Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. On guessing generalized clubs at the successors of regulars

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. On guessing generalized clubs at the successors of regulars"

Transcription

1 Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (2011) Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Annals of Pure and Applied Logic journal homepage: On guessing generalized clubs at the successors of regulars Assaf Rinot School of Mathematical Sciences, Tel Aviv University, Tel Aviv 69978, Israel a r t i c l e i n f o a b s t r a c t Article history: Available online 5 February 2011 MSC: primary 03E35 secondary 03E05 03E65 Keywords: Club guessing Generalized clubs Souslin tree Diamond Non-saturation Uniformization König, Larson and Yoshinobu initiated the study of principles for guessing generalized clubs, and introduced a construction of a higher Souslin tree from the strong guessing principle. Complementary to the author s work on the validity of diamond and non-saturation at the successor of singulars, we deal here with a successor of regulars. It is established that even the non-strong guessing principle entails non-saturation, and that, assuming the necessary cardinal arithmetic configuration, entails a diamond-type principle which suffices for the construction of a higher Souslin tree. We also establish the consistency of GCH with the failure of the weakest form of generalized club guessing. This, in particular, settles a question from the original paper Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved. 1. Background Given a regular cardinal, and a stationary subset S, Jensen s diamond principle S asserts the existence of a sequence A δ δ S such that {δ S A δ = A δ } is stationary for every A. Jensen discovered this principle in the course of establishing the existence of a Souslin tree in Gödel s constructible universe. He proved: Theorem 1.1 (Jensen, [7]). If = < is a regular cardinal for which E + tree. 1 holds, then there exists a -complete + -Souslin A famous, long-standing, open problem is whether GCH entails the existence of an ℵ 2 -Souslin tree. As GCH is consistent together with the failure of ℵ E 2 (see [8]), throughout the years, weakenings of the diamond principle has been suggested ℵ 1 and studied. Here is one. Given regular cardinals κ <, and a stationary set S Eκ, Shelah s club guessing principle asserts the existence of a sequence C δ δ S satisfying: 1. for every δ S, C δ is a club subset of δ; 2. {δ S C δ D} is stationary for every club D. Clearly, S entails the existence of a guessing sequence as above, but Shelah [13] proved that if κ + <, then the existence of such a sequence is provable just in ZFC. As for the remaining case of = κ +, he obtained the following approximation. address: assaf@rinot.com. URL: 1 Here, E κ := {δ < cf(δ) = κ}; For the definition of a Souslin tree, etc, see the end of this section /$ see front matter 2011 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved. doi: /j.apal

2 A. Rinot / Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (2011) Theorem 1.2 (Shelah, [13]). Suppose that is a regular uncountable cardinal, and S E + is stationary. Then there exists a sequence C δ δ S satisfying: 1. for every δ S, C δ is a club in δ of order-type ; 2. {δ S sup(c δ D E + ) = δ} is stationary for every club D. Shelah s club guessing principles were found to be fruitful in establishing many non-trivial ZFC results (see, for instance, [2]). Naturally, several variations of these principles have been studied, as well. To mention two of them: Definition 1.3 (Folklore). Suppose that κ < are regular cardinals, S Eκ is a stationary set, and C sequence such that C δ is a club in δ for all δ S. = C δ δ S is a C is a strong club guessing sequence iff for every club D, there exists a club C such that: S C {δ S β < δ(c δ \ β D)}. C is a tail club guessing sequence iff for every club D, the following set is stationary: {δ S β < δ(c δ \ β D)}. Having the Souslin problem in mind, König et al. considered in [10] a generalization of club guessing, for the notion of generalized club. Recall that, given cardinals κ, a set C is a (generalized) club in [] <κ := {x x < κ}, iff there exists a function f : [] <ω such that C = {x [] <κ f [x] <ω x}. Definition 1.4 (Strong Generalized Club Guessing, [10]). Suppose that κ are given cardinals, and that S is a stationary subset of = cf() > ω. (κ, S) asserts the existence of a sequence C δ δ S such that 1. for every δ S, C δ is a club in [δ] <κ ; 2. for every club D in [] <κ, there exists a club C such that: S C {δ S x C δ (x y C δ y D)}. In [10], Theorem 1.2 above has been utilized to prove: Theorem 1.5 (König-Larson-Yoshinobu, [10]). Suppose that = < is a regular uncountable cardinal, and 2 = +. If (, E + ) holds, then there exists a -closed + -Souslin tree. In this paper, we shall mostly be studying the non-strong, and the tail version of the generalized guessing principle. Definition 1.6. Suppose that κ are given cardinals, and that S is a stationary subset of = cf() > ω. (κ, S) asserts the existence of a sequence C δ δ S such that: 1. for every δ S, C δ is a club in [δ] <κ ; 2. for every club D in [] <κ, the following set is stationary: {δ S C δ D}. (κ, S) asserts the existence of a matrix Cδ i δ S, i < δ such that: 1. for every δ S and i < δ, C i δ is cofinal in [δ]<κ ; 2. for every club D in [] <κ, the following set is stationary: {δ S i < δ (C i δ D)}. Remark. If S +, then (κ, S) entails (κ, S) whenever cf([] <κ, ) =, and in particular, (, S) entails (, S). We shall link between generalized club guessing and the usual club guessing, and shall show that a diamond-type principle, which we denote by T S (see Definition 2.2 below), can be derived from the generalized principles. Here is a special case of these theorems. Theorem 1. Suppose that S is a stationary subset of E + for a given successor cardinal, and that (κ, S) holds for some κ. Then: 1. There exists a sequence C δ δ S such that the following holds: (a) C δ is a club subset of E< δ for all δ S; (b) {δ S C δ D} is stationary for every club D If 2 = +, then T S holds for every stationary T.

3 568 A. Rinot / Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (2011) Remark. Compare with Theorem 1.2 above. Then we shall exemplify how even the weakest form of T S can be utilized to construct an higher Souslin tree: Theorem 2. If < = is an uncountable cardinal and E + Remark. Compare with Theorem 1.1 above. holds, then there exists a -complete + -Souslin tree. We also introduce sufficient conditions for the principles T S and S, as well as (κ, S) and + S, to coincide.2 As consequences, we get: Theorem 3. Suppose that = < is a successor cardinal, and 2 = +. If (κ, E + ) holds for some κ, then at least one of the following holds: There exists a -Kurepa tree; There exists a + -Kurepa tree, and moreover, + + holds. Theorem 4. Suppose that is a regular uncountable cardinal, T is a stationary subset of, and S is a stationary subset of E +. If T S holds, while S fails, then NS T is non-saturated. So, altogether, we see that generalized club guessing principles at + can witness non-saturation at. Let us remind our reader that NS S is said to be non-saturated whenever there exists a collection of more than many pairwise-nonstationary stationary subsets of S. Note that non-saturation is yet another weakening of diamond. To see this, suppose that S is stationary and S holds; let A α α S be a S -sequence. Then {{δ S A δ = A δ } A } is a 2 -sized collection witnessing that NS S is non-saturated. By Shelah [13], if is a regular cardinal and S is a stationary subset of E< +, then NS + S is non-saturated, hence, we should focus our attention on subsets of E +. Probably, the main result of this paper is the introduction of the following GCH-free sufficient condition for non-saturation at stationary subsets of E +. Theorem 5. Suppose that S is a stationary subset of E +, for a given regular uncountable cardinal. If (κ, S) holds for some cardinal κ <, then NS + S is non-saturated. Note that by the work of Woodin and others, it is indeed consistent, modulo large cardinals, that NS S is saturated for inaccessible, successor of singular, successor of regular, and some S (see [5]). So, in general, GCH does not entail (κ, S). In [10], the authors prove that GCH does not imply (κ, E + ) for any ℵ 0 < κ, and write that they do not know whether GCH is moreover consistent with the failure of (κ, S) for every stationary S E +. Here, this is established (without appealing to large cardinals). Theorem 6. Suppose that is successor cardinal in Gödel s constructible universe, L. Then, in some forcing extension of L, we have: GCH is preserved; the cardinal structure and cofinalities are preserved; (κ, E + ) fails for every κ, and hence (κ, S) fails for every κ and every stationary S E +. Let us explain the value of getting the failure of (κ, E + ) in a model that shares the cardinal structure with L. For brevity, we assume GCH throughout the whole paragraph. In [9, Theorem 2], Kojman and Shelah introduced a certain club-guessing principle let us denote it by KS and demonstrated that KS suffices for the construction of a -complete + -Souslin tree. In light of Theorem 1.5, let us point out that KS is strictly weaker than (, E + ). ( ) By the proof of Theorem 1, (κ, E + ) (κ, E + ) KS. In fact, for a successor, we can just invoke the statement of Theorem 1, yielding (κ, E + ) (κ, E + ) E + KS, (κ ). ( ) By [9, Theorem 3], the existence of a non-reflecting stationary subset of E< + entails the validity of KS. As is wellknown, if the universe shares the cardinal s structure with L, then for every uncountable cardinal, there exists a nonreflecting stationary subset of E< +. It now follows from Theorem 6 that (κ, E + ) KS for all κ, and in particular, (, E + ) KS. 2 For + S, see Definition 2.8 below.

