {α nacc(c δ ) : Player I wins Gm ω I α [e α, κ i, γ ]} = nacc(c δ ) mod J δ (3) for any club E λ, for stationarily many δ S, where {α nacc(c δ ) : B 0 [E, e α ] / I α } / J δ, B 0 [E, e α ] = {β nacc(e α) : E meets the interval (sup(β e α ), β)}. Then there is a function h : λ (κ + ) and a sequence F = F δ : δ < λ, δ a limit such that F δ : [e δ ] <ω κ h(δ) (where κ := κ κ ) and

6 6 TODD EISWORTH AND SAHARON SHELAH 2 for every club E λ, for each i < κ there are stationarily many δ S such that the set of β nacc(c δ ) satisfying the following h(β) i B 0 [E, e β ] / I β for all γ < β, κ h(β) ran(f β [ B 0 [E, e β ] \ γ ] <ω ) is not in J δ. Now admittedly the previous claim is quite a lot to digest, so we will take a little time to illuminate the basic situation we have in mind. Claim 2.2. The assumptions of Claim 2. are satisfied if () λ = µ + where κ = cf(µ) < µ (2) S {δ < λ : cf(δ) = κ} (3) δ S δ = µ (i.e., S λ \ µ) (4) C is an S club system (5) J = J δ : δ S where J δ = J b[µ] C δ (6) id p ( C, J) is a proper ideal (7) κ i : i < κ is a non decreasing sequence of cardinals with supremum κ µ (8) γ < µ, and for each i < κ, Player I wins the game Gm ω [θ, κ i, γ ] for all large enough regular θ < µ (9) ē is a λ club system such that e β < µ (0) for α < λ, I α = J bd e α Proof of Claim 2.2. We need only check items (2) and (3) in the statement of Claim 2. everything else is trivially satisfied. Concerning (2), given δ S and i < κ, we need to show {α nacc(c δ ) : Player I wins Gm ω [e α, κ i, γ ]} = nacc(c δ ) mod J δ. Let A consist of those α nacc(c δ ) for which Player I does not win the game Gm ω [e α, κ i, γ ]. By our assumptions, there is a θ < µ such that e α < θ for all α A, and therefore A is in the ideal J b[µ] C δ = J δ and we have what we need. Concerning (3), given E λ club, we must find stationarily many δ S such that {α nacc(c δ ) : B 0 [E, e α ] / I α } / J δ. Let E = {ξ E : otp(e ξ) = ξand µ divides ξ}. Clearly E is a closed unbounded subset of E, and since id p ( C, J) is a proper ideal,

7 the set COLORING THEOREMS 7 S := {δ S E : E nacc(c δ ) / J δ } is stationary. Fix δ S, and suppose we are given θ < µ and ξ < δ. Since E nacc(c δ ) / J δ, we can find α E nacc(c δ ) such that α > max{ξ, µ} and cf(α) > θ. Since the order type of E α is α µ > e α, we know that B 0 [E, e α ] is unbounded in e α hence a member of I α. This shows that the set of such α is in J + δ, as required. Now we return to the proof of Claim 2.. Proof of Claim 2.. Let σ = cf(σ) be a regular cardinal < µ that is greater than µ and γ. For each limit β < λ, if there is an i κ such that Player I wins the version of Gm ω I β [e β, κ i, σ + ] where we allow Player II to pass, then we let h(β) be the maximal such i note that i exists by (5) of Claim.3 and let Str β be a strategy that witnesses this. Note that since γ < σ + and J δ = J b[µ] δ for δ S, we have that for δ S and i < κ that {β nacc(c δ ) : Str β is defined and i h(β)} = nacc(c δ ) mod J δ. We will make σ + attempts to build F witnessing the conclusion. In stage ζ < σ +, we assume that our prior work has furnished us with a decreasing sequence E ξ : ξ < ζ of clubs in λ, and, for each β < λ where Str β is defined, an initial segment F ξ β, Aξ β : ξ < ζ of a play of Gm ω I β [e β, κ h(β), σ+ ] in which Player I uses Str β. (Note that our convention is that if Player II chooses to pass at a stage, we let A ξ β be undefined.) For each such β, let F ζ β : [e β] <ω κ h(β) be given by Str β, and for those β for which Str β is undefined, we let F β ζ be any such function. Now if F ζ β : β < λ := F ζ is as required then we are done. Otherwise, there is a club E λ and i ζ < κ exemplifying the failure of F ζ, and without loss of generality, (2.2) ( δ S) [ B iζ [E ζ, C δ, Ī, ē, F ζ ] ] J δ. Now let E ζ = acc(e ζ ξ<ζ E ξ). For each β where Str β is defined, we let Player II respond to F ζ β by playing the set B 0[E ζ, e β ] if it is a legal move, otherwise we let him pass. We then proceed to stage ζ +. Assuming that this construction continues for all σ + stages, we will arrive at a contradiction. Let E = ζ<σ E + ζ. By assumption (3) there

8 8 TODD EISWORTH AND SAHARON SHELAH is a δ( ) S for which A := {β nacc(c δ( ) ) : B 0 [E, e β ] / I β } / J δ( ). By assumption (2), we have A 2 := {β A : Str β is defined } / J δ( ). For β A 2, look at the play F ζ β, Aζ β : ζ < σ+. Since Player I wins, there is a ζ β < σ + such that Player II passed at stage ζ for all ζ ζ β. Since σ > µ and J δ( ) is µ based, for some ζ < σ +, A 3 = {β A : Str β is defined and ζ β ζ } / J δ( ). Now E ζ was defined so that for some i ζ, for all δ S, (2.3) B iζ [E ζ, C δ, Ī, ē, F ζ ] J δ, but (again by assumption (2)) A 4 = {β A : Str β is defined, ζ β ζ, and i ζ h(β)} / J δ( ). For β A 4, we know that at stage ζ of our play of Gm ω I β [e β, κ h(β), σ + ] the set B 0 [E ζ, e β ] was not a legal move. Since our sequence of clubs is decreasing, we know that B 0 [E ζ, e β ] is a subset of B 0 [E ξ, e β ] for all ξ < ζ ], so we have B 0 [E ζ, e β ] ξ<ζ A ξ β. Since β A, we know that B 0 [E ζ, e β ] / I β. Thus the reason for B 0 [E ζ, e β ] being an illegal move must be that for all γ < β, κ h(β) ran(f ζ β [B 0[E ζ, e β ] \ γ] <ω ). All of these facts combine to tells us that β B iζ [E ζ, C δ, Ī, ē, F ζ ], and thus contradicting (2.3). A 4 B iζ [E ζ, C δ, Ī, ē, F ζ ] / J δ( ), The proofs in this section (and the next) can be considerably simplified if we are willing to restrict ourselves to the case κ < µ, as we can dispense with the sequence κ i : i < κ.

9 COLORING THEOREMS 9 3. Building the Coloring We now come to the main point of this paper; we dedicate this section and the next to proving the following theorem. Theorem. Assume λ = µ +, where µ is a singular cardinal of uncountable cofinality, say ℵ 0 < κ = cf(µ) < µ. Assume κ i : i < κ is non decreasing with supremum κ µ, and there is a γ < µ such that for each i, for every large enough regular θ < µ, Player I has a winning strategy in the game Gm ω [θ, κ i, γ ]. Then Pr (λ, λ, κ, κ) holds. Let S i : i < κ be a sequence of pairwise disjoint stationary subsets of {δ < λ : cf(δ) = κ}. For i < κ, let C i be an S i club system such that λ / id p ( C i, J i ), where J i = J b[µ] : δ S Cδ i i for δ S i, otp(cδ i ) = cf(δ) = κ = cf(µ) Such ladder systems can be found by Claim 2.6 (and Remark 2.6A (6)) of [2] for the second statement to hold, we need that µ has uncountable cofinality. Claim 3.. There is a λ club system ē such that e β cf(β) + cf(µ), and ē swallows each C i, i.e., if δ S i (e β {β}), then C i δ e β. Proof. Let S = i<κ S i, and let β < λ be a limit ordinal. Let e 0 β be a closed cofinal subset of β of order type cf(β). We will construct the required ladder e β in ω stages, with e n β denoting the result of the first n stages of our procedure. The construction is straightforward, but it is worthwhile to note that we need to use the fact that each member of S has uncountable cofinality. Given e n β, let us define (3.) B n = S (e n β {β}). Now we let e n+ β be the closure in β of (3.2) e n β {C δ : δ B n }. Note that e n+ cf(µ) + cf(β) as C δ = cf(µ) = κ for each δ S. Finally, we let e β be the closure of n<ω e n β in β. Clearly e β cf(µ) + cf(β). Also, since each element of S has uncountable cofinality, if δ S e β, then there is an n such that δ e n β, and therefore (3.3) C δ e n+ β e β, as required.

