Hierarchical Bayesian Persuasion

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Hierarchical Bayesian Persuasion"

Transcription

1 Hierarchical Bayesian Persuasion Weijie Zhong May 12, Introduction Information transmission between an informed sender and an uninformed decision maker has been extensively studied and applied in Economics studies. When both side has no commitment power, [Crawford and Sobel, 1982] showed the possibility of information transmission in the form of coarse intervals. When the sender has commitment power on how to garble his information conditional on the realizaiton of signal he receives, [Kamenica and Gentzkow, 2009] characterized the optimal signal structure that the sender will choose using a simple geometric characterization. In real life, information transmission is more complicated than these simplified models. One key difference is that the interaction is likely to involve multiple agents. For example, people rely on multiple sources news reports on a single event to get an unbiased understanding on it. While on the same time, the person who report directly to public, like journalist or the anchor person, is very unliky to be the person who discovers the first hand information. Within this complex network of interaction, every one has his own interest and own knowledge. The possibly contradicting persuit of unbiasedness, political correctness, freshness or profitability might lead to all kind of patterns in information transmission. Then a natural question to ask is how information is transmitted when there are multiple agents, multiple layers of agents, or even a complex network of agents in the game. Mutiple receivers case is not too different from the single receiver case because no matter how we aggregate receivers action, it is equivlent to modify sender s preference in a normal way. Thus the more interesting problem is the multiple senders case. When multiple senders share the same initial information and communicate with receiver in a symmetric way, key properties of information transmission is well characterized. In the cheap talk case, [Ambrus and Takahashi, 2008] showed that rational receiver can assign undesirable beliefs to off path signals and force senders to agree on telling truth. When senders have commitment power, [Gentzkow and Kamenica, 2011] characterized the game as if there is a pool of information and each sender can individually add information to the pool. Thus the equilibrium outcome will be strictly more informative when adding more competing senders. However, we are still interested in the case where senders are not symmetric. Consider an organization, with agents searching for relevent informationa and a decision maker. It s most likely in a hierarchical form. Figure 1 shows a typical hierarchical information transmission structure. Each sender in the network has his own private source of information and he can also receiver information from downstream senders. Information is transmitted from downstream senders to upstream senders and eventually to the decision 1

2 maker. Each sender in this network has his own preference in decision maker s action and can distort the information he send to the following senders. Decision Maker Sender Sender Information Sender Information Inforamtion Figure 1: Hierarchical information transmission If senders have no commitment power, then we are in the hierarchical cheap talk case. Researches have been done on generally characterizing equilibrium and on how adding intermediary sender can possibly improve information transmission. [Ambrus et al., 2013] generally characterized hierarchical cheap talk equilibrium. With pure strategy and state independent biases, there exists bottleneck intermediator, order of senders doesn t matter and intermediary hurts communication. With mixed strategy these are not generally true. [Ivanov, 2010] showed that a first best non-strategic mediator can be implemented by using a strategic mediater. [Li, 2009] showed strategic complementarity between biased sender and biased intermediary s truthfulness and studied biased sender s choice of communication channel. This paper studied hierarchical information transmission in a Bayesian persuasion framework with commitment power on senders side. We start from a simplified case when only one sender is informative and all other senders are as uninformed as the decision maker. Thus as in Figure 2, the network is simplified to a chain. Each sender in this chain can design and commit to a signal structure garbling the signal he receives and passes it to following senders. Decision Maker Sender Sender Information Sender Information Inforamtion Figure 2: Hierarchical information transmission The paper is arranged as following. In section 2, we setup the model of hierarchical Bayesian persuasion and characterized the equilibrium by introducing a notion of capacity set, In section 3, we characterized some properties of capacity sets and showed some direct corollaries having flavors of main results from [Ambrus et al., 2013]. In section 4, we did comparative statics with respect to initial information and capacity. In 5 we concluded our research and summarized some potential directions to go. 2

3 2 Model of Persuasion 2.1 Setup State of the world: There are finite possible state of the world ω Ω. There is a common prior belief over states among all players µ 0 int (Ω). Receiver: There is one receiver with continuous utility function v(a, ω). Action set A is assumed to be compact. Given receiver s belief about the true state µ (Ω), receiver is going to choose optimal action to maximize her expected utiltiy E µ [v(a, ω)]. a(µ) arg max a A E µ[v(a, ω)] The tie breaking rule is important in the ref[kamenica and Gentzkow 11] s setup. Note that Sender-preferred action doesn t exist here because we have potentially multiple senders. Let s first be vague about this and assume that reveiver stick to some rule to determine unique a(µ) as receiver s response. Senders: There are N senders with continuous utility u n (a, ω) Given receiver and sender holding common belief µ, a sender n s expected utility is E µ [u n (a(µ), ω)]. Without loss of generality, we can write sender s utility in terms of belief: U n (µ) = E µ [u n (a(µ), ω)] *Let s assume at this time {U n } C( (ω)). Here (ω) is a finite dimensional Euclidean space. Game setup and strategies: All senders act sequentially in the order of 1,..., N, Each sender s action set is a large enough signal set S. At the start of game, a piece of information is made available to the first sender. By information, we refer to a distribution q(π) ( (ω)) which induces belief π Supp(q) with density q(π). A history h n collects the initial information q and all senders actions prior to the n + 1th sender. History h N also contains the realization of signals. A sender s strategy is a mapping σ n : h n 1 S. Receiver s strategy is a mapping σ R : h N a. We make a first subgame perfection assumption. Conditional on the history and other player s strategy, an agent should be rational. Note that here senders has no uncertainty but receiver should act w.r.t. her belief about true state. 3

4 The timing of the game can be understood as following: The first sender commit to a signal structure conditional on all possible initial information. Each sender sequentially commits to a signal structure conditional on all previous senders signal structure. An initial information structure is choosen by the nature and released to all agents. The signal is released to the first sender. Every sender choose a signal according to the signal he receives from the last sender according to his strategy. Receiver acts when she observes sender N s signal. 2.2 Simplification Receiver Given the perfection assumption on receiver, she has to be rational given all sender s signal structure chosen and signal realized. Thus the realized signal induces receiver s belief over true state µ (Ω). As we discussed before, receiver is going to be passive in this game by choosing a(µ) arg max a A E µ [v(a, ω)]. The Last Sender Let s first think about the last sender s optimization problem given all other player s strategy fixed. According to our perfection assumption, we need the last player to be rational in choosing signal structure given any possible initial information and signal structure before him. Let s assume that in a history, initial information is given and, players 1,..., N 1 are going to send a variety of signals according to their action choice. What player N can observe is player N 1 s possible signals. And by Bayes rule, these signals induces a spectrum of beliefs for player N. This is actually ref[kamenica and Gentzkow] s model with imperfect information. This optimization problem finally reduces to: max E p(λ)u ( E λ(π) [π] ) (1) p ( ( (Ω))) s.t. E p(λ) [λ] = q Solving this problem is also using the convex hull argument: Proposition 1. Given q 2 (Ω), sender N will choose p(λ) 3 ( ) such that it induces a distribution over beliefs l (q) 2 (Ω), l B q and it attains utility level covû(q). Where Û(λ) = U(E λ[π]). Proposition 1 is saying that, effectively we are finding all distributions over beliefs that are Blackwell dominated by our initial information q that attains certain utility level of utility function Û. Û is actually expanding the original utility function U into the space of all possible distributions over beliefs, with dimensionality as the size of support of signals card(supp(q)). Given optimal set of priors P 3 (Ω), informativeness of a prior is defined by informativeness of the belief it induces l = E p [E λ ]. Lemma 1 is saying that there exists a most informative signal structure within all optimal signal structures. 4