4 A. Rinot / Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (2011) Terminology concerning trees We adopt the trees terminology of [1]. A tree T = T, is a partially ordered-set such that for every x T, the set x := {y T y x & y x} is well-ordered by. The order-type of the set x under is called the height of x in T, denoted by ht T (x). If α is an ordinal, the α th level of T is the set T α := {x T ht T (x) = α}. We let T α := {x T ht T (x) < α}, and denote by T α the restriction of the structure T to this set. A subset B of T is a branch if it is linearly ordered by and if x B x B for all x T. A set A T is an antichain if x y and y x for all distinct x, y A. The antichain A is maximal, if A {x} is not an antichain for any x T \ A. A tree T is said to be an (α, )-tree iff it is of height α and of width <, that is, T α =, while 0 < T β < for all β < α. A branch B T is cofinal iff B T β for all β < α. For a cardinal, a + -Kurepa tree is a ( +, + )-tree that has more than + many cofinal branches, and a -Souslin tree is a (, )-tree having no antichains of size. A tree T = T, is µ-complete if for every -increasing elements of the tree x i i < µ, there exists some y T for which i<µ (x i x). 2. Diamonds and trees 2.1. Club guessing We commence by giving a simple demonstration of the flavor of arguments for deriving consequences from generalized club guessing. Theorem 2.1. Suppose that S is a stationary subset of E + for a given regular uncountable cardinal,, If (κ, S) holds for some κ, then there exists a sequence C δ δ S such that the following holds: 1. C δ is a club subset of E< δ for all δ S; 2. {δ S C δ D} is stationary for every club D +. Proof. Let Cδ i i <, δ S witness (κ, S). Let be some well-ordering of [ + ] <κ. For all i < and δ S, define a function h i δ : δ δ by letting: h i δ min (β) := sup {x Ci δ β x}, (β < δ). It is not hard to verify that h i δ is well-defined, and that Cδ i := {α < δ hi δ [α] α & α is a limit ordinal} is a club subset of δ. Claim There exists some i < such that {δ S C i δ D} is stationary for every club D +. Proof. Suppose not. Then, for every i <, let us fix D i and E i, club subsets of + such that C i δ D i for all δ S E i. Put D := i< D i and E := i< E i. Define a function f : + + by letting: f (β) := min(d \ β + 1), (β < + ). Put D := {x [ + ] <κ f [x] x}. Then D is a club in [ + ] <κ, so let us pick some δ S E and i < such that Cδ i D. We now show that Cδ i D i, contradicting the fact that δ E i. Suppose α Cδ i. Then α is a limit ordinal, and so, to see that α D i, it suffices to prove that for every β < α, there exists some γ D with β < γ < α. Fix β < α, and let x := min{x Cδ i β x}. Then β x D, and hence f (β) x. Put γ := min(d \ β + 1). Then: β < γ = f (β) sup(x) = h i δ (β) hi δ [α] α. So, γ D and β < γ < α, as desired. Let i < be given by the previous claim. For all δ S, let C δ be some club subset of Cδ i Eδ <. Then C δ δ S is as requested Reflected diamond Definition 2.2 (Reflected Diamond). Suppose that is a regular uncountable cardinal, T is a stationary subset of, and S is a stationary subset of E +. T S asserts the existence of sequences C δ δ S and A δ i δ S, i < such that: 1. for all δ S, C δ is a club subset of δ of order-type ; 2. if for all δ S, {δ i i < } denotes the increasing enumeration of C δ, then for every club D + and every subset A +, there exist stationarily many δ S for which: {i T δ i+1 D & A δ i+1 = A δ i+1 } is stationary in.

5 570 A. Rinot / Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (2011) To motivate the above definition, we refer the reader to the proofs of Theorems 2.5 and 2.7 below. Theorem 2.3. Suppose that S is a stationary subset of E + for a given regular uncountable cardinal,. If (κ, S) holds for some cardinal κ <, and 2 = +, then T S holds for every stationary T. Proof. We may assume that S =. Let C δ δ S witness (κ, S), and let {X β β < + } be some enumeration of [κ + ]. Fix δ S. For all α < δ, pick x δ α C δ such that {0, α} x δ α. Define a function h δ : δ δ by letting: h δ (α) := sup(x δ α ), (α < δ). It is not hard to verify that h δ is well-defined, and that {α < δ h δ [α] α} is a club in δ. Thus, pick {δ i i < } in such a way that: {δ i i < } is the increasing enumeration of a set, C δ ; C δ is a club subset of δ, consisting of limit ordinals; h δ [α] α for all α C δ. For all i <, let {B δ[j] i j < κ} be some enumeration (possibly, with repetition) of {X β β x δ δ i }, and let A δ[j] := {γ < δ (j, γ ) i Bδ i [j]} for all j < κ. Claim For every stationary T, there exists some j < κ such that C δ δ S and A δ i [j] δ S, i < witnesses T S. Proof. Suppose not, and let T be a counterexample. It follows that for every j < κ, we may pick a club D j +, and a subset A j + such that for every δ D j S: {i T δ i+1 D j & A j δ i+1 = A δ i+1 [j]} is non-stationary. Put D := j<κ D j, and A := j<κ {j} A j. Define a function f : [ + ] <ω +, by letting for all σ [ + ] <ω : 0, σ = f (σ ) := min{β < + A (κ α) = X β }, σ = {α} min(d \ sup(σ ) + 1), σ > 1. Put D := {x [ + ] <κ f [x] <ω x}. As D is a club, let us pick some δ S D for which C δ D. Subclaim {δ i+1 i T} D. Proof. It suffices to show that sup(d α) = α for all α C δ. Fix α C δ and β < α, and let us find some γ (D α) above β. By α C δ, we have h δ [α] α, and that α is a limit ordinal. Clearly, we may assume that β > 0. By {0, β} x δ β, we have γ := f δ ({0, β}) = min(d \ β + 1) x δ β. But γ sup(xδ β ) = h δ(β) h δ [α] α. So γ D is above β and below α. Subclaim There exists a function g : κ such that for all i < : A (κ δ i ) = B δ i [g(i)]. Proof. Fix i <. Put β := min{β < + A (κ δ i ) = X β }. Then f ({δ i }) = β, and as δ i x δ δ i C δ D, we have β x δ δ i. So X β is a member of {B δ i [j] j < κ}. Let g be given by the previous claim. Define h : T κ by letting: h(i) := g(i + 1), (i T). Fix j < κ for which T := h 1 {j} is stationary. Then: T {i T δ i+1 D & A (κ δ i+1 ) = B δ i+1 [j]}. In particular, T {i T δ i+1 D j & A j δ i+1 = A δ i+1 [j]}. The indirect assumption lead to a contradiction, so we are done. The claim completes the proof. Note that a complication of the preceding arguments yields the following. Theorem 2.4. Suppose that S is a stationary subset of E + for a given uncountable cardinal,, and that at least one of the following holds: (κ, S) for some κ < ; (, S), and is a successor cardinal. If 2 = +, then T S holds for every stationary T.

6 A. Rinot / Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (2011) We omit the proof, but refer the reader to the proof of Theorem 3.2, for arguments of a similar flavor When the principles coincide Theorem 2.5. Suppose that is a regular uncountable cardinal, T is a stationary subset of, and S is a stationary subset of E +. Then (1) (2) (3) (4), where: 1. S ; 2. (κ, S) for all κ, and 2 = + ; 3. (κ, S) for some κ <, and 2 = + ; 4. T S. If NS T is saturated, then moreover (4) (1). Proof. (1) (2) This is similar to the proof in [10] that S (see Definition 2.8 below) entails (κ, S). By S, it is possible to find a sequence f δ : [δ] <ω δ δ S such that for every f : [ + ] <ω +, there exist stationarily many δ S for which f [δ] <ω = f δ. Let f δ δ S be as above. Given κ, let C δ := {x [δ] <κ f δ [x] <ω x}, and simply notice that C δ δ S witnesses (κ, S). The implication (2) (3) is trivial, and the implication (3) (4) is the content of Theorem 2.4 above. Finally, suppose that NS T is saturated and let us establish that (4) (1). Let C δ δ S and A δ i δ S, i < witness T S. Fix δ S. For every X δ, let T δ := X {i T X δ i+1 = A δ i+1 }. Then, put: A δ := {X δ T δ X is stationary}. Clearly, if X, Y are distinct elements of A δ, and j < is large enough such that X δ j Y δ j, then T δ X T δ Y j. So, elements of A δ may be identified with stationary subset of T, where distinct elements corresponds to sets whose pairwise intersection is nonstationary. As NS T is saturated, we conclude that A δ. Thus, by a famous argument of Kunen, to prove S, it now suffices to establish that for every A +, the following set is stationary: {δ S A δ A δ }. Fix A + and a club D +. We shall find δ D S for which A δ A δ. Pick δ S such that: {i T δ i+1 D & A δ i+1 = A δ i+1 } is stationary in. In particular, δ = sup(c δ D), and hence δ D S. Let X := A δ. As {i T δ i+1 D & X δ i+1 = A δ i+1 } is stationary, we get that T δ X is stationary, so A δ = X A δ. Theorem 2.6. Suppose that S is a stationary subset of E +, for a given successor cardinal. If there exist no -Kurepa trees, then the following are equivalent: 1. S holds; 2. (κ, S) holds for all κ, and 2 = + ; 3. (κ, S) for some κ, and 2 = +. Proof. (3) (1). Let Cδ i i <, δ S witness (, S). Let {X β β < + } be some enumeration of [ + ], and let be some well-ordering of [ + ] <κ. For every δ S, put: Fδ X i (α) := β β min {x Ci δ α x}, (i <, α < δ), Fδ i i := {X δ α < δ X α Fδ (α)}, A δ := {Fδ i i < }. (i < ), Thus, to establish S, it now suffices to prove the next two claims. Claim A δ for all δ S. Proof. Fix δ S and ι <. We argue that Fδ ι. Let {δ i i < } denote the increasing enumeration of some club subset of δ. For every X Fδ ι, define g X letting: g X (i) := min{β < + X δ i = X β }, (i < ). : + by Clearly, {g X j j <, X Fδ ι }, is a tree of height. Since there exists no -Kurepa tree, it now suffices to prove that {g X j X Fδ ι ι } Fδ (δ j) < for unboundedly many j <.

