Reciprocity in the Principal Multiple Agent Model

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Reciprocity in the Principal Multiple Agent Model"

Transcription

1 WORKING PAPER NO. 314 Reciprocity in the Principal Multiple Agent Model Giuseppe De Marco and Giovanni Immordino May 2012 University of Naples Federico II University of Salerno Bocconi University, Milan CSEF - Centre for Studies in Economics and Finance DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS UNIVERSITY OF NAPLES NAPLES - ITALY Tel. and fax csef@unisa.it

2

3 WORKING PAPER NO. 314 Reciprocity in the Principal Multiple Agent Model Giuseppe De Marco* and Giovanni Immordino** Abstract This paper studies how incentives are affected by intention-based reciprocity preferences when the principal hires many agents. Our results describe the agents' psychological attitudes required to sustain a given strategy profile. We also show that hiring reciprocal agents to implement a first or a second-best contract will always benefit the principal if the strategy profile is symmetric. When instead the profile (first or second-best) is asymmetric the principal's best interest might be better served by self- interested agents. We conclude the paper by clarifying when symmetric profiles are most likely to arise. JEL classification: C72; D03; D86. Keywords: reciprocity, many agents, psychological games. * University of Naples Parthenope and CSEF. Address for correspondence: Dipartimento di Statistica e Matematica per la Ricerca Economica, University of Naples Parthenope, Via Medina 40, Naples, Italy. ** University of Salerno and CSEF. Address for correspondence: Dipartimento di Scienze Economiche e Statistiche, University of Salerno, Via Ponte Don Melillo, Fisciano (SA), Italy.

4

5 Table of contents 1. Introduction 2. The Model 2.1. The moral hazard problem 2.2. Reciprocity 3. Implementation of the Frst Best 4. Principal's Utility in the Second Best 5. Collusion-proof Implementation 6. A Remark on Symmetric First Best Profiles 7. Conclusion Appendix References

6

7 1 Introduction In the seminal paper by Mookerjee (1984), the principal-agent model of moral hazard is extended to a multiple agent setting: Production depends on the entire profile of efforts exerted by the team of agents. The principal cannot observe the effort chosen by each member of the team and designs wage schedules contingent on outputs. Therefore, optimal contracts are chosen under a system of incentive compatibility constraints which take naturally the form of Nash equilibrium conditions of the underlying game between the agents. Given that each agent must share the marginal benefit of his effort, but he alone bears its costs, teams are affected by free riding problems which, in turn, might produce a (negative) psychological externality on agents. Therefore, teams seem to be a natural environment in which reciprocity plays an important role. Indeed, if a team member is sufficiently sensitive to reciprocity then he will reasonably have incentives to free ride if he believes that other players intentions are bad, in the sense that they plan to exert a level of effort which is lower than the one they expect from him, and, conversely, he will have incentives to work harder if he believes that his partners intentions are good. In this paper we address this issue and, building on the reciprocity motives previously described, we study how contracts are affected by intention-based reciprocity preferences when a self-interested principal hires reciprocal players. More precisely, we include reciprocal agents in the Mookerjee s model so that the IC conditions appear as a psychological game 1. Under the assumption that the principal chooses incentive schemes to implement agents actions as a psychological Nash equilibrium, necessary and sufficient conditions are derived for the attainability of the first best. Our results describe the psychological attitudes of the team members required to sustain a given strategy profile in equilibrium and, therefore, give useful insights for hiring and team design. However, the agents s psychological characteristics used to prove the previous results are not sufficient to attain the first best if some partners can collude. We show that additional psychological assumptions allow for the the collusion-proof implementation of the first best. Moreover, we ask whether hiring reciprocal agents would increase or decrease the net benefit of the principal. It turns out that a principal will always prefer reciprocal agents to implement a first or a second-best contract if the strategy profile is symmetric and show, by way of examples, that whenever the first or the second-best profiles are asymmetric the principal might prefer self-interested to intention-based reciprocity agents. Finally, since our previous results have underlined the important role played by symmetry for reciprocity to be in the principal s interest, we conclude the paper by clarifying when symmetric profiles are most likely to arise. Several papers have studied the welfare properties of the optimal incentive schemes in a principal-many agents problem (Holmstrom 1982, Demski and Sappington 1984, Mookherjee 1984, Malcomson 1986), and have attempted to solve the problems arising from the fact that those incentive schemes might not implement the principal s chosen vector of actions as a unique equilibrium (Demski and Sappington 1984, Mookherjee 1982 and 1984, Ma 1988). However, the role of reciprocity was not addressed in this early literature. More recently, experimental evidence in Fehr, Gächter, and Kirchsteiger (1997) has suggested that 1 See Geanakoplos, Pearce and Stacchetti (1989) for psychological games and equilibria. 2

8 reciprocal motives contribute to the enforcement of contracts. In this vein, Dufwenberg and Kirchsteiger (2000), Englmaier and Leider (2008) and Netzer and Schmutzler (2010) all show that efficiency is generally increased when a materialistic principal interacts with a reciprocal agent 2. Our contribution extends the study of the role played by reciprocity to the multiple agent case. The present paper is also related to a growing literature that studies the impact of inequity aversion to multiple agent models (Itoh 2004, Demougin and Fluet 2006, Rey Biel 2008). These articles find that when there are multiple agents who care about the final monetary distributions among each other, the principal can exploit their nature by designing interdependent contracts. However, reciprocity and inequity aversion are distinct motives, and often intention matters more, in particular in the domain of punishing behaviour, as suggested by recent evidence (Itoh 2004). Accordingly, in our model contracts are affected in a different way with respect to inequity aversion models since a team member may react badly to other agents free-riding regardless of everyone s rewards. Moreover, we show that if intentions are the driving motive the principal is more likely to exploit it if first or second best strategy profiles are symmetric. Finally, in De Marco and Immordino (2010) we study the impact of intention-based reciprocity preferences on the free-riding problem arising in non-stochastic partnerships. We suggest a tendency of efficient partnerships to consist of members whose sensitivity to reciprocity is individually or jointly sufficiently high and construct associated reciprocity based sharing rules. The analysis in this paper is motivated by this result and it extends the theoretical framework developed in our companion paper to encompass the more complex setting where a principal can write optimal contracts to incentivize the agents. The paper is organized as follows. In Section 2.1, Mookherjee s many agent model is summarized. We introduce the psychological features of our model in Section 2.2. In Section 3 we provide sufficient and necessary conditions for the implementation of the efficient strategy profile. Section 4 shows that reciprocal agents always increase the net benefit of the principal when the material second best is symmetric but not when the material second best is asymmetric. Section 5 deals with the collusion-proof implementation of the first best In Section 6 we provide the sufficient conditions for a symmetric first-best strategy profile to arise. Section 7 concludes. All proofs are relegated to the Appendix. 2 The model 2.1 The moral hazard problem We first introduce the moral hazard problem and to ease the comparison we borrow most assumptions and notation from Mookherjee (1984). Agents Material Payoffs.The model consists of a set of agents N = {1,..., n} with n 2, a set of effort levels A k for each agent and a disutility function G k : A k R for each agent. A = k N A k. Moreover, we assume that A i = {1,..., m} for any i. We donote with Q the 2 Even if, as shown by Netzer and Schmutzler (2010), firms may not want to employ a reciprocal worker. 3

9 finite set of outcomes and Q = ν. The probability distribution on Q induced by an effort (strategy) profile a = (a 1,..., a n ) is denoted by π(a) where π q (a) is the probability of the output q given a. 3 Denote also with J(a) the support of the probability distribution on π(a), that is J(a) = {q Q π q (a) > 0}. Each agent k has a von-neumann-morgenstern utility function u k which is additively separable in the action chosen by agent k and in the payment received u k (a k, I k ) = V k (I k ) G k (a k ), where the principal s payment I k ranges in an interval [I, I]. The agent k has a reservation utility u k and we impose the following Assumption 1. Each function V k is continuous, strictly increasing and concave over [I, I] with V k (I) min ak A k G k (a k ) < u k. Moreover, for every a k A k there exists I [I, I] such that V k (I) G k (a k ) = u k. Finally, we impose the normalization V k (I) = 0. The principal s benefit from an output profile q is denoted by B(q) and the principal s expected benefit is defined by B(a) = q Q π q (a) B(q). First-Best. In the first best the principal can observe the action chosen by the agents and, in light of Assumption 1 she can write contracts forcing any agent to choose any feasible action that guarantees the agent his reservation utility. If agent k was required to choose a k, the principal would pay him a sum of C k F B(a k ) = V 1 k (u k + G k (a k )) = h(u k + G k (a k )) where h = V 1 k if he chooses a k and I otherwise. The first best cost to the principal from the effort profile a is then C F B (a) = k N C k F B(a k ) and the first-best effort profile a = (a 1, a 2,..., a n) is the one which maximize in A the net benefit of the principal, that is, the function P : A R defined by P (a) = B(a) C F B (a) a A. Second-Best. In a second best world the principal cannot observe the actions chosen by agents, hence payments may only be based on the outcomes Q. An incentive scheme for player i is therefore an ν-dimensional vector I k = (Iq k ) q Q [I, I] ν where the element Iq k is the 3 This is different from Mookherjee (1984) and Ma (1988), where there exists for each player k a finite set of possible outputs Q k = {q k 1,..., q k ν k } and Q = k N Q k. Our approach is more general and simplifies notation. The reason we can adopt it is due to the fact that we do not need any assumption on the probability distribution over output pairs. 4

10 payment given to player k if the output vector q has occurred. Given the vector of incentive schemes I = (I 1, I 2,..., I n ) and the effort profile a the principal incurs an expected cost C(a, I) = [ ] π q (a). q Q Given an incentive scheme I k and the effort profile a = (a 1, a 2,..., a n ), the expected utility of agent k is E k (a, I k ) = q Q k N π q (a)u k (a k, I k q ) = q Q π q (a)v k (I k q ) G k (a k ). I k q Then, given the vector of incentive schemes I = (I 1, I 2,..., I n ), we define the game played by the agents with Γ(I) = {N; A 1,..., A n ; E 1 (, I 1 ),..., E n (, I n )}. We now introduce the useful definitions of second-best contract and attainable first-best profile. Definition 1. A second-best contract consists in a pair (a, I) which maximizes the net benefit subject to the constraints that IC) a is a Nash equilibrium of Γ(I), IR) E k (a, I k ) u k for every k N. B(a) C(a, I) Definition 2. The first-best effort profile a is said to be attainable if there exist incentive schemes I such that (a, I) satisfies (IR) and (IC) and C(a, I) = C F B (a ). We end this section by introducing the following useful notation. First, the set of incentive schemes such that (a, I) is a feasible contract is denoted with Then, the second-best cost is defined by L(a) = {I (a, I) satisfies IR and IC }. C SB (a) = min C(a, I) a I L(a) A and the correspondence of optimal incentive schemes is 4 M(a) = {I L(a) C(a, I) = C SB (a)}. 4 It can be easily checked that the second best contracts can be equivalently obtained as the pair (a, I) such that i) I M(a) and ii) a that maximizes B( ) C SB ( ) in A = {a A L(a) }. 5

