Rational Choice with Categories

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Rational Choice with Categories"

Transcription

1 Rational Choice with Categories Preliminary version. Bruno A. Furtado Leandro Nascimento Gil Riella June 25, 2015 Abstract We propose a model of rational choice in the presence of categories. Given a subjective categorization of the choice set, the agent, when faced with a choice problem, picks the best elements available from each category. The model explains certain important deviations from the Weak Axiom of Revealed Preferences, while being fully characterized by other observable properties of the agent s choice behaviour. In the more general framework, our representation generalizes the maximization of incomplete preferences. For the specific case in which categories are disjoint, we prove that it is equivalent to the maximization of incomplete preferences plus a somewhat intuitive property. JEL classification: D01 1 Introduction Categorization is one of the most fundamental and pervasive cognitive procedures. Its importance lies in the fact that it permits us to understand and make predictions about objects and events in our world (Medin and Aguilar, 1999; Smith and Medin, 1981), as well as to choose among the sometimes overwhelming array of alternatives available. When one wishes to acquire a cell phone plan, odds are she won t consider the whole array of products, sort them in decreasing order of preference, and then pick her favorite one. She will first categorize the plans according to certain characteristics - such as quality and size of data packages, whether they are prepaid or postpaid, size of the minutes allowance, and so on -, and only then choose the best products for each category. Since categorization and concept formation have such central roles in the study of cognition, and therefore of rationality, it is peculiar that they are seldom explicitly taken into account in economic decision theory. In fact, a recurring criticism of the theory of rational choice is that it fails to take into account the role of category formation in the human decision making process. 1 We therefore develop a model that departs from the traditional rational choice framework precisely in that it allows for categorization to play a part on the choice process. Ministério da Fazenda do Brasil. bruno.furtado@fazenda.gov.br. Departamento de Economia, Universidade de Brasília. lgnascimento@unb.br Departamento de Economia, Universidade de Brasília. riella@unb.br 1 For an example of such a critique, see Schwartz (2000). 1

2 A decision maker is assumed to be endowed with incomplete preferences over the set of all possible alternatives she might be asked to choose from. By incomplete we mean that there are pairs of alternatives in the choice set which cannot be ranked as either better, worse or indifferent to one another. For a given categorization of the choice set, the agent only compares elements within categories, and then chooses the best ones in each of them. The agent s final choice will simply be the union, over every category, of the elements chosen within the categories. The only restriction that will be imposed upon the categorization is that preferences be complete inside each one of the categories. The model we propose also has testable implications for observable behaviour. It is a well established fact in choice theory that if full rationality is understood to be behaviour which is compatible with the maximization of transitive and complete preferences, then it is equivalent to behaviour abiding by Samuelson s Weak Axiom of Revealed Preferences (WARP). Despite its apparent simplicity, the model we put forth can account for many important violations of WARP, while being fully characterized by other observable properties of the agent s choice behaviour, including choice axioms that are well known in the literature. More recently, many weakenings of WARP have been proposed, leading to different models of bounded rationality. The one that most closely resembles our work is Manzini and Mariotti (2012). Their model, called Categorize-Then-Choose (CTC), consists of a two-stage process: in the first stage, the agent ranks all categories within the feasible set, eliminating all alternatives belonging to a dominated category; in the second stage, she picks her most preferred alternative among the remaining ones. Hence, the crucial difference between CTC and our model is that CTC assumes that the agent can make comparisons between categories, as well as within them. It has been suggested that choices between categories can be problematic, 2 and therefore we restrict our model to choices inside categories. No priority is given to any category over another. In section 2 we present some key concepts. Section 3 defines what we mean by rational choice with categories, and describes and interprets the main representation results of the paper. In section 4 we explore a special case of our model, when categories are disjoint sets. Section 5 places our model within the wider context of rational choice theory. Finally, in section 6 are some concluding remarks, including suggestions for future studies. 2 Setup The nonempty set X represents the set of all mutually exclusive alternatives available to the decision maker. By a choice field on X we mean a collection of sets Ω X 2 X \ { } that includes all singleton sets and is closed under finite unions. A choice field on X is interpreted as the family of all choice problems that the decision maker can possibly face. Any set A Ω X is referred to as a choice problem. When X 3 and Ω X is a choice field on X we call the pair (X, Ω X ) a choice space. In the event Ω X consists of all nonempty finite subsets of X we refer to (X, Ω X ) as a finite choice space. A choice correspondence is a function c : Ω X 2 X satisfying c(a) A for all A Ω X. Note that this definition allows for the possibility of the decision maker choosing more than one alternative for any given choice problem. The set c(a) is interpreted as 2 Schwartz (2000, pp. 82): Within each category, it may be relatively easy to express preferences. Between categories, however, expressing preferences is more problematic. 2

3 the collection of all choosable elements from the choice problem A, and the final choice of the decision maker will inevitably be a member of c(a). The agent might finalize her choice by subjectively randomizing between members of A. The symmetric and asymmetric parts of a reflexive binary relation X X will be denoted, respectively, by and. Hence is the disjoint union of and. Lack of preference will be represented by : x y if, and only if, neither x y nor y x. With this notation at hand, the symbol is used to signify comparability. Recall that a binary relation is acyclic when for any n N and x 1,..., x n X, if x i x i+1 for i = 1,..., n 1, then it is not true that x n x 1. A transitive and reflexive binary relation on X will be called a preference relation on X. Alternatively, we may also simply use the mathematical jargon and call such a relation a preorder on X. Both terms will be used interchangeably in this paper. For any S X and X X, the restriction of to S is denoted by S. When X is a nonempty set endowed with a preorder, and T X, we define: max(t, ) = {x T : (y x), y T }, the set of all -maximal elements of T. max(t, ) = {x T : x y, y T }, the set of all -maximum elements of T. Note that max(t, ) max(t, ), and that both sets are equal if is complete. Furthermore, if T is finite, max(t, ). On the other hand, if T is infinite, without any additional requirements on T or, the set of -maximal elements may well be empty. 3 General Categories 3.1 Categorization Given a preference relation on a set X, we define a category as a subset S of X in which is complete. This restriction on the structure of categories is both mild and intuitive, since one of the foremost reasons to group objects in the same category is the existence of some similarity among them (Hahn and Chater, 1997). It seems natural that similar alternatives are more likely to be comparable to one another, and hence our assumption about their mutual comparability is not so restrictive. Definition 1 (Categorization) Let X be a set endowed with a preorder. A cover S of X (that is, a collection of nonempty subsets of X with S = X) is a categorization of (X, ) if S is complete for every S S. Any S S is called a category of S. It will be noted that the definition imposes very little structure on the cover S. Particularly, it does not require that the categories be mutually disjoint. Therefore, this formulation allows for an individual to have {Chinese food} as a category, with {Chinese noodles} as a separate category within the first, and another category, say {Pasta}, that also contains {Chinese noodles} but is not a subset of {Chinese food}. Such intersecting categories may arise if, for example, multiple criteria are used for the categorization procedure, and these criteria overlap. 3 Furthermore, implicit in the definition of categorization is the fact that categories are, at least in part, subjective. That is, the manner in which the acting agent categorizes 3 As Manzini and Mariotti (2012, pp. 11) exemplify, think of categorizing cameras by price band and brand, or flights by cheapness and convenience. 3