7 572 A. Rinot / Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (2011) Fix a limit j <. By definition of Fδ ι(δ j), there exists some y C δ and an injection from Fδ ι(δ j) to y. So Fδ ι(δ j) < κ. Finally, it is easy to see that the mapping h {X h(i) i < j} forms an injection from {g X j X Fδ ι} to F δ ι(δ j), so we are done. Claim For every A +, the following set is stationary: {δ S A δ A δ }. Proof. Fix a set A +. Let f : + + be the function satisfying: f (α) := min{β < + A α = X β }, (α < + ). Put D := {x [ + ] < f [x] x}. Since D is a club, let us fix some i < such that the following set is stationary: S := {δ S C i δ D}. It now suffices to prove that A δ A δ for all δ S. Fix δ S. We shall show that A δ Fδ i. For this, we need to show that A α Fδ i(α) for all α < δ. But this is easy; if α < δ, and x = min {x Cδ i α x}, then α x D and hence f (α) f [x] x. So, X α = X f (α) Fδ i(α). This completes the proof Trees The next theorem exemplifies the utility of the principle T S. Theorem 2.7. If < = is an uncountable cardinal and E + holds, then there exists a -complete + -Souslin tree. Remark. This can be considered as a special case of Theorem 2 from [9]. Proof. Let C δ δ E + and Aδ i δ E +, i < witness E + enumeration of C δ. Recall that a (δ, + )-tree T is said to be normal iff all of the following holds:. For all δ E +, let {δ i i < } denote the increasing T 0 = 1; for all α < δ and x T α, there are distinct y, z T α+1 with x y z, provided that α + 1 < δ; for all α < β < δ and x T α, there exists some y T β with x y; for all limit α < δ, the mapping x x is injective over T α. In other words, the elements of T α are unique limits. So, we build a -complete + -Souslin tree, T, by recursion on the levels, in such a way that T δ is a normal (δ, + )-tree. The elements of T will be the ordinals in +, and we shall ensure that α < T β α < β. Set T 0 := { }. If T δ + 1 is defined for an ordinal δ < +, T δ+1 is obtained by using new ordinals from + to provide each element of T δ with two successors in T δ+1. If T δ is defined for an ordinal δ E< +, T δ is obtained by using new ordinals from + to provide a unique extension in T δ to each cofinal branch in T δ. Since T δ cf(δ) < =, the resulting T δ + 1 is indeed a normal (δ + 1, + )-tree. Suppose that T δ is defined for an ordinal δ E +. Fix x T δ. We now define an increasing sequence xδ = x δ (i) i <, by induction on i <, in such a way that for all i <, either j i x δ(j) = x, or ht T δ (x δ (i)) = δ i. Base case: Let x δ (0) := x. Successor step: Suppose that x δ (j) j i is defined for an ordinal i <. If ht T δ (x) δ i, let x δ (i+1) := x. Now, suppose ht(x) T δ < δ i. Let: a x δ (i) := {y T δ i+1 x δ (i) < T δ y}, b x δ (i) := {y ax δ (i) z Aδ i+1 (z < y)}. Clearly, a x δ (i) is non-empty. If bx δ (i), let x δ(i + 1) := min(b x δ (i)), otherwise, let x δ(i + 1) := min(a x δ (i)). Limit case: Suppose that x δ (j) j < i is defined for a limit ordinal i <. If x δ (j) j < i is a constant sequence, let x δ (i) := x. Otherwise, sup{ht(x δ (j)) j < i} = δ i and δ i E< +, so let x δ(i) be the unique element of T δi that extends the branch {x δ (j) j < i}. Once the construction of the sequence x δ is over, let: B x δ := {x δ (j) j < }.

8 A. Rinot / Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (2011) Finally, T δ is obtained by using new ordinals from + to provide a unique extension in T δ to Bδ x for each x T δ. Since T δ, we get that T δ + 1 is indeed a normal (δ + 1, + )-tree. This completes the construction of the normal ( +, + )-tree, T. Thus, we are left with establishing the following. Claim T has no antichains of size +. Proof. Suppose not, and let A + denote a maximal antichain of size +. Put D := {δ < + T δ δ & A δ is a maximal antichain of T δ}. Since D is a club, let us pick some δ E + such that: H := {i < δ i+1 D & A δ i+1 = A δ i+1 } is stationary in. Since A = +, let us pick some a A with ht T (a) > δ. Let b be the unique element of T δ a. Since δ E +, the definition of T δ entails that there exists some x T δ such that b is the extension of Bδ x. Fix a large enough i H such that ht T (x) < δ i. As A δ i+1 = A δ i+1 is a maximal antichain of T δ i+1, we get that b x δ (i) is non-empty. Hence, by definition of x δ (i), we may pick some z A δ i+1 such that z < T x δ (i). So z < T x δ (i) < T b < T a, a contradiction to the fact that z and a are elements of the antichain, A. This completes the proof. Definition 2.8 (Jensen). Suppose S is a stationary subset of a given regular uncountable cardinal, and that A = A δ δ S is a sequence such that A δ for all δ S. A witnesses S if for every A, there exists a club C such that: C S {δ S A δ A δ }. A witnesses + S if for every A, there exists a club C such that: C S {δ S {C δ, A δ} A δ }. By Jensen and Solovay, for every successor cardinal,, + Consequently: Theorem 2.9. Suppose that = < is a successor cardinal, and 2 = +. If (κ, E + ) holds for some κ, then at least one of the following holds: There exists a -Kurepa tree; There exists a + -Kurepa tree, and moreover, + + holds. entails the existence of a -Kurepa tree (see [11, II.ğ5]). Proof. Suppose (κ, E + ) holds for some κ, and that there exist no -Kurepa trees. By <κ = and 2 = +, the proof of Theorem 2.6 yields that holds. By a theorem of Gregory from [6], < < + = 2 entails E +. So, altogether, E < + + holds. Let A δ δ < + witness +. For all δ < +, put: B δ := A δ C C [A δ ] ω. It now suffices to prove the next claim. Claim B δ δ < + witnesses + +. Proof. By ω =, we have B δ for all δ <. Now, suppose A is a given subset of +. Pick a club C 0 + such that A δ A δ for all δ C 0. Suppose n < ω and that C n is defined; pick a club C n+1 + such that C n δ A δ for all δ C n+1. Put C := n<ω C n. Then A δ A δ and {C n δ n < ω} [A δ ] ω for all δ C. In particular, A δ B δ, and C δ = {C n δ n < ω} B δ, for all δ C. So, we are done. Remark. The preceding proof shows that S is equivalent to + S, for all stationary S + with ℵ 0 =. 3. Non-trivial consequences of guessing 3.1. The failure of uniformization Definition 3.1 (Shelah, See [4]). A set S of limit ordinals is said to have the κ-uniformization property iff there exists a sequence A δ δ S such that: 1. A δ is a cofinal subset of δ for all δ S;

9 574 A. Rinot / Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (2011) for any sequence of functions f δ : A δ κ δ S, there exists some function f : δ S A δ κ such that for every δ S: sup{α A δ f δ (α) f (α)} < δ. The uniformization property is an anti-diamond principle, and indeed, the canonical models for the failure of diamond at successors of regulars, are, in fact, models of the uniformization property. In [10], König et al. established the consistency of GCH with the failure of (κ, E + ) for all uncountable κ. They wrote that they do not know whether GCH is consistent with the failure of (κ, S) for every stationary S E +, but conjectured that the forcing techniques of [8], that yields the consistency of GCH with the 2-uniformization property for E ℵ 2 ℵ 1, can be applied to achieve this. Motivated by this question, we were hoping to supply an affirmative answer by moreover establishing the consistency of GCH with the failure of the weakest among these principles, (κ, E + ).3 For a while, we were trying to attack this problem by contrasting Theorem 2.1 with the techniques of [14], but this was not fully successful. So we went back and reconsidered the uniformization property. It is easy to see that if (κ, S) holds, then S fails to have the κ-uniformization property, but deriving the failure of the 2-uniformization property seems harder. Fortunately, the next finding served as the key to that door. Theorem 3.2. Suppose that S is a stationary subset of E + for a given regular uncountable cardinal,, 2 = +, and that at least one of the following holds: (κ, S) for some κ < ; (, S), and is a successor cardinal. If A δ δ S is a sequence such that for all δ S, A δ is a cofinal subset of δ, then there exists a sequence f δ : A δ δ δ S such that for every function f : + +, the following set is stationary: {δ S sup{α A δ f δ (α) = f (α)} = δ}. Proof. If (κ, S) holds for some cardinal κ <, let Cδ i i <, δ S witness that. Otherwise, is a successor cardinal and (, S) holds. In this case, let κ be the cardinal such that = κ +, and let Cδ i i <, δ S witness (, S). In either case, κ is a well-defined cardinal <, and Cδ i [δ] κ for all (i, δ) S. Next, suppose that a sequence A δ δ S as above is given. We shall derive the existence of a sequence f δ : A δ δ δ S with the required guessing property. Let be some well-ordering of [ + ] κ. Fix a bijection ψ : κ + +. For all (i, j) κ, define a function ψ i,j : + + by letting: ψ i,j (α) := ψ 1 (α)(i, j), (α < + ). Fix δ S. For all α < δ, pick a function ϕ α δ : κ δ satisfying: ϕδ α [{i} κ] = min {x Ci δ α x}, (i < ). Finally, for all (i, j) κ, define f i,j δ : A δ δ by letting for all α A δ : f i,j 0, δ (α) := ψ i,j (ϕδ α (i, j)), otherwise. ψi,j (ϕδ α (i, j)) δ Claim There exists (i, j) κ such that f i,j δ δ S has the required properties. Proof. Suppose not. So, for every (i, j) κ, let us pick a function f i,j : + + and a club D i,j + such that: D i,j {δ S sup{α A δ f i,j δ (α) = f i,j(α)} = δ} =. For all α < +, let g α : κ + be the function satisfying g α (i, j) = f i,j (α) for all (i, j) κ. Define f : + + by letting f (α) := ψ(g α ) for all α < +. Put D := (i,j) κ {δ D i,j f i,j [δ] δ} and D := {x [ + ] < f [x] x}. Then D is a club in +, and D is a club in [ + ] <. Thus, let us pick some δ S D and i < such that Cδ i D. Then α ϕδ α[{i} κ] D for all α A δ, and hence f (α) ϕδ α[{i} κ] for all α A δ. Define h : A δ κ by letting: h(α) := min{j < κ f (α) = ϕδ α (i, j)}, (α A δ). 3 Note that under GCH, (κ, S) entails (κ, S) for every κ.

