Purification and roulette wheels

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Purification and roulette wheels"

Transcription

1 Economic Theory manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Purification and roulette wheels Michael Greinecker Konrad Podczeck Received: date / Accepted: date Abstract We use concepts introduced by Aumann more than thirty years ago to throw new light on purification in games with extremely dispersed private information. We show that one can embed payoff-irrelevant randomization devices in the private information of players and use these randomization devices to implement mixed strategies as deterministic functions of the private information. This approach gives rise to very short and intuitive proofs for a number of purification results that previously required sophisticated methods from functional analysis or nonstandard analysis. We use our methods to prove the first general purification theorem for games with private information in which a player s payoffs can depend in arbitrary ways on events in the private information of other players and in which we allow for shared information in a general way. Keywords purification games with incomplete information roulette wheels JEL Classification C72 1 Introduction In this paper we explore a new road to purification results. In the early days of game theory, mixed strategies have been interpreted as deliberate acts of randomization based on randomization devices. Robert Aumann took the step to explicitly model We are grateful to Rabeè Tourky and Nicholas Yannelis. Discussions with them on existence of purestrategy equilibria and the relation between randomization and decomposability techniques inspired this research. M. Greinecker Institut für Wirtschaftstheorie, Universität Innsbruck, SOWI-Gebäude, Universitätsstraße 15, A-6020, Austria michael.greinecker@uibk.ac.at K. Podczeck Institut für Volkswirtschaftslehre, Universität Wien, Oskar-Morgenstern-Platz 1, A-1010 Wien, Austria konrad.podczeck@univie.ac.at

2 2 Michael Greinecker, Konrad Podczeck such randomization devices. In Aumann (1964), he used explicit randomization devices to bypass measurability problems with mixing over measurable functions, and in Aumann (1974) he allows a player to condition on payoff-irrelevant information to study the role of subjectivity and correlation. If this information is private and includes an atomless algebra of events independent of the private information of other players, a secret roulette wheel in the terminology of Aumann, the player can use these events to implement all mixed strategies as deterministic functions of the private information. We use these ideas to provide elementary and intuitive proofs of recent purification results, and even generalize them. Moreover, we use our method to give a very general purification theorem for games with incomplete information. This latter result is the first purification result for games in which payoffs may depend in an arbitrary way on players types and in which general forms of public information are allowed for. Purification has a long history in game theory. Bayesian decision theory based on expect utility implies that players have no incentives to randomize, because mixed optimal choices must be mixtures over optimal deterministic choices. Applied game theorists have therefore often expressed a preference for equilibria in pure strategies. But the convexifying effect of randomization often guarantees that an equilibrium in mixed strategies exists. Purification theorems allow a researcher to construct pure strategy equilibria out of mixed strategy equilibria. The seminal papers 1 in this category are Dvoretzky, Wald, and Wolfowitz (1950), Dvoretzky et al (1951), Radner and Rosenthal (1982), Milgrom and Weber (1985), Balder (2008), and Khan and Rath (2009). These results are based on players having private information that gives rise to an atomless distribution and action spaces being finite or countably infinite. Mixed strategy equilibria can be shown to exist in great generality, 2 so this approach is quite powerful. These earlier purification results have never been extended to general compact metric action spaces. Indeed, an example in Khan, Rath, and Sun (1999) shows that this cannot be done when private information is assumed to be merely atomless. The first positive result to overcome this problem was given in Loeb and Sun (2006), where the authors used nonstandard analysis to extend the approach of Dvoretzky- Wald-Wolfowitz to atomless Loeb spaces and general compact metric spaces. They then applied this result to obtain a strong purification result for games with incomplete information in which players have general compact metric action spaces and private information is modeled by a Loeb probability space. It was subsequently shown in Podczeck (2009) that one can replace Loeb spaces by a much larger class of probability spaces, called super-atomless in that paper, and that theses spaces can be actually characterized as those spaces for which the abstract purification result holds. Mathematically, Podczeck used extreme point methods as introduced in Lindenstrauss (1966). Another proof of this more general purification result was subsequently given in Loeb and Sun (2009), which used the result in Loeb and Sun (2006) and methods developed in Hoover and Keisler (1984). A further strengthening of 1 We do not discuss purification based on perturbing the game as in Harsanyi (1973) and Govindan, Reny, and Robson (2003). See Morris (2008) for a comparison of these approaches. 2 See for example Milgrom and Weber (1985) and Balder (1988).