4 alternatives is dependent upon her (subjective) preferences. Thus, implicit categories are not assumed to be observable, except perhaps indirectly, from the decision maker s choice behaviour. An outside observer cannot assume, for instance, that {Chinese food} and {Mexican food} will be relevant categories to the decision maker in any particular application. This is in line with recent studies in the field of cognitive psychology. 4 Perhaps the most natural way to rationalize choices in the presence of categories is simply to pick, among the alternatives presented in the choice problem, the best elements from each category. For a categorization S 2 X \ { } and a preference relation X X, c can be said to admit a representation by categorization if, for every A Ω X, c(a) = S S max(a S, ). This type of representation allows for behaviour that would not be possible if choice was simply the result of the maximization of a preference relation over the choice problem, that is, c(a) = max(a, ) for all A Ω X. We will further explore this in section 5, but the following example illustrates this point. Example 1 Let X = {x, y, z} and Ω X = 2 X \{ }. The choice correspondence defined by c({x, y}) = {x, y}, c({x, z}) = {x, z}, c({y, z}) = {y, z} and c({x, y, z}) = {y, z} cannot be rationalized as c( ) = max(, ), for any preference relation. On the other hand, such a choice correspondence can be rationalized by a maximization over categories by defining = {(x, x), (y, y), (z, z), (y, x), (z, x)} and S = {{x, y}, {x, z}}. Notice that, in the example above, x may be chosen even though every other element of X is strictly preferred to it. Although this may seem counter-intuitive at first, one may think of it as a predilection for diversity: an individual may choose a second-best option simply because she feels like having something from a certain category, even though a better alternative from a different category is available (think of going to an Italian restaurant and having pasta for a change, even though you would normally prefer having pizza). 3.2 General Model Having established that categorization is an important cognitive mechanism, and that the analysis of rational choice with categories cannot be boiled down to the maximization of an incomplete preference relation, it remains to determine what types of choice behaviour can be rationalized by maximizing over categories. The following results aim to answer this question in the general setting considered so far, where the structure imposed upon the categorization is restricted to that in Definition 1. We begin by stating a couple of postulates. Axiom 1 (Chernoff - α) For every A Ω X, if x c(a), then x c(b) for every B Ω X such that x B A. The (α) axiom implies that if an alternative is chosen in some choice problem, it will still be chosen if the choice problem shrinks. In particular, it implies that c(c(a)) = c(a), provided that c(a) is a choice problem. It was originally proposed by Chernoff (1954). 4 For example, Smith et al. (1998) find that the type of categorization process used by an individual - whether it is rule-based or similarity-based, for instance - impacts the resulting categories in a predictable manner. 4

5 Axiom 2 (Dominance) There exists an acyclic relation such that, for any A, B Ω X with A B, if x c(a) but x / c(b), then there exists y B \ A with y x and y c(a {y}). We can now prove the following result. Theorem 1 Let (X, Ω X ) be an arbitrary choice space. A choice correspondence c : Ω X 2 X satisfies (α) and Dominance if, and only if, there exists a preorder X X and a collection S 2 X \{ } such that is complete inside every S S and, for any A Ω X, c(a) = S S max(a S, ). Theorem 1 establishes the necessary and sufficient conditions for a choice correspondence to be rationalizable by a maximization with categories, but relies on the Dominance axiom, which is not given in terms of observable behavior. However, it gives us the exact conditions which a choice correspondence must satisfy in order to be representable in the desired manner. Consequently, it provides an useful shortcut to prove more interesting representation theorems in specific environments, as we will see presently. Also, Dominance makes it easier to compare the representation by categorization to other models of choice with bounded rationality, as we will show in section General model with finite choice field The weakness of the Dominance axiom is that it presupposes the existence of an acyclic relation with some desired characteristics. Ideally, such a binary relation should be elicited directly from the choice correspondence. As a candidate for the necessary relation, define P by xp y if, and only if, there exists a choice problem A such that y c(a) but y / c(a {x}). It turns out that, if the choice correspondence c can indeed be represented by c( ) = S S max(, ) for some preorder X X and S 2 X \ { }, then xp y reveals that x is strictly preferred to y with respect to. That is, we must have x y. We impose the following postulates on c: Axiom 3 (Aizerman - AA) If A, B Ω X are such that c(a) B A, then c(b) c(a). This axiom, which had its prominent role in decision theory, social choice and control theory recognized by Aizerman and Malishevski (1981), states that eliminating from a choice problem some alternatives that are not in the choice set cannot make new alternatives chosen. Axiom 4 (Acyclicity) The relation P is acyclic. Recall that the binary relation P is defined so that xp y only if there exists a situation where the addition of x to a choice problem makes y stop being chosen. In some sense, xp y means that x was revealed to be strictly preferred to y, so that it makes sense to impose that P be acyclic. The next lemma is the last necessary ingredient for the characterization of a representation by rational choice with categories when (X, Ω X ) is a finite choice space. 5

6 Lemma 1 Let (X, Ω X ) be a finite choice space and c : Ω X 2 X a choice correspondence on Ω X satisfying (α), AA and Acyclicity. Then c satisfies Dominance with P as the relevant binary relation. We are now ready to state our main result for finite choice spaces, giving us a full characterization of the sort of choice correspondences which are rationalizable by maximizing subject to a given categorization. Its proof derives directly from Theorem 1 and Lemma 1, and, consequently, is omitted. Theorem 2 Let (X, Ω X ) be a finite choice space. A choice correspondence c : Ω X 2 X satisfies (α), AA and Acyclicity if, and only if, there exists a preorder X X and a collection S 2 X \{ } such that is complete inside every S S and, for any A Ω X, c(a) = S S max(a S, ). Crucially, the characterization in Theorem 2 depends only upon observable behaviour, and is therefore easily testable, at least in principle. This is in contrast to Theorem 1, which hinges upon the unobservable Dominance axiom. 4 Disjoint Categories 4.1 Categorization with disjoint categories In many particular applications, the process of categorization gives rise to disjoint categories. That is, every element of the choice set must belong to one, and only one, category. For instance, if the only relevant categories for a decision maker are {food} and {shelter}, it is improbable that any given element of the choice set will be in both groups at once. 5 With effect, in psychology and philosophy, the classical view of categorization, which goes back to Aristotle, claims that categories are discrete entities, characterized by necessary and sufficient conditions for membership. 6 Thus, according to this view, categories are by definition mutually exclusive. 7 More recently, it has been extensively documented and experimentally tested by cognitive psychologists that children, when learning novel words, tend to naturally form disjoint categories. That is, when presented with a new label, they will be mostly inclined to map it to a novel rather than a familiar object (Markman, 1990; Markman et al., 2003). Although not entirely conclusive, such examples provide evidence that dividing the world into disjoint categories comes naturally to humans, which justifies a detailed analysis of this special case of our representation. We therefore devote this section to characterizing a representation theorem for when the categorization is a partition of X. 5 Excluding, of course, the possibility of wicked witches with gingerbread houses. 6 For a review of theories of categorization in psychology, see for example Smith and Medin (1981) and Komatsu (1992). 7 Actually, the only sort of intersection between categories allowed by the classical view is when a category is a subset, or refinement, of another. Therefore, it could be said that, for the same degree of generality - or, in the psychological jargon, for the same hierarchical level - categories are disjoint. 6

7 4.2 Axioms and Representation We begin by stating a couple of postulates that will be crucial to characterize the representation by a disjoint categorization, the first of which is already well known in the literature on social choice and decision theory (Sen, 1971; Moulin, 1985). Axiom 5 (Expansion - γ) For any collection A Ω X such that A is a choice problem, if x c(a) for every A A, then x c( A). If some alternative is chosen over all choice problems in a collection, then it must also be chosen in their union, provided that the union is itself a choice problem. Axiom 6 (Revealed Mutual Comparability - RMC) For every A Ω X such that there exists x X with c({x, y}) = 1 for every y A, we have c(b) A = c(a), for all B Ω X such that A B and c(b) A. When there exists an alternative x X such that c({x, y}) = 1 for every y A, one can, in some sense, infer that all elements of A belong to the same class of objects, since they are all strictly comparable to a common alternative. The RMC axiom then imposes that a WARP-like property holds when we compare the choices from A with the choices from choice problems larger than A. As it turns out, (α), (γ) and RMC together give us a full characterization of choice by disjoint categories. We state this formally below. Theorem 3 Let (X, Ω X ) be a choice space and c : Ω X 2 X any choice correspondence on Ω X. Then, c satisfies (α), (γ) and RMC if, and only if, there exists a preorder X X and a partition S of X such that is complete inside every S S and, for any A Ω X, c(a) = max(a S, ). S S 5 Relation to Other Models 5.1 Categorization and Pseudo-rationalization We say that a choice correspondence c is pseudo-rationalizable if there exists a collection of complete preorders such that, for any choice problem A, c chooses the best elements from each of these preorders. More formally, we have the following definition. Definition 2 (Pseudo-rationalization) A choice correspondence c on a choice field (X, Ω X ) admits a representation by pseudo-rationalization if there exists a collection R of complete preorders on X such that, for any choice problem A Ω X, c(a) = R max(a, ). Pseudo-rationalizable choice correspondences, over a finite choice space, were axiomatized by Aizerman and Malishevski (1981) (see also Moulin (1985)). It turns out that, in such choice spaces, pseudo-rationalizability is exactly characterized by the (α) and AA postulates. Therefore, Theorem 2 implies that, in a finite choice space, the existence of 7