11 2.2 Reciprocity To complete the presentation of our set-up, we now introduce the psychological features and the equilibrium concept. Following our companion work (De Marco and Immordino, 2010) we innovate with respect to the previous literature in two main respects. First, to measure kindness we deviate from the previous literature that uses the concept of player s equitable payoff (see for instance Rabin, 1993) and we use instead the agents level of effort as a more direct measure of each agent contribution to the output of the partnership. In the traditional model of reciprocity (Rabin 1993, Dufwenberg and Kirchsteiger 2004), the strategy sets may represent choices of different nature so that the natural way to measure kindness is to look at the players payoffs. However, when the action sets represent comparable choices (efforts), we can adopt the simpler approach to use the level of efforts as a more direct and easier to test measure of kindness. In this case, the reciprocity term in the psychological utility function does not depend on the material payoffs, capturing the idea that an agent may react badly to other agents free-riding regardless of everyone s rewards. Our definition of kindness, besides being better suited to many applications (partnerships, principal with many agents), has also the advantage to be completely unrelated to Pareto efficiency. Second, to specify the psychological utility function for each player, we introduce for every pair of players a function that assigns to each combination of kindness and belief about reciprocated kindness the disutility caused to one player by the mismatch between his and the other agent s intentions. Our single-peaked preferences depend only on the distance between the kindness of k to t, and partner k s belief about how kind t is to him and differently from the functional forms in previous reciprocity models our formulation does not have their characteristic explosive feature. All this should become readily clear by looking at the rest of the section. Denote by b kt A t partner k s beliefs about partner t s strategy, and by c ktk A k partner k s beliefs about partner t s beliefs about partner k s strategy. We denote by χ kt (a k, b kt ) the kindness of k to t and by λ ktk (b kt, c ktk ) partner k s belief about how kind t is to him. The kindness terms are defined to be and χ kt (a k, b kt ) = a k b kt λ ktk (b kt, c ktk ) = b kt c ktk, so that positive kindness from k to t arises if partner k contributes to the output with an effort level larger than the one he expects from partner t. Moreover, partner k will believe that t is kind to him if the effort he expects from partner t is larger than the one he believes partner t expects from him. For every pair of players (k, t) the reciprocity term of k with respect to t assigns to each combination of kindness χ kt and belief about reciprocated kindness λ ktk the disutility caused to player k by the mismatch between these two intentions. Let h kt (χ kt, λ ktk ) = (ω k χ kt λ ktk ) 2, be the functional form of such reciprocity terms. Those single-peaked preferences depend uniquely on the distance between the kindness of k to t, and partner k s belief about how 6

12 kind t is to him. A remarkable characteristic of the present formulation is that it is free from the explosive feature that characterize the functional forms of previous reciprocity models such as Dufwenberg and Kirchsteiger (2004) where h kt (χ kt, λ ktk ) = χ kt λ ktk or Rabin (1993) where h kt (χ kt, λ ktk ) = λ ktk (1 + χ kt, ). Indeed, in all functional forms in which h kt diverges positively (negatively) with χ kt and accordingly with the sign of λ ktk then there is no limit to how kind (unkind) k wants to be to t. Then, the overall (psychological) utility function of player k is defined by ] U k (a k, a k, (b kt ) t k, (c ktk ) t k ; I k ) = E k (a, I k ) + ρ k [ t k h kt (χ kt (a k, b kt ), λ ktk (b kt, c ktk )), (1) [ and is made up by the sum of the material payoff E k (a, I k ) and the reciprocity term ] ρ k t k h kt(χ kt (a k, b kt ), λ ktk (b kt, c ktk ). Parameters ρ k and ω t summarize the psychological characteristics of each player k: ρ k > 0 measures the relative importance (the weight) of the psychological term with respect to the material payoff; instead, the parameter ω k relates the relative importance of player k s intentions towards the others to his beliefs about other players intentions. Each ω k is assumed to be positive, meaning that, for a given λ ktk, the optimal kindness of player k (taking into account only h kt ) is χ kt = λ ktk /ω k, which reciprocates kind behavior (λ ktk > 0) with kind behavior (χ kt > 0) and unkind behavior (λ ktk < 0) with unkind behavior (χ kt < 0). 5 Moreover, the magnitude of ω k affects the optimal kindness which increases in absolute value as ω k decreases to zero and, when ω k = 1, perfectly reciprocates the believed kindness, i.e. χ kt = λ ktk. Finally, key for our results is how those parameters affect the psychological disutilities caused by deviating from the optimal kindness for each pair of players (k, t). These disutilities are related to the products ρ k ωk 2 as follows: fix a pair of players (k, t) and the size ε of a deviation from the optimal kindness χ kt = λ ktk /ω k, then the player k s disutility with respect to t is given by ρ k (ω k (λ ktk /ω k + ε) λ ktk ) 2 = ρ k ωkε 2 2 and it decreases to zero as ρ k ωk 2 decreases to zero. Therefore, ρ kωk 2 from now on denoted with θ k measures the sensitivity of partner k s reciprocity. In other words, the greater is θ k the more sensible to the psychological reciprocity is partner k. We are now ready to define the psychological game (derived from the game Γ(I)) corresponding to the psychological utility functions defined in (1) Γ ρ,ω (I) = {N; A 1,..., A n ; U 1 (, I 1 ),..., U k (, I n )}. We conclude this section by recalling the equilibrium concept that will be used. 6 Definition 3 (Geanakoplos, Pearce and Stacchetti 1989). A strategy profile (a 1,..., a n ) A is a psychological Nash equilibrium of Γ ρ,ω (I) if for all k N i) a k arg max ak A k U k (a k, a k, (b kt ) t k, (c ktk ) k t ; I k ), ii) b kt = a t and c ktk = a k for all t k. 5 ω k = 0 is excluded, since regardless of k s kindness, k s overall utility would be always decreasing in k s belief of t s (positive) kindness. 6 In the rest of the paper a will usually denote an equilibrium and a a symmetric equilibrium. 7

13 3 Implementation of the First Best We start this section by redefining second-best contracts and attainable first-best profiles under the assumption that agents have intention-based reciprocity preferences. Definition 4. A second-best contract under reciprocity vectors (ρ, ω) consists in a pair (a, I) which maximizes the net benefit B(a) C(a, I) subject to the constraints that (P ρ,ω -IC) a is a psychological Nash equilibrium of Γ ρ,ω (I), (P ρ,ω -IR) U k (a k, a k, (b kt ) t k, (c ktk ) k t ; I k ) u k, b kt = a t and c ktk = a k for all t k and for every k N. Definition 5. The first-best effort profile a is said to be attainable under reciprocity vectors (ρ, ω) if there exist incentive schemes I such that (a, I) satisfies (P ρ,ω -IR) and (P ρ,ω -IC) and C(a, I) = C F B (a ). Denote with ν k (a ) = max a k A k [G k (a k) G k (a k )], an upper bound to the cost saving from an unilateral deviation for agent k. We are now ready to state our sufficient condition for the implementation of a symmetric first-best profile. Proposition 1. Let a be a symmetric first-best profile. If θ k ν k (a )/(n 1) for every player k then a is attainable under reciprocity vectors (ρ, ω). The proof of the previous proposition shows that a is attainable since, when agents sensitivity to reciprocity is sufficiently high, there exist an incentive scheme Î that satisfy (P ρ,ω -IR) and (P ρ,ω -IC) and C(a, I) = C F B (a ). Specifically, for every k N, Îk is the incentive scheme of player k defined by Î k q = { C k F B (a k ) if q J(a ) I if q Q \ J(a ). (2) Below, we always denote with Î the incentive schemes defined by (2) for every k N and q Q. Some more notation is needed to state our necessary conditions for the implementation of a symmetric first-best profile. Define M k (a k) = (a k a k) 2 a k A k and G k (a k) = a k A k (G k (a k) G k (a k )) 8

14 where M k (a k ) measures the variance of the efforts with respect to a k, whereas G k(a k ) measures the mean incremental cost from unilateral deviations from a k for agent k. Finally, ψ k (a k) = [ πq (a k, a k) π q (a ) ], a k A k q J(a ) measures the mean probability of reaching some outcome q outside the support J(a ), by unilaterally deviating from a k for agent k. Then, the next proposition gives a necessary condition for a symmetric strategy profile to be implemented by a psychological equilibrium. Proposition 2. Assume that each function V k is strictly concave and a is the symmetric first best profile. If a is attainable under reciprocity vectors (ρ, ω), then, for every k N, it follows that i) I k q = C k F B (a k ) for all q J(a ) ii) θ k ψ k(a k )V k(c k F B (a k )) + G k(a k ) (n 1)M k (a k ). (3) The next example illustrates how reciprocity sustains efficiency and puts Propositions 1 and 2 to work. Example 1: Consider a game with two agents with strategy sets A 1 = A 2 = {1, 2}, the random output has the following support Q = {q 1, q 2, q 3, q 4 }. Agents costs of effort are defined by G 1 (1) = 5, G 1 (2) = 10, G 2 (1) = 4 and G 2 (2) = 10 while agents reservation utilities are u 1 = u 2 = 10. Moreover, the utility functions V k are given by the identity mappings for each k = 1, 2. The probability distributions π(a) = (π q1 (a), π q2 (a), π q3 (a), π q4 (a)) on Q induced by the strategy profiles a A 1 A 2 are given by π(2, 2) = (1/8, 1/4, 5/8, 0), π(1, 2) = (1/8, 3/8, 3/8, 1/8), π(2, 1) = (1/4, 1/2, 1/8, 1/8) and π(1, 1) = (1/8, 1/8, 0, 3/4). It can be easily calculated that CF 1 B (1) = 15, C1 F B (2) = 20, CF 2 B (1) = 14 and C2 F B (2) = 20. If the principal s benefits from output are given by B(q 1 ) = B(q 2 ) = B(q 4 ) = 0 and B(q 3 ) = 80, then her net benefits are P (2, 2) = (5/8) = 10, P (2, 1) = (3/8) = 4, P (1, 2) = (1/8) = 25 and P (1, 1) = = 29. Hence, the first best would be obtained implementing (2, 2) at the cost C F B (2, 2) = 40. However, the first best would be attainable only if (2, 2) is a Nash equilibrium of the game defined by incentive schemes that give the first best cost on the support of (2, 2), as it is the case for Îk q 1 = Îk q 2 = Îk q 3 = 20 and (without loss of generality) Îq k 4 = I = 0, for k = 1, 2. It is immediate to see that (2, 2) is not a Nash equilibrium for the resulting game a 2 = 2 a 2 = 1 a 1 = 2 10, , 13.5 a 1 = , 7.5 0, 1 9