3 Liapounoff s theorem in Banach spaces 3 these results, based on machinery in Sun (2006) and Podczeck (2010), was given in Wang and Zhang (2012), showing that continuity and compactness assumptions required in earlier results can be dispensed with. Wang and Zhang thereby showed that purification is a purely measure theoretic problem. Along these lines, we present two abstract purification results in Section 3 below (Theorems 2 and 3). However, our proofs of these results substantially differ from the proofs found in the papers mentioned above, and are much simpler. In fact, our proofs are a straightforward application of the idea that a roulette wheel can be used to reproduce random distributions in an abstract setting (Theorem 1 in Section 3). In Section 4, we apply our approach to obtain a purification theorem for games with private information, our Theorem 4. In contrast to all previous purification theorems, a player s payoff may depend in arbitrary ways on the states of the world. We do not require a player s utility function to be measurable with respect to her private information or, in the language of Bayesian games, to depend only on her own type. We also allow for players to receive arbitrary Borel measurable signals about the private information of other players. We set our purification result in the framework of Aumann (1974), augmented by state dependent utility. This framework incorporates Bayesian games as a special case. 3 As will become clear, this level of generality is possible by identifying roulette wheels in the private information of players that players can use to mimic mixed strategies. The same idea will illuminate the saturation principle (for probability spaces) in Hoover and Keisler (1984) and we show that it can be seen as a purification principle in its own right in Section 5. In Section 6, we relate our work to a recent paper by He and Sun (2014) on games with incomplete information and to the problem of equilibrium existence in games with a continuum of players. Finally, in Section 7, we discuss the economic relevance of using super-atomless probability spaces. Closing the introduction, we remark that the classical purification results in Dvoretzky et al (1950), Dvoretzky et al (1951), Radner and Rosenthal (1982), Milgrom and Weber (1985), Balder (2008), and Khan and Rath (2009) do not depend on players being able to condition on payoff-irrelevant information. Thus our arguments cannot be applied to these settings directly. 2 Preliminaries This section contains several mathematical facts and introduces some terminology. These facts are largely well known, we collect them here for ease of reference. We start by introducing some notation and terminology. If U, V, and W are sets, and f : U V and g: U W are functions, then ( f,g) denotes the parallel product 3 A far reaching generalization of Aumann s framework can be found in Grant, Meneghel, and Tourky (2013), where the authors are able to prove the existence of pure strategy equilibria by employing a novel fixed-point theorem from Meneghel and Tourky (2013), in which convexity assumptions are replaced by a decomposability assumption from nonlinear analysis. They obtain pure strategy equilibria in Bayesian games directly without purifying mixed strategy equilibria. It is not clear to us whether a general purification result would hold in their framework, as their assumptions are not directly comparable to ours.

4 4 Michael Greinecker, Konrad Podczeck of f and g; thus ( f,g)(u) = ( f (u),g(u)) for each u U. By ι X we denote the identity on a set X. If Ω is a set and F 2 Ω, we denote by σ(f ) the smallest σ-algebra under set inclusion that contains F and call it the σ-algebra generated by F. A σ-algebra Σ on Ω is countably generated if there is a countable family C such that Σ = σ(c ). If Σ i i I is a family of sub-σ-algebras, we let i I Σ i = σ ( ) i I Σ i. If f is a function whose codomain is a measurable space (X,X ), the σ-algebra generated by f is the σ-algebra { f 1 (H) : H X } on the domain of f. It is the smallest σ-algebra that makes f measurable. A probability space is called super-atomless 4 if there is no non-negligible measurable set on which the subspace measure induces a measure algebra which is completely generated by a countable sub-algebra. The canonical example is the fair coinflipping measure on {0,1} κ with κ uncountable. But it is worth pointing out that the underlying space might be quite small. As a matter of fact, every atomless Borel probability measure on a Polish space can be extended to a super-atomless probability measure, as shown in Podczeck (2009, Appendix). We elaborate on this in Section 7. Maharam s representation theorem on the classification of finite measure spaces modulo null sets, given in Maharam (1942), can be used to provide a useful characterization of super-atomless probability spaces: A probability space is super-atomless if and only if there exists an uncountable family of independent random variables on it with uniform distribution on [0,1] (cf. Lemma 5). We denote the Borel σ-algebra of [0,1] by B, and the restriction of Lebesgue measure to B by λ. For a general topological space X, the Borel-σ-algebra of X is denoted by B(X). If (X,X ) is a measurable space, M (X) denotes the set of probability measures on (X,X ), endowed with the smallest σ-algebra such that for every B X the evaluation function given by ν ν(b) is measurable. If X is a topological space, then M (X) denotes the set of Borel probability measures on X, endowed with the σ-algebra defined in the previous paragraph, substituting B(X) for X. A topological space X is called Souslin if it is Hausdorff and if there is a continuous surjection from a Polish space onto X. Thus any Polish space is a Souslin space. If X is a Souslin space, then B(X) is countably generated. It is not hard to see that this implies that for a Souslin space X, the σ-algebra on M (X) defined above is countably generated. We shall make much use of distributions of random measures. Let (Ω,Σ, µ) be a probability space, and (X,X ) a measurable space. Let f : Ω M (X) be measurable. We define the distribution µ f of f by µ f (B) = f ( )(B) dµ Ω for all B X. We shall frequently identify a measurable function with values in X with a measurevalued function whose values are Dirac-measures. It is readily verified that, under 4 Terminology varies. See footnote 4 in Wang and Zhang (2012) for an overview over the various concepts that are equivalent to what we call super-atomless.