10 0 TODD EISWORTH AND SAHARON SHELAH For each i < κ, there are h i and F i = Fδ i : δ < λ, δ limit as in the conclusion of Claim 2. applied to C i and ē; note that we satisfy the assumptions of Claim 2. by way of Claim 2.2. Let λ i : i < κ be a strictly increasing sequence of regular cardinals > κ and cofinal in µ such that (3.4) λ = tcf ( ) λ i /Jκ bd, i<κ and let f α : α < λ exemplify this. Finally, let h 0 : κ ω and h : κ κ be such that (3.5) ( n)( i < κ)( κ j < κ)[h 0(j) = n and h (j) = i]. Before we can define our coloring, we must recall some of the terminology of [2]. Definition 3.2. Let 0 < α < β < λ, and define We also define (by induction on l) γ(α, β) = min{γ e β : γ α}. γ 0 (α, β) = β, γ l+ (α, β) = γ(α, γ l (α, β)) (if defined). We let k(α, β) be the first l for which γ l (α, β) = α. The sequence γ i (α, β) : i k(α, β) will be referred to as the walk from β to α along the ladder system ē. We now define the coloring c that will witness Pr (λ, λ, κ, κ). Recall that c must be a symmetric two place function from λ to κ. Given α < β, we let i = i(α, β) be the maximal j < κ such that f β (j) < f α (j) (if such an j exists). Next, we walk from β down to α along ē until we reach an ordinal ν(α, β) such that f α (i) < f ν(α,β) (i), (again, if such an ordinal exists.) After this, we walk along ē from α toward the ordinal max(α e ν(α,β) ) until we reach an ordinal η(α, β) for which f ν(α,β) (i) < f η(α,β) (i). The idea now is to look at how the ladders e ν(α,β) and e η(α,β) intertwine. Let us make a temporary definition by calling an ordinal ξ e ν(α,β) relevant if e η(α,β) meets the interval (sup(ξ e ν(α,β) ), ξ). If it makes sense, we let w(α, β) e ν(α,β) be the last h 0 (i(α, β)) relevant ordinals in e ν(α,β) (so we need that the relevant ordinals have order type γ + h 0(i(α, β)) for some γ).

11 COLORING THEOREMS Finally, we define our coloring by (3.6) c(α, β) = F h (i(α,β)) ν(α,β) (w(α, β)). If the attempt to define c(α, β) breaks down at some point for some specific α < β, then we set c(α, β) = 0. We now prove that this coloring works, so suppose t α : α < λ are pairwise disjoint subsets of λ such that t α = θ < κ and j < κ, and without loss of generality α < min t α and θ ω. We need to find δ 0 and δ such that (3.7) α t δ0 and β t δ α < β and c(α, β) = j. Let j be the least j such that j < κ j, and let S, C, and F denote S j, Cj, and F j respectively. Given δ < λ, we define the envelope of t δ (denoted env(t δ )) by the formula (3.8) env(t δ ) = {γ l (δ, ζ) : l k(δ, ζ)}. ζ t δ The envelope of t δ is the set of all ordinals obtained by walking down to δ from some ζ t δ using the ladder system ē. This makes sense as we have arranged that δ < min t δ. Note also that env(t δ ) t δ = θ. Next we define functions g min δ and g max δ in i<κ λ i by (3.9) g min δ (i) = min{f γ (i) : γ env(t δ )}, and (3.0) gδ max (i) = sup{f γ (i) + : γ env(t δ )}. Note that gδ max is well defined as we assume that κ < min{λ i : i < κ}. The following claim is quite easy, and the proof is left to the reader. Claim 3.3. () f δ = J bd g min κ δ (2) gδ min (i) gδ max (i) for all i < κ (3) There is a δ > δ such that gδ max J bd κ g min δ. Now let χ = (2 λ ) +, and let M α : α < λ be a sequence of elementary submodels of H(χ ),, < χ that is increasing and continuous in α and such that each M α λ is an ordinal, M β : β α M α+, and f α : α < λ, g, c, ē, S, C, tα : α < λ all belong to M 0. Note that µ + M 0. The set E = {α < λ : M α λ = α} is closed unbounded in λ, and furthermore, (3.) α < δ E sup t α < δ.

12 2 TODD EISWORTH AND SAHARON SHELAH By the choice of C and F, for some δ S E we have the set (3.2) A = {β nacc(c δ ) : ( γ < β) ran(f β [ B 0 [E, e β ] \ γ ] <ω ) κ j } is not in J b[µ] C δ. Note that A acc(e), as B 0 [E, e β ] is unbounded in β for β A. For β t δ, if l < k(δ, β) then e γl (δ,β) δ is bounded in δ, and since it is closed it has a well defined maximum. Since t δ < κ = cf(δ), this means the ordinal γ := sup{max[e γl (δ,β) δ] : β t δ and l < k(δ, β)} is strictly less than δ. For β t δ, let us define (3.3) A β := {β A : ( l k(β, δ))[cf(β ) e γl (δ,β) ]}. Since the cardinality of each ladder in ē is less than µ, each set A β is an element of J b[µ] C δ. The ideal J b[µ] C δ is κ complete, so the fact that t δ < κ and k(β, δ) is finite for each β t δ together imply that (3.4) A β J b[µ] C δ. β t δ By the definition of A and our choice of δ, this means it is possible to choose β A \ (γ + ) that is not in any A β, i.e., (3.5) β t δ and l < k(δ, β) = cf(β ) > e γl (δ,β). Claim 3.4. () If ɛ t δ, and l = k(δ, ɛ), then β nacc(e γl (δ,ɛ)). (2) If ɛ t δ and γ < γ β, then γ l (δ, ɛ) = γ l (γ, ɛ) for l < k(δ, ɛ), and γ k(δ,ɛ) (γ, ɛ) = β Proof. For the first clause, note that δ is an element of e γl (δ,ɛ) and hence by our choice of ē, C δ e γl (δ,ɛ). Thus β e γl (δ,ɛ), and since cf(β ) > e γl (δ,ɛ), we know that β cannot be an accumulation point of e γl (δ,ɛ). The first part of the second statement follows because of the definition of γ. As far as the second part of the second statement goes, it is best visualized as follows: We walk down the ladder system ē from ɛ to γ, we eventually hit a ladder that contains δ this happens at stage k(δ, ɛ). Since C δ is a subset of this ladder, the next step in our walk from ɛ to γ must be down to β because γ < γ < β.

13 COLORING THEOREMS 3 We can visualize the preceding claim in the following manner: β is chosen so that for all sufficiently large γ < β, all the walks from some element of t δ to γ are funnelled through β β acts as a bottleneck. This will be key when want to prove that our coloring works. Since β A, we can choose a finite increasing sequence ξ 0 < ξ < < ξ n of ordinals in acc(e) nacc(e β ) \ (γ + ) such that F j β ({ξ 0,..., ξ n }) = j, the color we are aiming for. For each l n, we can find ζ l E \ (γ + ) such that sup(e β ξ l ) < ζ l < ξ l. Now we let φ(x 0, y 0, x, y,..., x n, y n, z 0, z ) be the formula (with parameters γ, f, λ i : i < κ, C, ē, t α : α < λ, h, h 0, j ) that describes our current situation with x l, y l standing for ζ l, ξ l, and z 0, z standing for β, δ, i.e., φ states γ < x 0 < y 0 < < x n < y n < z 0 < z are ordinals < λ z S and z 0 nacc(c z ) γ = sup{max[e γl (z,ζ) z ] : l < k(z, ζ) and ζ t z } z 0 nacc(e γk(z,ɛ)(z,ɛ)) for all ɛ t z F j z 0 ({y 0,..., y n }) = j Now clearly we have (3.6) H(χ) = φ[ζ 0, ξ 0,..., ζ n, ξ n, β, δ]. Recall that all the parameters needed in φ are in M 0, except possibly for γ, so the model M γ + contains all the parameters we need. Also, {ζ 0, ξ 0,..., ζ n, ξ n } M β, β M δ \ M β, and since δ λ \ M δ, we have (recalling that z < λ means for unboundedly many z < λ) (3.7) M δ = ( z < λ)φ(ζ 0, ξ 0,..., ζ n, ξ n, β, z ). Therefore, this formula is true in H(χ) because of elementarity. Similarly, we have H(χ) = ( z 0 < λ)( z < λ)φ(ζ 0, ξ 0,..., ζ n, ξ n, z 0, z ). Now each of the intervals [γ +, ζ 0 ), [ζ 0, ξ 0 ),..., contains a member of E, so (by the definition of E) similar considerations give us H(χ) = ( x 0 < λ)... ( y n < λ)( z 0 < λ)( z < λ)φ(x 0, y 0,..., z 0, z ). Now we can choose (in order) (3.8) ζ a 0 < ζ b 0 < ξ a 0 < ζ a < ξ b 0 < ζ b < < ζ a n < ξ b n < ζ b n < ξ a n

14 4 TODD EISWORTH AND SAHARON SHELAH such that (3.9) ( z 0 < λ)( z < λ)[φ(ζ a 0,..., ξa n, ζ a n, ξa n, z 0, z )], and (3.20) ( y n < λ)( z 0 < λ)( z < λ)[φ(ζ b 0,..., ξ b n, ζ b n, y n, z 0, z )], Our goal is to show that for all sufficiently large i < κ, it is possible to choose objects β a, δ a, ξ b n, βb, and δ b such that () ζ b n < β a < δ a < min(t δ a) max(t δ a) < ξ b n < β b < δ b (2) φ(ζ a 0,..., ξa n, βa, δ a ) (3) φ(ζ b 0,..., ξ b n, β b, δ b ) (4) for all ɛ env(t δ a), g min δ a (5) for all ɛ env(t δ b), g min δ b (6) g max δ b (7) g max δ a [i, κ) f ɛ [i, κ) gδ max a [i, κ) [i, κ) f ɛ [i, κ) g max δ b [i, κ) (i) < g min (i) gmax (i) < f β b(i) < f β a(i) δ a δ a [i +, κ) < gmin [i +, κ) δ b Table Claim 3.5. If for all sufficiently large i < κ it is possible to find objects satisfying the requirements of Table, then we can find δ a < δ b such that c(ɛ a, ɛ b ) = j for all ɛ a t δ a and ɛ b t δ b. Proof. Let us choose i < κ such that suitable objects (as above) can be found, and h (i ) = j and h 0 (i ) = n Choose ɛ a t δ a and ɛ b t δ b; we verify that c(ɛ a, ɛ b ) = j. Subclaim. i(ɛ a, ɛ b ) = i. Proof. Immediate by (4)-(7) in the table. Subclaim 2. ν(ɛ a, ɛ b ) = β b. Proof. Note that γ < ɛ a < β b. Clause (3) of the table implies that the assumptions of Claim 3.4 hold. Thus by Claim 3.4, for l < k(δ b, ɛ b ) we have γ l (ɛ a, ɛ b ) = γ l (δ b, ɛ b ),