15 Suppose now that the agents are reciprocal with reciprocity parameters θ 1 = 2.5 and θ 2 = 3.5. Denote with a = (a 1, a 2) = (2, 2). Let b kt = a t and c ktk = a k for t k be the first and second order beliefs consistent with (a 1, a 2). Being a 1 = a 2 then λ ktk = 0 for k = 1, 2 and t k. U k (a k, a k, (b kt) t k, (c ktk) t k ; Îk ) = E k (a, Îk ) and Hence while U k (a k, a k, (b kt) t k, (c ktk) t k ; Îk ) = E k (a k, a k, Îk ) ρ k ωk(a 2 k b kt) 2 if a k a k. i) U 1 (a 1, a 2, b 12, c 121; Î1 ) = E 1 (a 1, a 2; Î1 ) = 10; ii) U 1 (a 1 = 1, a 2, b 12, c 121; Î1 ) = E 1 (a 1 = 1, a 2; Î1 ) ρ 1 ω 2 1 = 12.5 θ 1 iii) U 2 (a 1, a 2, b 21, c 212; Î2 ) = E 2 (a 1, a 2; Î2 ) = 10; iv) U 2 (a 1, a 2 = 1, b 21, c 212; Î2 ) = E 2 (a 1, a 2 = 1; Î2 ) ρ 2 ω 2 2 = 13.5 θ 2. Therefore if θ and θ it follows that 1) U 1 (a 1, a 2, b 12, c 121; Î1 ) U 1 (a 1 = 1, a 2, b 12, c 121; Î1 ) 2) U 2 (a 1, a 2, b 21, c 212; Î2 ) U 2 (a 1, a 2 = 1, b 21, c 212; Î2 ). Hence, a is a psychological Nash equilibrium of Γ ρ,ω (Î) (therefore a is attainable under reciprocity parameters ρ, ω) if and only if θ and θ It can be checked that in this game ν 1 (a ) = 5 and ν 2 (a ) = 6 hence the sufficient conditions in Proposition 1 give θ 1 5 and θ 2 6. However, it can be checked that ψ k (a k ) = 1/8, V k(cf k B (a k )) = 20 and M k (a k ) = 1 for k = 1, 2. Moreover, G 1(a 1) = 5 and G 2 (a 2) = 6. Hence, the necessary conditions (3) give back θ and θ The next example shows that reciprocity has instead a negative effect on asymmetric profiles and in particular it renders unattainable first best contracts which were attainable in the material game. Example 2: Consider the game presented in the previous example except that now the probability distributions over Q are given by π(2, 2) = (1/2, 1/2, 0, 0), π(1, 2) = (1/4, 1/4, 1/4, 1/4), π(2, 1) = (1/2, 1/2, 0, 0) and π(1, 1) = (1/4, 1/4, 1/4, 1/4). Again CF 1 B (1) = 15, C1 F B (2) = 20, C2 F B (1) = 14 and C2 F B (2) = 20. If the principal s benefits are given by B(q 2 ) = B(q 3 ) = B(q 4 ) = 0 and B(q 1 ) = 70 then her net benefits are P (2, 2) = = 5, P (2, 1) = = 1, P (1, 2) = = 17.5 and P (1, 1) = = Hence, the first best is obtained by implementing (2, 1) at the cost C F B (2, 1) = 34. Therefore, the first best is attainable only if (2, 1) is a Nash equilibrium of the game corresponding to incentive schemes Î such that Î1 q 1 = Î1 q 2 = 20, and Îq 2 1 = Î2 q 2 = 14 and Î1 q 3 = Î1 q 4 = Î2 q 3 = Î2 q 4 = I = 0. The resulting game is 10 t k

16 a 2 = 2 a 2 = 1 a 1 = 2 10, 4 10, 10 a 1 = 1 5, -3 5, 3 It can be checked that the asymmetric strategy profile (2, 1) is a Nash equilibrium and the IC conditions are satisfied. Now we show that, with a reciprocal player 1, the equilibrium (2, 1) is destroyed and therefore the P ρ,ω -IC conditions are not satisfied. Denote with a = (a 1, a 2) = (2, 1). Let b kt = a t and c ktk = a k for t k be the first and second order beliefs consistent with (a 1, a 2). Recalling that then U 1 (a 1, a 2, b 12, c 121; Î1 ) = E 1 (a 1, a 2, Î1 ) ρ 1 (ω 1 (a 1 b 12) (b 12 c 121)) 2 i) U 1 (a 1 = 2, a 2, b 12, c 121; Î1 ) = E 1 (2, 1, Î1 ) ρ 1 (ω 1 (2 b 12) (b 12 c 121)) 2 = 10 ρ 1 (ω 1 (2 1) (1 2)) 2 = 10 ρ 1 (ω 1 + 1) 2 ii) U 1 (a 1 = 1, a 2, b 12, c 121; Î1 ) = E 1 (1, 1, Î1 ) ρ 1 (ω 1 (1 b 12) (b 12 c 121)) 2 = Consider, for example, ϱ 1 1 and ω 1 2 then 5 ρ 1 (ω 1 (1 1) (1 2)) 2 = 5 ρ 1. U 1 (a 1 = 1, a 2, b 12, c 121; Î1 ) > U 1 (a 1 = 2, a 2, b 12, c 121; Î1 ) which implies that (2, 1) is not a psychological Nash equilibrium of Γ ϱ,ω (Î). This shows that a material asymmetric and efficient equilibrium might be destroyed by reciprocal agents. 4 Principal s utility in the Second Best In this section we show that reciprocal agents always increase the net benefit of the principal when the material second best is symmetric (Proposition 3 and Example 3). However, this result does not extend to the case where the material second best is asymmetric (Example 4). The next proposition states our first result. Proposition 3. Let (a, I) be a (material) second-best contract such that a is a symmetric strategy profile and at least one of the IR constraints is not binding. Then, for every pair of reciprocity vectors (ρ, ω) there exist incentive schemes I such that (a, I) satisfies (P ρ,ω -IR), (P ρ,ω -IC) and B(a ) C(a, I) < B(a ) C(a, I). In words, reciprocity reduces the costs of implementing the second best, whenever the second best profile is symmetric. The next example illustrates Proposition 3. Example 3: Consider a game with two agents with strategy sets A 1 = A 2 = {1, 2}, the random output has the following support Q = {q 1, q 2, q 3 }. Agents costs of effort are defined by G 1 (2) = G 2 (2) = 1, G 1 (1) = G 2 (1) = 0, while agents reservation utilities are u 1 = u 2 = 0. The probability distributions over Q are given by π(2, 2) = (1/2, 1/2, 0), 11

17 π(1, 2) = (1/3, 1/3, 1/3) and π(2, 1) = π(1, 1) = (0, 0, 1). It can be easily calculated that C 1 F B (1) = C2 F B (1) = 0, C1 F B (2) = C2 F B (2) = 1. Given the incentive schemes I where Ik q i denotes the payment to player k if outcome q i has occurred, then the material game is a 2 = 2 a 2 = 1 a 1 = 2 (Iq 1 1 /2) + (Iq 1 2 /2) 1, (Iq 2 1 /2) + (Iq 2 2 /2) 1 Iq 1 3 1, Iq 2 3 a 1 = 1 (Iq 1 1 /3) + (Iq 1 2 /3) + (Iq 1 3 /3), (Iq 2 1 /3) + (Iq 2 2 /3) + (Iq 2 3 /3) 1 Iq 1 3, Iq 2 3 Note that (2, 2) is a Nash equilibrium (and therefore satisfies the IC conditions) if and only if i) (I 1 q 1 /2) + (I 1 q 2 /2) 1 (I 1 q 1 /3) + (I 1 q 2 /3) + (I 1 q 3 /3) ii) (I 2 q 1 /2) + (I 2 q 2 /2) 1 I 2 q 3. It can be easily checked that C SB (2, 2) = 8 and M(2, 2) = {(I 1 q i ) 3 i=1, (I 2 q i ) 3 i=1 I 1 q 1 + I 1 q 2 = 6, I 2 q 1 + I 2 q 2 = 2, I 1 q 3 = I 2 q 3 = 0}. On the other hand (1, 2) is a Nash equilibrium if and only if i) (I 1 q 1 /3) + (I 1 q 2 /3) + (I 1 q 3 /3) (I 1 q 1 /2) + (I 1 q 2 /2) 1 ii) (I 2 q 1 /3) + (I 2 q 2 /3) + (I 2 q 3 /3) 1 I 2 q 3. Therefore C SB (1, 2) = 3 and M(1, 2) = {(I 1 q i ) 3 i=1, (I 2 q i ) 3 i=1 I 2 q 1 + I 2 q 2 = 3, I 1 q 1 = I 1 q 2 = I 1 q 3 = I 2 q 3 = 0}. Analogous calculations show that (2, 1) is never a Nash equilibrium, while C SB (1, 1) = 0. Now if the principal s benefits from output are B(q 1 ) = B(q 3 ) = 0 and B(q 2 ) = 36. It can be checked that the first best is to implement (2, 2) at the cost CF 1 B (2) + C2 F B (2) = 2. While the second best is to implement (2, 2) at the second best cost C SB (2, 2) = 8. In fact B(2, 2) C SB (2, 2) = 18 8 = 10, B(1, 2) C SB (1, 2) = 12 3 = 9 and B(1, 1) C SB (1, 1) = 0. Suppose now that agents are reciprocal with reciprocity vectors (ρ, ω). Following the same steps as in the previous examples for the calculation of psychological payoffs, we get the following psychological equilibrium conditions for the strategy profile (2, 2) i) (I 1 q 1 /2) + (I 1 q 2 /2) 1 (I 1 q 1 /3) + (I 1 q 2 /3) + (I 1 q 3 /3) θ 1 ii) (I 2 q 1 /2) + (I 2 q 2 /2) 1 I 2 q 3 θ 2. Such conditions tell that the strategy profile (2, 2) can be implemented as a psychological Nash equilibrium under the following incentive schemes {(I 1 q i ) 3 i=1, (I 2 q i ) 3 i=1 I 1 q 1 + I 1 q 2 = max{6(1 θ 1 ), 0}, I 2 q 1 + I 2 q 2 = max{2(1 θ 2 ), 0}, I 1 q 3 = I 2 q 3 = 0}. and therefore the second best costs under reciprocity vectors (ρ, ω) are C P SB(2, 2) = max{6(1 θ 1 ), 0} + max{2(1 θ 2 ), 0} < C SB (2, 2), implying that reciprocity reduces the costs of implementation of the second best, whenever the second best profile is symmetric. 12