5 Liapounoff s theorem in Banach spaces 5 this identification, the distribution as defined above coincides with the usual notion of distribution of a measurable function. Let (Ω,Σ, µ) be a probability space, and let X i,x i i I, I = {1,...,n}, be a finite family of measurable spaces. Endow i I X i with the product-σ-algebra i I X i. If ( f 1,..., f n ) is a family of measurable functions f i : Ω M (X i ), we define the distribution or joint distribution µ ( f1,..., f n ) of this family to be the distribution of the function i f i : Ω M ( i I X i ) given by ( i f i )(ω) = i f i (ω), where i f i (ω) is the usual product measure of the measures f i (ω), i I, on i I X i. A monotone class argument shows that this function is again measurable, so its distribution on ( i I X i, i I X i ) is well-defined. If all fi are deterministic measurable functions, our notion of joint distribution coincides with the usual one for random variables. If we look at the joint distribution of an ordinary random variable and a measure valued random variable, such as the µ (ιω, f ) in the following lemma, the ordinary random variable is identified with a measure-valued random variable with Dirac measures as values. Lemma 1 Let (Ω,Σ, µ) be a probability space, (X,X ) a measurable space, and ϕ : Ω X R a Σ X - measurable function. Suppose that for some integrable function ρ : Ω R +, sup x X ϕ(ω,x) ρ(ω) for almost all ω Ω. Then given any measurable function f : Ω M (X), ϕ(ω,x)dµ (ιω, f )(ω,x) = ϕ(ω,x)d f (ω)(x)dµ(ω). Ω X In particular, if g: Ω X is measurable, then ϕ(ω,x)dµ (ιω,g)(ω,x) = Ω X Ω X Ω ϕ(ω,g(ω))dµ(ω). Proof The statement concerning g is a special case of that concerning f, identifying g with the map ω δ g(ω), where δ g(ω) denotes Dirac measure at g(ω). Now as for f, we have Ω X ϕ(ω,x) dµ (ιω, f )(ω,x) Ω X ρ(ω)dµ (ιω, f )(ω,x) = ρ(ω)dµ(ω) <, Ω so the claim follows from the generalized Fubini theorem for random measures, see Bogachev (2007, Theorem ). Lemma 2 Let (Ω,Σ, µ) be a probability space, let (X,X ) and (Y,Y ) be measurable spaces, and let f : Ω X and g : Ω Y be independent measurable functions. Then µ ( f,g) = µ f µ g. Proof It suffices to show that µ ( f,g) and µ f µ g agree on all measurable rectangles A B in X Y. Now, µ ( ( f,g) 1 (A B) ) = µ ( f 1 (A) g 1 (B) ) = µ ( f 1 (A) ) µ ( g 1 (B) ) = µ f (A)µ g (B).