8 a representation by categorization implies the existence of a pseudo-rational representation. Moreover, as the following example shows, the Acyclicity axiom is not redundant, which means that pseudo-rationalizability is indeed a strictly more general concept than representation by categorization. Example 2 Let X = {x, y, z, w} and consider a choice correspondence c pseudo-rationalized by the linear orders y 1 x 1 z 1 w and w 2 z 2 x 2 y. Since x c({x, y}), x c({x, z}), but x / c({x, y, z}), we have yp x and zp x. On the other hand, since z c({x, z}), z c({z, w}), but z / c({x, z, w}), we also have wp z and xp z, which violates Acyclicity. Therefore, c does not have a representation by categories. Although we are not aware of any axiomatization of pseudo-rationalizable choice correspondences for general choice spaces, we can still show that, in fact, this is true in general. Consider the following, not so basic, postulate: Axiom 7 (Preference Maximization Compatibility (PMC)) For all A Ω X and every x c(a), there exists an acyclic relation A,x such that x A,x y for every y A \ {x} and, for any other choice problem B, max(b, A,x ) c(b). We can prove the following result: Theorem 4 Let (X, Ω X ) be any choice space. A choice correspondence c : Ω X 2 X satisfies (α) and PMC if, and only if, it admits a representation by pseudo-rationalization. We can also prove the following observation: Lemma 2 Let (X, Ω X ) be any choice space. If a choice correspondence c : Ω X satisfies (α) and Dominance, then it satisfies PMC. 2 X It is now clear that any choice correspondence that admits a representation by categorization is pseudo-rationalizable. Formally, we have the following: Corollary 1 Let (X, Ω X ) be any choice space. If a choice correspondence c : Ω X 2 X admits a representation by categorization, then c is pseudo-rationalizable. 5.2 Maximization of incomplete preferences and categorization Let (X, Ω X ) be an arbitrary choice space and consider any (possibly incomplete) preference relation on X. If c is a choice correspondence on (X, Ω X ) such that c(a) = max(a, ) for every A Ω X, we say that c has a representation by the maximization of the incomplete preference. Choice correspondences that maximize incomplete preferences were studied by Eliaz and Ok (2006). Suppose now that a choice correspondence c maximizes an incomplete preference relation. It is easy to see that c satisfies the Dominance postulate with the strict part of being the acyclic relation that appears in that property. Since it is also clear that c satisfies (α), Theorem 1 implies that c has a representation by categorization. Formally: Theorem 5 Let (X, Ω X ) be any choice space. If a choice correspondence c : Ω X 2 X admits a representation by the maximization of a (possibly incomplete) preference relation, then c admits a representation by categorization. 8

9 It is easily checked that the converse to Theorem 5 is not true. With effect, as Example 1 shows, a representation by categories does not necessarily satisfy (γ), which is a necessary condition for a representation by the maximization of incomplete preferences. Therefore, our more general model of choice with categories actually generalizes the maximization of incomplete preferences, in the sense that the former can explain all choice behaviour explained by the latter, but not conversely. Suppose now that a choice correspondence c admits a representation by a categorization S in which the categories are disjoint, and the preference relation is given by. Define the binary relation ˆ X X by x ˆ y if, and only if, x y and there exists S S with x, y S. It is easy to see that ˆ is a preference relation and that c maximizes ˆ. This shows that representations by categorization with disjoint categories are particular cases of the maximization of incomplete preferences. Formally: Theorem 6 Let (X, Ω X ) be any choice space. If a choice correspondence c : Ω X 2 X admits a representation by categorization with disjoint categories, then c admits a representation by the maximization of a (possibly incomplete) preference relation. 5.3 Categorization and the decomposition of incomplete preferences Let X be any set and consider a (possibly incomplete) preference relation on X. Gorno (2015) shows that can be decomposed into a set of local preferences which are complete in their respective domains, and this is the content of the next theorem. Theorem 7 (Gorno (2015)) Let be a (possibly incomplete) preference relation on an arbitrary set X. Then there exists a collection D of subsets of X such that: (i) is complete on D for every D D; (ii) for every D D and y X \ D, there exists x D such that x and y are incomparable; (iii) = D D D. 8 Now fix a subset A of X. It is clear that if x max(a, ), then x max(a D, ) for every D D with x D. Conversely, suppose that x A, but there exists y A with y x. By (iii), there must exist D D such that x, y D. For such D, it is clear that x / max(a D, ). This suggests that we can give the following interpretation for the maximization of an incomplete preference procedure. First, the individual divides the world into categories such that two elements that belong to a common category are always comparable. Second, like in the representation in Theorem 1, she identifies the best elements in each category. Differently from the representation in Theorem 1, however, she refines her choices by eliminating from the choice set the alternatives that, although best with respect to some category, are strictly worse than some alternative in another category. This discussion can be summarized by the following result: 8 Theorem 1 in Gorno (2015) shows that D satisfies three properties in addition to the ones listed above, but they are not relevant for the discussion in this section. 9

10 Theorem 8 Let be a (possibly incomplete) preference relation on an arbitrary set X. Then there exists a collection D of subsets of X such that conditions (i), (ii) and (iii) are satisfied and, for every A X, max(a, ) = {x A : x max(a D, ) for every D D with x D} We note that if it weren t for condition (ii), Theorem 8 would be trivial, since we could simply define D by D := {{x, y} : x y}. It is also easily seen that, although we do not impose it in the statement of Theorem 3, we can assume, without loss of generality, that the pair (, S) in that theorem satisfies (ii). This suggests that we can think of the representation by categorization with disjoint categories as the particular case of the decomposition in Theorem 8 when D is a partition. In fact, such a case is characterized by the transitivity of the comparability relation induced by. To see that, consider the following postulate on : Axiom 8 (Transitive Comparability) A binary relation X X satisfies Transitive Comparability if x y and y z together imply x z. We can now show the following: Theorem 9 A preference relation on an arbitrary set X satisfies Transitive Comparability if, and only if, there exists a partition D of X such that properties (i), (ii) and (iii) are satisfied and, for every A X, max(a, ) = D D max(a D, ). 6 Conclusion We have presented a pure model of rational choice with categories. Categorization is an universal cognitive mechanism, and its importance for human understanding and decision making is widely recognized in many fields, such as psychology, philosophy and linguistics. More recently, some researchers in economics have also taken interest in this phenomenon, notably Mullainathan et al. (2008) and Manzini and Mariotti (2012). However, their models are quite different from our own. Mullainathan et al. (2008) focuses on the effects of categorization - or, as they call it, coarse thinking - on Bayesian updating, and apply the model to the study of uninformative persuasion. On the other hand, Manzini and Mariotti (2012) develop a pure theory of choice in the presence of categorization, but assume that the individual chooses both between and within categories. The representation put forth in this paper gives an accurate description of choices inside categories, but assumes that some external factor, inaccessible to the modeller, is responsible for the agent s choice of a category in any given situation. Such an approach has two major advantages: (i) from an empirical standpoint, comparisons among categories are known to be complicated, and it is not clear a stable preference among categories should exist, and (ii) it can account for some major violations of full rationality, such as some forms of menu effects. While leaving the method of choice between categories as an open question, we encourage future research on the subject. Also, our model fits nicely within the existing rational choice framework. It is a particular case of pseudo-rationalization, a representation well known in the theory of social 10