10 A. Rinot / Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (2011) Since δ = cf() > κ, let us pick some j < κ such that h 1 {j} is a cofinal subset of A δ. So: sup{α A δ f (α) = ϕδ α (i, j)} = δ, and in particular sup(b δ ) = δ, where B δ := {α A δ ψ i,j (ϕ α δ (i, j)) = ψ i,j(f (α))}. Since δ D, we get that f i,j [δ] δ, and hence, for all α B δ : f i,j δ (α) = ψ i,j(ϕ α δ (i, j)) = ψ i,j(f (α)) = ψ 1 (f (α))(i, j) = g α (i, j) = f i,j (α), so, sup{α A δ f i,j δ (α) = f i,j(α)} = δ, contradicting the fact that δ D i,j. This completes the proof. Back to the question that was left open in [10], we conclude: Corollary 3.3. Suppose that is a successor cardinal in L. Then, in some forcing extension of L, we have: GCH is preserved; the cardinal structure and cofinalities are preserved; (κ, E + ) fails for every κ, and hence: (κ, S) fails for every κ and every stationary S E +. Proof. Work in L. By the technique of [8], there exists a forcing notion that preserves cofinalities and the GCH, such that in the generic extension, E + has the 2-uniformization property. More specifically, there exists a sequence A δ δ E + such that: for every δ E +, A δ is a cofinal subset of δ, with otp(δ) = ; in the generic extension, for every sequence of functions g δ : A δ 2 δ E +, there exists some function f : + 2 such that sup{α A δ g δ (α) f (α)} < δ for all δ E +. Now, work in this generic extension and assume indirectly that κ is a cardinal for which (κ, E + ) holds. By GCH, we may appeal to Theorem 3.2 to obtain a sequence of functions f δ : A δ δ δ E + such that for every function f : + +, the following set is stationary: {δ S sup{α A δ f δ (α) = f (α)} = δ}. Now, for all δ E +, define g δ : A δ 2 by letting for every α A δ : 0, fδ (α) = 1 g δ (α) := 1, otherwise. By the 2-uniformization property, let us fix a function f : + 2 such that sup{α A δ g δ (α) f (α)} < δ for all δ E +. By the choice of f δ δ E +, we may pick some δ E + such that sup{β A δ f δ (β) = f (β)} = δ. In particular, we have: δ {δ E + This is a contradiction Non-saturation sup{β A δ g δ (β) f (β)} < δ}. We commence with a simple corollary to a result of a previous section, and then turn to the main result of this paper. Theorem 3.4. Suppose that is a regular uncountable cardinal, T is a stationary subset of, and S is a stationary subset of E +. If T S holds, while S fails, then NS T is non-saturated. Proof. By Theorem 2.5 above. Theorem 3.5. Suppose that S is a stationary subset of E +, for a given regular uncountable cardinal. If (κ, S) holds for some cardinal κ <, then NS + S is non-saturated. Proof. We extend the arguments of [3] to apply to stationary subsets of E +. Let Ci δ i <, δ S exemplify (κ, S). For all δ S, fix a function h δ : δ [δ] <κ satisfying j h δ (i, j) Cδ i for all j < δ and i <. Put µ := +. For functions f, g µ µ, denote by f < g the statement that sup {j < µ f (j) g(j)} < µ. Let f α α < µ + be a sequence of functions

11 576 A. Rinot / Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (2011) in µ µ, which is increasing with respect to <. For all δ S and α < µ +, define a function f δ α f δ α (i, j) := min((h δ(i, j) {µ}) \ f α (j)), (i <, j < δ). : δ δ {µ} as follows: Notice that if f α (j) f β (j), then fα δ(i, j) f β δ (i, j). For all α < β < µ + and i <, consider the set: Sα,β i := {δ S sup{j < δ f α δ (i, j) = f β δ (i, j)} < δ}. Claim For every α < β < γ < µ + and i <, there exists some ε < + such that the two holds: (1) S i α,β \ ε Si α,γ ; (2) S i β,γ \ ε Si α,γ. Proof. Fix α < β < γ < µ +. By the choice of the sequence f α α < µ +, let us pick some ε < µ such that f α (j) < f β (j) < f γ (j) whenever ε j < µ. Fix also i <. (1) Suppose δ Sα,β i \ ε. Put A := {j < δ f α δ(i, j) = f β δ (i, j)} ε. Then A is a bounded subset of δ. Fix j δ \ A. Then f α (j) < f β (j) < f γ (j) and fα δ(i, j) < f β δ(i, j). In particular, f α δ(i, j) < f β δ(i, j) f γ δ(i, j). It follows that {j < δ f α δ (i, j) = fγ δ(i, j)} A, and hence δ Si α,γ. (2) Suppose δ Sβ,γ i \ ε. Put A := {j < δ f β δ(i, j) = f γ δ (i, j)} ε. Then A is a bounded subset of δ. Fix j δ \ A. Then f α (j) < f β (j) < f γ (j) and fβ δ(i, j) < f γ δ(i, j). In particular, f α δ(j) f β δ(j) < f γ δ(j). It follows that {j < δ f α δ(i, j) = f γ δ (i, j)} A, and hence δ S i α,γ. Claim There exists a function g : µ + such that S g(α) α,β is stationary for every α < β < µ+. Proof. Fix α < µ +. We would like to define g(α). By Claim 3.5.1(1), if i < is such that S i α,α+1 is stationary, then Si α,β is stationary for all β > α. Thus, let us argue the existence of some i < such that S i α,α+1 is stationary. Put j := sup {j < µ f α (j) f α+1 (j)} + 1. Next, define a function f : [ + ] <ω + as follows: 0, σ = f (σ ) = f α (min(σ )), σ = 1, (σ [ + ] <ω ). f α+1 (min(σ )), otherwise Put D := {x [ + ] <κ f [x] <ω x}. Then D is a club in [ + ] <κ, and hence there exists some i < such that {δ S Cδ i D} is stationary. Fix such i <, and let us show that T S i α,α+1, for the stationary set T := {δ S \ j Cδ i D}. Fix δ T. For j < δ, we have j h δ (i, j) C i j D, and hence f α (j) = f ({j}) h δ (i, j). Likewise, f α+1 (j) h δ (i, j) for all j < δ. So fα δ(i, j) = f α(j) < f α+1 (j) = f δ (i, j) α+1 for all j δ \ j, testifying that δ S i α,α+1. Let g be given by the previous claim. Fix an ordinal i < such that g 1 {i } is cofinal in µ +. By thinning out the sequence f α α < µ +, we may assume without loss of generality that g(α) = i for all α < µ +. For a set S S, let [S ] denote its equivalence class in P (S)/NS + S. By Claim 3.5.1, [Sα,β i ] α < β < µ+ is weakly increasing for all α < µ +, and [Sβ,γ i ] β < γ is weakly decreasing for all γ < µ+. Assume now that NS + S is saturated. Then, for all α < µ +, the sequence [Sα,β i ] α < β < µ+ is eventually constant, thus for all α < µ +, let us pick a large enough α < µ +, for which the sequence [Sα,β i ] α < β < µ + is constant. Now, if α < β < µ +, and γ > max{α, β }, then [Sβ,β i ] = [Si β,γ ] [Si α,γ ] = [Si α,α ], and hence the sequence [Si β,β ] β < µ+ is weakly decreasing and so eventually constant. Pick a large enough γ < µ + at which this sequence is constant. By the choice of i, Sγ i,γ is stationary, so let us fix a cardinal θ < κ such that the following set is stationary: S := {δ S i γ,γ sup{j < δ h δ(i, j) = θ} = δ}. Recursively define an increasing function g : θ + µ + by letting g(0) := γ + 1 and g(ς) := sup{g(ι) ι < ς} + 1 for all ς < θ +. Notice that if ι < ς < θ +, then [Sg(ι),g(ς) i ] = [Si g(ι),g(ι) ] = [Si γ,γ ], and we may find a club C ι,ς such that Sg(ι),g(ς) i C ι,ς = Sγ i,γ C ι,ς. Let C := C ι,ς ι < ς < θ +, then we have: S i g(ι),g(ς) C = Si γ,γ C, (ι < ς < θ + ).