18 We now show by way of an example that reciprocity does not always benefit the principal if the material second best is asymmetric. Example 4: Consider a game similar to the one in Example 3. Two agents have strategy sets A 1 = A 2 = {1, 2}. Again, the random output has support Q = {q 1, q 2, q 3 }, agents costs of effort are G 1 (2) = G 2 (2) = 1, G 1 (1) = G 2 (1) = 0, while reservation utilities are u 1 = u 2 = 0. The probability distributions over Q are now given by π(2, 2) = (1/2, 1/2, 0), π(1, 2) = (0, 1/2, 1/2) and π(2, 1) = π(1, 1) = (0, 0, 1). It can be easily calculated that CF 1 B (1) = C2 F B (1) = 0, C1 F B (2) = C2 F B (2) = 1. Given the incentive schemes I then the material game is a 2 = 2 a 2 = 1 a 1 = 2 (Iq 1 1 /2) + (Iq 1 2 /2) 1, (Iq 2 1 /2) + (Iq 2 2 /2) 1 Iq 1 3 1, Iq 2 3 a 1 = 1 (Iq 1 2 /2) + (Iq 1 3 /2), (Iq 2 2 /2) + (Iq 2 3 /2) 1 Iq 1 3, Iq 2 3 Note that (2, 2) is a Nash equilibrium (and therefore satisfies the IC conditions) if and only if i) (I 1 q 1 /2) + (I 1 q 2 /2) 1 (I 1 q 2 /2) + (I 1 q 3 /2) ii) (I 2 q 1 /2) + (I 2 q 2 /2) 1 I 2 q 3. It can be easily checked that C SB (2, 2) = 4 and M(2, 2) = {(I 1 q i ) 3 i=1, (I 2 q i ) 3 i=1 I 1 q 1 = 2, I 2 q 1 + I 2 q 2 = 2, I 1 q 2 = I 1 q 3 = I 2 q 3 = 0}. On the other hand (1, 2) is a Nash equilibrium if and only if Therefore C SB (1, 2) = 2 and i) (I 1 q 2 /2) + (I 1 q 3 /2) (I 1 q 1 /2) + (I 1 q 2 /2) 1 ii) (I 2 q 2 /2) + (I 2 q 3 /2) 1 I 2 q 3. M(1, 2) = {(I 1 q i ) 3 i=1, (I 2 q i ) 3 i=1 I 2 q 2 = 2, I 2 q 1 = I 1 q 1 = I 1 q 2 = I 1 q 3 = I 2 q 3 = 0}. Analogous calculations show that (2, 1) is never a Nash equilibrium, while C SB (1, 1) = 0. If the principal s benefits from output are now B(q 1 ) = 0, B(q2 ) = 10 and B(q 3 ) = 2. It can be checked that the first best is to implement (1, 2) at the cost C F B (1, 2) = 1. While the second best is to implement (1, 2) at the second best cost C SB (1, 2) = 2. In fact B(2, 2) C SB (2, 2) = 5 4 = 1, B(1, 2) C SB (1, 2) = 6 2 = 4 and B(1, 1) C SB (1, 1) = 2. Suppose now that agents are reciprocal with reciprocity vectors (ρ, ω). Following the same steps as in the previous examples for the calculation of psychological payoffs, we get the following psychological equilibrium conditions for the strategy profile (2, 2) i) (I 1 q 1 /2) + (I 1 q 2 /2) 1 (I 1 q 2 /2) + (I 1 q 3 /2) θ 1 ii) (I 2 q 1 /2) + (I 2 q 2 /2) 1 I 2 q 3 θ 2. 13

19 For (1, 2), we have the following equilibrium conditions i) (I 1 q 2 /2) + (I 1 q 3 /2) ρ 1 (ω 1 + 1) 2 (I 1 q 1 /2) + (I 1 q 2 /2) 1 ρ 1 ii) (I 2 q 2 /2) + (I 2 q 3 /2) 1 ρ 2 (ω 2 + 1) 2 I 2 q 3 ρ 2 Fix for example ρ 1 = ρ 2 = 1/2 and ω 1 = ω 2 = 1. Then the equilibrium conditions tell that the strategy profile (2, 2) can be implemented as a psychological Nash equilibrium under the following incentive schemes {(I 1 q i ) 3 i=1, (I 2 q i ) 3 i=1 I 1 q 1 = 1, I 2 q 1 + I 2 q 2 = 1, I 1 q 2 = I 1 q 3 = I 2 q 3 = 0}. Therefore the second best costs is CSB P (2, 2) = 2. The strategy profile (1, 2) can be implemented as a psychological Nash equilibrium under the following incentive schemes {(I 1 q i ) 3 i=1, (I 2 q i ) 3 i=1 I 1 q 1 = 5/2, I 2 q 2 = 5, I 2 q 1 = I 1 q 1 = I 1 q 2 = I 1 q 3 = I 2 q 3 = 0}. and the second best cost is now CSB P (1, 2) = 15/2. Therefore the second best under reciprocity vectors (ρ, ω) is obtained, in this case, by the strategy profile (2, 2) which yields a net benefit to the principal equal to B(2, 2) CSB P (2, 2) = 5 2 = 3 > B(1, 2) CSB P (1, 2) = 6 15/2 = 3/2. Since B(1, 2) C SB(1, 2) = 4 > B(2, 2) CSB P (2, 2), we deduce that reciprocal agents may reduce the net benefit of the principal when the material second best is asymmetric. 5 Collusion-proof Implementation In the presence of many players, collusion-proof implementation of the efficient strategy profile is often an issue. In particular, in the (material) principal-multiple agents framework, Mookherjee (1982) investigates the effects of a principal who seeks to implement action pairs as a strong Nash equilibrium (Aumann (1959)) in the two-agent case. An equilibrium is said to be a strong Nash equilibrium if no subset of players, taking the actions of the others as fixed, can jointly deviate in a way that benefits all of them. This concept has been introduced for environments in which players can agree privately upon a joint deviation. In that case, any meaningful agreement by the whole set of players must be stable against deviations by all possible coalitions of players. More precisely, Definition 6 (Aumann 1959). A strategy profile (a 1,..., a n ) is a strong Nash equilibrium of the material game Γ if for all subset of players T N and for all a T A T = t T A t there exists a player k T such that u k (a T, a T ) u k (a T, a T ), with a T = (a t ) t/ T. Building upon the work of Aumann, in our companion paper we introduced the definition of psychological strong Nash equilibrium which extends the Aumann s concept to psychological games. The definition is based on the idea that since players commit ex-ante to a deviation the deviants beliefs should be consistent with the deviation itself. 7 More precisely 7 Note that when we consider only deviations by singletons, this definition boils down to the definition of psychological Nash equilibrium. Moreover, it generalizes the Aumann s definition of strong Nash equilibrium which can be easily obtained removing the psychological term from the payoffs. In the next two sections we will introduce our results on implementation and unique implementation, respectively. 14

20 Definition 7. A strategy profile (a 1,..., a n ) is a psychological strong Nash equilibrium of Γ ρ,ω (I) if it is stable with respect to joint deviations of each coalition T N: for every a T A T there exists a player k T such that i) U k (a k, a k, (b kt ) t k, (c ktk ) t k ; I k ) U k (a T, a T, (b kt ) t k ), (c ktk ) t k ; I k ), with a T = (a t ) t/ T ii) b kt = a t and c ktk = a k for all t k, iii) b kt = a t and c ktk = a k for all t N \ T, iv) b kt = a t and c ktk = a k for all t T \ {k}. In De Marco and Immordino (2010), we found out that this concept allows for the unique and collusion proof implementation of the efficient (symmetric) strategy profile in a classical partnership model. Now we address the question whether the psychological strong Nash equilibrium allows for an analogous result for symmetric first best profiles in the principalmultiple agents model. Indeed, the condition used to prove Proposition 1 is not sufficient to sustain the first best if agents can collude. In the next proposition we show that there exists a set of parameters θ k such that the symmetric first best is attainable even if proper coalitions can collude. Whether the symmetric first best is stable also with respect to joint deviations of the grand coalition (and therefore a psychological strong Nash equilibrium), it depends only on the material game, meaning that only the (first best) incentives schemes prevent from the joint deviations of the grand coalition. Indeed, as it can be easily deduced from the definition of psychological strong Nash equilibrium, in the agents psychological utilities corresponding to a deviation of the grand coalition from a symmetric strategy profile towards another symmetric strategy profile the psychological terms disappear and therefore psychological utilities coincide with the material ones. Proposition 4. Let a be the symmetric first best profile. If θ k ν k (a ) for every player k then a is attainable and stable with respect to joint deviations of each proper coalition T N in the psychological game Γ ρ,ω (Î). Finally, whenever the symmetric first best profile is sustained as a psychological strong Nash equilibrium then additional assumptions on the psychological parameters of the agents are needed to guarantee that it is unique 8. 6 A remark on symmetric first best profiles The previous results underline the important role played by symmetry for reciprocity to be in the principal s interest. It is then natural to ask when a symmetric first-best strategy profile is likely to arise. Given a strategy profile a = (a 1,..., a n ), denote with n i=1 a i the integer part of n and let µ(a) = (m(a),..., m(a)) be the symmetric profile in A defined by n i=1 a n n i i=1 if a i i=1 = a i n n n m(a) = n i=1 a i + 1 otherwise. n n i=1 a i 8 Even if the first best profile is not the unique psychological strong Nash equilibrium of the game, it is possible to show that if a is the symmetric first best profile and if ρ k [ (ωk + 1) 2 (n 1)(m 1) 2] > ν(a ) k N then every asymmetric strategy profile is not a strong psychological equilibrium of Γ ρ,ω (I). The proof is in the appendix. 15 n

21 Then, the following proposition immediately follows Proposition 5. Assume that, i) the function B is increasing in the sum of agents efforts, i.e., n a i > i=1 n a i = B(a) > B(a ) i=1 ii) C F B (µ(a)) C F B (a) for every a A. Then there exists at least a symmetric first best profile. The proof is obvious since B(µ(a )) C F B (µ(a )) B(a ) C F B (a ) which implies that if a is a first best profile then also µ(a ) is a first best profile 9. In the next lemma we provide sufficient conditions to obtain condition (ii) in Proposition 5 in the case agents are symmetric. For the sake of simplicity denote in this case A 1 = = A n = {1,..., m} = S. Moreover, for every x [1, m] denote with N(x) = {s S such that x s 1} the discrete neighborood of x. Then Lemma 1. Assume that CF 1 B (s) = C2 F B (s) = = Cn F B (s) = c(s) for every s in S where c(s) is a discretely strict convex function in S, that is, given s, s S and α [0, 1] it follows that max s N(αs +(1 α)s ) c(s) αc(s ) + (1 α)c(s ). (4) Then C F B (µ(a)) C F B (a) for every a A. 10 This section has shown that symmetric first-best profiles arise naturally when the principal s benefit increases in the total amount of effort provided by the agents and the first-best cost features a convexity-like property. Note that the discretely strict convexity of C k F B follows from the analogous property for agent k disutility function G k. Finally, notice that those assumptions are only sufficient and it is simple to find examples where the first-best profile is symmetric despite the previous assumptions are not satisfied. 7 Conclusion In this paper, we examine the impact of intention-based reciprocity preferences on the multiple agent model. Our main result is that a principal will always prefer to hire reciprocal agents to implement a contract when the strategy profile is symmetric, while if profiles are 9 If the strategy sets were closed convex subsets of finite dimensional spaces then condition (ii) in n Proposition 5 could be replaced by C F B convex and by the following property: i=1 a i = n i=1 a i = C F B (a) = C F B (a ). 10 Note that the discretely strict convexity assumption used in the lemma is stronger than the discretely convexity assumption introduced in Miller (1991) where the max in (4) is replaced with min. Moreover, it can be easily checked that in the continuous (strategy set) case if we replace condition (ii) in Proposition 5 with the assumpion that agents are symmetric with a convex cost function c then we obtain again the existence of a symmetric first best profile. 16