15 COLORING THEOREMS 5 hence γ l (ɛ a, ɛ b ) env(t δ b) and (by (6) of the table and the definitions involved) (3.2) f γl (ɛ a,ɛ )(i ) g max b δ (i ) < g min b δ a (i ) f ɛ a(i ). For l = k(δ b, ɛ b ), Claim 3.4 tells us and we have arranged that γ l (ɛ a, ɛ b ) = β b, (3.22) f ɛ a(i ) g max δ a (i ) < f β b(i ). This establishes β b = ν(ɛ a, ɛ b ). Subclaim 3. η(ɛ a, ɛ b ) = β a. Proof. Let α = max(e β b ɛ a ). We have arranged that ζ b n < β a < δ a < ɛ a < ξ b n and γ < max(e β b δ a ), hence γ < α < β a. For l < k(δ a, ɛ a ), Claim 3.4 implies γ l (α, ɛ a ) = γ l (δ a, ɛ a ) env(t δ a). By our choice of i, we have (3.23) f γl (α,ɛ a )(i ) g max δ a (i ) < f β b(i ). For l = k(δ a, ɛ a ), Claim 3.4 implies γ l (α, ɛ a ) = β a, and we have ensured (3.24) f β b(i ) < f β a(i ). Thus β a is the first ordinal η in the walk from ɛ a to max(e β b ɛ a ) for which f η (i ) > f β b(i ), and therefore η(ɛ a, ɛ b ) = β a. Subclaim 4. w(ɛ a, ɛ b ) = {ξ b 0,... ξb n }. Proof. Our previous subclaims imply that an ordinal ξ e β b is relevant if and only if the ladder e β a meets the interval (sup(e β b ξ), ξ). Since h 0 (i ) = n +, we know that w(ɛ a, ɛ b ) consists of the last n + relevant ordinals in e β b. For i n, clearly ξi b e β and b sup(ξb i e β b) ζb n. We have made sure that e β a (ζi b, ξi b ) (for example, ξi a is an element in this intersection) and so each ξi b is relevant. Since β a < ξn, b it is clear that there are no relevant ordinals larger than ξn. b Given i < n, if ξ e β b (ξi b, ξb i+ ), then ξ b i sup(ξ e β b) ξ ζ b i+.

16 6 TODD EISWORTH AND SAHARON SHELAH Since ζi+ a < ξb i < ζ i+ b < ξa i+, it follows that [sup(ξ e β b), ξ) [ζ a i+, ξa i+ ), and so ξ is not relevant. Thus {ξ0, b..., ξn} b are the last n + relevant elements of e β b, as was required. To finish the proof of Claim 3.5, we note that as h (i ) = j, we have (3.25) c(ɛ a, ɛ b ) = F j β b ({ξ b 0,..., ξ b n}) = j. 4. Finding the required ordinals The whole of this section will be occupied with showing that for all sufficiently large i < κ, it is possible to find objects satisfying the requirements of Table. We begin with some notation intended to simplify the presentation. φ a (z 0, z ) abbreviates the formula φ(ζ a 0,..., ξa n, z 0, z ) φ b (y n, z 0, z ) abbreviates the formula φ(ζ b 0, ζ n b, y n, z 0, z ) For i < κ, ψ(i, z ) abbreviates the formula (4.) ( ɛ env(t z ))[g min z [i, κ) f ɛ [i, κ) g max z We have arranged things so that the sentence (4.2) ( z a 0 < λ)( z a < λ)( y b n < λ) [i, κ)] ( z b 0 < λ)( z b < λ)[φa (z a 0, za ) φb (y b n, zb 0, zb )] holds. There are far too many alternations of quantifiers in the above formula for most people to deal with comfortably; the best way to view them is as a single quantifier that asserts the existence of a tree of 5 tuples with the property that every node of the tree has λ successors, and every branch through the tree gives us five objects satisfying φ a φ b. Let Φ(i, z0 a,..., zb ) abbreviate the formula φ a (z0, a z) a φ b (yn, b z0, b z) b ψ(i, z) a ψ(i, z) b ( ) gz max [i +, κ) < g min a z [i +, κ). b

17 COLORING THEOREMS 7 By pruning the tree so that every branch through it is a strictly increasing 5 tuple, we get (4.3) ( z a 0 < λ)( z a < λ)( y b n < λ) ( z b 0 < λ)( z b < λ)( i < κ)[φ(i, z a 0,..., z b )]. We now make a rather ad hoc definition of another quantifier in an attempt to make the arguments that follow a little bit clearer. Given i < κ, let the quantifier,i z0 b < λ mean that not only are there unboundedly many z0 b s below λ satisfying whatever property, but also that for each α < λ i, we can find unboundedly many suitable z0 b s for which f z b 0 (i) is greater than α. Claim 4.. If we choose β a < δ a < ξn b such that (4.4) ( z b 0 < λ)( z b < λ)( i < κ)[φ(i, β a, δ a, ξ b n, zb 0, zb )], then (4.5) ( i < κ)(,i z b 0 < λ)( z b < λ)[φ(i, βa, δ a, ξ b n, zb 0, zb )]. Proof. Suppose that we have β a < δ a < ξn b such that (4.4) holds but (4.5) fails. Then there is an unbounded I κ such that for each i I, (4.6) (,i z b 0 < λ)( z b < λ)[φ(i, βa, δ a, ξ b n, zb 0, zb )]. In (4.4), we can move the quantifier i < κ past the quantifiers to its left, i.e., (4.7) ( i < κ)( z b 0 < λ)( z b < λ)[φ(i, β a, δ a, ξ b n, z b 0, z b )], so without loss of generality, for all i I, (4.8) ( z b 0 < λ)( z b < λ)[φ(i, β a, δ a, ξ b n, z b 0, z b )]. Since (4.6) holds for all i I, it must be the case that for each i I, there is a value g(i) < λ i such that for all sufficiently large β < λ, if (4.9) ( z b < λ)[φ(i, β a, δ a, ξ b n, β, z b )], then (4.0) f β (i) g(i). Since {f α : α < λ} witnesses that the true cofinality of i<κ λ i is λ, we know (4.) ( x < λ)( i I)[g(i) < f x (i)]. When we combine this with (4.4), we see that it is possible to choose β b < λ such that (4.2) ( i I)[g(i) < f β b(i)],

18 8 TODD EISWORTH AND SAHARON SHELAH and (4.3) ( z b < λ)( j < κ)[φ(j, β a, δ a, ξ b n, β b, z b )]. (Note that we have quietly used the fact that I < λ = cf(λ) to get a β b that is large enough so that (4.9) implies (4.0) for all i I for this particular β b.) This last equation implies ( j < κ)( z b < λ)[φ(j, βa, δ a, ξ b n, βb, z b )], so it is possible to choose i I large enough so that g(i) < f β b(i) and ( z b < λ)[φ(i, βa, δ a, ξn b, βb, z b )]. This is a contradiction, as (4.9) holds for our choice of i and β = β b, yet (4.0) fails. Notice that an immediate corollary of the preceding claim is (4.4) ( z a 0 < λ)( z a < λ)( y b n < λ)( i < κ) Claim 4.2. If β a < λ is chosen so that (4.5) ( z a < λ)( y b n < λ)( i < κ) then where and (,i z b 0 < λ)( z b < λ)[φ(i, βa, δ a, ξ b n, zb 0, zb )]. (,i z b 0 < λ)( z b < λ)[φ(i, βa, z a, yb n, zb 0, zb )], ( i < κ)( v < λ i )( z a < λ)[ψ ψ ] ψ := gz max (i) < v, a ψ := ( y b n < λ)( z b 0 < λ) [ v < f z b 0 (i) and ( z b < λ)[φ(i, βa, z a, yb n, zb 0, zb )] ]. Proof. In (4.5), we can move the quantifier ( i < κ) past the other quantifiers to its left, so (4.6) ( i < κ)( z a < λ)( y b n < λ) (,i z b 0 < λ)( z b < λ)[φ(i, βa, z a, yb n, zb 0, zb )] holds. The claim will be established if we show that for each i < κ for which (4.7) ( z a < λ)( y b n < λ) (,i z b 0 < λ)( z b < λ)[φ(i, β a, z a, y b n, z b 0, z b )]