12 A. Rinot / Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (2011) In particular: S i g(ι),g(ς) S C, (ι < ς < θ + ). Put j := sup j < µ ι < ς < θ + = f g(ι) (j) f g(ς) (j) + 1, and pick δ S C above j. Let L := {j δ \ j h δ (i, j) = θ}. Then sup(l) = δ, and for all j L, the sequence f g(ι) (j) ι < is strictly increasing. Hence, for all j L, f δ g(ι) (i, j) ι < θ + is a weakly increasing sequence of elements of h δ (i, j), and as h δ (i, j) = θ < θ +, the sequence is eventually constant. Thus, for every j L, let us pick a large enough ι(j) < θ + at which this sequence is constant. As δ = cf() > κ θ +, let A be a cofinal subset of L and let ι < θ + be such that ι(j) = ι for all j A. Finally, fix ι < ς < θ + with ι > ι. Since ι < ι < ς, we get that f δ g(ι) ({i } A) = f δ δ Sg(ι),g(ς) i δ, that is, sup{j < δ fg(ι) (i, j) = fg(ς) δ (i, j)} < δ. This is a contradiction. 4. Open problems g(ς) ({i } A), while, by δ S C and (1) above, we get that Question 1. Is it consistent with GCH that for some regular uncountable cardinal,, T E + fails for all stationary T? Note that by Theorem 2.7, a negative answer would have yielded that GCH implies the existence of an ω 2 -Souslin tree. But we expect a positive answer, and have already obtained a few results in this direction. For instance, the following two are consistent: GCH, and for some stationary S E ω 2 ω 1 for which (E ω 2 ω 1 \ S) is stationary as well, T S fails for all stationary T ω 1 ; GCH, and for some stationary T ω 1 for which (ω 1 \ T) is stationary as well, T ω E 2 fails. ω 1 On another front, Alex Primavesi considered a generalization for stationary sets of the tail club guessing principle (Definition 1.3), and asked about its consistency. Definition (Primavesi). For a regular cardinal and a stationary T, Stat T asserts the existence of a sequence A δ δ T such that: A δ δ and sup(a δ ) = δ for every limit δ T ; for every stationary S T, {δ S β < δ(a δ \ β S)} is stationary. We have noticed that if > ω 1, then Stat T fails for every stationary T. Thus, the remaining question is as follows. Question 2. Is it consistent that Stat T holds for some stationary T ω 1? (1) Acknowledgements The author would like to thank his Ph.D. advisor, Moti Gitik, for his comments and remarks. I thank the organizers of the Logic Colloquium 2009 for a successful meeting, and for inviting me to present the results of my dissertation [12] in the Set Theory special session of that meeting. References [1] Keith J. Devlin, Constructibility, in: Perspectives in Mathematical Logic, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, [2] Mirna Džamonja, Club guessing and the universal models, Notre Dame J. Formal Logic 46 (3) (2005) (electronic). [3] Mirna Džamonja, Saharon Shelah, Saturated filters at successors of singular, weak reflection and yet another weak club principle, Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 79 (3) (1996) [4] Paul C. Eklof, Alan H. Mekler, Almost free modules, in: North-Holland Mathematical Library, vol. 46, North-Holland Publishing Co., Amsterdam, Set-theoretic methods. [5] Matthew Foreman, Ideals and generic elementary embeddings, in: Matthew Foreman, Akihiro Kanamori (Eds.), in: Handbook of Set Theory, vol. II, Springer-Verlag, 2010, pp [6] John Gregory, Higher Souslin trees and the generalized continuum hypothesis, J. Symbolic Logic 41 (3) (1976) [7] R. Björn Jensen, The fine structure of the constructible hierarchy, Ann. Math. Logic 4 (1972) ; R. Björn Jensen, The fine structure of the constructible hierarchy, Ann. Math. Logic 4 (1972) 443 (erratum). With a section by Jack Silver. [8] James H. King, Charles I. Steinhorn, The uniformization property for ℵ 2, Israel J. Math. 36 (3 4) (1980) [9] Menachem Kojman, Saharon Shelah, µ-complete Souslin trees on µ +, Arch. Math. Logic 32 (3) (1993) [10] Bernhard König, Paul Larson, Yasuo Yoshinobu, Guessing clubs in the generalized club filter, Fund. Math. 195 (2) (2007) [11] Kenneth Kunen, Set theory, in: Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, vol. 102, North-Holland Publishing Co., Amsterdam, An introduction to independence proofs. [12] Assaf Rinot, Squares, diamonds and stationary reflection. Ph.D. Thesis, Tel Aviv University, [13] Saharon Shelah, Cardinal arithmetic, in: Oxford Logic Guides, vol. 29, The Clarendon Press Oxford University Press, New York, 1994, Oxford Science Publications. [14] Saharon Shelah, Not collapsing cardinals κ in (<κ)-support iterations, Israel J. Math. 136 (2003)

Diamond, non-saturation, and weak square principles

Diamond, non-saturation, and weak square principles Diamond, non-saturation, and weak square principles Logic Colloquium 2009 (European ASL summer meeting) 02-Aug-09, Sofia Assaf Rinot Tel-Aviv University http://www.tau.ac.il/ rinot 1 Diamond on successor

More information

Diamond on successors of singulars

Diamond on successors of singulars Diamond on successors of singulars ESI workshop on large cardinals and descriptive set theory 18-Jun-09, Vienna Assaf Rinot Tel-Aviv University http://www.tau.ac.il/ rinot 1 Diamond on successor cardinals

More information

THE FAILURE OF DIAMOND ON A REFLECTING STATIONARY SET

THE FAILURE OF DIAMOND ON A REFLECTING STATIONARY SET THE FAILURE OF DIAMOND ON A REFLECTING STATIONARY SET MOTI GITIK AND ASSAF RINOT Abstract. 1. It is shown that the failure of S, for a set S ℵ ω+1 that reflects stationarily often, is consistent with GCH

More information

VARIATIONS FOR SEPARATING CLUB GUESSING PRINCIPLES

VARIATIONS FOR SEPARATING CLUB GUESSING PRINCIPLES P max VARIATIONS FOR SEPARATING CLUB GUESSING PRINCIPLES TETSUYA ISHIU AND PAUL B. LARSON Abstract. In his book on P max [6], Woodin presents a collection of partial orders whose extensions satisfy strong

More information

A NOTE ON THE EIGHTFOLD WAY

A NOTE ON THE EIGHTFOLD WAY A NOTE ON THE EIGHTFOLD WAY THOMAS GILTON AND JOHN KRUEGER Abstract. Assuming the existence of a Mahlo cardinal, we construct a model in which there exists an ω 2 -Aronszajn tree, the ω 1 -approachability

More information

Singular Failures of GCH and Level by Level Equivalence

Singular Failures of GCH and Level by Level Equivalence Singular Failures of GCH and Level by Level Equivalence Arthur W. Apter Department of Mathematics Baruch College of CUNY New York, New York 10010 USA and The CUNY Graduate Center, Mathematics 365 Fifth

More information

THE TREE PROPERTY AND THE FAILURE OF THE SINGULAR CARDINAL HYPOTHESIS AT ℵ ω 2

THE TREE PROPERTY AND THE FAILURE OF THE SINGULAR CARDINAL HYPOTHESIS AT ℵ ω 2 THE TREE PROPERTY AND THE FAILURE OF THE SINGULAR CARDINAL HYPOTHESIS AT ℵ ω 2 DIMA SINAPOVA Abstract. We show that given ω many supercompact cardinals, there is a generic extension in which the tree property

More information

Forcing notions in inner models

Forcing notions in inner models Forcing notions in inner models David Asperó Abstract There is a partial order P preserving stationary subsets of! 1 and forcing that every partial order in the ground model V that collapses asu ciently

More information

CLUB GUESSING SEQUENCES NATURAL STRUCTURES IN SET THEORY

CLUB GUESSING SEQUENCES NATURAL STRUCTURES IN SET THEORY Unspecified Journal Volume 00, Number 0, Pages 000 000 S????-????(XX)0000-0 CLUB GUESSING SEQUENCES NATURAL STRUCTURES IN SET THEORY TETSUYA ISHIU Abstract. Natural structures in set theory played key

More information

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (2010) 916 922 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Annals of Pure and Applied Logic journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/apal Cardinal characteristics and

More information

Aronszajn Trees and the SCH

Aronszajn Trees and the SCH Aronszajn Trees and the SCH Itay Neeman and Spencer Unger February 28, 2009 1 Introduction These notes are based on results presented by Itay Neeman at the Appalachian Set Theory workshop on February 28,

More information

Tallness and Level by Level Equivalence and Inequivalence

Tallness and Level by Level Equivalence and Inequivalence Tallness and Level by Level Equivalence and Inequivalence Arthur W. Apter Department of Mathematics Baruch College of CUNY New York, New York 10010 USA and The CUNY Graduate Center, Mathematics 365 Fifth

More information

THE TREE PROPERTY AT ℵ ω+1 DIMA SINAPOVA

THE TREE PROPERTY AT ℵ ω+1 DIMA SINAPOVA THE TREE PROPERTY AT ℵ ω+1 DIMA SINAPOVA Abstract. We show that given ω many supercompact cardinals, there is a generic extension in which there are no Aronszajn trees at ℵ ω+1. This is an improvement

More information

A NEW LINDELOF SPACE WITH POINTS G δ

A NEW LINDELOF SPACE WITH POINTS G δ A NEW LINDELOF SPACE WITH POINTS G δ ALAN DOW Abstract. We prove that implies there is a zero-dimensional Hausdorff Lindelöf space of cardinality 2 ℵ1 which has points G δ. In addition, this space has

More information

Successive cardinals with the tree property

Successive cardinals with the tree property UCLA March 3, 2014 A classical theorem Theorem (König Infinity Lemma) Every infinite finitely branching tree has an infinite path. Definitions A tree is set T together with an ordering < T which is wellfounded,

More information

A variant of Namba Forcing

A variant of Namba Forcing A variant of Namba Forcing Moti Gitik School of Mathematical Sciences Raymond and Beverly Sackler Faculty of Exact Science Tel Aviv University Ramat Aviv 69978, Israel August 0, 009 Abstract Ronald Jensen

More information

Independence of Boolean algebras and forcing

Independence of Boolean algebras and forcing Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 124 (2003) 179 191 www.elsevier.com/locate/apal Independence of Boolean algebras and forcing Milos S. Kurilic Department of Mathematics and Informatics, University of Novi

More information

M ath. Res. Lett. 15 (2008), no. 00, NN c International Press 2008 A UNIVERSAL ARONSZAJN LINE. Justin Tatch Moore. 1.