5 Lemma 1. There exists l {E p [E λ π]} such that no other l strictly Blackwell more informative than it yields a higher expected utility. The proof of lemma 1 is just applying Zorn s lemma. The exsitence of optimal l is guaranteed by the theorem in [Kamenica & Gentzkow]. Then we can pick a largest element from the set of optiml experiments. Let s make another assumption on equilibrium perfection: Assumption 1. Whenever there exists most informative signal structures in the set of optimal action, agents will choose a most informative signal structure in equilibrium. Thus, although we can say nothing at this time about the other senders action choice, we know that the last sender is going to choose a most informative action given any prior. Also we know that for whatever most informative experiments, given its posterior itself as prior, than the persuader can at most do at good as this experiment itself. By the choice of action, this must be a Blackwell dominating action and must be chosen under this prior information. Let s summarize all these actions by: L 0 N = { l l 2 (Ω) solves (1) for q (π) and U N } LN 0 is the set of all posteriors that sender N will possibly induce given some prior information. This set summarizes all information about sender N for other senders in the game. Whenever sender N receives a signal structure that induces posterior out of LN 0, he will choose an optimal signal structure that induces a l LN 0. Whenever sender N receives a signal structure that induces posterior in LN 0, he will choose a signal structure that induces exactly the same posterior because of our tie breaking assumption. To utilize LN 0 to solve for equilibrium, we also need a lemma on property of the set LN 0. Lemma 2. If U N (π) C ( (Ω)), L 0 N is bounded and closed in 2 (Ω), thus a compact set. 2.3 Equilibrium The Second Last Sender Consider the second last sender, sender N 1 s problem. He can choose any information structure p 3 (Ω) Bayes plausible and take sender N s reaction into account. Here whenever player N 1 chooses an information structure that induces distribution over beliefs l / LN 0, player N will choose some information structure that induces distribution over beliefs in LN 0. Thus by outcome equivalence, it is without loss of generality to assume player N 1 s optimal strategy is choosing an information structure that induces distribution over beliefs in LN 0. Lemma 3. Given sender N s capacity LN 0 and initial information q N 1, it is optimal for sender N 1 to use a direct mechanism as strategy l LN 0. With Lemma 3, we can rewrite sender N 1 s optimization problem: max E l [U(π)] (2) l LN 0, p 3 (Ω) s.t. E p [λ] = q N 1 E λ [π ] l(π) 5

6 Thus, given q N 1 and compact LN 0, we can solve for p (N 1) 3 (Ω) and ln 1 E λ [π] LN 0. Similarly, we can use Zorn s lemma to set the tie breaking rule: a sender is not going to choose a strictly Blackwell dominated l. Thus we can recursively define the capacity set: LN 1 0 = { } l l 2 (Ω) solves 1 for q (π) and U N 1 L N 1 = { } l l LN 0 solves 2 for q (π) and U N 1 The definition of LN 1 0 is exactly same as the definition of L N 0 except that we use sender N 1 s utility in the optimization. Thus LN 1 0 is defined as the set of ditributions over beliefs that sender N 1 is willing to induce under some initial information without any other constraint. L N 1 is defined recursively using LN 0. It is defined as the set of distributions over belifs that sender N 1 is willing to induce under some initial information knowing that there is sender N between him and the decision maker. The Equilibrium Now we can solve for the whole equilibrium with a chain of senders. We can recursively define the capacity set if the chain using the following definition: Definition 1. The individual capacity set L 0 n is defined as: L 0 n = { l l 2 (Ω) solves 1 for q (π) and U n } The chain capacity set L n is defined as: L n = { l l L 0 n+1 solves 2 for q (π) and U n } Thus, given initial information q, the first sender s problem can be written as: max E l [U 1 (π)] (3) l L 2, p 3 (Ω) s.t. E p [λ] = q N 1 E λ [π ] l(π) Let the first sender s optimal action be p 1(q, L 2 ) and induced distribution over beliefs l 1(q, L 2 ), we have a full charactrization of equilibrium: Proposition 2. SPNE is defined by as set of strategies {p n 3 (Ω)} defined according to {p n(q, L n+1 )}. On equilibrium path, first persuader chooses according to p 1 and all following persuaders truthfully pass the information they get. 3 Properties of Capacity Set In this section, we want to derive some important properties about the capacity set we defined in the previous section. Let s start from two direct corollary: 6

7 Corollary 1. N n=1l 0 n L 1 Corollary 1 is directly from the construction of the capacity sets. By Lemma 3, we know that each L n L n+1. Also q Ln 0 L n 1, q can be implemented as a direct mechanism for sender n. Then by reduction, the intersection of individual capacity set will be a subset of the chain capacity set. Although corollary 1 is very straight forward, the interpretation of it is non-trivial. Since N n=1ln 0 might be a strict subset of L 1, there might be some initial information q 2 (Ω) which some senders in this chain are not willing to pass through when they are the only sender, now being able to be passed through by the chain. Specifically, a weaker result is that, by adding other senders after a first sender, the first sender might be willing to pass through some information that he is not willing to pass through when being the only sender. Then, locally (for some initial information), adding more senders might be strictly desirable. Let s consider a simple example with two senders. Assume sender Ais willing to pass through all information whenever a signal is not very informative. And for a signal Blackwell more informative than some threshold, he will just pass through that threshold information. Thus, with A as the only sender, any signals more informative than the threshold will not be passed through. However, let s consider a second sender B, who is only willing to pass through very informative signals or the uninformative prior. If the utility from prior is relatively low for sender A, then he would rather pass trough a very informative signal to B instead of making it less informative thus undesirable for B. In fact, we can make up the preference of B very extreme that this chain can almost pass through the perfectly informative signal Figure 3: An example with two senders In figure 3, we illustrate a binary state example. The horizontal axis is the space of beliefs, denoted by the probability of true state being 1. The vertical axis is utility level. The red curve represents the utility of sender A and the blue curve represents the utility of sender B. Let s assume the initial information is perfect (induces two beliefs at p = 0 and p = 1). The prior is p = 0.5. Thus for the sender A, as we can see from the graph, his utility on beliefs is convex on interval [0.3, 0.7] and he is willing to pass through any signal inducing beliefs within this interval. However, given a very informative signal, he will induce beliefs p = 0.2 and p = 0.8. Now let s consider sender B, for signals inducing p 1 < 0.2, p 2 > 0.9, his utility is convex thus he is willing to pass through. For any other 7

8 signals, he would rather induce the prior. Let s explicitly plot their capacity sets in Figure 4: Figure 4: Capacty sets of Example 1 Point on Figure 4 represents the beliefs induced by a binary signal structure. The horizontal axis represents the belief with lower p induced by the signal and the vertical axis represents the belief with higher p induced by the signal minus the prior belief. Thus the upper left corner represents the perfectly informative signal and the y = 0 and x = 0.5 area represents the totally uninformative signals. The red area is the pairs of beliefs that sender A is willing to induce LA0. As we can see, the red area coveres some relatively uninformative pairs of beliefs. The blue area is the pairs of beliefs that sender B is willing to induce LB0 and it covers relatively informative pairs beliefs (and of course the prior). It s easy to see that LA0 LB0 contains only the prior. However, the black area is pairs of beliefs that sender A is willing to induce knowing sender B is following him LA. We can see that LA contains some pairs of beliefs strictly more informative than any pair of beliefs in LA0. Thus, whenever the initial signal is more informative than these signals, including a second sender is strictly better in terms of information transmission. Naturally, we want to ask whether we can extend this local result to global result: Is it possible that a chain performs weakly better than a single persuader under any initial information and strictly better under some initial information? The following corollary answers this question. Corollary 2. If there exists n N such that Ln0 L1, then Ln0 = L1. Corollary 2 is saying that a chain can never perform strictly better than a single sender (in this chain) given all possible initial information. If a chain performs weakly better than a single sender n, then given any initial information, the outcome signal from the chain should be Blackwell no less informative than the outcome signal from the single sender. Then let s restrict the initial information to Ln0, this should still be true. Then if Ln0 6 L1, there exists some l Ln0 that will not be passed through the chain. Thus the interpretation of the concept Ln0 L1 is clear. The proof of corollary 2 is also straight forward. Since for sender n, when he is making decision, given any initial information, 8