22 asymmetric she might prefer self-interested to intention-based reciprocity agents. Moreover, we describe the agents psychological characteristics required to sustain a given strategy profile. Finally, since our main results underline the important role played by symmetry for reciprocity to be in the principal s best interest, we show when symmetric strategy profiles are most likely to arise. The current paper together with the companion one (De Marco and Immordino, 2010) on partnerships study natural environments for reciprocity to play a central role and are intended to be a step toward the economic analysis of teamwork and optimal team design in the presence of reciprocal agents. An important by-product of our analysis is to demonstrate that, despite their apparent complexity, intention-based reciprocity models can be useful to study economically relevant settings in a novel and simple way. 8 Appendix Proof of Proposition 1. From the assumptions it follows that, for every player k, ρ k ωk(a 2 k b kt) 2 (n 1)ρ k ωk 2 ν k (a ) G k (a k) G k (a k ) a k A k. (5) t k Moreover, let Îk the incentive scheme of player k defined by Î k q = { C k F B (a k ) if q J(a ) I if q Q \ J(a ) (6) In this case, we get E k (a, Îk ) = q Q π q (a )V k (C k F B(a k)) G k (a k) = V k (C k F B(a k)) G k (a k) while E k (a k, a k, Îk ) = q Q π q (a k, a k)v k (Îk q ) G k (a k ) = V k (CF k B(a k)) q J(a ) π q (a k, a k) + V k (I) Note that V k (I) V k (CF k B (a k )) which implies that V k (CF k B(a k)) q / J(a ) V k (C k F B(a k)) = q Q π q (a )V k (C k F B(a k)) q J(a ) π q (a k, a k) + V k (I) π q (a k, a k) G k (a k ). q / J(a ) Hence from the previous inequality and from (5) it follows that V k (C k F B(a k)) + t k π q (a k, a k). ω 2 k(a k b kt) 2 q Q π q (a k, a k)v k (Îk q ) + G k (a k) G k (a k ) a k A k. 17

23 which implies that E k (a, Îk ) E k (a k, a k, Îk ) ρ k ωk(a 2 k b kt) 2 a k A k \ {a k}. (7) t k If b kt = a t and c ktk = a k for all t k, then U k (a k, a k, (b kt) t k, (c ktk) t k ; Îk ) = E k (a, Îk ) and U k (a k, a k, (b kt) t k, (c ktk) t k ; Îk ) = E k (a k, a k, Îk ) ρ k ωk(a 2 k b kt) 2 t k a k A k \ {a k}. Since the previous arguments apply for every player k, then (7) implies that a is a psychological Nash equilibrium of Γ ρ,ω (Î), where each Îk is defined as in (6). Therefore (a, Î) satisfies the condition P ρ,ω-ic. Finally, since for every player k it follows that U k (a k, a k, (b kt) t k, (c ktk) t k ; Îk ) = E k (a, Îk ) = V k (C k F B(a k)) G k (a k) = u k then (a, Î) satisfies the condition P ρ,ω-ir. And the assertion follows. Proof of Proposition 2. The first best a is attainable, then it satisfies the P ρ,ω -IR conditions. Notice that since a is a symmetric strategy profile and P ρ,ω -IR involves correct beliefs then the P ρ,ω -IR condition is equivalent to the IR condition for material payoffs. Hence, following the same steps in Proposition 5 in Mookherjee (1984) we get that, given the strict concavity of V the principal can attain the first best only if each agent is paid a constant sum with probability one under a. Given that the contract is optimal, agent k will be paid CF k B (a k ) whenever the outcome belongs to J(a ). Now, without loss of generality, we assume that the principal always gives the minimum payment I for q / J(a ). Let b kt = a t and c ktk = a k for all t k. From the assumptions it follows that a satisfies the P ρ,ω -IC conditions under incentive schemes Î, then it is a psychological Nash equilibrium of Γ ρ,ω (Î). Hence, for every player k, it follows that U k (a k, a k, (b kt) t k, (c ktk) t k ; Îk ) U k (a k, a k, (b kt) t k, (c ktk) t k ; Îk ) a k A k \ {a k}, (8) where U k (a k, a k, (b kt) t k, (c ktk) t k ; Îk ) = E k (a, Îk ) and U k (a k, a k, (b kt) t k, (c ktk) t k ; Îk ) = E k (a k, a k, Îk ) ρ k ωk(a 2 k b kt) 2 t k a k A k \ {a k}. Condition (8) implies that ρ k ωk(a 2 k b kt) 2 E k (a k, a k, Îk ) E k (a, Îk ) = t k 18

24 V k (CF k B(a k)) q J(a ) [ πq (a k, a k) π q (a ) ] + V k (I) q / J(a ) Being V k (I) = 0 and taking the sum over a k A k we get θ k (n 1)M k (a k) = ρ k ωk 2 (a k b kt) 2 a k A k V k (CF k B(a k)) q J(a ) a k A k t k [ πq (a k, a k) π q (a ) ] π q (a k, a k) + G k (a k) G k (a k ). + ψ k (a k)v k (C k F B(a k)) + G k (a k) a k A k (G k (a k) G k (a k )) = Hence condition (3) holds and the assertion follows. Proof of Proposition 3. Assume that (a, I) is a (material) second best contract with a symmetric strategy profile. Fix reciprocity vectors (ρ, ω). Given the incentive schemes I and ɛ k 0 for all k N, denote with I ɛ = (Iɛ 1 1,..., Iɛ n n ) the incentive schemes defined by I k ɛ k,q = max{i, I k q ɛ k } k N, q Q. Denote with g k (ɛ k ) = E k (a, Iɛ k k ). It easily follows that each function g k is continuous and g k (0) u k for every k. Denote with N IR = {k N g k (0) > u k } which is not empty by assumption. Then for every k N IR there exists κ k such that g k (ɛ k ) > u k for all ɛ k < κ k. Hence the P ρ,ω -IR conditions are satisfied for every k N IR and ɛ k < κ k. For every k N IR and every a k A k \ {a k }, let h k (ɛ k, a k ) = q Q [ πq (a k, a k) π q (a ) ] [ V k (I k ɛ k,q) V k (I k q ) ]. For every a k A k \ {a k }, h k(0, a k ) = 0 and h k (, a k ) is continuous. Hence there exists κ k (a k ) such that θ k (a k a k) 2 [ πq (a k, a k) π q (a ) ] [ V k (Iɛ k k,q) V k (Iq k ) ] ɛ k κ k (a k ). q Q t k Therefore, if κ k = min ak A k \{a k } κ k (a k ) and ɛ k κ k, it follows that θ k (a k a k) 2 [ πq (a k, a k) π q (a ) ] [ V k (Iɛ k k,q) V k (Iq k ) ] a k A k \ {a k}. q Q t k Since (a, I) is a (material) second best contract then from the IC condition it follows that q Q V k (I k q ) [ π q (a k, a k) π q (a ) ] G k (a k) G k (a k ) a k A k \ {a k}. Hence for ɛ k κ k, it follows that [ πq (a k, a k) π q (a ) ] V k (Iɛ k k,q) + θ k (a k a k) 2 G k (a k) G k (a k ) a k A k \ {a k} q Q t k 19

25 which implies that q Q π q (a )V k (I k ɛ k,q) G k (a k) q Q π q (a k, a k)v k (I k ɛ k,q) G k (a k ) t k If b kt = a t and c ktk = a k for all t k, then θ k (a k a k) 2 a k A k \{a k}. (9) U k (a k, a k, (b kt) t k, (c ktk) t k ; I k ɛ ) = q Q π q (a )V k (I k ɛ k,q) G k (a k) and U k (a k, a k, (b kt) t k, (c ktk) t k ; Iɛ k ) = π q (a k, a k)v k (Iɛ k k,q) G k (a k ) θ k (a k b k,h ) 2 q Q t k Therefore, for every player k in N IR and every ɛ k κ k, a k A k \ {a k}. U k (a k, a k, (b kt) t k, (c ktk) t k ; I k ɛ ) U k (a k, a k, (b kt) t k, (c ktk) t k ; I k ɛ ) a k A k \ {a k}, (10) which finally implies that the P ρ,ω -IC conditions are satisfied for every player k in N IR and every ɛ k κ k. Consider a vector ɛ = (ɛ 1, ɛ 2,..., ɛ n ) { ɛk = 0 ifk / N IR 0 < ɛ k < min{κ k, κ k } ifk N IR. Denote with I = I ɛ. Previous arguments imply that for every k N IR, the contract (a, I) satisfies P ρ,ω -IR and P ρ,ω -IC. Now we consider players k / N IR. Note that if ɛ k = 0 one obviously gets that Iɛ k k = I k. Being (a, I) a (material) second best contract, then the contract (a, I) clearly satisfies the P ρ,ω -IR conditions also for every k / N IR since a is symmetric and the psychological term in the P ρ,ω -IR conditions disappears when beliefs are correct. Finally, if k / N IR, it follows that U k (a k, a k, (b kt) t k, (c ktk) t k ; Iɛ k ) = E k (a k, a k, Îk ɛ ) E k (a k, a k, Îk ɛ ) E k (a k, a k, Îk ɛ ) ρ k ωk(a 2 k b kt) 2 = U k (a k, a k, (b kt) t k, (c ktk) t k ; Iɛ k ) a k A k t k which implies that the P ρ,ω -IR conditions hold also for every k / N IR in the contract (a, I). Finally, by construction it follows that I k q = I k ε k,q I k q for every k N and q Q.. Let k N IR, then there exists q J(a ) such that I k q > I. It follows that Ik q = Iε k k, q < Ik q, which implies C(a, I) > C(a, I) (11) and the assertion follows. Proof of Proposition 4. From the assumptions it follows that, for every coalition T there exists a player k T such that θ k (a k a k) 2 (n T ))θ k ν k (a ) G k (a k) G k (a k ) a k A k. (12) t/ T 20

Module 8: Multi-Agent Models of Moral Hazard

Module 8: Multi-Agent Models of Moral Hazard Module 8: Multi-Agent Models of Moral Hazard Information Economics (Ec 515) George Georgiadis Types of models: 1. No relation among agents. an many agents make contracting easier? 2. Agents shocks are

More information

Moral hazard in teams

Moral hazard in teams Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences Moral hazard in teams KC Border November 2004 These notes are based on the first part of Moral hazard in teams by Bengt Holmström [1], and fills in the gaps

More information

Game Theory and Economics of Contracts Lecture 5 Static Single-agent Moral Hazard Model

Game Theory and Economics of Contracts Lecture 5 Static Single-agent Moral Hazard Model Game Theory and Economics of Contracts Lecture 5 Static Single-agent Moral Hazard Model Yu (Larry) Chen School of Economics, Nanjing University Fall 2015 Principal-Agent Relationship Principal-agent relationship

More information

Teoria das organizações e contratos

Teoria das organizações e contratos Teoria das organizações e contratos Chapter 6: Adverse Selection with two types Mestrado Profissional em Economia 3 o trimestre 2015 EESP (FGV) Teoria das organizações e contratos 3 o trimestre 2015 1

More information

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers September 6, 016 ONLINE APPENDIX In this Appendix we present in full additional results and extensions which are only mentioned in the paper. In the exposition

More information

Combinatorial Agency of Threshold Functions

Combinatorial Agency of Threshold Functions Combinatorial Agency of Threshold Functions Shaili Jain 1 and David C. Parkes 2 1 Yale University, New Haven, CT shaili.jain@yale.edu 2 Harvard University, Cambridge, MA parkes@eecs.harvard.edu Abstract.