11 pseudo-rationality general categories incomplete preferences disjoint categories rational model Figure 1: Relation to other models choice, and at the same time generalizes the maximization of incomplete preferences, which in turn is a generalization of the model with disjoint categories. Finally, throughout the paper we mostly take categories as given and place very few restrictions on their possible structures. This allows our model to explain a wide range of behavioural patterns, but says nothing about what kinds of categorization procedures are actually undertaken in concrete situations. Although determining the process through which categories are formed is an important and interesting question, it lies beyond the scope of this paper and is indeed still very much a matter of contention among cognitive psychologists. 9 It seems, however, that the way in which people categorize is context dependent (Smith and Samuelson, 1997). That could imply that, in a rational choice context, the categorization structure would depend on the preferences of the agent. This makes the study of such structure a matter of considerable interest to decision theorists. A Proofs A.1 Proof of Theorem 1 It is easily seen that the representation implies (α) and Dominance, where the acyclic relation in the statement of Dominance is the strict part of. Conversely, suppose c satisfies (α) and Dominance for an acyclic relation. Let be any complete preorder that extends. 10 Fix any A Ω X and x c(a). Define S := {x} {y X \ A : y x and y c(b) for every B Ω X with A {y} B (A {z X : y z})}. Notice that A S = {x} and, consequently, {x} = max(a S, ). Now fix any choice problem B and suppose that y max(b S, ). We need the following claim: 9 For an overview of the the competing theories of categorization and concept formation, see for instance Heit (1997); Smith and Samuelson (1997); Shanks (1997). 10 Since is acyclic, the transitive closure of is a strict partial order that extends. Now the Szpilrajn Theorem (see Szpilrajn (1930)) guarantees that there exists a complete partial order that extends. 11

12 Claim A.1: For any z B \ A such that z y, we have that z / c(a {z}). Proof. Take any z B \ A such that z y. Since, by construction, y max(b S, ), we have that z / S. Hence, there exists a choice problem E with A {z} E (A {w X : z w}) and z / c(e). But then, if z c(a {z}), by Dominance, there must exist w with z w, but w z. This contradicts the construction of. Because of (α) and the claim above, we know that z / c(a {y, z}) for any z B \ A with z y. But then Dominance implies that y c(a B). By (α), this implies that y c(b). We have shown that, for every choice problem A and x c(a), there exists S x,a X such that {x} = max(a S x,a, ) and, for every other choice problem B, max(b S x,a, ) c(b). Let S = {S x,a X : x c(a) and A Ω X } be the collection of all such sets. Then, for every A Ω X, c(a) = S S max(a S, ). A.2 Proof of Lemma 1 Take any A, B Ω X with A B, and suppose there exists x c(a) \ c(b). Enumerate (B \ A) {x} = {y 1,..., y n }, where y 1 = x. Define the set N := {i {1,..., n 1} : x / c(a {y 1,..., y i+1 })}. Because N, there exists a smallest element i N. Notice that y i +1P x. Moreover, if y i +1 / c(a {y 1,..., y i +1}), then c(a {y 1,..., y i +1}) A {y 1,..., y i }, and it follows from AA that c(a {y 1,..., y i }) c(a {y 1,..., y i +1}). Hence x / c(a {y 1,..., y i }), a contradiction to the definition of i. It now follows from (α) that y i +1 c(a {y i +1}). A.3 Proof of Theorem 3 It is easily seen that the representation implies the three axioms. Conversely, suppose that c is a choice correspondence that satisfies (α), (γ) and RMC. Define the binary relation X X by x y if, and only if, x c({x, y}) and there exists z X such that c({x, z}) = c({y, z}) = 1. We note that, for any distinct x, y X, x y if, and only if, {x} = c({x, y}). Given that, it is easy to see that (α) and (γ) imply that c(a) = max(a, ) for every A Ω X. We need the following claim. Claim A.2: The relation is a preorder. Proof. It is clear that is reflexive, so we only have to show that it is transitive. Suppose first that x, y, z X are such that x y and y z. That is, {x} = c({x, y}) and y = c({y, z}). By (α), we learn that {x} = c({x, y, z}). Now RMC implies that {x} = c({x, y, z}) {x, z} = c({x, z}). That is, x z. Note that this observation implies that whenever x y, there exists z X such that either x z and y z, or z x and z y. Suppose now that x, y, z X are such that x y and y z. By RMC, if z c({x, y, z}), then we would have y c({x, y, z}), which cannot happen, because of (α). We conclude that {x} = c({x, y, z}). Now (γ) implies that {x} = c({x, z}) and, consequently, x z. Now suppose that x y and y z for some distinct x, y, z X. If there exists w X such that w x and w y, it must also be the case that w z. But then, 12

13 z c({x, z}) would imply that z x and our previous observation would give us that y x. We conclude that, in such a case, {x} = c({x, z}) and, therefore, x z. If, on the other hand, there exists w X such that x w and y w, then, since y z, we know that z and w are -comparable. If w z, then we have already seen that x w implies x z. If z w, then (α) and RMC imply that z / c({x, y, z}) and c({x, y, z}) {x, z} = c({x, z}) = {x}. Again, we learn that x z. Finally, suppose that x, y, z are distinct alternatives such that x y and y z. If there exists w X such that w x and w y, then we have already seen that w z. Consequently, RMC implies that c({x, y, z}) = {x, y, z} and c({x, z}) = c({x, y, z}) {x, z} = {x, z}. We learn that x z. If there exists w X with x w and y w, then our previous observations imply that z w. A similar reasoning to the one above then shows that x z. To complete the proof of the theorem, we observe that is comparability-transitive. To see that, suppose x, y, z X are such that x is -comparable to y and y is comparable to z. The only cases that are not immediate consequences of the transitivity of are when x y and z y, or y x and y z. In both cases, the definition of guarantees that x and z are -comparable. The theorem is then a direct implication of Theorem 9 and the fact that c(a) = max(a, ) for every choice problem A Ω X. A.4 Proof of Theorem 4 Suppose first that c admits a representation by pseudo-rationalization for some collection of complete preorders R. It is clear that c satisfies (α). Now, fix A Ω X and x c(a), and pick any complete preorder R with x max(a, ). Define the binary relation A,x X X by y A,x z if, and only if, y = x, z x and x z, or y z. It is easy to see that A,x is an acyclic relation such that x A,x y for every y A \ {x}, and, for every choice problem B, max(b, A,x ) max(b, ) c(b). This shows that c satisfies PMC Conversely, suppose that c satisfies (α) and PMC. For every choice problem A and every x c(a), let A,x be a complete preorder that extends A,x. Since A,x extends A,x, we have {x} = max(a, A,x ) and max(b, A,x ) max(b, A,x ) for every choice problem B. Define R by R := { A,x : A Ω X and x c(a)}. It is clear that R is a pseudo-rational representation of c. A.5 Proof of Lemma 2 Suppose that c satisfies (α) and Dominance, for some acyclic relation. Fix a choice problem A and some x c(a). Define the set à by à := (A \ {x}) {y X : y / c(a {y})}. Now define the relation A,x by y A,x z if, and only if, y / à and z Ã, or y, z à and y z, or y, z / à and y z. Let s first show that A,x is acyclic. For that, suppose that y 1 A,x y 2 A,x A,x y n 1 A,x y n. If y i / à and y i+1 à for some i n 1, then it is clear that y 1 / à and y n Ã. Consequently, we do not have y n A,x y 1. If this does not happen, then we have y 1 y 2 y n 1 y n. Since is acyclic, we do not have y n y 1 and, again, we do not have y n A,x y 1. This shows that A,x is acyclic. Moreover, it is clear that x A,x y for every y A \ {x}. Finally, fix a choice problem B and suppose that y / c(b). Since y c({y}), Dominance guarantees that there exists z B such that z y. If y Ã, this implies that z A,x y. Suppose, thus, that y / Ã. By (α), we know that y / c(a B). Since y c(a {y}), Dominance 13