9 he knows that the unconstrained optimal signal can be passed through the other players. Thus he will choose that optimal signal. Thus 1 L 0 n and they have to be the same set. The intuition of this corollary is also simple. If a chain can locally improve information transmission, it must has ability to credibly threaten a sender by garbling its signal in an undesirable way. However this ability actually means the chain will shrink some initial information that a single sender passes through. Up to this time, although we derived some relationships between a chain s capacity and individual sender s capacity, the concept of capacity set is still abstract. Let s characterize some important properties of individual capacity set. Corollary 3. If initial information q L 1, then the equilibrium will be: First sender induces distribution over beliefs l = q. All following persuaders truthfully pass through the information they get. Corollary 3 is saying that the capacity set defines exactly all the possible initial information that can be truthfully passed through a chain. This corollary is straight forward following the definition of capacity set and our tie breaking rule Assumption 1. Given initial information q L 1, if optimal signal structure chosen by the first sender is not q, then l must be strictly less informative than q and generates strictly higher utility. Then given any information structure leading to l as optimal signal structure, q is also plausible and strictly better than l for the first sender. This contradicts the fact that q L 1. Proposition 3. Capacity defined by support: l L 0 n, if l 2 (Ω) satisfies: 1. Supp(l) = Supp(l ) 2. E l [π] = µ 0 then l L 0 n Proposition 3 is saying that the individual capacity set is actually only defined by the support of the distribution over beliefs it contains. Information structures contained in L 0 n have two cases: 1. Number of beliefs induced by the signal less than or equal to number of states. Then given a set of beliefs, the distribution over these beliefs is uniquely pinned down by Bayes plausibility. 2. Number of beliefs induced by the signal is larger than number of states. Then there are still degrees of freedom given Bayes plausibility. However with corollary 3, all these Bayesian plausible distribution over beliefs will be a best response to some initial information, i.e. they are all contained in the individual capacity set. Thus, the characterization of individual capacity set is largely simplified. For a finite number of signals, the information structures can be characterized in a finite dimensional space. Now we know that the individual capacity sets have good property, thus the intersection of individual capacity sets still has this good property. It s will be good if we can do further analysis only on the intersection of individual capacity sets. So let s derive some sufficient conditions under which capacity of a chain is intersection of individual capacities. 9

10 Corollary 4. If there exists n N such that L 0 n L 0 n for all n N, then L 1 = L 0 n. Corollary 4 is simply saying the whenever there is a bottleneck sender in a chain, then the chain capacity is same as intersection of individual capacities. The proof is straight forward by combining Corollary 1 and Corollary 2. 4 Comparative Statics In this section, we want to study two factors potentially affecting information transmission through a chain. 1. Fix a chain, if initial information q becomes more information, what about the outcome l? 2. Fix intial information q, if the chain capacity L 1 becomes larger, what about the outcome l? These two questions can also be asked on a chain with a single persuader. However, even with a single sender, these comparative statics haven t been well studied. In these two questions, by more informative, we refer to Blackwell informativeness, by larger, we refer to set inclusion and we are interested in the Blackwell informativeness of the outcome. As one might have expected, the answer to these two questions are quite ambiguous because Blackwell informativeness is a very partial order, especially in a high dimensional signal space. In our model, even though the state space is small, since the initial signal can be high dimensional, studying Blackwell informativeness will be very hard. Let s first see an example show why even with the simplest setup, comparative statics is ambiguous. Single sender and ternary states It s very easy to construct examples with ternary states in which more informative initial information doesn t lead to more informative outcome. Because Blackwell sufficiency in a ternary states belief space is equivalent to inclusion of triangles and inclusion of triangles is a very strong result. Let s assume there are three states {S 1, S 2, S 3 }. Thus all beliefs over the three states can be represented in a two dimensional simplex S 1 S 2 S 3. In this simplex, independent of how we parametrize the space, each point can be uniquely represented as a linear combination of S 1, S 2 and S 3. Thus we can use the three coefficients to represent the probability of the corresponding states. The largest blue triangle in Figure 5 represents the space of all possible beliefs over the three states. A full mix of the three states µ 0 is assumed to be the prior belief. Utility of the sender is represented by the arrows in Figure 5. The utility function is peaked at these arrows and decreases very fast to zero. Since we assumed the utility to be continuous in the beginning, we construct the utility as an approximation of a summation of Delta function. The utility level at three red arrows is 0.5 and at three black arrows is 0.8. Prior belief is point µ 0 in the left figure and the black line in the right figure. 10

11 B 3 B 2 A 3 Μ 0 A 1 A 2 S B Figure 5: Ternary states example Initial Information q contains three signals inducing belief A 1, A 2, A 3, which locates exactly at the three red peaks of the utility function. Thus given initial information q, the sender will definitely choose to induce l = q and get expected utility 0.5. Now let s consider a Blackwell more informative information structure q which fully reveals true states (inducing beliefs S 1, S 2, S 3 ). Then from the right figure, we can easily see that the sender s optimal signal will induce the three black peaks B 1, B 2, B 3 and get expected utility 0.8 (which is also the highest possible utility he can get). It s easy to see that information structures inducing A 1, A 2, A 3 and B 1, B 2, B 3 are not Blackwell comparable. Thus, increasing information contained in initial signal will not necessarily increase information passed through by the sender. Single sender and binary states Although with more than two states, it s quite obvious that comparative statics is ambiguous, the binary states case is less trivial. Let s consider the following example. Let s assume there are two states {S 1, S 2 }. Thus all beliefs over the two states can be represented in a one dimensional simplex S 1, S 2 (A line). The only parameter for a belief is the probability p [0, 1] of state S 1. Each point within [0, 1] represents an induced belief as in the left graph in Figure 6. Utility of the sender is represented by the arrows in Figure 6. The utility function is peaked at these arrows and decreases very fast to zero. This is also an approximation of a summation of Delta functions. U(0.2) = U(0.6) = 0.4, U(0.4) = 0.3 and U(0.8) = 0.9. Prior belief is µ 0 = 0.5, represented by the black dashed lines. Initial information q contains two signals inducing beliefs 0.2, 0.6, which locates exactly at the two blue arrows. Thus it s easy to see that given initial information q, the optimal induced belief will be l = q. Now let s assume that the sender can discover more information and then he induces two beliefs 0.4, 0.8, which locate exactly at the two red arrows. Since the expected 11