More information

Microeconomic Theory (501b) Problem Set 10. Auctions and Moral Hazard Suggested Solution: Tibor Heumann

Microeconomic Theory (501b) Problem Set 10. Auctions and Moral Hazard Suggested Solution: Tibor Heumann Dirk Bergemann Department of Economics Yale University Microeconomic Theory (50b) Problem Set 0. Auctions and Moral Hazard Suggested Solution: Tibor Heumann 4/5/4 This problem set is due on Tuesday, 4//4..

More information

Mechanism Design: Basic Concepts

Mechanism Design: Basic Concepts Advanced Microeconomic Theory: Economics 521b Spring 2011 Juuso Välimäki Mechanism Design: Basic Concepts The setup is similar to that of a Bayesian game. The ingredients are: 1. Set of players, i {1,

More information

Kalai-Smorodinsky Bargaining Solution Equilibria

Kalai-Smorodinsky Bargaining Solution Equilibria WORKING PAPER NO. 235 Kalai-Smorodinsky Bargaining Solution Equilibria Giuseppe De Marco and Jacqueline Morgan July 2009 University of Naples Federico II University of Salerno Bocconi University, Milan

More information

Definitions and Proofs

Definitions and Proofs Giving Advice vs. Making Decisions: Transparency, Information, and Delegation Online Appendix A Definitions and Proofs A. The Informational Environment The set of states of nature is denoted by = [, ],

More information

Slightly Altruistic Equilibria in Normal Form Games

Slightly Altruistic Equilibria in Normal Form Games WORKING PAPER NO. 185 Slightly Altruistic Equilibria in Normal Form Games Giuseppe De Marco and Jacqueline Morgan October 2007 University of Naples Federico II University of Salerno Bocconi University,

More information

Competition relative to Incentive Functions in Common Agency

Competition relative to Incentive Functions in Common Agency Competition relative to Incentive Functions in Common Agency Seungjin Han May 20, 2011 Abstract In common agency problems, competing principals often incentivize a privately-informed agent s action choice

More information

Theory Field Examination Game Theory (209A) Jan Question 1 (duopoly games with imperfect information)

Theory Field Examination Game Theory (209A) Jan Question 1 (duopoly games with imperfect information) Theory Field Examination Game Theory (209A) Jan 200 Good luck!!! Question (duopoly games with imperfect information) Consider a duopoly game in which the inverse demand function is linear where it is positive

More information

Other-Regarding Preferences in Organizational Hierarchies

Other-Regarding Preferences in Organizational Hierarchies ERC Working Papers in Economics 18/02 February / 2018 Other-Regarding Preferences in Organizational Hierarchies Kemal Saygili Department of Economics, Middle East Technical University, Ankara, Turkey E-mail:

More information

Informed Principal in Private-Value Environments

Informed Principal in Private-Value Environments Informed Principal in Private-Value Environments Tymofiy Mylovanov Thomas Tröger University of Bonn June 21, 2008 1/28 Motivation 2/28 Motivation In most applications of mechanism design, the proposer

More information

Epsilon Ex Post Implementation

Epsilon Ex Post Implementation Epsilon Ex Post Implementation Mehmet Barlo Nuh Aygun Dalkiran February 10, 2014 Abstract We provide necessary and sufficient conditions for epsilon ex post implementation. Our analysis extends Bergemann

More information

Moral Hazard: Hidden Action

Moral Hazard: Hidden Action Moral Hazard: Hidden Action Part of these Notes were taken (almost literally) from Rasmusen, 2007 UIB Course 2013-14 (UIB) MH-Hidden Actions Course 2013-14 1 / 29 A Principal-agent Model. The Production

More information

1. The General Linear-Quadratic Framework

1. The General Linear-Quadratic Framework ECO 317 Economics of Uncertainty Fall Term 2009 Slides to accompany 21. Incentives for Effort - Multi-Dimensional Cases 1. The General Linear-Quadratic Framework Notation: x = (x j ), n-vector of agent

More information

A New and Robust Subgame Perfect Equilibrium in a model of Triadic Power Relations *

A New and Robust Subgame Perfect Equilibrium in a model of Triadic Power Relations * A New and Robust Subgame Perfect Equilibrium in a model of Triadic Power Relations * by Magnus Hatlebakk ** Department of Economics, University of Bergen Abstract: We present a new subgame perfect equilibrium

More information

The Value of Symmetric Information in an Agency Model with Moral Hazard: The Ex Post Contracting Case

The Value of Symmetric Information in an Agency Model with Moral Hazard: The Ex Post Contracting Case Faculty of Business and Law SCHOOL OF ACCOUNTING, ECONOMICS AND FINANCE School Working Paper - Economic Series 2006 SWP 2006/24 The Value of Symmetric Information in an Agency Model with Moral Hazard:

More information

1 Web Appendix: Equilibrium outcome under collusion (multiple types-multiple contracts)

1 Web Appendix: Equilibrium outcome under collusion (multiple types-multiple contracts) 1 Web Appendix: Equilibrium outcome under collusion (multiple types-multiple contracts) We extend our setup by allowing more than two types of agent. The agent s type is now β {β 1, β 2,..., β N }, where

More information

This is designed for one 75-minute lecture using Games and Information. October 3, 2006

This is designed for one 75-minute lecture using Games and Information. October 3, 2006 This is designed for one 75-minute lecture using Games and Information. October 3, 2006 1 7 Moral Hazard: Hidden Actions PRINCIPAL-AGENT MODELS The principal (or uninformed player) is the player who has

More information

NEGOTIATION-PROOF CORRELATED EQUILIBRIUM

NEGOTIATION-PROOF CORRELATED EQUILIBRIUM DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS UNIVERSITY OF CYPRUS NEGOTIATION-PROOF CORRELATED EQUILIBRIUM Nicholas Ziros Discussion Paper 14-2011 P.O. Box 20537, 1678 Nicosia, CYPRUS Tel.: +357-22893700, Fax: +357-22895028

More information

Moral Hazard in Teams

Moral Hazard in Teams Moral Hazard in Teams Ram Singh Department of Economics September 23, 2009 Ram Singh (Delhi School of Economics) Moral Hazard September 23, 2009 1 / 30 Outline 1 Moral Hazard in Teams: Model 2 Unobservable

More information

Contracts in informed-principal problems with moral hazard

Contracts in informed-principal problems with moral hazard Contracts in informed-principal problems with moral hazard Nicholas C Bedard January 20, 2016 Abstract In many cases, an employer has private information about the potential productivity of a worker, who

More information

Assignment Games with Externalities

Assignment Games with Externalities Working Paper 2013:27 Department of Economics School of Economics and Management Assignment Games with Externalities Jens Gudmundsson Helga Habis August 2013 Assignment Games with Externalities Jens Gudmundsson

More information

Bayes Correlated Equilibrium and Comparing Information Structures

Bayes Correlated Equilibrium and Comparing Information Structures Bayes Correlated Equilibrium and Comparing Information Structures Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris Spring 2013: 521 B Introduction game theoretic predictions are very sensitive to "information structure"

More information

Contracts under Asymmetric Information

Contracts under Asymmetric Information Contracts under Asymmetric Information 1 I Aristotle, economy (oiko and nemo) and the idea of exchange values, subsequently adapted by Ricardo and Marx. Classical economists. An economy consists of a set

More information

Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 5: Cheap Talk. Patrick Legros

Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 5: Cheap Talk. Patrick Legros Graduate Microeconomics II Lecture 5: Cheap Talk Patrick Legros 1 / 35 Outline Cheap talk 2 / 35 Outline Cheap talk Crawford-Sobel Welfare 3 / 35 Outline Cheap talk Crawford-Sobel Welfare Partially Verifiable

More information

NTU IO (I) : Auction Theory and Mechanism Design II Groves Mechanism and AGV Mechansim. u i (x, t i, θ i ) = V i (x, θ i ) + t i,

NTU IO (I) : Auction Theory and Mechanism Design II Groves Mechanism and AGV Mechansim. u i (x, t i, θ i ) = V i (x, θ i ) + t i, Meng-Yu Liang NTU O : Auction Theory and Mechanism Design Groves Mechanism and AGV Mechansim + 1 players. Types are drawn from independent distribution P i on [θ i, θ i ] with strictly positive and differentiable

More information

Government 2005: Formal Political Theory I

Government 2005: Formal Political Theory I Government 2005: Formal Political Theory I Lecture 11 Instructor: Tommaso Nannicini Teaching Fellow: Jeremy Bowles Harvard University November 9, 2017 Overview * Today s lecture Dynamic games of incomplete

More information

Appendix of Homophily in Peer Groups The Costly Information Case

Appendix of Homophily in Peer Groups The Costly Information Case Appendix of Homophily in Peer Groups The Costly Information Case Mariagiovanna Baccara Leeat Yariv August 19, 2012 1 Introduction In this Appendix we study the information sharing application analyzed

More information

Hidden information. Principal s payoff: π (e) w,

Hidden information. Principal s payoff: π (e) w, Hidden information Section 14.C. in MWG We still consider a setting with information asymmetries between the principal and agent. However, the effort is now perfectly observable. What is unobservable?