M ath. Res. Lett. 15 (2008), no. 00, NN c International Press 2008 A UNIVERSAL ARONSZAJN LINE. Justin Tatch Moore. 1. M ath. Res. Lett. 15 (2008), no. 00, 10001 100NN c International Press 2008 A UNIVERSAL ARONSZAJN LINE Justin Tatch Moore Abstract. The purpose of this note is to define an Aronszajn line η C and prove

More information

FORCING AXIOMS AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS, PART II: TRANSCENDING ω 1 -SEQUENCES OF REAL NUMBERS

FORCING AXIOMS AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS, PART II: TRANSCENDING ω 1 -SEQUENCES OF REAL NUMBERS FORCING AXIOMS AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS, PART II: TRANSCENDING ω 1 -SEQUENCES OF REAL NUMBERS JUSTIN TATCH MOORE Abstract. The purpose of this article is to prove that the forcing axiom for completely

More information

SET MAPPING REFLECTION

SET MAPPING REFLECTION SET MAPPING REFLECTION JUSTIN TATCH MOORE Abstract. In this note we will discuss a new reflection principle which follows from the Proper Forcing Axiom. The immediate purpose will be to prove that the

More information

SHELAH S SINGULAR COMPACTNESS THEOREM

SHELAH S SINGULAR COMPACTNESS THEOREM SHELAH S SINGULAR COMPACTNESS THEOREM PAUL C. EKLOF Abstract. We present Shelah s famous theorem in a version for modules, together with a self-contained proof and some examples. This exposition is based

More information

THE PRECIPITOUSNESS OF TAIL CLUB GUESSING IDEALS

THE PRECIPITOUSNESS OF TAIL CLUB GUESSING IDEALS THE PRECIPITOUSNESS OF TAIL CLUB GUESSING IDEALS TETSUYA ISHIU Abstract. From a measurable cardinal, we build a model in which the nonstationary ideal on ω 1 is not precipitous, but there is a precipitous

More information

A DIRECT PROOF OF THE FIVE ELEMENT BASIS THEOREM

A DIRECT PROOF OF THE FIVE ELEMENT BASIS THEOREM A DIRECT PROOF OF THE FIVE ELEMENT BASIS THEOREM BOBAN VELIČKOVIĆ AND GIORGIO VENTURI Abstract. We present a direct proof of the consistency of the existence of a five element basis for the uncountable

More information

ORGANIC AND TIGHT J. CUMMINGS, M. FOREMAN, AND E. SCHIMMERLING

ORGANIC AND TIGHT J. CUMMINGS, M. FOREMAN, AND E. SCHIMMERLING ORGANIC AND TIGHT J. CUMMINGS, M. FOREMAN, AND E. SCHIMMERLING 1. Introduction This report is motivated by the combinatorics of ℵ ω in L where there are canonical examples of scales, square sequences other

More information

20 Ordinals. Definition A set α is an ordinal iff: (i) α is transitive; and. (ii) α is linearly ordered by. Example 20.2.

20 Ordinals. Definition A set α is an ordinal iff: (i) α is transitive; and. (ii) α is linearly ordered by. Example 20.2. 20 Definition 20.1. A set α is an ordinal iff: (i) α is transitive; and (ii) α is linearly ordered by. Example 20.2. (a) Each natural number n is an ordinal. (b) ω is an ordinal. (a) ω {ω} is an ordinal.

More information

ITERATING ALONG A PRIKRY SEQUENCE

ITERATING ALONG A PRIKRY SEQUENCE ITERATING ALONG A PRIKRY SEQUENCE SPENCER UNGER Abstract. In this paper we introduce a new method which combines Prikry forcing with an iteration between the Prikry points. Using our method we prove from

More information

On versions of on cardinals larger than ℵ 1

On versions of on cardinals larger than ℵ 1 arxiv:math/9911228v1 [math.lo] 28 Nov 1999 On versions of on cardinals larger than ℵ 1 1 Mirna Džamonja School of Mathematics University of East Anglia Norwich, NR47TJ, UK M.Dzamonja@uea.ac.uk Saharon

More information

THE STRONG TREE PROPERTY AND THE FAILURE OF SCH

THE STRONG TREE PROPERTY AND THE FAILURE OF SCH THE STRONG TREE PROPERTY AND THE FAILURE OF SCH JIN DU Abstract. Fontanella [2] showed that if κ n : n < ω is an increasing sequence of supercompacts and ν = sup n κ n, then the strong tree property holds

More information

Generic Absoluteness. Joan Bagaria and Sy D. Friedman. Abstract. However, this is not true for 1 3 predicates. Indeed, if we add a Cohen real

Generic Absoluteness. Joan Bagaria and Sy D. Friedman. Abstract. However, this is not true for 1 3 predicates. Indeed, if we add a Cohen real Generic Absoluteness Joan Bagaria and Sy D. Friedman Abstract We explore the consistency strength of 3 and 4 absoluteness, for a variety of forcing notions. Introduction Shoeneld's absoluteness theorem

More information

TOPOLOGY PROCEEDINGS Volume 28, No. 1, 2004 Pages

TOPOLOGY PROCEEDINGS Volume 28, No. 1, 2004 Pages TOPOLOGY PROCEEDINGS Volume 28, No. 1, 2004 Pages 113-132 A FAMILY OF TREES WITH NO UNCOUNTABLE BRANCHES MIRNA DŽAMONJA AND JOUKO VÄÄNÄNEN Abstract. We construct a family of 2 ℵ 1 trees of size ℵ 1 and

More information

FRAGILITY AND INDESTRUCTIBILITY II

FRAGILITY AND INDESTRUCTIBILITY II FRAGILITY AND INDESTRUCTIBILITY II SPENCER UNGER Abstract. In this paper we continue work from a previous paper on the fragility and indestructibility of the tree property. We present the following: (1)

More information

ORGANIC AND TIGHT J. CUMMINGS, M. FOREMAN, AND E. SCHIMMERLING

ORGANIC AND TIGHT J. CUMMINGS, M. FOREMAN, AND E. SCHIMMERLING ORGANIC AND TIGHT J. CUMMINGS, M. FOREMAN, AND E. SCHIMMERLING 1. Introduction This paper is motivated by the combinatorics of ℵ ω in L where there are canonical examples of scales, square sequences other

More information

The Ultrapower Axiom implies GCH above a supercompact cardinal

The Ultrapower Axiom implies GCH above a supercompact cardinal The Ultrapower Axiom implies GCH above a supercompact cardinal arxiv:1810.05036v1 [math.lo] 9 Oct 2018 Gabriel Goldberg October 12, 2018 Abstract We prove that the Generalized Continuum Hypothesis holds

More information

BOUNDING THE CONSISTENCY STRENGTH OF A FIVE ELEMENT LINEAR BASIS

BOUNDING THE CONSISTENCY STRENGTH OF A FIVE ELEMENT LINEAR BASIS BOUNDING THE CONSISTENCY STRENGTH OF A FIVE ELEMENT LINEAR BASIS BERNHARD KÖNIG, PAUL LARSON, JUSTIN TATCH MOORE, AND BOBAN VELIČKOVIĆ Abstract. In [13] it was demonstrated that the Proper Forcing Axiom

More information

REVIEW ON TODD EISWORTH S CHAPTER FOR THE HANDBOOK OF SET THEORY: SUCCESSORS OF SINGULAR CARDINALS

REVIEW ON TODD EISWORTH S CHAPTER FOR THE HANDBOOK OF SET THEORY: SUCCESSORS OF SINGULAR CARDINALS REVIEW ON TODD EISWORTH S CHAPTER FOR THE HANDBOOK OF SET THEORY: SUCCESSORS OF SINGULAR CARDINALS ASSAF RINOT This chapter offers a comprehensive and lucid exposition of the questions and techniques involved

More information

On squares, outside guessing of clubs and I <f [λ]

On squares, outside guessing of clubs and I <f [λ] F U N D A M E N T A MATHEMATICAE 148 (1995) On squares, outside guessing of clubs and I

More information

SOME REMARKS ON NON-SPECIAL COHERENT ARONSZAJN TREES

SOME REMARKS ON NON-SPECIAL COHERENT ARONSZAJN TREES SOME REMARKS ON NON-SPECIAL COHERENT ARONSZAJN TREES MICHAEL HRUŠÁK AND CARLOS MARTÍNEZ RANERO Abstract. We introduce some guessing principles sufficient for the existence of non-special coherent Aronszajn

More information

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.lo] 4 May 2006

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.lo] 4 May 2006 KUREPA-TREES AND NAMBA FORCING arxiv:math/0605130v1 [math.lo] 4 May 2006 BERNHARD KÖNIG AND YASUO YOSHINOBU Abstract. We show that compact cardinals and MM are sensitive to λ-closed forcings for arbitrarily

More information

Appalachian Set Theory Workshop, May 31, 2008 Lectures by Justin Tatch Moore Notes taken by David Milovich

Appalachian Set Theory Workshop, May 31, 2008 Lectures by Justin Tatch Moore Notes taken by David Milovich SET MAPPING REFLECTION Appalachian Set Theory Workshop, May 31, 2008 Lectures by Justin Tatch Moore Notes taken by David Milovich 1. Introduction The goal of these lectures is to give an exposition of

More information

GREGORY TREES, THE CONTINUUM, AND MARTIN S AXIOM

GREGORY TREES, THE CONTINUUM, AND MARTIN S AXIOM The Journal of Symbolic Logic Volume 00, Number 0, XXX 0000 GREGORY TREES, THE CONTINUUM, AND MARTIN S AXIOM KENNETH KUNEN AND DILIP RAGHAVAN Abstract. We continue the investigation of Gregory trees and

More information

On the Length of Borel Hierarchies

On the Length of Borel Hierarchies University of Wisconsin, Madison July 2016 The Borel hierachy is described as follows: open = Σ 0 1 = G closed = Π 0 1 = F Π 0 2 = G δ = countable intersections of open sets Σ 0 2 = F σ = countable unions

More information

The choice of ω 1 and combinatorics at ℵ ω

The choice of ω 1 and combinatorics at ℵ ω The choice of ω 1 and combinatorics at ℵ ω Spencer Unger UCLA October 19, 2013 Outline Combinatorial properties Theorems using supercompactness Bringing results down to ℵ ω Some new theorems A sketch of

More information

NAMBA FORCING, WEAK APPROXIMATION, AND GUESSING

NAMBA FORCING, WEAK APPROXIMATION, AND GUESSING NAMBA FORCING, WEAK APPROXIMATION, AND GUESSING SEAN COX AND JOHN KRUEGER Abstract. We prove a variation of Easton s lemma for strongly proper forcings, and use it to prove that, unlike the stronger principle