12 utility (height of the dashed line at prior) is higher with 0.4 and 0.8, we know that the sender is better off given more information. However, we know that in this case, since given q, the sender can always garble some probability to p = 0.4 the utility level at 0.4 should be dominated by a combination of 0.2 and 0.6, as shown in the left figure. Thus it seems that given more information and if the sender induces 0.4 and 0.8, he can split some weight on 0.4 onto 0.2 and 0.6 to get a higher expected utility. We want to show in this example that this can be impossible and 0.4, 0.8 is indeed optimal p 0 A 1 B 2 B 1 A 2 Μ 0 1 B 2 1 A 1 A 2 B 1 Μ 0 0 Figure 6: Binary states example Initial information q contains three signals inducing beliefs (0, 0.5, 1). Noticing here there the distribution over the three signals is not uniquely determined. Let s look at the right graph of Figure 6. We use the three vertices of the blue triangle to represent the three signals. If we use the edge between 0 and 1 to represent the space of beliefs, then the induced belief of a point in this triangle is its projection onto the edge 0 1. For example, the third signal s projection onto edge 0 1 is 0.5. The Bayesian plausibility of these three signals requires the expectation of induced belief should be µ 0 = 0.5. Thus, prior is actually any point in the triangle projecting onto µ = 0.5, the exact location depends on the probabilities of the three signals. Let s assume the three signals are constructed such that prior is located on the dashed line. Let s define the utility function on the triangle. The utility of a point is the utility of its induced belief. Thus indifference curves of the utility function should all be perpendicular to the 0 1 edge. The utility function we defined can thus be represented as the four rectangles. The optimal signal structure should be the highest plane over prior (the dashed line) defined by points on the utility function. We can see that it s actually edge B 1 B 2. It s also easy to see on this graph why it s not possible to split the signal inducing 0.4 onto 0.2 and 0.6. Because given our prior, the only possible representation of information structure q is points A 1 12

13 and A 2. Although it seems that 0.4 is Blackwell dominated by (0.2, 0.6), actually a signal constructed by (0.2, 0.6) inducing 0.4 can not be the signal B 2. The key intuition is that with more signals than states, signals inducing the same belief might be very different. The above two examples showed that generally comparative statics on information in a persuasion problem can be very ambiguous. However, we can make some progress utilizing the capacity set of a chain. 4.1 Initial information within capacity set By Corollary 3, we know that when initial information is in the capacity set, then it will be truthfully passed through the chain. Thus comparing the initial information is actually equivalent to comparing the equilibrium outcome. Comparative statics is almost free: Corollary If q, q L 1 and q B q, then l (q ) = q B q = l (q). 2. If L 1 L 1 and q L 1, then l (q, L 1) = q B l (q, L 1 ). ( B means Blackwell weakly more informative) 4.2 Binary initial information Although Corollary 5 provides some possibility of doing comparative statics, the capacity set of a chain might be small and in most more general cases comparative statics are ambiguous. Also the undiscussed case is actually more relevant because the chain capacity set is small when preferences of senders are misaligned. We need some more restrictive assumptions to proceed. Assumption Binary initial information: Card(Supp(q)) = Minimal capacity: L 1 = L n The first assumption we made in Assumption 2 is necessary because we ve already seen examples with higher dimensional initial information where comparative statics are ambiguous. The second assumption is useful because we ve already known some good properties of individual capacity sets and we will utilize these properties. Lemma 4. If Card(Supp(q)) = 2, then the unique equilibrium is that the first sender chooses p inducing l 2 (Ω) with Card(Supp(l )) = 2 and following senders truthfully pass through signals. In the proof of Lemma 4, we utilize Proposition 3. Fixing the support of induced distribution over beliefs, when the first sender modify the weight on different beliefs in a Bayesian plausible way, the incentives for all the following senders are not violated. Thus, we can freely let the first sender to reduce probability of dominated beliefs. Noticing that with binary initial signal, any signal structure having more than 2 signals will 13

14 have dominated signal. Thus the only induced distribution over beliefs will have binary support. With Lemma 4, we know that given binary initial information, only binary signal structure will be chosen in equilibrium over the chain. Thus the effect of increasing informativeness of initial information is monotonic: Proposition 4. Assume L 1 = L 0 n, if binary initial information q B q, then l (q) B l (q ). Noticing that in Proposition 4, we don t require the less informative initial information q to be binary. Proposition 4 is saying that, when the capacity of a chain attains the minimal capacity, then increasing the informativeness of initial information to more informative binary initial information will increase the informativeness of equilibrium outcome. Proposition 5. Assume initial information q has binary support, if L 1 L 1 = Ln 0, then l (q, L 1) B l (q, L 1 ). Noticing that in Proposition 5, we don t require L 1 to be Ln 0, also we allow for preferences of all senders to be different. Proposition 5 is saying that, when the initial signal is binary, replacing a chain with a chain with larger capacity set and that attains minimal capacity will increase the informativeness of equilibrium outcome. Now we ve characterized the comparative statics with respect to information under the restrictive assumption 2. However, although binary information might not be that unrealistic, the minimal capacity assumption is very restrictive. The first reason is that it s very hard to acquire L 1 = Ln 0. Figure 7 shows an example with three senders in a chain. There are two states and thus the space of beliefs is one dimensional. The utility functions of the three senders are randomly generated as in the left graph. We consider all binary signal equilibria and plot them in the right graph. The meaning of the graphs is exactly the same as in the first example. The blue area in the right graph is Ln 0 and combining the red area with blue area is L Figure 7: Example with three senders We can see that except for placing a bottleneck sender in a chain, generally L 1 will not be the same as L 0 n. Thus now we still can only do comparative statics on a very restrictive range of problems. The next step is to relax the assumption that L 1 = L 0 n. 14

15 Conjecture 1. Assume initial information q has binary support, then l (q, L 0 n ) B l (q, L 1 ) Conjecture 1 is saying that, letting the first sender to optimize with constraint L 0 n actually provides an information lower bound under binary initial information. Thus, we can perform comparative statics with extra constraint L 0 n on first sender and use that as a lower bound of actually change in equilibrium outcome. A full characterization of our comparative statics results can be shown in the following graphs: Comparative statics w.r.t. initial information Bin info q B Bin info q l (q, L 1 )? l (q, L 1 ) B l (q, L 0 n ) B l (q, L 0 n ) Comparative statics w.r.t. capacity set L 0 n B L 0 n l (q, L 1 )? l (q, L 1) B B l (q, L 0 n ) B l (q, L 0 B n ) 5 Conclusion In this paper, we characterized the equilibrium of a hierarchical Bayesian persuasion problem, studied the properties of the equilibrium and derived some comparative statics results. The main results can be summarized as following: 1. Equilibrium can be characterized as the first sender persuading decision maker directly with an additional constraint on the distribution over beliefs he can induce. 2. For some initial information, adding intermediary can improve information transmission of a chain. 3. For all possible initial information, adding intermediary can not always improve information transmission of a chain. 4. Assume binary initial information. There is an information lower bound of equilibrium outcome and this lower bound becomes more informative when: 1) initial information becomes more informative, 2) chain capacity becomes larger. Work plan: 1. Prove conjecture 1 2. Clarify the robustness of model by studying different commitment scheme. One direction is to try to establish the equivalence between garble conditional on information structure and garble conditional on information received. 15

16 3. A full characterization of capacity set L. Establish equivalence between a capacity set and a strategic sender. 4. Extend the model to allow for multiple sources. References [Ambrus et al., 2013] Ambrus, A., Azevedo, E. M., and Kamada, Y. (2013). Hierarchical cheap talk. Theoretical Economics, 8(1): [Ambrus and Takahashi, 2008] Ambrus, A. and Takahashi, S. (2008). Multi-sender cheap talk with restricted state spaces. Theoretical Economics, 3(1):1 27. [Crawford and Sobel, 1982] Crawford, V. P. and Sobel, J. (1982). Strategic information transmission. Econometrica: Journal of the Econometric Society, pages [Gentzkow and Kamenica, 2011] Gentzkow, M. and Kamenica, E. (2011). Competition in persuasion. Technical report, National Bureau of Economic Research. [Ivanov, 2010] Ivanov, M. (2010). Communication via a strategic mediator. Journal of Economic Theory, 145(2): [Kamenica and Gentzkow, 2009] Kamenica, E. and Gentzkow, M. (2009). Bayesian persuasion. Technical report, National Bureau of Economic Research. [Li, 2009] Li, W. (2009). Peddling influence through intermediaries. American Economic Review, Forthcoming. 16