19 holds, it is possible to find v < λ i such that [ (4.8) ( z a < λ) gz max (i) < v and a COLORING THEOREMS 9 ( y b n < λ)( z b 0 < λ) [v < f z b 0 (i) and ( z b < λ)[φ(i, βa, z a, yb n, zb 0, zb )] ] ]. Despite the lengths of the formulas involved, this is not that hard to accomplish. Since λ i < λ = cf(λ), we can find v < λ i such that ( z a < λ) [ gz max (i) < v and a ( yn b < λ)(,i z0 b < λ)( z b < λ)[φ(i, βa, z a, yb n, zb 0, zb )]], and now the result follows from of the definition of,i z b < λ. Thus there are unboundedly many z0 a < λ for which there is a function g i<κ λ i such that for all sufficiently large i < κ, [ (4.9) ( z a < λ) g max (i) g(i) and z a ( y b n < λ)( z b 0 < λ)[ g(i) < f z b 0 (i) and ( z b < λ)[φ(i, za 0, za, yb n, zb 0, zb )]]]. Now this is logically equivalent to the statement (4.20) ( z a < λ)( yn b < λ)( z0 b < λ) [ g max z (i) g(i) < f a z b 0 (i) and ( z b < λ)[φ(i, za 0, za, yb n, zb 0, zb )]]. Suppose we are given a particular z0 a < λ for which a function g as above can be found, and let us fix i < κ large enough so that (4.9) holds. Also fix ordinals δ a < λ and ξn b < λ that serve as suitable z a and yn b. Just to be clear, this means that for these choices we have ( z b 0 < λ) [ g max δ a (i) g(i) < f z b 0 (i) and ( z b < λ)[φ(i, β a, δ a, ξ b n, z b 0, z b )] ]. Since λ i < λ = cf(λ), there must be some value w satisfying ( z b 0 < λ)[ g(i) < f z b 0 (i) < w and ( z b < λ)[φ(i, βa, δ a, ξ b n, zb 0, zb )]]. This implies for our particular β a, g, i, δ a, and ξ b n that (4.2) ( w < λ i )( z b 0 < λ) [ g max δ a (i) g(i) < f z b (i) < w and ( z b < λ)[φ(i, β a, δ a, y b n, z b 0, z b )] ].

20 20 TODD EISWORTH AND SAHARON SHELAH Since λ i < λ = cf(λ), the quantifier ( w < λ i ) can move to the left past the quantifiers ( z a < λ)( yn b < λ). This tells us that for our βa and g, (4.22) ( i < κ)( w < λ i )( z a < λ)( yn b < λ)( z0 b < λ) [ g max z (i) g(i) < f a z b 0 (i) < w and ( z b < λ)[φ(i, βa, z a, yb n, zb 0, zb )]]. When we put all this together, we end up with the statement (4.23) ( z a 0 < λ)( i < κ)( v < λ i )( w < λ i )( z a < λ) ( yn b < λ)( z0 b < λ)[ gz max (i) v < f a z b 0 (i) < w and ( z b < λ)[φ(i, β a, z, a yn, b z0, b z)] ] b. Since both κ and λ i are less than λ = cf(λ), we can move some quantifiers around and achieve (4.24) ( i < κ)( w < λ i )( z a 0 < λ)( v < λ i )( z a < λ) ( yn b < λ)( z0 b < λ)[ gz max (i) v < f a z b 0 (i) < w and ( z b < λ)[φ(i, β a, z, a yn, b z0, b z)] ] b. Thus there is a function h i<κ λ i such that (4.25) ( i < κ)( z a 0 < λ)( v < λ i )( z a < λ) ( yn b < λ)( z0 b < λ)[ gz max (i) v < f a z b 0 (i) < h(i) and ( z b < λ)[φ(i, β a, z, a yn, b z0, b z)] ] b. After all this work, it is finally time to prove that we can select objects β a < δ a < ξ b n < βb < δ b that satisfy all of our requirements. Clearly, for every unbounded Λ λ, ( i < κ)( x Λ)(h [i, κ) < f x [i, κ). Thus we can choose i < κ such that h (i ) = j and h 0(i ) = n, and ( z a 0 < λ) [h [i, κ) < f za 0 [i, κ) and ( v < λ i )( z a < λ)( y b n < λ) ( z0 b < λ)[ gz max (i ) v < f a z b 0 (i ) < h(i ) and ( z b < λ)[φ(i, z a 0,..., zb )]]].

21 COLORING THEOREMS 2 So now we choose β a such that h(i ) < f β a(i ) and for some α < λ i, ( z a < λ)( yn b < λ)( z0 b < λ)[ gz max (i ) α < f a z b 0 (i ) < h(i ) and ( z b < λ)[φ(i, z0, a..., z)] ] b. Now we choose δ a, ξ b n, βb, and δ b such that β a < δ a < ξ b n < βb g max δ a (i ) α < f β b(i ) < h(i ) < f β a(i ) Φ(i, β a, δ a, ξ b n, βb, δ b ) It is straightforward to check that these objects satisfy all the requirements listed in Table, so by Claim 3.5, we are done. 5. Conclusions In this final section, we will deduce some conclusions in a few concrete cases. Theorem 2. If µ is a singular cardinal of uncountable cofinality that is not a limit of regular Jonsson cardinals, then Pr (µ +, µ +, µ +, cf(µ)) holds. Proof. The proof of this theorem occurs in two stages we first show that Pr (µ +, µ +, µ, cf(µ)) holds, and then we show that this result can be upgraded to obtain Pr (µ +, µ +, µ +, cf(µ). Let µ be as hypothesized, and let us define λ = µ + and κ = cf(µ). Claim 5.. Pr (λ, λ, µ, κ) holds. Proof. Let κ i : i < κ be a strictly increasing continuous sequence cofinal in µ. Let S {δ [µ, λ) : cf(δ) = κ} be stationary. Standard club guessing results tell us that there is an S club system C such that id p ( C, J) is a proper ideal, where J δ is the ideal J b[µ] C δ for δ S, and furthermore, satisfying C δ = κ. (Note that this last requires that κ = cf(µ) is uncountable.) At this point, we have satisfied all of the assumptions of Claim 2.2 except possibly for clause (8). It suffices to show that for each i < κ, for all sufficiently large regular θ < µ, Player I has a winning strategy in the game Gm ω [θ, κ i, ]. Since µ is not a limit of regular Jonsson cardinals, it follows that for all sufficiently large regular θ < µ, Player I has a winning strategy in Gm ω [θ, θ, ]. This implies, by Lemma.3 (), that for all sufficiently large regular θ, Player I has a winning strategy in Gm ω [θ, κ i, ], and so clause (8) of Claim 2.2 is satisfied.

22 22 TODD EISWORTH AND SAHARON SHELAH To finish the proof of Theorem 2, it remains to show that we can increase the number of colors from µ to λ = µ + we need Pr (λ, λ, λ, κ) instead of Pr (λ, λ, µ, κ). Lemma 5.2. There is a coloring c : [λ] 2 λ such that whenever we are given θ < κ, t α : α < λ a sequence of pairwise disjoint elements of [λ] θ, ζ α t α for α < λ, and Υ < λ, we can find α < β such that t α min(t β ) and (5.) ( ζ t α )[c (ζ, ζ β ) = Υ]. Proof. Let c : [λ] 2 µ be a coloring that witnesses Pr (λ, λ, µ, κ). For each α < λ, let g α be a one to one function from α into µ. We define (5.2) c (α, β) = g (c(α, β)). β Suppose now that we are given objects θ, t α : α < λ, ζ α : α < λ, and Υ as in the statement of the lemma. Clearly we may assume that min(t α ) > α. For i < µ, we define X i := {α [γ, λ) : g ζα (Υ) = i}. Since λ is a regular cardinal, it is clear that there is i < µ for which X i = λ. Since c exemplifies Pr (λ, λ, µ, κ), for some α < β in X i we have t α min(t β ) and (5.3) ( ζ t α )[c(ζ, ζ β ) = i ]. By definition, this means (5.4) ( ζ t α )[c (ζ, ζ β ) = g (c(α, β)) = g (i ) = Υ], hence α and β are as required. To continue the proof of Theorem 2, we define a coloring c 2 : [λ] 2 λ by (5.5) c 2 (α, β) = c (α, ν(α, β)), where ν(α, β) is as in the proof of Theorem. It remains to check that c 2 witnesses Pr (λ, λ, λ, κ). Toward this end, suppose we are given θ < κ, t α : α < λ a sequence of pairwise disjoint members of [λ] θ, and Υ < λ. We need to find δ a and δ b less than λ such that (5.6) ɛ a t δ a ɛ b t δ b = c 2 (ɛ a, ɛ b ) = Υ.

23 COLORING THEOREMS 23 Lemma 5.3. There is a stationary set of γ < λ such that for some γ 0 < γ and β [γ, λ), if γ 0 α < γ, then the function ν is constant on t α t β. Proof. Let E be an arbitrary closed unbounded subset of λ, and let W be the set of ordinals < λ satisfying the properties of γ. In the proof of Theorem, without loss of generality we can have E M 0. This means that the ordinal β found in the course of that proof will be in E, so we finish by observing that β W. An application of Fodor s Lemma gives us a single ordinal γ 0 and a stationary W W such that for all γ W, there is a β γ [γ, λ) such that for all α [γ 0, γ), ν (t α t β ) is constant. Using properties of the coloring c, we can find α and γ such that γ 0 α < λ γ W \ (sup(t α ) + ), and ζ t α = c (ζ, γ) = Υ. Now given ɛ a t α and ɛ b t βγ, we find (5.7) c 2 (ɛ a, ɛ b ) = c (ɛ a, γ) = Υ, and therefore c 2 exemplifies Pr(λ, λ, λ, κ). Theorem 2 strengthens results in [] as clearly Pr (µ +, µ +, µ +, cf(µ)) implies that µ + has a Jonsson algebra (i.e., µ + is not a Jonsson cardinal). The question of whether the successor of a singular cardinal can be a Jonsson cardinal is a well known open question. We note that many of the results from Section 2 of [] dealing with the existence of winning strategies for Player I in Gm ω [λ, µ, γ] can be combined with Theorem to give new results. For example, we have the following result from []. Proposition 5.4. If τ 2 κ but ( θ < κ)[2 θ < τ], then Player I has a winning strategy in the game Gm ω (τ, κ, κ + ). Proof. See Claim 2.3() and Claim 2.4() of []. Armed with this, the following claim is straightforward. Claim 5.5. Let µ be a singular cardinal of uncountable cofinality. Further assume that χ is a cardinal such that 2 <χ µ < 2 χ. Then Pr (µ +, µ +, χ, cf(µ)) holds. Proof. If 2 <χ < µ, then Claims 2.3() and 2.4() of [] imply that for every sufficiently large θ < µ, Player I has a winning strategy in the game Gm ω (θ, χ, χ + ).