14 implies that there exists z B \ A such that z y and z c(a {y, z}). By (α), this implies that z Ã. Consequently, we get that z A,x y. This shows that, for every choice problem B, max(b, A,x ) c(b). A.6 Proof of Theorem 9 It is clear that if there exists a partition D of X such that (i), (ii) and (iii) are satisfied,then satisfies Transitive Comparability. Conversely, suppose that is a preference relation on X that satisfies Transitive Comparability. By Theorem 8, there exists a collection D of subsets of X such that conditions (i), (ii) and (iii) are satisfied and, for every A X, max(a, ) = {x A : x max(a D, ) for every D D with x D} Thus, we will be done if we can show that D is a partition. To see that, assume that there exists distinct D 1, D 2 D and x X such that x D 1 D 2. Since D 1 and D 2 are distinct, we can assume, without loss of generality, that there exists y D 1 \ D 2. By (ii), there exists z D 2 such that y and z are incomparable. Since both y and z are comparable to x, this violates Transitive Comparability. We conclude that D is a partition. References Aizerman, M. A. and A. V. Malishevski (1981). General theory of best variants choice: Some aspects. IEEE Transactions on Automatic Control 26 (5), Chernoff, H. (1954). Rational selection of decision functions. Econometrica 22 (4), Eliaz, K. and E. Ok (2006, July). Indifference or indecisiveness? Choice-theoretic foundations of incomplete preferences. Games and Economic Behavior 56 (1), Gorno, L. (2015). On the structure of incomplete preferences. Hahn, U. and N. Chater (1997). Concepts and Similarity. In Knowledge, concepts and categories. Studies in cognition., pp Heit, E. (1997). Knowledge and Concept Learning. In Knowledge, concepts and categories. Studies in cognition., pp Komatsu, L. K. (1992). Recent views of conceptual structure. Psychological Bulletin 112 (3), Manzini, P. and M. Mariotti (2012). Categorize then choose: Boundedly rational choice and welfare. Journal of the European Economic Association 10, Markman, E. M. (1990). Constraints Children Place on Word Meanings. Cognitive Science 14 (1590), Markman, E. M., J. L. Wasow, and M. B. Hansen (2003). Use of the mutual exclusivity assumption by young word learners. 14

15 Medin, D. L. and C. Aguilar (1999). Categorization. Moulin, H. (1985). Choice functions over a finite set: A summary. Social Choice and Welfare 2, Mullainathan, S., J. Schwartzstein, and A. Shleifer (2008). Coarse Thinking and Persuasion. The Quarterly Journal of Economics 123 (2), Schwartz, B. (2000). Self-determination. The tyranny of freedom. The American psychologist 55 (1), Sen, A. (1971). Choice functions and revealed preference. Review of Economic Studies 38. Shanks, D. R. (1997). Distributed Representations and Implicit Knowledge: A Brief Introduction. In Knowledge, concepts and categories. Studies in cognition., pp Smith, E. E. and D. L. Medin (1981). Categories and concepts. Smith, E. E., A. L. Patalano, and J. Jonides (1998). Alternative strategies of categorization. Cognition 65, Smith, L. B. and L. K. Samuelson (1997). Perceiving and Remembering: Category Stability, Variability and Development. In Knowledge, concepts and categories. Studies in cognition., pp Szpilrajn, E. (1930). Sur l extension de l ordre partiel. Fundamenta Mathematicae 16 (1),

Revealed Reversals of Preferences

Revealed Reversals of Preferences Revealed Reversals of Preferences Houy Nicolas October 5, 2009 Abstract We weaken the implicit assumption of rational choice theory that imposes that preferences do not depend on the choice set. We concentrate

More information

Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity

Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity Analyse & Kritik 29/2007 ( c Lucius & Lucius, Stuttgart) p. 163 187 Walter Bossert/Kotaro Suzumura Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity Abstract: Although the theory of greatest-element rationalizability

More information

Utility Representation of Lower Separable Preferences

Utility Representation of Lower Separable Preferences Utility Representation of Lower Separable Preferences Özgür Yılmaz June 2008 Abstract Topological separability is crucial for the utility representation of a complete preference relation. When preferences

More information

Axiomatic Decision Theory

Axiomatic Decision Theory Decision Theory Decision theory is about making choices It has a normative aspect what rational people should do... and a descriptive aspect what people do do Not surprisingly, it s been studied by economists,

More information

Preference, Choice and Utility

Preference, Choice and Utility Preference, Choice and Utility Eric Pacuit January 2, 205 Relations Suppose that X is a non-empty set. The set X X is the cross-product of X with itself. That is, it is the set of all pairs of elements

More information

Rationality and solutions to nonconvex bargaining problems: rationalizability and Nash solutions 1

Rationality and solutions to nonconvex bargaining problems: rationalizability and Nash solutions 1 Rationality and solutions to nonconvex bargaining problems: rationalizability and Nash solutions 1 Yongsheng Xu Department of Economics Andrew Young School of Policy Studies Georgia State University, Atlanta,

More information

Lexicographic Choice under Variable Capacity Constraints

Lexicographic Choice under Variable Capacity Constraints Lexicographic Choice under Variable Capacity Constraints Battal Doğan Serhat Doğan Kemal Yıldız May 14, 2017 Abstract In several matching markets, in order to achieve diversity, agents priorities are allowed

More information

Norm-Constrained Choices

Norm-Constrained Choices Analyse & Kritik 29/2007 ( c Lucius & Lucius, Stuttgart) p. 329 339 Yongsheng Xu Norm-Constrained Choices Abstract: This paper develops a general and unified framework to discuss individual choice behaviors

More information

Choosing the two finalists

Choosing the two finalists Choosing the two finalists Economic Theory ISSN 0938-2259 Volume 46 Number 2 Econ Theory (2010) 46:211-219 DOI 10.1007/ s00199-009-0516-3 1 23 Your article is protected by copyright and all rights are

More information

Individual Rationality in Collective Choice

Individual Rationality in Collective Choice Individual Rationality in Collective Choice Hiroki Nishimura February 21, 2014 Abstract This paper studies the rationality of an individual player in sequential games of perfect information played with

More information

Choice, Consideration Sets and Attribute Filters

Choice, Consideration Sets and Attribute Filters Choice, Consideration Sets and Attribute Filters Mert Kimya Brown University, Department of Economics, 64 Waterman St, Providence RI 02912 USA. October 6, 2015 Abstract It is well known that decision makers

More information

Rationalization of Collective Choice Functions by Games with Perfect Information. Yongsheng Xu

Rationalization of Collective Choice Functions by Games with Perfect Information. Yongsheng Xu Rationalization of Collective Choice Functions by Games with Perfect Information by Yongsheng Xu Department of Economics, Andrew Young School of Policy Studies Georgia State University, Atlanta, GA 30303

More information

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM Discussion Papers in Economics Discussion Paper No. 0/06 CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY by Indraneel Dasgupta July 00 DP 0/06 ISSN 1360-438 UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM

More information

Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility*

Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility* Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility* Francis C. Chu and Joseph Y. Halpern Department of Computer Science Cornell University Ithaca, NY 14853, U.S.A. Email:

More information

Dominance and Admissibility without Priors

Dominance and Admissibility without Priors Dominance and Admissibility without Priors Jörg Stoye Cornell University September 14, 2011 Abstract This note axiomatizes the incomplete preference ordering that reflects statewise dominance with respect

More information

Choosing the Two Finalists

Choosing the Two Finalists Choosing the Two Finalists K r Eliaz Department of Economics, Brown University Michael Richter Department of Economics, New York University Ariel Rubinstein University of Tel Aviv Cafés and Department

More information

Individual decision-making under certainty

Individual decision-making under certainty Individual decision-making under certainty Objects of inquiry Our study begins with individual decision-making under certainty Items of interest include: Feasible set Objective function (Feasible set R)

More information

Partially Dominant Choice

Partially Dominant Choice Partially Dominant Choice Georgios Gerasimou February 19, 2015 Abstract This paper proposes and analyzes a model of context-dependent choice with stable but incomplete preferences that is based on the

More information

Bounded Rationality and Limited Datasets: Testable Implications, Identifiability, and Out-of-Sample Prediction

Bounded Rationality and Limited Datasets: Testable Implications, Identifiability, and Out-of-Sample Prediction Bounded Rationality and Limited Datasets: Testable Implications, Identifiability, and Out-of-Sample Prediction Geoffroy de Clippel Brown University Kareen Rozen Yale University March 2012 Abstract Theories

More information

13 Social choice B = 2 X X. is the collection of all binary relations on X. R = { X X : is complete and transitive}

13 Social choice B = 2 X X. is the collection of all binary relations on X. R = { X X : is complete and transitive} 13 Social choice So far, all of our models involved a single decision maker. An important, perhaps the important, question for economics is whether the desires and wants of various agents can be rationally

More information

Suzumura-consistent relations: an overview

Suzumura-consistent relations: an overview Suzumura-consistent relations: an overview Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ University of Montreal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7 Canada walter.bossert@videotron.ca

More information

QUASI-PREFERENCE: CHOICE ON PARTIALLY ORDERED SETS. Contents

QUASI-PREFERENCE: CHOICE ON PARTIALLY ORDERED SETS. Contents QUASI-PREFERENCE: CHOICE ON PARTIALLY ORDERED SETS ZEFENG CHEN Abstract. A preference relation is a total order on a finite set and a quasipreference relation is a partial order. This paper first introduces

More information

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics. Contraction consistent stochastic choice correspondence

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics. Contraction consistent stochastic choice correspondence UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHM Discussion Papers in Economics Discussion Paper No. 08/04 Contraction consistent stochastic choice correspondence y Indraneel Dasgupta June 2008 2008 DP 08/04 Contraction consistent

More information

Coalitionally strategyproof functions depend only on the most-preferred alternatives.