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Emir Kamenica and Matthew Gentzkow University of Chicago June 2010 1 Persuasion mechanisms In this paper we study a particular game where Sender chooses a signal π whose

More information

Persuasion Under Costly Lying

Persuasion Under Costly Lying Persuasion Under Costly Lying Teck Yong Tan Columbia University 1 / 43 Introduction Consider situations where agent designs learning environment (i.e. what additional information to generate) to persuade

More information

Introduction. Introduction

Introduction. Introduction Bayesian Persuasion Emir Kamenica and Matthew Gentzkow (2010) presented by Johann Caro Burnett and Sabyasachi Das March 4, 2011 Emir Kamenica and Matthew Gentzkow (2010) (presentedbayesian by Johann Persuasion

More information

Persuading Skeptics and Reaffirming Believers

Persuading Skeptics and Reaffirming Believers Persuading Skeptics and Reaffirming Believers May, 31 st, 2014 Becker-Friedman Institute Ricardo Alonso and Odilon Camara Marshall School of Business - USC Introduction Sender wants to influence decisions

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago September 2015 Abstract Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970) introduce a

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago December 2015 Abstract Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970) represent random

More information

Definitions and Proofs

Definitions and Proofs Giving Advice vs. Making Decisions: Transparency, Information, and Delegation Online Appendix A Definitions and Proofs A. The Informational Environment The set of states of nature is denoted by = [, ],

More information

Ex Post Cheap Talk : Value of Information and Value of Signals

Ex Post Cheap Talk : Value of Information and Value of Signals Ex Post Cheap Talk : Value of Information and Value of Signals Liping Tang Carnegie Mellon University, Pittsburgh PA 15213, USA Abstract. Crawford and Sobel s Cheap Talk model [1] describes an information

More information

We set up the basic model of two-sided, one-to-one matching

We set up the basic model of two-sided, one-to-one matching Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory I Dan Quint Fall 2009 Lecture 18 To recap Tuesday: We set up the basic model of two-sided, one-to-one matching Two finite populations, call them Men and Women, who want to

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago January 2016 Consider a situation where one person, call him Sender,

More information

Supplementary appendix to the paper Hierarchical cheap talk Not for publication

Supplementary appendix to the paper Hierarchical cheap talk Not for publication Supplementary appendix to the paper Hierarchical cheap talk Not for publication Attila Ambrus, Eduardo M. Azevedo, and Yuichiro Kamada December 3, 011 1 Monotonicity of the set of pure-strategy equilibria

More information

Sequential Games with Incomplete Information

Sequential Games with Incomplete Information Sequential Games with Incomplete Information Debraj Ray, November 6 For the remaining lectures we return to extensive-form games, but this time we focus on imperfect information, reputation, and signalling

More information

The Social Value of Credible Public Information

The Social Value of Credible Public Information The Social Value of Credible Public Information Ercan Karadas NYU September, 2017 Introduction Model Analysis MOTIVATION This paper is motivated by the paper Social Value of Public Information, Morris

More information

Wars of Attrition with Budget Constraints

Wars of Attrition with Budget Constraints Wars of Attrition with Budget Constraints Gagan Ghosh Bingchao Huangfu Heng Liu October 19, 2017 (PRELIMINARY AND INCOMPLETE: COMMENTS WELCOME) Abstract We study wars of attrition between two bidders who

More information

Static Information Design

Static Information Design Static Information Design Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris Frontiers of Economic Theory & Computer Science, Becker-Friedman Institute, August 2016 Mechanism Design and Information Design Basic Mechanism

More information

Benefits from non-competing persuaders

Benefits from non-competing persuaders Benefits from non-competing persuaders Jiemai Wu November 26, 2017 Abstract This paper shows that biased persuaders can provide better information to a decision maker due to cooperative, and not competitive,

More information

Persuading a Pessimist

Persuading a Pessimist Persuading a Pessimist Afshin Nikzad PRELIMINARY DRAFT Abstract While in practice most persuasion mechanisms have a simple structure, optimal signals in the Bayesian persuasion framework may not be so.

More information

Government 2005: Formal Political Theory I

Government 2005: Formal Political Theory I Government 2005: Formal Political Theory I Lecture 11 Instructor: Tommaso Nannicini Teaching Fellow: Jeremy Bowles Harvard University November 9, 2017 Overview * Today s lecture Dynamic games of incomplete

More information

Notes on Blackwell s Comparison of Experiments Tilman Börgers, June 29, 2009

Notes on Blackwell s Comparison of Experiments Tilman Börgers, June 29, 2009 Notes on Blackwell s Comparison of Experiments Tilman Börgers, June 29, 2009 These notes are based on Chapter 12 of David Blackwell and M. A.Girshick, Theory of Games and Statistical Decisions, John Wiley

More information

Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 5: Cheap Talk. Patrick Legros

Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 5: Cheap Talk. Patrick Legros Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 5: Cheap Talk Patrick Legros 1 / 35 Outline Cheap talk 2 / 35 Outline Cheap talk Crawford-Sobel Welfare 3 / 35 Outline Cheap talk Crawford-Sobel Welfare Partially Verifiable

More information

Hierarchical cheap talk

Hierarchical cheap talk Hierarchical cheap talk Attila Ambrus, Eduardo Azevedo, and Yuichiro Kamada July 15, 2009 Abstract We investigate situations in which agents can only communicate to each other through a chain of intermediators,

More information

Hierarchical cheap talk

Hierarchical cheap talk Hierarchical cheap talk Attila Ambrus, Eduardo M. Azevedo, and Yuichiro Kamada December 29, 2011 Abstract We investigate situations in which agents can only communicate to each other through a chain of

More information

Discussion of "Persuasion in Global Games with an Application to Stress Testing" by Nicolas Inostroza and Alessandro Pavan

Discussion of Persuasion in Global Games with an Application to Stress Testing by Nicolas Inostroza and Alessandro Pavan Discussion of "Persuasion in Global Games with an Application to Stress Testing" by Nicolas Inostroza and Alessandro Pavan Stephen Morris IUB Stern Workshop March 2017 Basic Question Some policy ingredients:

More information

Disclosure of Endogenous Information

Disclosure of Endogenous Information Disclosure of Endogenous Information Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago March 2016 Abstract We study the effect of disclosure requirements in environments

More information

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E.