24 24 TODD EISWORTH AND SAHARON SHELAH If µ = 2 <χ, then cf(µ) = cf(χ). Let κ i : i < cf(µ) be a strictly increasing continuous sequence of cardinals cofinal in χ. Given i < cf(µ), we claim that for all sufficiently large regular τ < µ, Player I has a winning strategy in Gm ω (τ, κ i, χ). Once we have established this, Pr (µ +, µ +, χ, cf(µ)) follows by Theorem. Given τ = cf(τ) satisfying 2 κ i < τ < µ, let η be the least cardinal such that τ 2 η. Clearly κ i < η < χ. By Proposition 5.4, Player I wins the game Gm ω (τ, η, η + ). This implies (since η + < χ and κ i < η) that Player I wins the game Gm ω (τ, κ i, χ) as required. We can also use Claim.4 to prove similar results. For example we have the following. Claim 5.6. Let µ be a singular cardinal of uncountable cofinality. Further assume that χ < µ satisfies 2 χ < µ < ℶ (2 χ ) +(χ). Then Pr (µ +, µ +, χ, cf(µ)) holds. Proof. Again, the main point is that for all sufficiently large regular θ < µ, Player I has a winning strategy in the game Gm ω [θ, χ, (2 χ ) + ]. This follows immediately from Claim.4. Since (2 χ ) + < µ, Theorem is applicable. In a sequel to this paper, we will address the situation where λ is the successor of a singular cardinal of countable cofinality. Similar results hold, but the combinatorics involved are trickier. References [] Saharon Shelah, More Jonsson algebras, Archive for Mathematical Logic accepted. [2], Cardinal arithmetic, Oxford Logic Guides, vol. 29, Oxford University Press, 994. [3], Jonsson Algebras in an inaccessible λ not λ-mahlo, Cardinal Arithmetic, Oxford Logic Guides, vol. 29, Oxford University Press, 994. [4], There are Jonsson algebras in many inaccessible cardinals, Cardinal Arithmetic, Oxford Logic Guides, vol. 29, Oxford University Press, 994. [5], Proper and improper forcing, Perspectives in Mathematical Logic, Springer, 998. Department of Mathematics, University of Northern Iowa, Cedar Falls, IA, address: eisworth@uni.edu Institute of Mathematics, Hebrew University of Jerusalem, Jerusalem, Israel address: shlhetal@math.huji.ac.il

On squares, outside guessing of clubs and I <f [λ]

On squares, outside guessing of clubs and I <f [λ] F U N D A M E N T A MATHEMATICAE 148 (1995) On squares, outside guessing of clubs and I

More information

VARIATIONS FOR SEPARATING CLUB GUESSING PRINCIPLES

VARIATIONS FOR SEPARATING CLUB GUESSING PRINCIPLES P max VARIATIONS FOR SEPARATING CLUB GUESSING PRINCIPLES TETSUYA ISHIU AND PAUL B. LARSON Abstract. In his book on P max [6], Woodin presents a collection of partial orders whose extensions satisfy strong

More information

FORCING AXIOMS AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS, PART II: TRANSCENDING ω 1 -SEQUENCES OF REAL NUMBERS

FORCING AXIOMS AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS, PART II: TRANSCENDING ω 1 -SEQUENCES OF REAL NUMBERS FORCING AXIOMS AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS, PART II: TRANSCENDING ω 1 -SEQUENCES OF REAL NUMBERS JUSTIN TATCH MOORE Abstract. The purpose of this article is to prove that the forcing axiom for completely

More information

NAMBA FORCING, WEAK APPROXIMATION, AND GUESSING

NAMBA FORCING, WEAK APPROXIMATION, AND GUESSING NAMBA FORCING, WEAK APPROXIMATION, AND GUESSING SEAN COX AND JOHN KRUEGER Abstract. We prove a variation of Easton s lemma for strongly proper forcings, and use it to prove that, unlike the stronger principle

More information

On versions of on cardinals larger than ℵ 1

On versions of on cardinals larger than ℵ 1 arxiv:math/9911228v1 [math.lo] 28 Nov 1999 On versions of on cardinals larger than ℵ 1 1 Mirna Džamonja School of Mathematics University of East Anglia Norwich, NR47TJ, UK M.Dzamonja@uea.ac.uk Saharon

More information

A variant of Namba Forcing

A variant of Namba Forcing A variant of Namba Forcing Moti Gitik School of Mathematical Sciences Raymond and Beverly Sackler Faculty of Exact Science Tel Aviv University Ramat Aviv 69978, Israel August 0, 009 Abstract Ronald Jensen

More information

THE TREE PROPERTY AT ℵ ω+1 DIMA SINAPOVA

THE TREE PROPERTY AT ℵ ω+1 DIMA SINAPOVA THE TREE PROPERTY AT ℵ ω+1 DIMA SINAPOVA Abstract. We show that given ω many supercompact cardinals, there is a generic extension in which there are no Aronszajn trees at ℵ ω+1. This is an improvement

More information

many). But no other examples were known even Sacks forcing. Also for e.g. V = V = L, we did not know a forcing making it not proper.

many). But no other examples were known even Sacks forcing. Also for e.g. V = V = L, we did not know a forcing making it not proper. SARAJEVO JOURNAL OF MATHEMATICS Vol.13 (26), No.2, (2017), 141 154 DOI: 10.5644/SJM.13.2.02 PRESERVING OLD ([ω] ℵ0, ) IS PROPER SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. We give some sufficient and necessary conditions

More information

Semi-stationary reflection and weak square

Semi-stationary reflection and weak square Semi-stationary reflection and weak square Hiroshi Sakai Results in this note will be included in a forthcoming joint paper with Fuchino, Torres and Usuba. 1 Introduction In this note we investigate how

More information

THE FAILURE OF DIAMOND ON A REFLECTING STATIONARY SET

THE FAILURE OF DIAMOND ON A REFLECTING STATIONARY SET THE FAILURE OF DIAMOND ON A REFLECTING STATIONARY SET MOTI GITIK AND ASSAF RINOT Abstract. 1. It is shown that the failure of S, for a set S ℵ ω+1 that reflects stationarily often, is consistent with GCH

More information

A NOTE ON THE EIGHTFOLD WAY

A NOTE ON THE EIGHTFOLD WAY A NOTE ON THE EIGHTFOLD WAY THOMAS GILTON AND JOHN KRUEGER Abstract. Assuming the existence of a Mahlo cardinal, we construct a model in which there exists an ω 2 -Aronszajn tree, the ω 1 -approachability

More information

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES ITAY NEEMAN Abstract. We present an approach to forcing with finite sequences of models that uses models of two types. This approach builds on earlier work

More information

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Keith A. Kearnes and Greg Oman Abstract. We show that if P is an infinite poset whose proper order ideals have cardinality strictly less than P, and κ is a cardinal

More information

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.lo] 15 Oct 1995

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.lo] 15 Oct 1995 arxiv:math/9510216v1 [math.lo] 15 Oct 1995 On squares, outside guessing of clubs and I

More information

Increasing δ 1 2 and Namba-style forcing

Increasing δ 1 2 and Namba-style forcing Increasing δ 1 2 and Namba-style forcing Richard Ketchersid Miami University Jindřich Zapletal University of Florida April 17, 2007 Paul Larson Miami University Abstract We isolate a forcing which increases

More information

TOPOLOGY PROCEEDINGS Volume 28, No. 1, 2004 Pages

TOPOLOGY PROCEEDINGS Volume 28, No. 1, 2004 Pages TOPOLOGY PROCEEDINGS Volume 28, No. 1, 2004 Pages 113-132 A FAMILY OF TREES WITH NO UNCOUNTABLE BRANCHES MIRNA DŽAMONJA AND JOUKO VÄÄNÄNEN Abstract. We construct a family of 2 ℵ 1 trees of size ℵ 1 and

More information

GREGORY TREES, THE CONTINUUM, AND MARTIN S AXIOM

GREGORY TREES, THE CONTINUUM, AND MARTIN S AXIOM The Journal of Symbolic Logic Volume 00, Number 0, XXX 0000 GREGORY TREES, THE CONTINUUM, AND MARTIN S AXIOM KENNETH KUNEN AND DILIP RAGHAVAN Abstract. We continue the investigation of Gregory trees and

More information

More forcing notions imply diamond

More forcing notions imply diamond More forcing notions imply diamond Andrzej Ros lanowski Dept. of Mathematics and Computer Science Bar-Ilan University 52900 Ramat-Gan, Israel and Mathematical Institute of Wroclaw University 50384 Wroclaw,

More information

COUNTABLE COMPACTNESS, HEREDITARY π CHARACTER, AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS

COUNTABLE COMPACTNESS, HEREDITARY π CHARACTER, AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS COUNTABLE COMPACTNESS, HEREDITARY π CHARACTER, AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS TODD EISWORTH Abstract. We prove that the Continuum Hypothesis is consistent with the statement that countably compact regular