Coalitionally strategyproof functions depend only on the most-preferred alternatives. Coalitionally strategyproof functions depend only on the most-preferred alternatives. H. Reiju Mihara reiju@ec.kagawa-u.ac.jp Economics, Kagawa University, Takamatsu, 760-8523, Japan April, 1999 [Social

More information

Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1)

Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1) Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1) Tsun-Feng Chiang* *School of Economics, Henan University, Kaifeng, China November 2, 2014 1 / 28 Primitive Notions 1.1 Primitive Notions Consumer

More information

Static Decision Theory Under Certainty

Static Decision Theory Under Certainty Static Decision Theory Under Certainty Larry Blume September 22, 2010 1 basics A set of objects X An individual is asked to express preferences among the objects, or to make choices from subsets of X.

More information

Talking Freedom of Choice Seriously

Talking Freedom of Choice Seriously Talking Freedom of Choice Seriously Susumu Cato January 17, 2006 Abstract In actual life, we face the opportunity of many choices, from that opportunity set, we have to choose from different alternatives.

More information

Choice, Consideration Sets and Attribute Filters

Choice, Consideration Sets and Attribute Filters Choice, Consideration Sets and Attribute Filters Mert Kimya Koç University, Department of Economics, Rumeli Feneri Yolu, Sarıyer 34450, Istanbul, Turkey December 28, 2017 Abstract It is well known that

More information

Regular Choice and the Weak Axiom of Stochastic Revealed Preference

Regular Choice and the Weak Axiom of Stochastic Revealed Preference Regular Choice and the Weak xiom of Stochastic Revealed Preference Indraneel Dasgupta School of Economics, University of Nottingham, UK. and Prasanta K. Pattanaik Department of Economics, University of

More information

Single-plateaued choice

Single-plateaued choice Single-plateaued choice Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ, University of Montreal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7, Canada walter.bossert@umontreal.ca and Hans Peters

More information

Definitions: A binary relation R on a set X is (a) reflexive if x X : xrx; (f) asymmetric if x, x X : [x Rx xr c x ]

Definitions: A binary relation R on a set X is (a) reflexive if x X : xrx; (f) asymmetric if x, x X : [x Rx xr c x ] Binary Relations Definition: A binary relation between two sets X and Y (or between the elements of X and Y ) is a subset of X Y i.e., is a set of ordered pairs (x, y) X Y. If R is a relation between X

More information

Tree sets. Reinhard Diestel

Tree sets. Reinhard Diestel 1 Tree sets Reinhard Diestel Abstract We study an abstract notion of tree structure which generalizes treedecompositions of graphs and matroids. Unlike tree-decompositions, which are too closely linked

More information

Arrow s Paradox. Prerna Nadathur. January 1, 2010

Arrow s Paradox. Prerna Nadathur. January 1, 2010 Arrow s Paradox Prerna Nadathur January 1, 2010 Abstract In this paper, we examine the problem of a ranked voting system and introduce Kenneth Arrow s impossibility theorem (1951). We provide a proof sketch

More information

Krivine s Intuitionistic Proof of Classical Completeness (for countable languages)

Krivine s Intuitionistic Proof of Classical Completeness (for countable languages) Krivine s Intuitionistic Proof of Classical Completeness (for countable languages) Berardi Stefano Valentini Silvio Dip. Informatica Dip. Mat. Pura ed Applicata Univ. Torino Univ. Padova c.so Svizzera

More information

Expected utility without full transitivity

Expected utility without full transitivity Expected utility without full transitivity Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ University of Montreal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7 Canada FAX: (+1 514) 343 7221 e-mail:

More information

Representation Theorems

Representation Theorems Representation Theorems Mark Dean Lecture Notes for Fall 2017 PhD Class in Behavioral Economics - Columbia University 1 Introduction A key set of tools that we are going to make use of in this course are

More information

Locally Complete Path Independent Choice Functions and Their Lattices Mark R. Johnson and Richard A. Dean Addresses: Abstract

Locally Complete Path Independent Choice Functions and Their Lattices Mark R. Johnson and Richard A. Dean Addresses: Abstract Locally Complete Path Independent Choice Functions and Their Lattices Mark R. Johnson and Richard A. Dean Addresses: Mark R. Johnson Richard A. Dean A. B. Freeman School of Business Department of Mathematics

More information

A Note on Incompleteness, Transitivity and Suzumura Consistency

A Note on Incompleteness, Transitivity and Suzumura Consistency A Note on Incompleteness, Transitivity and Suzumura Consistency Richard Bradley Department of Philosophy, Logic and Scientific Method London School of Economics and Political Science February 24, 2015

More information

Isomorphisms between pattern classes

Isomorphisms between pattern classes Journal of Combinatorics olume 0, Number 0, 1 8, 0000 Isomorphisms between pattern classes M. H. Albert, M. D. Atkinson and Anders Claesson Isomorphisms φ : A B between pattern classes are considered.

More information

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 10 Apr 2018

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 10 Apr 2018 Individual and Group Stability in Neutral Restrictions of Hedonic Games Warut Suksompong Department of Computer Science, Stanford University 353 Serra Mall, Stanford, CA 94305, USA warut@cs.stanford.edu

More information

This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices from different menus.

This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices from different menus. Testing Revealed Preference Theory, I: Methodology The revealed preference theory developed last time applied to a single agent. This corresponds to a within-subject experiment: see same subject make choices

More information

An Equivalence result in School Choice

An Equivalence result in School Choice An Equivalence result in School Choice Jay Sethuraman May 2009 Abstract The main result of the paper is a proof of the equivalence of single and multiple lottery mechanisms for the problem of allocating

More information

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes These notes form a brief summary of what has been covered during the lectures. All the definitions must be memorized and understood. Statements

More information

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces Part III 10 Topological Space Basics Topological Spaces Using the metric space results above as motivation we will axiomatize the notion of being an open set to more general settings. Definition 10.1.

More information

Relations. Relations. Definition. Let A and B be sets.