More information

Correlated Equilibrium in Games with Incomplete Information

Correlated Equilibrium in Games with Incomplete Information Correlated Equilibrium in Games with Incomplete Information Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris Econometric Society Summer Meeting June 2012 Robust Predictions Agenda game theoretic predictions are very

More information

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract Pure strategy dominance with quasiconcave utility functions Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam Abstract By a result of Pearce (1984), in a finite strategic form game, the set of a player's serially

More information

Robust Predictions in Games with Incomplete Information

Robust Predictions in Games with Incomplete Information Robust Predictions in Games with Incomplete Information joint with Stephen Morris (Princeton University) November 2010 Payoff Environment in games with incomplete information, the agents are uncertain

More information

1 Moral Hazard: Multiple Agents 1.1 Moral Hazard in a Team

1 Moral Hazard: Multiple Agents 1.1 Moral Hazard in a Team 1 Moral Hazard: Multiple Agents 1.1 Moral Hazard in a Team Multiple agents (firm?) Partnership: Q jointly affected Individual q i s. (tournaments) Common shocks, cooperations, collusion, monitor- ing.

More information

On the Pareto Efficiency of a Socially Optimal Mechanism for Monopoly Regulation

On the Pareto Efficiency of a Socially Optimal Mechanism for Monopoly Regulation MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive On the Pareto Efficiency of a Socially Optimal Mechanism for Monopoly Regulation Ismail Saglam Ipek University 4 May 2016 Online at https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/71090/

More information

Price of Stability in Survivable Network Design

Price of Stability in Survivable Network Design Noname manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Price of Stability in Survivable Network Design Elliot Anshelevich Bugra Caskurlu Received: January 2010 / Accepted: Abstract We study the survivable

More information

Ex Post Cheap Talk : Value of Information and Value of Signals

Ex Post Cheap Talk : Value of Information and Value of Signals Ex Post Cheap Talk : Value of Information and Value of Signals Liping Tang Carnegie Mellon University, Pittsburgh PA 15213, USA Abstract. Crawford and Sobel s Cheap Talk model [1] describes an information

More information

Minimum Wages and Excessive E ort Supply

Minimum Wages and Excessive E ort Supply Minimum Wages and Excessive E ort Supply Matthias Kräkel y Anja Schöttner z Abstract It is well-known that, in static models, minimum wages generate positive worker rents and, consequently, ine ciently

More information

Dynamic Common Agency

Dynamic Common Agency Dynamic Common Agency Dirk Bergemann Juuso Välimäki January 2001 Abstract A general model of dynamic common agency with symmetric information is considered. The set of truthful Markov perfect equilibrium

More information

ONLINE APPENDICES FOR INCENTIVES IN EXPERIMENTS: A THEORETICAL INVESTIGATION BY AZRIELI, CHAMBERS & HEALY

ONLINE APPENDICES FOR INCENTIVES IN EXPERIMENTS: A THEORETICAL INVESTIGATION BY AZRIELI, CHAMBERS & HEALY ONLINE APPENDICES FOR INCENTIVES IN EXPERIMENTS: A THEORETICAL INVESTIGATION BY AZRIELI, CHAMBERS & HEALY Appendix B. Modeling Games as Decisions In this appendix we describe how one can move seamlessly

More information

Equilibrium Refinements

Equilibrium Refinements Equilibrium Refinements Mihai Manea MIT Sequential Equilibrium In many games information is imperfect and the only subgame is the original game... subgame perfect equilibrium = Nash equilibrium Play starting

More information

Organizational Barriers to Technology Adoption: Evidence from Soccer-Ball Producers in Pakistan

Organizational Barriers to Technology Adoption: Evidence from Soccer-Ball Producers in Pakistan Organizational Barriers to Technology Adoption: Evidence from Soccer-Ball Producers in Pakistan David Atkin, Azam Chaudhry, Shamyla Chaudry Amit K. Khandelwal and Eric Verhoogen Sept. 016 Appendix B: Theory

More information

Costly Expertise. Dino Gerardi and Leeat Yariv yz. Current Version: December, 2007

Costly Expertise. Dino Gerardi and Leeat Yariv yz. Current Version: December, 2007 Costly Expertise Dino Gerardi and Leeat Yariv yz Current Version: December, 007 In many environments expertise is costly. Costs can manifest themselves in numerous ways, ranging from the time that is required

More information

General idea. Firms can use competition between agents for. We mainly focus on incentives. 1 incentive and. 2 selection purposes 3 / 101

General idea. Firms can use competition between agents for. We mainly focus on incentives. 1 incentive and. 2 selection purposes 3 / 101 3 Tournaments 3.1 Motivation General idea Firms can use competition between agents for 1 incentive and 2 selection purposes We mainly focus on incentives 3 / 101 Main characteristics Agents fulll similar

More information

What happens when there are many agents? Threre are two problems:

What happens when there are many agents? Threre are two problems: Moral Hazard in Teams What happens when there are many agents? Threre are two problems: i) If many agents produce a joint output x, how does one assign the output? There is a free rider problem here as

More information

Controlling versus enabling Online appendix

Controlling versus enabling Online appendix Controlling versus enabling Online appendix Andrei Hagiu and Julian Wright September, 017 Section 1 shows the sense in which Proposition 1 and in Section 4 of the main paper hold in a much more general

More information

Guilt aversion in trust games

Guilt aversion in trust games Guilt aversion in trust games Elena Manzoni Università degli Studi di Milano Bicocca MMRG, 5 May 01 E. Manzoni Bicocca 5/5 1 / 31 Plan of the talk Trust games Experimental results Psychological games Attanasi

More information

x ax 1 2 bx2 a bx =0 x = a b. Hence, a consumer s willingness-to-pay as a function of liters on sale, 1 2 a 2 2b, if l> a. (1)

x ax 1 2 bx2 a bx =0 x = a b. Hence, a consumer s willingness-to-pay as a function of liters on sale, 1 2 a 2 2b, if l> a. (1) Answers to Exam Economics 201b First Half 1. (a) Observe, first, that no consumer ever wishes to consume more than 3/2 liters (i.e., 1.5 liters). To see this, observe that, even if the beverage were free,

More information

Weak Robust (Virtual) Implementation

Weak Robust (Virtual) Implementation Weak Robust (Virtual) Implementation Chih-Chun Yang Institute of Economics, Academia Sinica, Taipei 115, Taiwan April 2016 Abstract We provide a characterization of (virtual) implementation in iterated

More information

An Infinitely Farsighted Stable Set

An Infinitely Farsighted Stable Set An Infinitely Farsighted Stable Set By Parkash Chander * May 2015 Revised: November 2015 Abstract In this paper, we first introduce and characterize a new and general concept of a credible deviation in

More information

A Theory of Financing Constraints and Firm Dynamics by Clementi and Hopenhayn - Quarterly Journal of Economics (2006)

A Theory of Financing Constraints and Firm Dynamics by Clementi and Hopenhayn - Quarterly Journal of Economics (2006) A Theory of Financing Constraints and Firm Dynamics by Clementi and Hopenhayn - Quarterly Journal of Economics (2006) A Presentation for Corporate Finance 1 Graduate School of Economics December, 2009

More information

Fall 2017 Recitation 10 Notes

Fall 2017 Recitation 10 Notes 14.770-Fall 017 Recitation 10 Notes Arda Gitmez December 8, 017 Today: Why incentives can backfire Holmstrom and Milgrom s multitasking model (1991, JLEO) Two papers by Benabou and Tirole (003, REStud

More information

Knightian uncertainty and moral hazard

Knightian uncertainty and moral hazard Journal of Economic Theory 146 (2011) 1148 1172 www.elsevier.com/locate/jet Knightian uncertainty and moral hazard Giuseppe Lopomo a, Luca Rigotti b,, Chris Shannon c a Fuqua School of Business, Duke University,

More information

Disguising Lies - Image Concerns and Partial Lying in Cheating Games

Disguising Lies - Image Concerns and Partial Lying in Cheating Games Disguising Lies - Image Concerns and Partial Lying in Cheating Games Kiryl Khalmetski Dirk Sliwka February 3, 207 Abstract We study equilibrium reporting behavior in Fischbacher and Föllmi- Heusi (203)

More information

Optimal Shirking in Teams

Optimal Shirking in Teams Optimal Shirking in Teams Hajime Kobayashi Osaka Prefecture University Katsunori Ohta Wakayama University November 18, 2009 Tadashi Sekiguchi Kyoto University Abstract We study a model of repeated team

More information

Termination of Dynamic Contracts in an Equilibrium Labor Market Model

Termination of Dynamic Contracts in an Equilibrium Labor Market Model Termination of Dynamic Contracts in an Equilibrium Labor Market Model Cheng Wang First version: May, 2004 Final version: February, 2006 Abstract I construct an equilibrium model of the labor market where

More information

Intentions and Ex-Post Implementation

Intentions and Ex-Post Implementation Intentions and Ex-Post Implementation Nick Netzer André Volk University of Zurich January 2014 Abstract Intention-based reciprocity is an important motivation for human behavior, and it can be exploited

More information

A technical appendix for multihoming and compatibility

A technical appendix for multihoming and compatibility A technical appendix for multihoming and compatibility Toker Doganoglu and Julian Wright July 19, 2005 We would like to thank two anonymous referees and our editor, Simon Anderson, for their very helpful

More information

Investor s Increased Shareholding due to Entrepreneur Manager Collusion

Investor s Increased Shareholding due to Entrepreneur Manager Collusion Investor s Increased Shareholding due to Entrepreneur Manager Collusion Özgün Atasoy Sabancı University Mehmet Barlo Sabancı University August, 2007 Abstract This study presents an investor/entrepreneur

More information

Crowdsourcing contests

Crowdsourcing contests December 8, 2012 Table of contents 1 Introduction 2 Related Work 3 Model: Basics 4 Model: Participants 5 Homogeneous Effort 6 Extensions Table of Contents 1 Introduction 2 Related Work 3 Model: Basics

More information

RECIPROCAL RELATIONSHIPS AND MECHANISM DESIGN

RECIPROCAL RELATIONSHIPS AND MECHANISM DESIGN RECIPROCAL RELATIONSHIPS AND MECHANISM DESIGN GORKEM CELIK AND MICHAEL PETERS A. We study an incomplete information game in which players can coordinate their actions by contracting among themselves. We

More information

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Emir Kamenica and Matthew Gentzkow University of Chicago June 2010 1 Persuasion mechanisms In this paper we study a particular game where Sender chooses a signal π whose

More information

Impatience vs. Incentives

Impatience vs. Incentives Impatience vs. Incentives Marcus Opp John Zhu University of California, Berkeley (Haas) & University of Pennsylvania, Wharton January 2015 Opp, Zhu (UC, Wharton) Impatience vs. Incentives January 2015

More information

Game Theory Fall 2003

Game Theory Fall 2003 Game Theory Fall 2003 Problem Set 1 [1] In this problem (see FT Ex. 1.1) you are asked to play with arbitrary 2 2 games just to get used to the idea of equilibrium computation. Specifically, consider the

More information

Negotiation and Take it or Leave it in Common Agency

Negotiation and Take it or Leave it in Common Agency Negotiation and Take it or Leave it in Common Agency Michael Peters Department of Economics University of Toronto 150 St. George St. Toronto, Canada M5S 3G7 email:peters@economics.utoronto.ca First Draft

More information

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7).