More information

PROPER FORCING REMASTERED

PROPER FORCING REMASTERED PROPER FORCING REMASTERED BOBAN VELIČKOVIĆ AND GIORGIO VENTURI Abstract. We present the method introduced by Neeman of generalized side conditions with two types of models. We then discuss some applications:

More information

SHELAH S SINGULAR COMPACTNESS THEOREM

SHELAH S SINGULAR COMPACTNESS THEOREM SHELAH S SINGULAR COMPACTNESS THEOREM PAUL C. EKLOF Abstract. We present Shelah s famous theorem in a version for modules, together with a self-contained proof and some examples. This exposition is based

More information

ON CUTS IN ULTRAPRODUCTS OF LINEAR ORDERS I. 1. introduction

ON CUTS IN ULTRAPRODUCTS OF LINEAR ORDERS I. 1. introduction ON CUTS IN ULTRAPRODUCTS OF LINEAR ORDERS I MOHAMMAD GOLSHANI AND SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. For an ultrafilter D on a cardinal κ, we wonder for which pair (θ 1, θ 2 ) of regular cardinals, we have: for

More information

THE STRONG TREE PROPERTY AND THE FAILURE OF SCH

THE STRONG TREE PROPERTY AND THE FAILURE OF SCH THE STRONG TREE PROPERTY AND THE FAILURE OF SCH JIN DU Abstract. Fontanella [2] showed that if κ n : n < ω is an increasing sequence of supercompacts and ν = sup n κ n, then the strong tree property holds

More information

Successive cardinals with the tree property

Successive cardinals with the tree property UCLA March 3, 2014 A classical theorem Theorem (König Infinity Lemma) Every infinite finitely branching tree has an infinite path. Definitions A tree is set T together with an ordering < T which is wellfounded,

More information

A DIRECT PROOF OF THE FIVE ELEMENT BASIS THEOREM

A DIRECT PROOF OF THE FIVE ELEMENT BASIS THEOREM A DIRECT PROOF OF THE FIVE ELEMENT BASIS THEOREM BOBAN VELIČKOVIĆ AND GIORGIO VENTURI Abstract. We present a direct proof of the consistency of the existence of a five element basis for the uncountable

More information

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007)

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω 0. Introduction David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) In its simplest form the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem for L ω1 ω states that if σ L ω1

More information

FRAGILITY AND INDESTRUCTIBILITY II

FRAGILITY AND INDESTRUCTIBILITY II FRAGILITY AND INDESTRUCTIBILITY II SPENCER UNGER Abstract. In this paper we continue work from a previous paper on the fragility and indestructibility of the tree property. We present the following: (1)

More information

KNASTER AND FRIENDS I: CLOSED COLORINGS AND PRECALIBERS

KNASTER AND FRIENDS I: CLOSED COLORINGS AND PRECALIBERS KNASTER AND FRIENDS I: CLOSED COLORINGS AND PRECALIBERS CHRIS LAMBIE-HANSON AND ASSAF RINOT Abstract. The productivity of the κ-chain condition, where κ is a regular, uncountable cardinal, has been the

More information

Forcing notions in inner models

Forcing notions in inner models Forcing notions in inner models David Asperó Abstract There is a partial order P preserving stationary subsets of! 1 and forcing that every partial order in the ground model V that collapses asu ciently

More information

COVERING MATRICES, SQUARES, SCALES, AND STATIONARY REFLECTION

COVERING MATRICES, SQUARES, SCALES, AND STATIONARY REFLECTION COVERING MATRICES, SQUARES, SCALES, AND STATIONARY REFLECTION A thesis presented for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Chris Lambie-Hanson Department of Mathematical Sciences Carnegie Mellon University

More information

Tutorial 1.3: Combinatorial Set Theory. Jean A. Larson (University of Florida) ESSLLI in Ljubljana, Slovenia, August 4, 2011

Tutorial 1.3: Combinatorial Set Theory. Jean A. Larson (University of Florida) ESSLLI in Ljubljana, Slovenia, August 4, 2011 Tutorial 1.3: Combinatorial Set Theory Jean A. Larson (University of Florida) ESSLLI in Ljubljana, Slovenia, August 4, 2011 I. Generalizing Ramsey s Theorem Our proof of Ramsey s Theorem for pairs was

More information

1. Introduction Definition 1.1. For an L ω1,ω-sentence φ, the spectrum of φ is the set

1. Introduction Definition 1.1. For an L ω1,ω-sentence φ, the spectrum of φ is the set KUREPA TREES AND SPECTRA OF L ω1,ω-sentences DIMA SINAPOVA AND IOANNIS SOULDATOS Abstract. We construct a single L ω1,ω-sentence ψ that codes Kurepa trees to prove the consistency of the following: (1)

More information

Diamond, non-saturation, and weak square principles

Diamond, non-saturation, and weak square principles Diamond, non-saturation, and weak square principles Logic Colloquium 2009 (European ASL summer meeting) 02-Aug-09, Sofia Assaf Rinot Tel-Aviv University http://www.tau.ac.il/ rinot 1 Diamond on successor

More information

The constructible universe

The constructible universe The constructible universe In this set of notes I want to sketch Gödel s proof that CH is consistent with the other axioms of set theory. Gödel s argument goes well beyond this result; his identification

More information

Forcing Axioms and Inner Models of Set Theory

Forcing Axioms and Inner Models of Set Theory Forcing Axioms and Inner Models of Set Theory Boban Veličković Equipe de Logique Université de Paris 7 http://www.logique.jussieu.fr/ boban 15th Boise Extravaganza in Set Theory Boise State University,

More information

ORGANIC AND TIGHT J. CUMMINGS, M. FOREMAN, AND E. SCHIMMERLING

ORGANIC AND TIGHT J. CUMMINGS, M. FOREMAN, AND E. SCHIMMERLING ORGANIC AND TIGHT J. CUMMINGS, M. FOREMAN, AND E. SCHIMMERLING 1. Introduction This paper is motivated by the combinatorics of ℵ ω in L where there are canonical examples of scales, square sequences other

More information

ORGANIC AND TIGHT J. CUMMINGS, M. FOREMAN, AND E. SCHIMMERLING

ORGANIC AND TIGHT J. CUMMINGS, M. FOREMAN, AND E. SCHIMMERLING ORGANIC AND TIGHT J. CUMMINGS, M. FOREMAN, AND E. SCHIMMERLING 1. Introduction This report is motivated by the combinatorics of ℵ ω in L where there are canonical examples of scales, square sequences other

More information

Tallness and Level by Level Equivalence and Inequivalence

Tallness and Level by Level Equivalence and Inequivalence Tallness and Level by Level Equivalence and Inequivalence Arthur W. Apter Department of Mathematics Baruch College of CUNY New York, New York 10010 USA and The CUNY Graduate Center, Mathematics 365 Fifth

More information

The Ultrapower Axiom implies GCH above a supercompact cardinal

The Ultrapower Axiom implies GCH above a supercompact cardinal The Ultrapower Axiom implies GCH above a supercompact cardinal arxiv:1810.05036v1 [math.lo] 9 Oct 2018 Gabriel Goldberg October 12, 2018 Abstract We prove that the Generalized Continuum Hypothesis holds

More information

Cardinal invariants above the continuum

Cardinal invariants above the continuum arxiv:math/9509228v1 [math.lo] 15 Sep 1995 Cardinal invariants above the continuum James Cummings Hebrew University of Jerusalem cummings@math.huji.ac.il Saharon Shelah Hebrew University of Jerusalem shelah@math.huji.ac.il

More information

The extent of the failure of Ramsey s theorem at successor cardinals

The extent of the failure of Ramsey s theorem at successor cardinals The extent of the failure of Ramsey s theorem at successor cardinals 2012 North American Annual Meeting of the ASL University of Wisconsin Madison 31-March-2012 Assaf Rinot University of Toronto Mississauga

More information

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. On guessing generalized clubs at the successors of regulars

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. On guessing generalized clubs at the successors of regulars Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (2011) 566 577 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Annals of Pure and Applied Logic journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/apal On guessing generalized clubs

More information

Bounding by canonical functions, with CH

Bounding by canonical functions, with CH Bounding by canonical functions, with CH Paul Larson Saharon Shelah April 12, 2002 Abstract We show that the members of a certain class of semi-proper iterations do not add countable sets of ordinals.

More information

VAUGHT S THEOREM: THE FINITE SPECTRUM OF COMPLETE THEORIES IN ℵ 0. Contents

VAUGHT S THEOREM: THE FINITE SPECTRUM OF COMPLETE THEORIES IN ℵ 0. Contents VAUGHT S THEOREM: THE FINITE SPECTRUM OF COMPLETE THEORIES IN ℵ 0 BENJAMIN LEDEAUX Abstract. This expository paper introduces model theory with a focus on countable models of complete theories. Vaught

More information

A Hanf number for saturation and omission: the superstable case

A Hanf number for saturation and omission: the superstable case A Hanf number for saturation and omission: the superstable case John T. Baldwin University of Illinois at Chicago Saharon Shelah The Hebrew University of Jerusalem Rutgers University April 29, 2013 Abstract

More information

arxiv: v2 [math.lo] 16 Oct 2015

arxiv: v2 [math.lo] 16 Oct 2015 CATEGORICITY AND INFINITARY LOGICS arxiv:1508.03316v2 [math.lo] 16 Oct 2015 WILL BONEY AND SEBASTIEN VASEY Abstract. We point out a gap in Shelah s proof of the following result: Claim 0.1. Let K be an

More information

Appalachian Set Theory Workshop, May 31, 2008 Lectures by Justin Tatch Moore Notes taken by David Milovich

Appalachian Set Theory Workshop, May 31, 2008 Lectures by Justin Tatch Moore Notes taken by David Milovich SET MAPPING REFLECTION Appalachian Set Theory Workshop, May 31, 2008 Lectures by Justin Tatch Moore Notes taken by David Milovich 1. Introduction The goal of these lectures is to give an exposition of

More information

Reasonable ultrafilters

Reasonable ultrafilters Reasonable ultrafilters Andrzej Rosłanowski Department of Mathematics University of Nebraska at Omaha Report on works done in cooperation with Saharon Shelah BEST: Boise, ID, March 2008 Reasonability Reasonable

More information

The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count?