Relations. Relations. Definition. Let A and B be sets. Relations Relations. Definition. Let A and B be sets. A relation R from A to B is a subset R A B. If a A and b B, we write a R b if (a, b) R, and a /R b if (a, b) / R. A relation from A to A is called

More information

On the Impossibility of Certain Ranking Functions

On the Impossibility of Certain Ranking Functions On the Impossibility of Certain Ranking Functions Jin-Yi Cai Abstract Suppose all the individuals in a field are linearly ordered. Groups of individuals form teams. Is there a perfect ranking function

More information

Asymmetric Dominance, Deferral and Status Quo Bias in a Theory of Choice with Incomplete Preferences

Asymmetric Dominance, Deferral and Status Quo Bias in a Theory of Choice with Incomplete Preferences MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive Asymmetric Dominance, Deferral and Status Quo Bias in a Theory of Choice with Incomplete Preferences Georgios Gerasimou 7. July 2012 Online at http://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/40097/

More information

Sufficient Conditions for Weak Group-Strategy-Proofness

Sufficient Conditions for Weak Group-Strategy-Proofness Sufficient Conditions for Weak Group-Strategy-Proofness T.C.A. Madhav Raghavan 31 July, 2014 Abstract In this note we study group-strategy-proofness, which is the extension of strategy-proofness to groups

More information

TitleList-based decision problems Author(s) Dimitrov, Dinko; Mukherjee, Saptars Citation Issue 2013-03 Date Type Technical Report Text Version publisher URL http://hdl.handle.net/10086/25504 Right Hitotsubashi

More information

On the Chacteristic Numbers of Voting Games

On the Chacteristic Numbers of Voting Games On the Chacteristic Numbers of Voting Games MATHIEU MARTIN THEMA, Departments of Economics Université de Cergy Pontoise, 33 Boulevard du Port, 95011 Cergy Pontoise cedex, France. e-mail: mathieu.martin@eco.u-cergy.fr

More information

Set-Rationalizable Choice and Self-Stability

Set-Rationalizable Choice and Self-Stability Set-Rationalizable Choice and Self-Stability Felix Brandt and Paul Harrenstein Technische Universität München 85748 Garching bei München, Germany {brandtf,harrenst}@in.tum.de Rationalizability and similar

More information

Notes on the Dual Ramsey Theorem

Notes on the Dual Ramsey Theorem Notes on the Dual Ramsey Theorem Reed Solomon July 29, 2010 1 Partitions and infinite variable words The goal of these notes is to give a proof of the Dual Ramsey Theorem. This theorem was first proved

More information

Revealed Preferences and Utility Functions

Revealed Preferences and Utility Functions Revealed Preferences and Utility Functions Lecture 2, 1 September Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Outline 1 Weak Axiom of Revealed Preference 2 Equivalence between Axioms and Rationalizable Choices. 3 An Application:

More information

PETER A. CHOLAK, PETER GERDES, AND KAREN LANGE

PETER A. CHOLAK, PETER GERDES, AND KAREN LANGE D-MAXIMAL SETS PETER A. CHOLAK, PETER GERDES, AND KAREN LANGE Abstract. Soare [23] proved that the maximal sets form an orbit in E. We consider here D-maximal sets, generalizations of maximal sets introduced

More information

THE EMPIRICAL IMPLICATIONS OF PRIVACY-AWARE CHOICE

THE EMPIRICAL IMPLICATIONS OF PRIVACY-AWARE CHOICE THE EMPIRICAL IMPLICATIONS OF PRIVACY-AWARE CHOICE RACHEL CUMMINGS, FEDERICO ECHENIQUE, AND ADAM WIERMAN Abstract. This paper initiates the study of the testable implications of choice data in settings

More information

Preferences for Randomization and Anticipation

Preferences for Randomization and Anticipation Preferences for Randomization and Anticipation Yosuke Hashidate Abstract In decision theory, it is not generally postulated that decision makers randomize their choices. In contrast, in real life, even

More information

Existence of Order-Preserving Functions for Nontotal Fuzzy Preference Relations under Decisiveness

Existence of Order-Preserving Functions for Nontotal Fuzzy Preference Relations under Decisiveness axioms Article Existence of Order-Preserving Functions for Nontotal Fuzzy Preference elations under Decisiveness Paolo Bevilacqua 1 ID, Gianni Bosi 2, *, ID and Magalì Zuanon 3 1 Dipartimento di Ingegneria

More information

Realization Plans for Extensive Form Games without Perfect Recall

Realization Plans for Extensive Form Games without Perfect Recall Realization Plans for Extensive Form Games without Perfect Recall Richard E. Stearns Department of Computer Science University at Albany - SUNY Albany, NY 12222 April 13, 2015 Abstract Given a game in

More information

THE STRUCTURE OF 3-CONNECTED MATROIDS OF PATH WIDTH THREE

THE STRUCTURE OF 3-CONNECTED MATROIDS OF PATH WIDTH THREE THE STRUCTURE OF 3-CONNECTED MATROIDS OF PATH WIDTH THREE RHIANNON HALL, JAMES OXLEY, AND CHARLES SEMPLE Abstract. A 3-connected matroid M is sequential or has path width 3 if its ground set E(M) has a

More information

Monotonic models and cycles

Monotonic models and cycles Int J Game Theory DOI 10.1007/s00182-013-0385-7 Monotonic models and cycles José Alvaro Rodrigues-Neto Accepted: 16 May 2013 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2013 Abstract A partitional model of knowledge

More information

Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: a generalization of May s theorem to many alternatives

Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: a generalization of May s theorem to many alternatives Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: a generalization of May s theorem to many alternatives Sean Horan, Martin J. Osborne, and M. Remzi Sanver December 24, 2018 Abstract May

More information

A Systematic Approach to the Construction of Non-empty Choice Sets

A Systematic Approach to the Construction of Non-empty Choice Sets A Systematic Approach to the Construction of Non-empty Choice Sets John Duggan Department of Political Science and Department of Economics University of Rochester May 17, 2004 Abstract Suppose a strict

More information

Bounded Rationality and Limited Datasets

Bounded Rationality and Limited Datasets Bounded Rationality and Limited Datasets Geoffroy de Clippel Brown University Kareen Rozen Yale University May 2014 Abstract Theories of bounded rationality are typically characterized over an exhaustive

More information

Bayesian consistent prior selection

Bayesian consistent prior selection Bayesian consistent prior selection Christopher P. Chambers and Takashi Hayashi August 2005 Abstract A subjective expected utility agent is given information about the state of the world in the form of

More information

Expected utility without full transitivity

Expected utility without full transitivity Expected utility without full transitivity Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ University of Montreal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7 Canada FAX: (+1 514) 343 7221 e-mail:

More information

Background on Coherent Systems

Background on Coherent Systems 2 Background on Coherent Systems 2.1 Basic Ideas We will use the term system quite freely and regularly, even though it will remain an undefined term throughout this monograph. As we all have some experience

More information

Constitutional Rights and Pareto Efficiency

Constitutional Rights and Pareto Efficiency Journal of Economic and Social Research, 1 (1) 1999, 109-117 Constitutional Rights and Pareto Efficiency Ahmet Kara 1 Abstract. This paper presents a sufficient condition under which constitutional rights

More information

A Simplified Test for Preference Rationality of Two-Commodity Choice

A Simplified Test for Preference Rationality of Two-Commodity Choice A Simplified Test for Preference Rationality of Two-Commodity Choice Samiran Banerjee and James H. Murphy December 9, 2004 Abstract We provide a simplified test to determine if choice data from a two-commodity

More information

THE SURE-THING PRINCIPLE AND P2

THE SURE-THING PRINCIPLE AND P2 Economics Letters, 159: 221 223, 2017 DOI 10.1016/j.econlet.2017.07.027 THE SURE-THING PRINCIPLE AND P2 YANG LIU Abstract. This paper offers a fine analysis of different versions of the well known sure-thing

More information

Introductory Analysis I Fall 2014 Homework #5 Solutions

Introductory Analysis I Fall 2014 Homework #5 Solutions Introductory Analysis I Fall 2014 Homework #5 Solutions 6. Let M be a metric space, let C D M. Now we can think of C as a subset of the metric space M or as a subspace of the metric space D (D being a

More information

Revealed Attention. Y. Masatlioglu D. Nakajima E. Ozbay. Jan 2011

Revealed Attention. Y. Masatlioglu D. Nakajima E. Ozbay. Jan 2011 Revealed Attention Y. Masatlioglu D. Nakajima E. Ozbay Jan 2011 Limited Attention People do not pay attention to all products because Information Overload, Unawareness, Or both. Breakfast Cereal Breakfast

More information

CHAPTER 7. Connectedness

CHAPTER 7. Connectedness CHAPTER 7 Connectedness 7.1. Connected topological spaces Definition 7.1. A topological space (X, T X ) is said to be connected if there is no continuous surjection f : X {0, 1} where the two point set

More information

Technical Results on Regular Preferences and Demand

Technical Results on Regular Preferences and Demand Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences Technical Results on Regular Preferences and Demand KC Border Revised Fall 2011; Winter 2017 Preferences For the purposes of this note, a preference relation