More information

SINGULAR COFINALITY CONJECTURE AND A QUESTION OF GORELIC. 1. introduction

SINGULAR COFINALITY CONJECTURE AND A QUESTION OF GORELIC. 1. introduction SINGULAR COFINALITY CONJECTURE AND A QUESTION OF GORELIC MOHAMMAD GOLSHANI Abstract. We give an affirmative answer to a question of Gorelic [5], by showing it is consistent, relative to the existence of

More information

KNASTER AND FRIENDS I: CLOSED COLORINGS AND PRECALIBERS

KNASTER AND FRIENDS I: CLOSED COLORINGS AND PRECALIBERS KNASTER AND FRIENDS I: CLOSED COLORINGS AND PRECALIBERS CHRIS LAMBIE-HANSON AND ASSAF RINOT Abstract. The productivity of the κ-chain condition, where κ is a regular, uncountable cardinal, has been the

More information

On the Length of Borel Hierarchies

On the Length of Borel Hierarchies On the Length of Borel Hierarchies Arnold W. Miller November 7, 2016 This is a survey paper on the lengths of Borel hierarchies and related hierarchies. It consists of lecture notes of a lecture given

More information

Forcing Axioms and Inner Models of Set Theory

Forcing Axioms and Inner Models of Set Theory Forcing Axioms and Inner Models of Set Theory Boban Veličković Equipe de Logique Université de Paris 7 http://www.logique.jussieu.fr/ boban 15th Boise Extravaganza in Set Theory Boise State University,

More information

COLLAPSING FUNCTIONS

COLLAPSING FUNCTIONS COLLAPSING FUNCTIONS ERNEST SCHIMMERLING AND BOBAN VELICKOVIC Abstract. We define what it means for a function on ω 1 to be a collapsing function for λ and show that if there exists a collapsing function

More information

The constructible universe

The constructible universe The constructible universe In this set of notes I want to sketch Gödel s proof that CH is consistent with the other axioms of set theory. Gödel s argument goes well beyond this result; his identification

More information

HYBRID PRIKRY FORCING

HYBRID PRIKRY FORCING HYBRID PRIKRY FORCING DIMA SINAPOVA Abstract. We present a new forcing notion combining diagonal supercompact Prikry focing with interleaved extender based forcing. We start with a supercompact cardinal

More information

Increasing δ 1 2 and Namba-style forcing

Increasing δ 1 2 and Namba-style forcing Increasing δ 1 2 and Namba-style forcing Richard Ketchersid Miami University Jindřich Zapletal University of Florida April 17, 2007 Paul Larson Miami University Abstract We isolate a forcing which increases

More information

INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS

INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS TOM CUCHTA 1. Introduction This paper was written as a final project for the 2013 Summer Session of Mathematical Logic 1 at Missouri S&T. We intend to present a short discussion

More information

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES ITAY NEEMAN Abstract. We present an approach to forcing with finite sequences of models that uses models of two types. This approach builds on earlier work

More information

Title Covering a bounded set of functions by Author(s) Kada, Masaru Editor(s) Citation Topology and its Applications. 2007, 1 Issue Date 2007-01 URL http://hdl.handle.net/10466/12488 Rights c2007 Elsevier

More information

Cardinal invariants above the continuum

Cardinal invariants above the continuum arxiv:math/9509228v1 [math.lo] 15 Sep 1995 Cardinal invariants above the continuum James Cummings Hebrew University of Jerusalem cummings@math.huji.ac.il Saharon Shelah Hebrew University of Jerusalem shelah@math.huji.ac.il

More information

SUPERSTABILITY FROM CATEGORICITY IN ABSTRACT ELEMENTARY CLASSES

SUPERSTABILITY FROM CATEGORICITY IN ABSTRACT ELEMENTARY CLASSES SUPERSTABILITY FROM CATEGORICITY IN ABSTRACT ELEMENTARY CLASSES WILL BONEY, RAMI GROSSBERG, MONICA M. VANDIEREN, AND SEBASTIEN VASEY Abstract. Starting from an abstract elementary class with no maximal

More information

Projective well-orderings of the reals and forcing axioms

Projective well-orderings of the reals and forcing axioms Projective well-orderings of the reals and forcing axioms Andrés Eduardo Department of Mathematics Boise State University 2011 North American Annual Meeting UC Berkeley, March 24 27, 2011 This is joint

More information

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007)

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω 0. Introduction David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) In its simplest form the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem for L ω1 ω states that if σ L ω1

More information

Covering a bounded set of functions by an increasing chain of slaloms

Covering a bounded set of functions by an increasing chain of slaloms Topology and its Applications 154 (2007) 277 281 www.elsevier.com/locate/topol Covering a bounded set of functions by an increasing chain of slaloms Masaru Kada Graduate School of Science, Osaka Prefecture

More information

RESEARCH STATEMENT CHRIS LAMBIE-HANSON

RESEARCH STATEMENT CHRIS LAMBIE-HANSON RESEARCH STATEMENT CHRIS LAMBIE-HANSON My research lies mostly in logic and set theory, and in applications of set-theoretic tools to other areas of mathematics, such as graph theory, algebra, and topology.

More information

SQUARE WITH BUILT-IN DIAMOND-PLUS

SQUARE WITH BUILT-IN DIAMOND-PLUS SQUARE WITH BUILT-IN DIAMOND-PLUS ASSAF RINOT AND RALF SCHINDLER Abstract. We formulate combinatorial principles that combine the square principle with various strong forms of the diamond principle, and

More information

1. Introduction Definition 1.1. For an L ω1,ω-sentence φ, the spectrum of φ is the set

1. Introduction Definition 1.1. For an L ω1,ω-sentence φ, the spectrum of φ is the set KUREPA TREES AND SPECTRA OF L ω1,ω-sentences DIMA SINAPOVA AND IOANNIS SOULDATOS Abstract. We construct a single L ω1,ω-sentence ψ that codes Kurepa trees to prove the consistency of the following: (1)

More information

ITERATIONS WITH MIXED SUPPORT

ITERATIONS WITH MIXED SUPPORT ITERATIONS WITH MIXED SUPPORT VERA FISCHER Abstract. In this talk we will consider three properties of iterations with mixed (finite/countable) supports: iterations of arbitrary length preserve ω 1, iterations

More information

CCC Forcing and Splitting Reals

CCC Forcing and Splitting Reals CCC Forcing and Splitting Reals Boban Velickovic Equipe de Logique, Université de Paris 7 2 Place Jussieu, 75251 Paris, France Abstract Prikry asked if it is relatively consistent with the usual axioms

More information

Souslin s Hypothesis

Souslin s Hypothesis Michiel Jespers Souslin s Hypothesis Bachelor thesis, August 15, 2013 Supervisor: dr. K.P. Hart Mathematical Institute, Leiden University Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 Trees 2 3 The -Principle 7 4 Martin

More information

SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS

SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS NATHAN BOWLER AND STEFAN GESCHKE Abstract. We extend the notion of a uniform matroid to the infinitary case and construct, using weak fragments of Martin s Axiom,

More information

HOW DO ULTRAFILTERS ACT ON THEORIES? THE CUT SPECTRUM AND TREETOPS

HOW DO ULTRAFILTERS ACT ON THEORIES? THE CUT SPECTRUM AND TREETOPS HOW DO ULTRAFILTERS ACT ON THEORIES? THE CUT SPECTRUM AND TREETOPS DIEGO ANDRES BEJARANO RAYO Abstract. We expand on and further explain the work by Malliaris and Shelah on the cofinality spectrum by doing

More information

Cardinal Preserving Elementary Embeddings

Cardinal Preserving Elementary Embeddings Outline Andrés E. Department of Mathematics California Institute of Technology XIII SLALM, Oaxaca, México, August 2006 Outline Outline 1 : Forcing axioms and inner models 2 Inner models M with ω1 M = ω

More information

Handbook of Set Theory. Foreman, Kanamori, and Magidor (eds.)

Handbook of Set Theory. Foreman, Kanamori, and Magidor (eds.) Handbook of Set Theory Foreman, Kanamori, and Magidor (eds.) August 5, 2006 2 Contents I Forcing over models of determinacy 5 by Paul B. Larson 1 Iterations............................... 7 2 P max.................................

More information

Forcing axioms and inner models

Forcing axioms and inner models Outline Andrés E. Department of Mathematics California Institute of Technology Boise State University, February 27 2008 Outline Outline 1 Introduction 2 Inner models M with ω1 M = ω 1 Inner models M with

More information

Forcing Closed Unbounded Subsets of ω 2

Forcing Closed Unbounded Subsets of ω 2 Forcing Closed Unbounded Subsets of ω 2 M.C. Stanley July 2000 Abstract. It is shown that there is no satisfactory first-order characterization of those subsets of ω 2 that have closed unbounded subsets

More information

Cardinal characteristics, projective wellorders and large continuum

Cardinal characteristics, projective wellorders and large continuum Cardinal characteristics, projective wellorders and large continuum Vera Fischer a,1,, Sy David Friedman a,1, Lyubomyr Zdomskyy a,1 a Kurt Gödel Research Center, University of Vienna, Währinger Strasse

More information

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Keith A. Kearnes and Greg Oman Abstract. We show that if P is an infinite poset whose proper order ideals have cardinality strictly less than P, and κ is a cardinal

More information

The Bounded Axiom A Forcing Axiom

The Bounded Axiom A Forcing Axiom The Bounded Axiom A Forcing Axiom Thilo Weinert 1 1 Contact: e-mail: weinert@math.uni-bonn.de, Phone: +49 228 73 3791 Abstract We introduce the Bounded Axiom A Forcing Axiom(BAAFA). It turns out that it

More information

SOME USES OF SET THEORY IN ALGEBRA. Stanford Logic Seminar February 10, 2009

SOME USES OF SET THEORY IN ALGEBRA. Stanford Logic Seminar February 10, 2009 SOME USES OF SET THEORY IN ALGEBRA Stanford Logic Seminar February 10, 2009 Plan I. The Whitehead Problem early history II. Compactness and Incompactness III. Deconstruction P. Eklof and A. Mekler, Almost