The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count? The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count? John T. Baldwin Department of Mathematics, Statistics and Computer Science University of Illinois at Chicago May 22, 2005 1 Is the Vaught Conjecture model

More information

Short notes on Axioms of set theory, Well orderings and Ordinal Numbers

Short notes on Axioms of set theory, Well orderings and Ordinal Numbers Short notes on Axioms of set theory, Well orderings and Ordinal Numbers August 29, 2013 1 Logic and Notation Any formula in Mathematics can be stated using the symbols and the variables,,,, =, (, ) v j

More information

TOWARD A STABILITY THEORY OF TAME ABSTRACT ELEMENTARY CLASSES

TOWARD A STABILITY THEORY OF TAME ABSTRACT ELEMENTARY CLASSES TOWARD A STABILITY THEORY OF TAME ABSTRACT ELEMENTARY CLASSES SEBASTIEN VASEY Abstract. We initiate a systematic investigation of the abstract elementary classes that have amalgamation, satisfy tameness

More information

NOTES ON WELL ORDERING AND ORDINAL NUMBERS. 1. Logic and Notation Any formula in Mathematics can be stated using the symbols

NOTES ON WELL ORDERING AND ORDINAL NUMBERS. 1. Logic and Notation Any formula in Mathematics can be stated using the symbols NOTES ON WELL ORDERING AND ORDINAL NUMBERS TH. SCHLUMPRECHT 1. Logic and Notation Any formula in Mathematics can be stated using the symbols,,,, =, (, ) and the variables v j : where j is a natural number.

More information

SOME COMBINATORIAL PRINCIPLES DEFINED IN TERMS OF ELEMENTARY SUBMODELS. 1. Introduction

SOME COMBINATORIAL PRINCIPLES DEFINED IN TERMS OF ELEMENTARY SUBMODELS. 1. Introduction SOME COMBINATORIAL PRINCIPLES DEFINED IN TERMS OF ELEMENTARY SUBMODELS SAKAÉ FUCHINO AND STEFAN GESCHKE Abstract. We give an equivalent, but simpler formulation of the axiom SEP, which was introduced in

More information

M ath. Res. Lett. 15 (2008), no. 00, NN c International Press 2008 A UNIVERSAL ARONSZAJN LINE. Justin Tatch Moore. 1.

M ath. Res. Lett. 15 (2008), no. 00, NN c International Press 2008 A UNIVERSAL ARONSZAJN LINE. Justin Tatch Moore. 1. M ath. Res. Lett. 15 (2008), no. 00, 10001 100NN c International Press 2008 A UNIVERSAL ARONSZAJN LINE Justin Tatch Moore Abstract. The purpose of this note is to define an Aronszajn line η C and prove

More information

PSEUDO P-POINTS AND SPLITTING NUMBER

PSEUDO P-POINTS AND SPLITTING NUMBER PSEUDO P-POINTS AND SPLITTING NUMBER ALAN DOW AND SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. We construct a model in which the splitting number is large and every ultrafilter has a small subset with no pseudo-intersection.

More information

AMS regional meeting Bloomington, IN April 1, 2017

AMS regional meeting Bloomington, IN April 1, 2017 Joint work with: W. Boney, S. Friedman, C. Laskowski, M. Koerwien, S. Shelah, I. Souldatos University of Illinois at Chicago AMS regional meeting Bloomington, IN April 1, 2017 Cantor s Middle Attic Uncountable

More information

CLUB GUESSING SEQUENCES NATURAL STRUCTURES IN SET THEORY

CLUB GUESSING SEQUENCES NATURAL STRUCTURES IN SET THEORY Unspecified Journal Volume 00, Number 0, Pages 000 000 S????-????(XX)0000-0 CLUB GUESSING SEQUENCES NATURAL STRUCTURES IN SET THEORY TETSUYA ISHIU Abstract. Natural structures in set theory played key

More information

HYBRID PRIKRY FORCING

HYBRID PRIKRY FORCING HYBRID PRIKRY FORCING DIMA SINAPOVA Abstract. We present a new forcing notion combining diagonal supercompact Prikry focing with interleaved extender based forcing. We start with a supercompact cardinal

More information

Distributivity of Quotients of Countable Products of Boolean Algebras

Distributivity of Quotients of Countable Products of Boolean Algebras Rend. Istit. Mat. Univ. Trieste Volume 41 (2009), 27 33. Distributivity of Quotients of Countable Products of Boolean Algebras Fernando Hernández-Hernández Abstract. We compute the distributivity numbers

More information

ITERATING ALONG A PRIKRY SEQUENCE

ITERATING ALONG A PRIKRY SEQUENCE ITERATING ALONG A PRIKRY SEQUENCE SPENCER UNGER Abstract. In this paper we introduce a new method which combines Prikry forcing with an iteration between the Prikry points. Using our method we prove from

More information

MAD FAMILIES AND THEIR NEIGHBORS

MAD FAMILIES AND THEIR NEIGHBORS MAD FAMILIES AND THEIR NEIGHBORS ANDREAS BLASS, TAPANI HYTTINEN, AND YI ZHANG Abstract. We study several sorts of maximal almost disjoint families, both on a countable set and on uncountable, regular cardinals.

More information

THE PRECIPITOUSNESS OF TAIL CLUB GUESSING IDEALS

THE PRECIPITOUSNESS OF TAIL CLUB GUESSING IDEALS THE PRECIPITOUSNESS OF TAIL CLUB GUESSING IDEALS TETSUYA ISHIU Abstract. From a measurable cardinal, we build a model in which the nonstationary ideal on ω 1 is not precipitous, but there is a precipitous

More information

Singular Failures of GCH and Level by Level Equivalence

Singular Failures of GCH and Level by Level Equivalence Singular Failures of GCH and Level by Level Equivalence Arthur W. Apter Department of Mathematics Baruch College of CUNY New York, New York 10010 USA and The CUNY Graduate Center, Mathematics 365 Fifth

More information

TRANSFERING SATURATION, THE FINITE COVER PROPERTY, AND STABILITY

TRANSFERING SATURATION, THE FINITE COVER PROPERTY, AND STABILITY TRANSFERING SATURATION, THE FINITE COVER PROPERTY, AND STABILITY John T. Baldwin Department of Mathematics University of Illinois at Chicago Chicago, IL 60680 Rami Grossberg Department of Mathematics Carnegie

More information

MARTIN S MAXIMUM AND DEFINABILITY IN H(ℵ 2 ) Keywords: Forcing Axioms; Definability; Large Cardinals. 1. Introduction

MARTIN S MAXIMUM AND DEFINABILITY IN H(ℵ 2 ) Keywords: Forcing Axioms; Definability; Large Cardinals. 1. Introduction MARTIN S MAXIMUM AND DEFINABILITY IN H(ℵ 2 ) PAUL B. LARSON Abstract. In [6], we modified a coding device from [14] and the consistency proof of Martin s Maximum from [3] to show that from a supercompact

More information

INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS

INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS TOM CUCHTA 1. Introduction This paper was written as a final project for the 2013 Summer Session of Mathematical Logic 1 at Missouri S&T. We intend to present a short discussion

More information

HOW DO ULTRAFILTERS ACT ON THEORIES? THE CUT SPECTRUM AND TREETOPS

HOW DO ULTRAFILTERS ACT ON THEORIES? THE CUT SPECTRUM AND TREETOPS HOW DO ULTRAFILTERS ACT ON THEORIES? THE CUT SPECTRUM AND TREETOPS DIEGO ANDRES BEJARANO RAYO Abstract. We expand on and further explain the work by Malliaris and Shelah on the cofinality spectrum by doing

More information

FORCING AXIOMS AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS

FORCING AXIOMS AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS FORCING AXIOMS AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS DAVID ASPERÓ, PAUL LARSON, AND JUSTIN TATCH MOORE 1. Introduction One way to formulate the Baire Category Theorem is that no compact space can be covered by

More information

Six lectures on the stationary tower

Six lectures on the stationary tower Six lectures on the stationary tower Paul B. Larson November 19, 2012 1 The stationary tower 1.1 Definition. Let X be a nonempty set. A set c P(X) is club in P(X) if there is a function f : X

More information

DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET

DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET 1. THE AXIOM OF FOUNDATION Early on in the book (page 6) it is indicated that throughout the formal development set is going to mean pure set, or set whose elements,

More information

DENSELY k-separable COMPACTA ARE DENSELY SEPARABLE

DENSELY k-separable COMPACTA ARE DENSELY SEPARABLE DENSELY k-separable COMPACTA ARE DENSELY SEPARABLE ALAN DOW AND ISTVÁN JUHÁSZ Abstract. A space has σ-compact tightness if the closures of σ-compact subsets determines the topology. We consider a dense

More information

SQUARE WITH BUILT-IN DIAMOND-PLUS

SQUARE WITH BUILT-IN DIAMOND-PLUS SQUARE WITH BUILT-IN DIAMOND-PLUS ASSAF RINOT AND RALF SCHINDLER Abstract. We formulate combinatorial principles that combine the square principle with various strong forms of the diamond principle, and

More information

UNIVERSALLY BAIRE SETS AND GENERIC ABSOLUTENESS TREVOR M. WILSON

UNIVERSALLY BAIRE SETS AND GENERIC ABSOLUTENESS TREVOR M. WILSON UNIVERSALLY BAIRE SETS AND GENERIC ABSOLUTENESS TREVOR M. WILSON Abstract. We prove several equivalences and relative consistency results involving notions of generic absoluteness beyond Woodin s ) (Σ

More information

Lecture 11: Minimal types

Lecture 11: Minimal types MODEL THEORY OF ARITHMETIC Lecture 11: Minimal types Tin Lok Wong 17 December, 2014 Uniform extension operators are used to construct models with nice structural properties Thus, one has a very simple

More information

CHAINS OF SATURATED MODELS IN AECS

CHAINS OF SATURATED MODELS IN AECS CHAINS OF SATURATED ODELS IN AECS WILL BONEY AND SEBASTIEN VASEY Abstract. We study when a union of saturated models is saturated in the framework of tame abstract elementary classes (AECs) with amalgamation.