More information

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals 18 Andreas Gathmann 2. Prime and Maximal Ideals There are two special kinds of ideals that are of particular importance, both algebraically and geometrically: the so-called prime and maximal ideals. Let

More information

Some Background Material

Some Background Material Chapter 1 Some Background Material In the first chapter, we present a quick review of elementary - but important - material as a way of dipping our toes in the water. This chapter also introduces important

More information

Economics Bulletin, 2012, Vol. 32 No. 1 pp Introduction. 2. The preliminaries

Economics Bulletin, 2012, Vol. 32 No. 1 pp Introduction. 2. The preliminaries 1. Introduction In this paper we reconsider the problem of axiomatizing scoring rules. Early results on this problem are due to Smith (1973) and Young (1975). They characterized social welfare and social

More information

Claw-free Graphs. III. Sparse decomposition

Claw-free Graphs. III. Sparse decomposition Claw-free Graphs. III. Sparse decomposition Maria Chudnovsky 1 and Paul Seymour Princeton University, Princeton NJ 08544 October 14, 003; revised May 8, 004 1 This research was conducted while the author

More information

A Generic Bound on Cycles in Two-Player Games

A Generic Bound on Cycles in Two-Player Games A Generic Bound on Cycles in Two-Player Games David S. Ahn February 006 Abstract We provide a bound on the size of simultaneous best response cycles for generic finite two-player games. The bound shows

More information

Two-Stage-Partitional Representation and Dynamic Consistency 1

Two-Stage-Partitional Representation and Dynamic Consistency 1 Two-Stage-Partitional Representation and Dynamic Consistency 1 Suguru Ito June 5 th, 2015 Abstract In this paper, we study an individual who faces a three-period decision problem when she accepts the partitional

More information

Attribute-Based Inferences: An Axiomatic Analysis of Reference-Dependent Preferences

Attribute-Based Inferences: An Axiomatic Analysis of Reference-Dependent Preferences Attribute-Based Inferences: An Axiomatic Analysis of Reference-Dependent Preferences Yosuke Hashidate Graduate School of Economics, The University of Tokyo First Draft: January 2015 This Draft: February

More information

An analogy from Calculus: limits

An analogy from Calculus: limits COMP 250 Fall 2018 35 - big O Nov. 30, 2018 We have seen several algorithms in the course, and we have loosely characterized their runtimes in terms of the size n of the input. We say that the algorithm

More information

A Comprehensive Approach to Revealed Preference Theory

A Comprehensive Approach to Revealed Preference Theory A Comprehensive Approach to Revealed Preference Theory Hiroki Nishimura Efe A. Ok John K.-H. Quah July 11, 2016 Abstract We develop a version of Afriat s Theorem that is applicable to a variety of choice

More information

LIMITED ATTENTION AND STATUS QUO BIAS

LIMITED ATTENTION AND STATUS QUO BIAS LIMITED ATTENTION AND STATUS QUO BIAS Mark Dean Özgür Kıbrıs Yusufcan Masatlioglu January 16, 2016 Abstract We introduce and axiomatically characterize a model of status quo bias in which the status quo

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago December 2015 Abstract Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970) represent random

More information

Linear Algebra (part 1) : Vector Spaces (by Evan Dummit, 2017, v. 1.07) 1.1 The Formal Denition of a Vector Space

Linear Algebra (part 1) : Vector Spaces (by Evan Dummit, 2017, v. 1.07) 1.1 The Formal Denition of a Vector Space Linear Algebra (part 1) : Vector Spaces (by Evan Dummit, 2017, v. 1.07) Contents 1 Vector Spaces 1 1.1 The Formal Denition of a Vector Space.................................. 1 1.2 Subspaces...................................................

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago September 2015 Abstract Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970) introduce a

More information

Intro to Economic analysis

Intro to Economic analysis Intro to Economic analysis Alberto Bisin - NYU 1 Rational Choice The central gure of economics theory is the individual decision-maker (DM). The typical example of a DM is the consumer. We shall assume

More information

Report 1 The Axiom of Choice

Report 1 The Axiom of Choice Report 1 The Axiom of Choice By Li Yu This report is a collection of the material I presented in the first round presentation of the course MATH 2002. The report focuses on the principle of recursive definition,

More information

Implementation in undominated strategies by bounded mechanisms: The Pareto Correspondence

Implementation in undominated strategies by bounded mechanisms: The Pareto Correspondence Implementation in undominated strategies by bounded mechanisms: The Pareto Correspondence Saptarshi Mukherjee Eve Ramaekers Arunava Sen September 5, 2016 Preliminary and Incomplete Abstract We show that

More information

Ordered categories and additive conjoint measurement on connected sets

Ordered categories and additive conjoint measurement on connected sets Ordered categories and additive conjoint measurement on connected sets D. Bouyssou a, T. Marchant b a CNRS - LAMSADE, Université Paris Dauphine, F-75775 Paris Cedex 16, France b Ghent University, Dunantlaan

More information

Boolean Algebras. Chapter 2

Boolean Algebras. Chapter 2 Chapter 2 Boolean Algebras Let X be an arbitrary set and let P(X) be the class of all subsets of X (the power set of X). Three natural set-theoretic operations on P(X) are the binary operations of union

More information

THE SURE-THING PRINCIPLE AND P2

THE SURE-THING PRINCIPLE AND P2 Economics Letters, 159: 221 223, 2017. Doi: 10.1016/j.econlet.2017.07.027 THE SURE-THING PRINCIPLE AND P2 YANG LIU Abstract. This paper offers a fine analysis of different versions of the well known sure-thing

More information

Richter-Peleg multi-utility representations of preorders

Richter-Peleg multi-utility representations of preorders Richter-Peleg multi-utility representations of preorders José Carlos R. Alcantud a, Gianni Bosi b,, Magalì Zuanon c a Facultad de Economía y Empresa and Multidisciplinary Institute of Enterprise (IME),

More information

Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Ton Storcken. Manipulation under k-approval scoring rules RM/08/056. JEL code: D71, D72

Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Ton Storcken. Manipulation under k-approval scoring rules RM/08/056. JEL code: D71, D72 Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Ton Storcken Manipulation under k-approval scoring rules RM/08/056 JEL code: D71, D72 Maastricht research school of Economics of TEchnology and ORganizations Universiteit Maastricht

More information

On preferences over subsets and the lattice structure of stable matchings

On preferences over subsets and the lattice structure of stable matchings On preferences over subsets and the lattice structure of stable matchings Ahmet Alkan Sabanci University, Tuzla 81474 Istanbul, Turkey (e-mail: alkan@sabanciuniv.edu) Abstract. This paper studies the structure

More information

Every Choice Correspondence is Backwards-Induction Rationalizable

Every Choice Correspondence is Backwards-Induction Rationalizable Every Choice Correspondence is Backwards-Induction Rationalizable John Rehbeck Department of Economics University of California-San Diego jrehbeck@ucsd.edu Abstract We extend the result from Bossert and

More information

An axiomatic characterization of the prudent order preference function

An axiomatic characterization of the prudent order preference function An axiomatic characterization of the prudent order preference function Claude Lamboray Abstract In this paper, we are interested in a preference function that associates to a profile of linear orders the

More information

The uniform distributions puzzle

The uniform distributions puzzle The uniform distributions puzzle by Luc LAUWERS Econometrics Center for Economic Studies Discussions Paper Series (DPS) 09.06 http://www.econ.kuleuven.be/ces/discussionpapers/default.htm March 2009 The

More information

The core of voting games: a partition approach

The core of voting games: a partition approach The core of voting games: a partition approach Aymeric Lardon To cite this version: Aymeric Lardon. The core of voting games: a partition approach. International Game Theory Review, World Scientific Publishing,

More information

MATH 521, WEEK 2: Rational and Real Numbers, Ordered Sets, Countable Sets

MATH 521, WEEK 2: Rational and Real Numbers, Ordered Sets, Countable Sets MATH 521, WEEK 2: Rational and Real Numbers, Ordered Sets, Countable Sets 1 Rational and Real Numbers Recall that a number is rational if it can be written in the form a/b where a, b Z and b 0, and a number

More information