More information

many). But no other examples were known even Sacks forcing. Also for e.g. V = V = L, we did not know a forcing making it not proper.

many). But no other examples were known even Sacks forcing. Also for e.g. V = V = L, we did not know a forcing making it not proper. SARAJEVO JOURNAL OF MATHEMATICS Vol.13 (26), No.2, (2017), 141 154 DOI: 10.5644/SJM.13.2.02 PRESERVING OLD ([ω] ℵ0, ) IS PROPER SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. We give some sufficient and necessary conditions

More information

PCF THEORY AND CARDINAL INVARIANTS OF THE REALS

PCF THEORY AND CARDINAL INVARIANTS OF THE REALS PCF THEORY AND CARDINAL INVARIANTS OF THE REALS LAJOS SOUKUP Abstract. The additivity spectrum ADD(I) of an ideal I P(I) is the set of all regular cardinals κ such that there is an increasing chain {A

More information

Thomas Jech 1 and Saharon Shelah 2,3 The Pennsylvania State University The Hebrew University of Jerusalem and Rutgers University

Thomas Jech 1 and Saharon Shelah 2,3 The Pennsylvania State University The Hebrew University of Jerusalem and Rutgers University SIMPLE COMPLETE BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS Thomas Jech 1 and Saharon Shelah 2,3 The Pennsylvania State University The Hebrew University of Jerusalem and Rutgers University Abstract. For every regular cardinal κ

More information

ON CUTS IN ULTRAPRODUCTS OF LINEAR ORDERS I. 1. introduction

ON CUTS IN ULTRAPRODUCTS OF LINEAR ORDERS I. 1. introduction ON CUTS IN ULTRAPRODUCTS OF LINEAR ORDERS I MOHAMMAD GOLSHANI AND SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. For an ultrafilter D on a cardinal κ, we wonder for which pair (θ 1, θ 2 ) of regular cardinals, we have: for

More information

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved. Topology Proceedings Web: http://topology.auburn.edu/tp/ Mail: Topology Proceedings Department of Mathematics & Statistics Auburn University, Alabama 36849, USA E-mail: topolog@auburn.edu ISSN: 0146-4124

More information

A BOREL SOLUTION TO THE HORN-TARSKI PROBLEM. MSC 2000: 03E05, 03E20, 06A10 Keywords: Chain Conditions, Boolean Algebras.

A BOREL SOLUTION TO THE HORN-TARSKI PROBLEM. MSC 2000: 03E05, 03E20, 06A10 Keywords: Chain Conditions, Boolean Algebras. A BOREL SOLUTION TO THE HORN-TARSKI PROBLEM STEVO TODORCEVIC Abstract. We describe a Borel poset satisfying the σ-finite chain condition but failing to satisfy the σ-bounded chain condition. MSC 2000:

More information

MARTIN S MAXIMUM AND DEFINABILITY IN H(ℵ 2 ) Keywords: Forcing Axioms; Definability; Large Cardinals. 1. Introduction

MARTIN S MAXIMUM AND DEFINABILITY IN H(ℵ 2 ) Keywords: Forcing Axioms; Definability; Large Cardinals. 1. Introduction MARTIN S MAXIMUM AND DEFINABILITY IN H(ℵ 2 ) PAUL B. LARSON Abstract. In [6], we modified a coding device from [14] and the consistency proof of Martin s Maximum from [3] to show that from a supercompact

More information

Scales, topological reflections, and large cardinal issues by Peter Nyikos

Scales, topological reflections, and large cardinal issues by Peter Nyikos Scales, topological reflections, and large cardinal issues by Peter Nyikos Reflection theorems in set-theoretic topology typically take the following form: if all small subspaces of a suitable kind of

More information

CH AND THE MOORE-MROWKA PROBLEM

CH AND THE MOORE-MROWKA PROBLEM CH AND THE MOORE-MROWKA PROBLEM ALAN DOW AND TODD EISWORTH Abstract. We show that the Continuum Hypothesis is consistent with all regular spaces of hereditarily countable π-character being C-closed. This

More information

Fréchet cardinals. Gabriel Goldberg. October 12, 2018

Fréchet cardinals. Gabriel Goldberg. October 12, 2018 Fréchet cardinals Gabriel Goldberg arxiv:1810.05035v1 [math.lo] 9 Oct 2018 October 12, 2018 Abstract An infinite cardinal λ is called Fréchet if the Fréchet filter on λ extends to a countably complete

More information

Club degrees of rigidity and almost Kurepa trees

Club degrees of rigidity and almost Kurepa trees Club degrees of rigidity and almost Kurepa trees Gunter Fuchs The College of Staten Island/CUNY August 25, 2012 Abstract A highly rigid Souslin tree T is constructed such that forcing with T turns T into

More information

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.lo] 15 Oct 1995

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.lo] 15 Oct 1995 arxiv:math/9510216v1 [math.lo] 15 Oct 1995 On squares, outside guessing of clubs and I

More information

Slow P -point Ultrafilters

Slow P -point Ultrafilters Slow P -point Ultrafilters Renling Jin College of Charleston jinr@cofc.edu Abstract We answer a question of Blass, Di Nasso, and Forti [2, 7] by proving, assuming Continuum Hypothesis or Martin s Axiom,

More information

The Arkhangel skiĭ Tall problem under Martin s Axiom

The Arkhangel skiĭ Tall problem under Martin s Axiom F U N D A M E N T A MATHEMATICAE 149 (1996) The Arkhangel skiĭ Tall problem under Martin s Axiom by Gary G r u e n h a g e and Piotr K o s z m i d e r (Auburn, Ala.) Abstract. We show that MA σ-centered

More information

DENSELY k-separable COMPACTA ARE DENSELY SEPARABLE

DENSELY k-separable COMPACTA ARE DENSELY SEPARABLE DENSELY k-separable COMPACTA ARE DENSELY SEPARABLE ALAN DOW AND ISTVÁN JUHÁSZ Abstract. A space has σ-compact tightness if the closures of σ-compact subsets determines the topology. We consider a dense

More information

TEST GROUPS FOR WHITEHEAD GROUPS

TEST GROUPS FOR WHITEHEAD GROUPS TEST GROUPS FOR WHITEHEAD GROUPS PAUL C. EKLOF, LÁSZLÓ FUCHS, AND SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. We consider the question of when the dual of a Whitehead group is a test group for Whitehead groups. This turns

More information

2 RENATA GRUNBERG A. PRADO AND FRANKLIN D. TALL 1 We thank the referee for a number of useful comments. We need the following result: Theorem 0.1. [2]

2 RENATA GRUNBERG A. PRADO AND FRANKLIN D. TALL 1 We thank the referee for a number of useful comments. We need the following result: Theorem 0.1. [2] CHARACTERIZING! 1 AND THE LONG LINE BY THEIR TOPOLOGICAL ELEMENTARY REFLECTIONS RENATA GRUNBERG A. PRADO AND FRANKLIN D. TALL 1 Abstract. Given a topological space hx; T i 2 M; an elementary submodel of

More information

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year Part II Year 2018 2017 2016 2015 2014 2013 2012 2011 2010 2009 2008 2007 2006 2005 2018 60 Paper 4, Section II 16G State and prove the ǫ-recursion Theorem. [You may assume the Principle of ǫ- Induction.]

More information

GROUPS WITH UNBOUNDED POTENTIAL AUTOMORPHISM TOWER HEIGHTS

GROUPS WITH UNBOUNDED POTENTIAL AUTOMORPHISM TOWER HEIGHTS GROUPS WITH UNBOUNDED POTENTIAL AUTOMORPHISM TOWER HEIGHTS PHILIPP LÜCKE Abstract. We show that it is consistent with the axioms of ZFC that there exists an infinite centreless group G with the property

More information

TRANSFERING SATURATION, THE FINITE COVER PROPERTY, AND STABILITY

TRANSFERING SATURATION, THE FINITE COVER PROPERTY, AND STABILITY TRANSFERING SATURATION, THE FINITE COVER PROPERTY, AND STABILITY John T. Baldwin Department of Mathematics University of Illinois at Chicago Chicago, IL 60680 Rami Grossberg Department of Mathematics Carnegie

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 1 Feb 2016

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 1 Feb 2016 arxiv:160200605v1 [mathlo] 1 Feb 2016 A Borel-reducibility Counterpart of Shelah s Main Gap Theorem Tapani Hyttinen, Vadim Kulikov, Miguel Moreno University of Helsinki Abstract We study the Borel-reducibility

More information

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved. Topology Proceedings Web: http://topology.auburn.edu/tp/ Mail: Topology Proceedings Department of Mathematics & Statistics Auburn University, Alabama 36849, USA E-mail: topolog@auburn.edu ISSN: 0146-4124

More information

Distributivity of Quotients of Countable Products of Boolean Algebras

Distributivity of Quotients of Countable Products of Boolean Algebras Rend. Istit. Mat. Univ. Trieste Volume 41 (2009), 27 33. Distributivity of Quotients of Countable Products of Boolean Algebras Fernando Hernández-Hernández Abstract. We compute the distributivity numbers

More information

EXTERNAL AUTOMORPHISMS OF ULTRAPRODUCTS OF FINITE MODELS

EXTERNAL AUTOMORPHISMS OF ULTRAPRODUCTS OF FINITE MODELS EXTERNAL AUTOMORPHISMS OF ULTRAPRODUCTS OF FINITE MODELS PHILIPP LÜCKE AND SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. Let L be a finite first-order language and M n n < ω be a sequence of finite L-models containing models

More information

The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count?

The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count? The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count? John T. Baldwin Department of Mathematics, Statistics and Computer Science University of Illinois at Chicago May 22, 2005 1 Is the Vaught Conjecture model

More information