More information

BPFA and BAAFA. Their equiconsistency and their nonequivalence. Thilo Weinert. February 4, 2009

BPFA and BAAFA. Their equiconsistency and their nonequivalence. Thilo Weinert. February 4, 2009 Their equiconsistency and their nonequivalence February 4, 2009 1 Basics Axiom A The strengthened proper game Σ n-correct cardinals 2 Bounded Forcing Axioms Their definition A remedy for Axiom A Some facts

More information

THE TREE PROPERTY AND THE FAILURE OF THE SINGULAR CARDINAL HYPOTHESIS AT ℵ ω 2

THE TREE PROPERTY AND THE FAILURE OF THE SINGULAR CARDINAL HYPOTHESIS AT ℵ ω 2 THE TREE PROPERTY AND THE FAILURE OF THE SINGULAR CARDINAL HYPOTHESIS AT ℵ ω 2 DIMA SINAPOVA Abstract. We show that given ω many supercompact cardinals, there is a generic extension in which the tree property

More information

ω-stable Theories: Introduction

ω-stable Theories: Introduction ω-stable Theories: Introduction 1 ω - Stable/Totally Transcendental Theories Throughout let T be a complete theory in a countable language L having infinite models. For an L-structure M and A M let Sn

More information

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting 5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting Let N denote the positive integers, N 0 := N {0} be the non-negative integers and Z = N 0 ( N) the positive and negative integers including 0, Q the rational numbers,

More information

March 3, The large and small in model theory: What are the amalgamation spectra of. infinitary classes? John T. Baldwin

March 3, The large and small in model theory: What are the amalgamation spectra of. infinitary classes? John T. Baldwin large and large and March 3, 2015 Characterizing cardinals by L ω1,ω large and L ω1,ω satisfies downward Lowenheim Skolem to ℵ 0 for sentences. It does not satisfy upward Lowenheim Skolem. Definition sentence

More information

The choice of ω 1 and combinatorics at ℵ ω

The choice of ω 1 and combinatorics at ℵ ω The choice of ω 1 and combinatorics at ℵ ω Spencer Unger UCLA October 19, 2013 Outline Combinatorial properties Theorems using supercompactness Bringing results down to ℵ ω Some new theorems A sketch of

More information

LINDSTRÖM S THEOREM SALMAN SIDDIQI

LINDSTRÖM S THEOREM SALMAN SIDDIQI LINDSTRÖM S THEOREM SALMAN SIDDIQI Abstract. This paper attempts to serve as an introduction to abstract model theory. We introduce the notion of abstract logics, explore first-order logic as an instance

More information

Cardinal characteristics, projective wellorders and large continuum

Cardinal characteristics, projective wellorders and large continuum Cardinal characteristics, projective wellorders and large continuum Vera Fischer a,1,, Sy David Friedman a,1, Lyubomyr Zdomskyy a,1 a Kurt Gödel Research Center, University of Vienna, Währinger Strasse

More information

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (2010) 916 922 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Annals of Pure and Applied Logic journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/apal Cardinal characteristics and

More information

Handbook of Set Theory. Foreman, Kanamori, and Magidor (eds.)

Handbook of Set Theory. Foreman, Kanamori, and Magidor (eds.) Handbook of Set Theory Foreman, Kanamori, and Magidor (eds.) August 5, 2006 2 Contents I Forcing over models of determinacy 5 by Paul B. Larson 1 Iterations............................... 7 2 P max.................................

More information

Forcing Closed Unbounded Subsets of ω 2

Forcing Closed Unbounded Subsets of ω 2 Forcing Closed Unbounded Subsets of ω 2 M.C. Stanley July 2000 Abstract. It is shown that there is no satisfactory first-order characterization of those subsets of ω 2 that have closed unbounded subsets

More information

IDEAL GAMES AND RAMSEY SETS

IDEAL GAMES AND RAMSEY SETS IDEAL GAMES AND RAMSEY SETS CARLOS DI PRISCO, JOSÉ G. MIJARES, AND CARLOS UZCÁTEGUI Abstract. It is shown that Matet s characterization ([9]) of the Ramsey property relative to a selective co-ideal H,

More information

GO-SPACES AND NOETHERIAN SPECTRA

GO-SPACES AND NOETHERIAN SPECTRA GO-SPACES AND NOETHERIAN SPECTRA DAVID MILOVICH Abstract. The Noetherian type of a space is the least κ for which the space has a κ op -like base, i.e., a base in which no element has κ-many supersets.

More information

Scott processes. Paul B. Larson June 23, 2014

Scott processes. Paul B. Larson June 23, 2014 Scott processes Paul B. Larson June 23, 2014 Abstract The Scott process of a relational structure M is the sequence of sets of formulas given by the Scott analysis of M. We present axioms for the class

More information

Scales, topological reflections, and large cardinal issues by Peter Nyikos

Scales, topological reflections, and large cardinal issues by Peter Nyikos Scales, topological reflections, and large cardinal issues by Peter Nyikos Reflection theorems in set-theoretic topology typically take the following form: if all small subspaces of a suitable kind of

More information

CH AND THE MOORE-MROWKA PROBLEM

CH AND THE MOORE-MROWKA PROBLEM CH AND THE MOORE-MROWKA PROBLEM ALAN DOW AND TODD EISWORTH Abstract. We show that the Continuum Hypothesis is consistent with all regular spaces of hereditarily countable π-character being C-closed. This

More information

HIERARCHIES OF FORCING AXIOMS II

HIERARCHIES OF FORCING AXIOMS II HIERARCHIES OF FORCING AXIOMS II ITAY NEEMAN Abstract. A Σ 2 1 truth for λ is a pair Q, ψ so that Q H λ, ψ is a first order formula with one free variable, and there exists B H λ + such that (H λ +;, B)

More information

Almost Galois ω-stable classes

Almost Galois ω-stable classes Almost Galois ω-stable classes John T. Baldwin Paul B. Larson Saharon Shelah March 11, 2015 Abstract Theorem. Suppose that k = (K, k ) is an ℵ 0-presentable abstract elementary class with Löwenheim-Skolem

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 28 Mar 2015

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 28 Mar 2015 MODEL-THEORETIC APPLICATIONS OF COFINALITY SPECTRUM PROBLEMS arxiv:1503.08338v1 [math.lo] 28 Mar 2015 M. MALLIARIS AND S. SHELAH Abstract. We apply the recently developed technology of cofinality spectrum

More information

COLLAPSING FUNCTIONS

COLLAPSING FUNCTIONS COLLAPSING FUNCTIONS ERNEST SCHIMMERLING AND BOBAN VELICKOVIC Abstract. We define what it means for a function on ω 1 to be a collapsing function for λ and show that if there exists a collapsing function

More information

Iteratively changing the heights of automorphism towers

Iteratively changing the heights of automorphism towers Iteratively changing the heights of automorphism towers Gunter Fuchs The College of Staten Island/CUNY 28 Victory Blvd. Staten Island, NY 1314 Philipp Lücke Westfälische Wilhelms-Universität Münster Einsteinstraße

More information

Aronszajn Trees and the SCH

Aronszajn Trees and the SCH Aronszajn Trees and the SCH Itay Neeman and Spencer Unger February 28, 2009 1 Introduction These notes are based on results presented by Itay Neeman at the Appalachian Set Theory workshop on February 28,

More information

Diamond on successors of singulars

Diamond on successors of singulars Diamond on successors of singulars ESI workshop on large cardinals and descriptive set theory 18-Jun-09, Vienna Assaf Rinot Tel-Aviv University http://www.tau.ac.il/ rinot 1 Diamond on successor cardinals

More information

SOME CALKIN ALGEBRAS HAVE OUTER AUTOMORPHISMS

SOME CALKIN ALGEBRAS HAVE OUTER AUTOMORPHISMS SOME CALKIN ALGEBRAS HAVE OUTER AUTOMORPHISMS ILIJAS FARAH, PAUL MCKENNEY, AND ERNEST SCHIMMERLING Abstract. We consider various quotients of the C*-algebra of bounded operators on a nonseparable Hilbert

More information

The Proper Forcing Axiom: a tutorial

The Proper Forcing Axiom: a tutorial Young Set Theory Workshop 2010, Raach, Austria. The Proper Forcing Axiom: a tutorial Justin Tatch Moore 1 Notes taken by Giorgio Venturi In these notes we will present an exposition of the Proper Forcing

More information