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E. Tilburg University On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E. Publication date: 1997 Link to publication General rights Copyright and

More information

Endogenous Persuasion with Rational Verification

Endogenous Persuasion with Rational Verification Endogenous Persuasion with Rational Verification Mike FELGENHAUER July 16, 2017 Abstract This paper studies a situation in which a sender tries to persuade a receiver with evidence that is generated via

More information

Information Design. Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris. Johns Hopkins University April 2017

Information Design. Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris. Johns Hopkins University April 2017 Information Design Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris Johns Hopkins University April 2017 Mechanism Design and Information Design Basic Mechanism Design: Fix an economic environment and information structure

More information

Competition in Persuasion

Competition in Persuasion Competition in Persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica University of Chicago September 2011 Abstract Does competition among persuaders increase the extent of information revealed? We study ex ante

More information

On Bayesian Persuasion with Multiple Senders

On Bayesian Persuasion with Multiple Senders On Bayesian Persuasion with Multiple Senders Fei Li Peter Norman January 8, 05 Abstract In a multi-sender Bayesian persuasion game, Gentzkow and Kamenica 0 show that increasing the number of senders cannot

More information

Equilibrium Refinements

Equilibrium Refinements Equilibrium Refinements Mihai Manea MIT Sequential Equilibrium In many games information is imperfect and the only subgame is the original game... subgame perfect equilibrium = Nash equilibrium Play starting

More information

Some Notes on Costless Signaling Games

Some Notes on Costless Signaling Games Some Notes on Costless Signaling Games John Morgan University of California at Berkeley Preliminaries Our running example is that of a decision maker (DM) consulting a knowledgeable expert for advice about

More information

BAYES CORRELATED EQUILIBRIUM AND THE COMPARISON OF INFORMATION STRUCTURES IN GAMES. Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris

BAYES CORRELATED EQUILIBRIUM AND THE COMPARISON OF INFORMATION STRUCTURES IN GAMES. Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris BAYES CORRELATED EQUILIBRIUM AND THE COMPARISON OF INFORMATION STRUCTURES IN GAMES By Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris September 203 Revised October 204 COWLES FOUNDATION DISCUSSION PAPER NO. 909RR COWLES

More information

Belief Meddling in Social Networks: an Information-Design Approach. October 2018

Belief Meddling in Social Networks: an Information-Design Approach. October 2018 Belief Meddling in Social Networks: an Information-Design Approach Simone Galperti UC San Diego Jacopo Perego Columbia University October 2018 Motivation introduction 2012 Presidential race, Romney at

More information

Correlated Equilibrium in Games with Incomplete Information

Correlated Equilibrium in Games with Incomplete Information Correlated Equilibrium in Games with Incomplete Information Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris Econometric Society Summer Meeting June 2012 Robust Predictions Agenda game theoretic predictions are very

More information

9 A Class of Dynamic Games of Incomplete Information:

9 A Class of Dynamic Games of Incomplete Information: A Class of Dynamic Games of Incomplete Information: Signalling Games In general, a dynamic game of incomplete information is any extensive form game in which at least one player is uninformed about some

More information

Blackwell s Informativeness Theorem Using Diagrams

Blackwell s Informativeness Theorem Using Diagrams Blackwell s Informativeness Theorem Using Diagrams Henrique de Oliveira 1, a Department of Economics, Pennsylvania State University, University Park, PA 16802 Abstract This paper gives a simple proof of

More information

Competition in Persuasion

Competition in Persuasion Competition in Persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica University of Chicago September 2012 Abstract Does competition among persuaders increase the extent of information revealed? We study ex ante

More information

Blackwell s Informativeness Theorem Using Category Theory

Blackwell s Informativeness Theorem Using Category Theory Blackwell s Informativeness Theorem Using Category Theory Henrique de Oliveira March 29, 2016 1 Introduction An agent faces a decision problem under uncertainty, whose payoff u (a, ω) depends on her action

More information

Static Information Design

Static Information Design Static nformation Design Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris European Summer Symposium in Economic Theory, Gerzensee, July 2016 Mechanism Design and nformation Design Mechanism Design: Fix an economic environment

More information

Hierarchical cheap talk

Hierarchical cheap talk Hierarchical cheap talk Attila Ambrus, Eduardo M. Azevedo, and Yuichiro Kamada February 24, 2012 Abstract We investigate situations in which agents can communicate to each other only through a chain of

More information

. Introduction to Game Theory Lecture Note 8: Dynamic Bayesian Games. HUANG Haifeng University of California, Merced

. Introduction to Game Theory Lecture Note 8: Dynamic Bayesian Games. HUANG Haifeng University of California, Merced .. Introduction to Game Theory Lecture Note 8: Dynamic Bayesian Games HUANG Haifeng University of California, Merced Basic terminology Now we study dynamic Bayesian games, or dynamic/extensive games of

More information

SFB E C O N O M I C R I S K B E R L I N

SFB E C O N O M I C R I S K B E R L I N SFB 649 Discussion Paper 0-0 A strategic mediator who is biased into the same direction as the expert can improve information transmission Lydia Mechtenberg* Johannes Münster** * Wissenschaftszentrum Berlin

More information

joint with Jonathan Pogach (Penn) 2009 FESAMES at Tokyo Hong Kong University of Science and Technology Honesty vs. White Lies Kim & Pogach Overview

joint with Jonathan Pogach (Penn) 2009 FESAMES at Tokyo Hong Kong University of Science and Technology Honesty vs. White Lies Kim & Pogach Overview vs. White vs. joint with Jonathan Pogach (Penn) Kyungmin (Teddy) Kim Hong Kong University of Science and Technology 2009 FESAMES at Tokyo vs. White vs. Question Models Main Results Contributions 1 Honest

More information

Organizational Barriers to Technology Adoption: Evidence from Soccer-Ball Producers in Pakistan

Organizational Barriers to Technology Adoption: Evidence from Soccer-Ball Producers in Pakistan Organizational Barriers to Technology Adoption: Evidence from Soccer-Ball Producers in Pakistan David Atkin, Azam Chaudhry, Shamyla Chaudry Amit K. Khandelwal and Eric Verhoogen Sept. 016 Appendix B: Theory

More information

Nash Codes for Noisy Channels

Nash Codes for Noisy Channels OPERATIONS RESEARCH Vol. 62, No. 6, November December 2014, pp. 1221 1235 ISSN 0030-364X (print) ISSN 1526-5463 (online) http://dx.doi.org/10.1287/opre.2014.1311 2014 INFORMS Nash Codes for Noisy Channels

More information

Cheap Talk with Correlated Signals

Cheap Talk with Correlated Signals Cheap Talk with Correlated Signals A.K.S. Chand, Sergio Currarini, Giovanni Ursino July 1, 213 Abstract We consider a game of information transmission, with one informed decision maker gathering information

More information

CMS-EMS Center for Mathematical Studies in Economics And Management Science. Discussion Paper #1583. Monotone Persuasion

CMS-EMS Center for Mathematical Studies in Economics And Management Science. Discussion Paper #1583. Monotone Persuasion CMS-EMS Center for Mathematical Studies in Economics And Management Science Discussion Paper #1583 Monotone Persuasion Jeffrey Mensch Northwestern University May 24 th, 2016 Monotone Persuasion Jeffrey

More information

Multi-Sender Cheap Talk with Restricted State Spaces

Multi-Sender Cheap Talk with Restricted State Spaces Multi-Sender Cheap Talk with Restricted State Spaces The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Ambrus, Attila,

More information

Games and Economic Behavior

Games and Economic Behavior Games and Economic Behavior 104 (2017) 411 429 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Games and Economic Behavior www.elsevier.com/locate/geb Bayesian persuasion with multiple senders and rich signal

More information

n Communication and Binary Decisions : Is it Better to Communicate?

n Communication and Binary Decisions : Is it Better to Communicate? Série des Documents de Travail n 2013-50 Communication and Binary Decisions : Is it Better to Communicate? F. LOSS 1 E. MALAVOLTI 2 T. VERGÉ 3 September 2013 Les documents de travail ne reflètent pas la

More information

Bayes Correlated Equilibrium and Comparing Information Structures

Bayes Correlated Equilibrium and Comparing Information Structures Bayes Correlated Equilibrium and Comparing Information Structures Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris Spring 2013: 521 B Introduction game theoretic predictions are very sensitive to "information structure"

More information

On Reputation with Imperfect Monitoring

On Reputation with Imperfect Monitoring On Reputation with Imperfect Monitoring M. W. Cripps, G. Mailath, L. Samuelson UCL, Northwestern, Pennsylvania, Yale Theory Workshop Reputation Effects or Equilibrium Robustness Reputation Effects: Kreps,

More information

Robust Mechanism Design and Robust Implementation

Robust Mechanism Design and Robust Implementation Robust Mechanism Design and Robust Implementation joint work with Stephen Morris August 2009 Barcelona Introduction mechanism design and implementation literatures are theoretical successes mechanisms

More information

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7).