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). The axiomatic approach (OR 15) Nash s (1950) work is the starting point

More information

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Midterm Exam #2 - Answer Key

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Midterm Exam #2 - Answer Key EconS 50 - Microeconomic Theory II Midterm Exam # - Answer Key 1. Revenue comparison in two auction formats. Consider a sealed-bid auction with bidders. Every bidder i privately observes his valuation

More information

NASH IMPLEMENTATION USING SIMPLE MECHANISMS WITHOUT UNDESIRABLE MIXED-STRATEGY EQUILIBRIA

NASH IMPLEMENTATION USING SIMPLE MECHANISMS WITHOUT UNDESIRABLE MIXED-STRATEGY EQUILIBRIA NASH IMPLEMENTATION USING SIMPLE MECHANISMS WITHOUT UNDESIRABLE MIXED-STRATEGY EQUILIBRIA MARIA GOLTSMAN Abstract. This note shows that, in separable environments, any monotonic social choice function

More information

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E.

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E. Tilburg University On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E. Publication date: 1997 Link to publication General rights Copyright and

More information

Optimal Contracts with Imperfect Monitoring

Optimal Contracts with Imperfect Monitoring Optimal Contracts with Imperfect Monitoring Harrison Cheng University of Southern California visiting Kyoto Institute of Economic Research March, 2004 Abstract We use the duality in linear programming

More information

General equilibrium with externalities and tradable licenses

General equilibrium with externalities and tradable licenses General equilibrium with externalities and tradable licenses Carlos Hervés-Beloso RGEA. Universidad de Vigo. e-mail: cherves@uvigo.es Emma Moreno-García Universidad de Salamanca. e-mail: emmam@usal.es

More information

Martin Gregor IES, Charles University. Abstract

Martin Gregor IES, Charles University. Abstract On the strategic non-complementarity of complements Martin Gregor IES, Charles University Abstract This paper examines the equilibrium provision of a public good if the private monetary contributions of

More information

Intrinsic and Extrinsic Motivation

Intrinsic and Extrinsic Motivation Intrinsic and Extrinsic Motivation Roland Bénabou Jean Tirole. Review of Economic Studies 2003 Bénabou and Tirole Intrinsic and Extrinsic Motivation 1 / 30 Motivation Should a child be rewarded for passing

More information

Introduction to Game Theory

Introduction to Game Theory Introduction to Game Theory Part 3. Dynamic games of incomplete information Chapter 3. Job Market Signaling Ciclo Profissional 2 o Semestre / 2011 Graduação em Ciências Econômicas V. Filipe Martins-da-Rocha

More information

EC476 Contracts and Organizations, Part III: Lecture 2

EC476 Contracts and Organizations, Part III: Lecture 2 EC476 Contracts and Organizations, Part III: Lecture 2 Leonardo Felli 32L.G.06 19 January 2015 Moral Hazard: Consider the contractual relationship between two agents (a principal and an agent) The principal

More information

Supervision, Collusion, and Optimal Contract Design with Costly Information Acquisition

Supervision, Collusion, and Optimal Contract Design with Costly Information Acquisition Supervision, Collusion, and Optimal Contract Design with Costly Information Acquisition XiaoGang Che Guanxi Yi PRELIMINARY and INCOMPLETE November 2014 Abstract In this paper, we study the impacts of costly

More information

Asymmetric Information and Search Frictions: A Neutrality Result

Asymmetric Information and Search Frictions: A Neutrality Result Asymmetric Information and Search Frictions: A Neutrality Result Neel Rao University at Buffalo, SUNY August 26, 2016 Abstract This paper integrates asymmetric information between firms into a canonical

More information

Introduction. 1 University of Pennsylvania, Wharton Finance Department, Steinberg Hall-Dietrich Hall, 3620

Introduction. 1 University of Pennsylvania, Wharton Finance Department, Steinberg Hall-Dietrich Hall, 3620 May 16, 2006 Philip Bond 1 Are cheap talk and hard evidence both needed in the courtroom? Abstract: In a recent paper, Bull and Watson (2004) present a formal model of verifiability in which cheap messages

More information

Lecture Slides - Part 4

Lecture Slides - Part 4 Lecture Slides - Part 4 Bengt Holmstrom MIT February 2, 2016. Bengt Holmstrom (MIT) Lecture Slides - Part 4 February 2, 2016. 1 / 65 Mechanism Design n agents i = 1,..., n agent i has type θ i Θ i which

More information

Social Choice and Welfare Epsilon-Ex Post Implementation

Social Choice and Welfare Epsilon-Ex Post Implementation Social Choice and Welfare Epsilon-Ex Post Implementation --Manuscript Draft-- Manuscript Number: Full Title: Article Type: Corresponding Author: Epsilon-Ex Post Implementation Original Paper Nuh Aygun

More information

On the Interaction between Heterogeneity and Decay in Two-way Flow Models*

On the Interaction between Heterogeneity and Decay in Two-way Flow Models* On the Interaction between Heterogeneity and Decay in Two-way Flow Models* pascal billand a, christophe bravard a, sudipta sarangi b a Université de Lyon, Lyon, F-69003, France ; Université Jean Monnet,

More information

Supplementary appendix to the paper Hierarchical cheap talk Not for publication

Supplementary appendix to the paper Hierarchical cheap talk Not for publication Supplementary appendix to the paper Hierarchical cheap talk Not for publication Attila Ambrus, Eduardo M. Azevedo, and Yuichiro Kamada December 3, 011 1 Monotonicity of the set of pure-strategy equilibria

More information

Moral hazard with discrete soft information

Moral hazard with discrete soft information Moral hazard with discrete soft information September 2012 Abstract I study a simple model of moral hazard with soft information. The risk-averse agent takes an action and she alone observes the stochastic

More information

A new perspective to rational expectations: maximin rational expectations equilibrium

A new perspective to rational expectations: maximin rational expectations equilibrium A new perspective to rational expectations: maximin rational expectations equilibrium Luciano I. de Castro 1 Marialaura Pesce 2 and Nicholas C. Yannelis 3 First Draft: October, 2010 Current Draft: April

More information

Notes on Coursera s Game Theory

Notes on Coursera s Game Theory Notes on Coursera s Game Theory Manoel Horta Ribeiro Week 01: Introduction and Overview Game theory is about self interested agents interacting within a specific set of rules. Self-Interested Agents have

More information

SURPLUS SHARING WITH A TWO-STAGE MECHANISM. By Todd R. Kaplan and David Wettstein 1. Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel. 1.

SURPLUS SHARING WITH A TWO-STAGE MECHANISM. By Todd R. Kaplan and David Wettstein 1. Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel. 1. INTERNATIONAL ECONOMIC REVIEW Vol. 41, No. 2, May 2000 SURPLUS SHARING WITH A TWO-STAGE MECHANISM By Todd R. Kaplan and David Wettstein 1 Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel In this article we consider

More information

Econ 618: Correlated Equilibrium

Econ 618: Correlated Equilibrium Econ 618: Correlated Equilibrium Sunanda Roy 1 Basic Concept of a Correlated Equilibrium MSNE assumes players use a random device privately and independently, that tells them which strategy to choose for

More information

A New Class of Non Existence Examples for the Moral Hazard Problem

A New Class of Non Existence Examples for the Moral Hazard Problem A New Class of Non Existence Examples for the Moral Hazard Problem Sofia Moroni and Jeroen Swinkels April, 23 Abstract We provide a class of counter-examples to existence in a simple moral hazard problem

More information

Area I: Contract Theory Question (Econ 206)

Area I: Contract Theory Question (Econ 206) Theory Field Exam Winter 2011 Instructions You must complete two of the three areas (the areas being (I) contract theory, (II) game theory, and (III) psychology & economics). Be sure to indicate clearly

More information

COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY: CORE AND SHAPLEY VALUE

COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY: CORE AND SHAPLEY VALUE 1 / 54 COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY: CORE AND SHAPLEY VALUE Heinrich H. Nax hnax@ethz.ch & Bary S. R. Pradelski bpradelski@ethz.ch February 26, 2018: Lecture 2 2 / 54 What you did last week... There appear

More information

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Ozan Candogan, Asuman Ozdaglar and Pablo A. Parrilo September 6, 2011 Abstract Potential games are a special class of games for which many adaptive user dynamics

More information

Subjective Evaluation in the Agency Contract and the Reputation of the Principal

Subjective Evaluation in the Agency Contract and the Reputation of the Principal Subjective Evaluation in the Agency Contract and the Reputation of the Principal Shinsuke Kambe*** Faculty of Economics Gakushuin University 1-5-1 Mejiro Toshima-ku, Tokyo 171-8588 Japan October 2005 *

More information

Guilt in Games. P. Battigalli and M. Dufwenberg (AER, 2007) Presented by Luca Ferocino. March 21 st,2014

Guilt in Games. P. Battigalli and M. Dufwenberg (AER, 2007) Presented by Luca Ferocino. March 21 st,2014 Guilt in Games P. Battigalli and M. Dufwenberg (AER, 2007) Presented by Luca Ferocino March 21 st,2014 P. Battigalli and M. Dufwenberg (AER, 2007) Guilt in Games 1 / 29 ADefinitionofGuilt Guilt is a cognitive

More information

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance Geoffroy de Clippel February 2010 Nehring (2004) proposes an interesting methodology to extend the utilitarian criterion defined under complete information to an

More information

Farsighted stability of collusive price leadership. Yoshio Kamijo and Shigeo Muto Discussion Paper No

Farsighted stability of collusive price leadership. Yoshio Kamijo and Shigeo Muto Discussion Paper No Farsighted stability of collusive price leadership Yoshio Kamijo and Shigeo Muto Discussion Paper No. 07-09 August 2007 Farsighted stability of collusive price leadership Yoshio Kamijo and Shigeo Muto

More information

EC319 Economic Theory and Its Applications, Part II: Lecture 7

EC319 Economic Theory and Its Applications, Part II: Lecture 7 EC319 Economic Theory and Its Applications, Part II: Lecture 7 Leonardo Felli NAB.2.14 27 February 2014 Signalling Games Consider the following Bayesian game: Set of players: N = {N, S, }, Nature N strategy

More information

On the Informed Principal Model with Common Values

On the Informed Principal Model with Common Values On the Informed Principal Model with Common Values Anastasios Dosis ESSEC Business School and THEMA École Polytechnique/CREST, 3/10/2018 Anastasios Dosis (ESSEC and THEMA) Informed Principal with Common

More information