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). The axiomatic approach (OR 15) Nash s (1950) work is the starting point

More information

Communication with Self-Interested Experts Part II: Models of Cheap Talk

Communication with Self-Interested Experts Part II: Models of Cheap Talk Communication with Self-Interested Experts Part II: Models of Cheap Talk Margaret Meyer Nuffield College, Oxford 2013 Cheap Talk Models 1 / 27 Setting: Decision-maker (P) receives advice from an advisor

More information

The ambiguous impact of contracts on competition in the electricity market Yves Smeers

The ambiguous impact of contracts on competition in the electricity market Yves Smeers The ambiguous impact of contracts on competition in the electricity market Yves Smeers joint work with Frederic Murphy Climate Policy and Long Term Decisions-Investment and R&D, Bocconi University, Milan,

More information

ECO421: Communication

ECO421: Communication ECO421: Communication Marcin P ski February 9, 2018 Plan Introduction Asymmetric information means some players know more than the others. In real life, information can be transmitted A simple model of

More information

Multi-sender cheap talk with restricted state space

Multi-sender cheap talk with restricted state space Multi-sender cheap talk with restricted state space Attila Ambrus and Satoru Takahashi This Version: February 2006 Abstract This paper analyzes multi-sender cheap talk in multidimensional environments.

More information

WHEN ARE SIGNALS COMPLEMENTS OR SUBSTITUTES?

WHEN ARE SIGNALS COMPLEMENTS OR SUBSTITUTES? Working Paper 07-25 Departamento de Economía Economic Series 15 Universidad Carlos III de Madrid March 2007 Calle Madrid, 126 28903 Getafe (Spain) Fax (34-91) 6249875 WHEN ARE SIGNALS COMPLEMENTS OR SUBSTITUTES?

More information

1 The General Definition

1 The General Definition MS&E 336 Lecture 1: Dynamic games Ramesh Johari April 4, 2007 1 The General Definition A dynamic game (or extensive game, or game in extensive form) consists of: A set of players N; A set H of sequences

More information

Game Theory Lecture 10+11: Knowledge

Game Theory Lecture 10+11: Knowledge Game Theory Lecture 10+11: Knowledge Christoph Schottmüller University of Copenhagen November 13 and 20, 2014 1 / 36 Outline 1 (Common) Knowledge The hat game A model of knowledge Common knowledge Agree

More information

An Example of Conflicts of Interest as Pandering Disincentives

An Example of Conflicts of Interest as Pandering Disincentives An Example of Conflicts of Interest as Pandering Disincentives Saori Chiba and Kaiwen Leong Current draft: January 205 Abstract Consider an uninformed decision maker (DM) who communicates with a partially

More information

BAYES CORRELATED EQUILIBRIUM AND THE COMPARISON OF INFORMATION STRUCTURES IN GAMES. Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris

BAYES CORRELATED EQUILIBRIUM AND THE COMPARISON OF INFORMATION STRUCTURES IN GAMES. Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris BAYES CORRELATED EQUILIBRIUM AND THE COMPARISON OF INFORMATION STRUCTURES IN GAMES By Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris September 203 Revised April 205 COWLES FOUNDATION DISCUSSION PAPER NO. 909RRR COWLES

More information

First Prev Next Last Go Back Full Screen Close Quit. Game Theory. Giorgio Fagiolo

First Prev Next Last Go Back Full Screen Close Quit. Game Theory. Giorgio Fagiolo Game Theory Giorgio Fagiolo giorgio.fagiolo@univr.it https://mail.sssup.it/ fagiolo/welcome.html Academic Year 2005-2006 University of Verona Summary 1. Why Game Theory? 2. Cooperative vs. Noncooperative

More information

Where does the sender s information come from? Communication with Endogenous Information Acquisition

Where does the sender s information come from? Communication with Endogenous Information Acquisition Where does the sender s information come from? Communication with Endogenous Information Acquisition Harry Di Pei January 24, 2013 Abstract This paper revisits the Crawford-Sobel game by allowing the sender

More information

EC319 Economic Theory and Its Applications, Part II: Lecture 7

EC319 Economic Theory and Its Applications, Part II: Lecture 7 EC319 Economic Theory and Its Applications, Part II: Lecture 7 Leonardo Felli NAB.2.14 27 February 2014 Signalling Games Consider the following Bayesian game: Set of players: N = {N, S, }, Nature N strategy

More information

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers September 6, 016 ONLINE APPENDIX In this Appendix we present in full additional results and extensions which are only mentioned in the paper. In the exposition

More information

Coordination and Cheap Talk in a Battle of the Sexes with Private Information

Coordination and Cheap Talk in a Battle of the Sexes with Private Information Department of Economics Coordination and Cheap Talk in a Battle of the Sexes with Private Information Department of Economics Discussion Paper 3-0 Chirantan Ganguly Indrajit Ray Coordination and Cheap

More information

Costly Expertise. Dino Gerardi and Leeat Yariv yz. Current Version: December, 2007

Costly Expertise. Dino Gerardi and Leeat Yariv yz. Current Version: December, 2007 Costly Expertise Dino Gerardi and Leeat Yariv yz Current Version: December, 007 In many environments expertise is costly. Costs can manifest themselves in numerous ways, ranging from the time that is required

More information

SF2972 Game Theory Exam with Solutions March 15, 2013

SF2972 Game Theory Exam with Solutions March 15, 2013 SF2972 Game Theory Exam with s March 5, 203 Part A Classical Game Theory Jörgen Weibull and Mark Voorneveld. (a) What are N, S and u in the definition of a finite normal-form (or, equivalently, strategic-form)

More information

Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium For an important class of extensive games, a solution concept is available that is simpler than sequential equilibrium, but with similar properties. In a Bayesian extensive

More information

Bayesian Persuasion. Emir Kamenica and Matthew Gentzkow University of Chicago. September 2009

Bayesian Persuasion. Emir Kamenica and Matthew Gentzkow University of Chicago. September 2009 Bayesian Persuasion Emir Kamenica and Matthew Gentzkow University of Chicago September 2009 Abstract When is it possible for one person to persuade another to change her action? We take a mechanism design

More information

When to Ask for an Update: Timing in Strategic Communication

When to Ask for an Update: Timing in Strategic Communication When to Ask for an Update: Timing in Strategic Communication Work in Progress Ying Chen Johns Hopkins University Atara Oliver Rice University March 19, 2018 Main idea In many communication situations,

More information

Strategic Learning and Information Transmission

Strategic Learning and Information Transmission Strategic Learning and Information Transmission Alexander Frug November 5, 2014 Abstract This paper addresses the problem of information transmission between a biased expert and a decision maker in an

More information

When to Ask for an Update: Timing in Strategic Communication. National University of Singapore June 5, 2018

When to Ask for an Update: Timing in Strategic Communication. National University of Singapore June 5, 2018 When to Ask for an Update: Timing in Strategic Communication Ying Chen Johns Hopkins University Atara Oliver Rice University National University of Singapore June 5, 2018 Main idea In many communication

More information

Area I: Contract Theory Question (Econ 206)

Area I: Contract Theory Question (Econ 206) Theory Field Exam Summer 2011 Instructions You must complete two of the four areas (the areas being (I) contract theory, (II) game theory A, (III) game theory B, and (IV) psychology & economics). Be sure

More information

Strategic Abuse and Accuser Credibility

Strategic Abuse and Accuser Credibility 1 / 33 Strategic Abuse and Accuser Credibility HARRY PEI and BRUNO STRULOVICI Department of Economics, Northwestern University November 16th, 2018 Montréal, Canada 2 / 33 Motivation Many crimes/abuses

More information

Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions

Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions by Roger B. Myerson and Philip J. Reny* Draft notes October 2011 http://home.uchicago.edu/~preny/papers/bigseqm.pdf Abstract:

More information

Lecture December 2009 Fall 2009 Scribe: R. Ring In this lecture we will talk about

Lecture December 2009 Fall 2009 Scribe: R. Ring In this lecture we will talk about 0368.4170: Cryptography and Game Theory Ran Canetti and Alon Rosen Lecture 7 02 December 2009 Fall 2009 Scribe: R. Ring In this lecture we will talk about Two-Player zero-sum games (min-max theorem) Mixed

More information

Reputation and Bounded Memory in Repeated Games with Incomplete Information

Reputation and Bounded Memory in Repeated Games with Incomplete Information Reputation and Bounded Memory in Repeated Games with Incomplete Information A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Yale University in Candidacy for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy

More information

Game Theory. Wolfgang Frimmel. Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

Game Theory. Wolfgang Frimmel. Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium Game Theory Wolfgang Frimmel Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium / 22 Bayesian Nash equilibrium and dynamic games L M R 3 2 L R L R 2 2 L R L 2,, M,2, R,3,3 2 NE and 2 SPNE (only subgame!) 2 / 22 Non-credible

More information

Online Appendix for Sourcing from Suppliers with Financial Constraints and Performance Risk

Online Appendix for Sourcing from Suppliers with Financial Constraints and Performance Risk Online Appendix for Sourcing from Suppliers with Financial Constraints and Performance Ris Christopher S. Tang S. Alex Yang Jing Wu Appendix A: Proofs Proof of Lemma 1. In a centralized chain, the system

More information

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract Pure strategy dominance with quasiconcave utility functions Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam Abstract By a result of Pearce (1984), in a finite strategic form game, the set of a player's serially

More information

BELIEFS & EVOLUTIONARY GAME THEORY

BELIEFS & EVOLUTIONARY GAME THEORY 1 / 32 BELIEFS & EVOLUTIONARY GAME THEORY Heinrich H. Nax hnax@ethz.ch & Bary S. R. Pradelski bpradelski@ethz.ch May 15, 217: Lecture 1 2 / 32 Plan Normal form games Equilibrium invariance Equilibrium

More information

Costly Social Learning and Rational Inattention

Costly Social Learning and Rational Inattention Costly Social Learning and Rational Inattention Srijita Ghosh Dept. of Economics, NYU September 19, 2016 Abstract We consider a rationally inattentive agent with Shannon s relative entropy cost function.

More information

Nash Codes for Noisy Channels

Nash Codes for Noisy Channels Nash Codes for Noisy Channels Penélope Hernández Bernhard von Stengel arxiv:1202.1547v3 [cs.gt] 16 Feb 2014 February 16, 2014 Abstract This paper studies the stability of communication protocols that deal

More information

Dating and Divorce. Li, Hao and Sergei Severinov Vancouver School of Economics University of British Columbia. August 9, 2018.

Dating and Divorce. Li, Hao and Sergei Severinov Vancouver School of Economics University of British Columbia. August 9, 2018. Dating and Divorce Li, Hao and Sergei Severinov Vancouver School of Economics University of British Columbia August 9, 2018 Abstract We introduce private information in an otherwise standard search and

More information

Persuasion of Heterogenous Audiences and Optimal Media Censorship

Persuasion of Heterogenous Audiences and Optimal Media Censorship Persuasion of Heterogenous Audiences and Optimal Media Censorship Tymofiy Mylovanov joint work with Anton Kolotilin, Ming Li, Andriy Zapechelnyuk October 6, 2017 1 Environment Sender Receiver Receiver

More information

Cheap talk theoretic tools for distributed sensing in the presence of strategic sensors

Cheap talk theoretic tools for distributed sensing in the presence of strategic sensors 1 / 37 Cheap talk theoretic tools for distributed sensing in the presence of strategic sensors Cédric Langbort Department of Aerospace Engineering & Coordinated Science Laboratory UNIVERSITY OF ILLINOIS

More information

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance Geoffroy de Clippel February 2010 Nehring (2004) proposes an interesting methodology to extend the utilitarian criterion defined under complete information to an

More information

Bayesian consistent prior selection

Bayesian consistent prior selection Bayesian consistent prior selection Christopher P. Chambers and Takashi Hayashi August 2005 Abstract A subjective expected utility agent is given information about the state of the world in the form of

More information

Crowdsourcing contests

Crowdsourcing contests December 8, 2012 Table of contents 1 Introduction 2 Related Work 3 Model: Basics 4 Model: Participants 5 Homogeneous Effort 6 Extensions Table of Contents 1 Introduction 2 Related Work 3 Model: Basics

More information

Virtual Robust Implementation and Strategic Revealed Preference

Virtual Robust Implementation and Strategic Revealed Preference and Strategic Revealed Preference Workshop of Mathematical Economics Celebrating the 60th birthday of Aloisio Araujo IMPA Rio de Janeiro December 2006 Denitions "implementation": requires ALL equilibria

More information

Mechanism Design: Basic Concepts

Mechanism Design: Basic Concepts Advanced Microeconomic Theory: Economics 521b Spring 2011 Juuso Välimäki Mechanism Design: Basic Concepts The setup is similar to that of a Bayesian game. The ingredients are: 1. Set of players, i {1,

More information

Competition relative to Incentive Functions in Common Agency

Competition relative to Incentive Functions in Common Agency Competition relative to Incentive Functions in Common Agency Seungjin Han May 20, 2011 Abstract In common agency problems, competing principals often incentivize a privately-informed agent s action choice

More information

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer Social learning and bargaining (axiomatic approach)

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer Social learning and bargaining (axiomatic approach) UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2015 Social learning and bargaining (axiomatic approach) Block 4 Jul 31 and Aug 1, 2015 Auction results Herd behavior and

More information

Mediated Persuasion: Some Examples

Mediated Persuasion: Some Examples Mediated Persuasion: Some Examples Andrew Kosenko Department of Economics, University of Pittsburgh June, 208 Abstract We study a game of strategic information design between a sender, who chooses state-dependent

More information

A remark on discontinuous games with asymmetric information and ambiguity

A remark on discontinuous games with asymmetric information and ambiguity Econ Theory Bull DOI 10.1007/s40505-016-0100-5 RESEARCH ARTICLE A remark on discontinuous games with asymmetric information and ambiguity Wei He 1 Nicholas C. Yannelis 1 Received: 7 February 2016 / Accepted:

More information

Dynamic Bayesian Persuasion with Public News

Dynamic Bayesian Persuasion with Public News Dynamic Bayesian Persuasion with Public News Jacopo Bizzotto, Jesper Rüdiger and Adrien Vigier First version: December 015 This version: September 016 Abstract We introduce and examine a class of dynamic

More information

Industrial Organization Lecture 3: Game Theory

Industrial Organization Lecture 3: Game Theory Industrial Organization Lecture 3: Game Theory Nicolas Schutz Nicolas Schutz Game Theory 1 / 43 Introduction Why game theory? In the introductory lecture, we defined Industrial Organization as the economics

More information