6 6 Michael Greinecker, Konrad Podczeck The following lemma is fundamental for our constructions. It says that a random probability measure can be seen as the distribution of a random function. According to Rustichini (1993), the result dates back to work of Skorokhod in the 1950s. Lemma 3 Let (Ω,Σ) be a measurable space, X a Souslin space, and p: Ω M (X) a measurable map. Then there exists a Σ B-measurable map h: Ω [0,1] X such that for all ω Ω and all B B(X), p(ω) ( B ) { } = λ r [0,1] : h(ω,r) B Proof Bogachev (2007, Proposition ), or Aumann (1964, Lemma F). Lemma 4 Let (X,X ) and (Y,Y ) be measurable spaces and let A be a countably generated sub-σ-algebra of X Y. Then there exists a countably generated sub-σalgebra C of X such that A C Y. Proof We use the easily proved and well known fact that if a set is in the σ-algebra generated by some family, it is already in the σ-algebra generated by a countable sub-family. Let G X Y be a countable family generating A. By the fact just stated, for each G G we can find a countable family R G of measurable rectangles in X Y such that G is in the σ-algebra generated by R G. Let π X be the projection of X Y onto X. Then {π X (R) : R R G,G G } is countable, and we can take C to be the σ-algebra generated by this family. Lemma 5 Let (Ω,Σ, µ) be a probability space. Then: (a) µ is atomless if and only if there is an infinite independent family E i i I in Σ with µ(e i ) = 1/2 for each i I. (b) µ is super-atomless if and only if there is an uncountable independent family E i i I in Σ with µ(e i ) = 1/2 for each i I. Proof (a) follows from the fact that a probability space (Ω,Σ, µ) is atomless if and only if there is a map h: Ω {0,1} N whose distribution is the fair coin-flipping measure. For (b), see Podczeck (2010, Remark 1 and Lemma 2). If (Ω,Σ, µ) is a probability space and Σ Σ is a sub-σ-algebra, we say that µ is atomless on Σ if the restriction µ Σ is atomless; similarly for super-atomless. Lemma 6 Let (Ω,Σ, µ) be a probability space, and Σ, Σ 1 two sub-σ-algebra of Σ. Suppose Σ 1 is countably generated and that µ Σ is super-atomless. Then there is a countably generated sub-σ-algebra Σ 2 Σ which is independent of Σ 1 and such that µ Σ 2 is atomless. Proof By Lemma 5(b) there is an uncountable independent family E i i I in Σ with µ(e i ) = 1/2 for each i I. Now by Fremlin (2010, Theorem 272Q), there is a countable H I such that the σ-algebras Σ 1 and σ ( {E i : i I\H} ) are independent. As I is uncountable, there is a countable infinite set J I\H. Let Σ 2 = σ ( {E i : i J} ). In view of Lemma 5(a), Σ 2 is as required.

7 Liapounoff s theorem in Banach spaces 7 3 Purification in an abstract setting Purification theorems in the tradition of Dvoretzky-Wald-Wolfowitz show that a family of functions evaluated with respect to a deterministic function agrees with the evaluation with respect to a given random measure. By Lemma 1, this can be reduced to showing that the induced measures on a product space agree on a σ-algebra that makes all these functions measurable. If there is a σ-algebra which is independent of the former and on which µ is atomless, we can use it as a roulette wheel. It is a randomization device that can be used to make the implicit randomization in a random measure explicit by using Lemma 3. Theorem 1 Let (Ω,Σ, µ) be a probability space and let Σ 1 and Σ 2 be independent sub-σ-algebras of Σ such that µ is atomless on Σ 2. Let X be a Souslin space, and f : Ω M (X) a Σ 1 -measurable function. Then there is a measurable map g : Ω X such that the restriction of µ (ιω,g) to Σ 1 B(X) coincides with the restriction of µ (ιω, f ) to Σ 1 B(X). Proof Choose a Σ 2 -measurable map w : Ω [0,1] with µ w = λ, as is possible because µ is atomless on Σ 2, and let h : Ω [0,1] X be a Σ 1 B-measurable map chosen according to Lemma 3. Now let g = h (ι Ω,w). To see that (ι Ω,g) has the desired distribution, it suffices to consider a rectangle A B Σ 1 B(X). By Lemma 2, µ (ιω,w) Σ 1 B = µ Σ 1 λ. Thus, using Fubini s theorem, A f (ω)(b)dµ(ω) = λ ( h(ω, ) 1 (B) ) dµ(ω) A = µ Σ 1 λ ( (A [0,1]) h 1 (B) ) = µ (ιω,w) Σ 1 B ( (A [0,1]) h 1 (B) ) = µ ( (ι Ω,w) 1( (A [0,1]) h 1 (B) )) = µ ( (ι Ω,w) 1 (A [0,1]) (ι Ω,w) 1 (h 1 (B)) ) = µ(a g 1 (B)) = µ (ιω,g)(a B). As a corollary, we get a generalization of the purification results in Podczeck (2009) and Loeb and Sun (2009): Theorem 2 Let (Ω,Σ, µ) be a probability space, let X be a Souslin space, and let f : Ω M (X) be a measurable function. Let J be a countable set, and for each j J let ϕ j : Ω X R be a jointly measurable mapping such that for some integrable function ρ j : Ω R +, sup x X ϕ j (ω,x) ρ j (ω) for almost all ω Ω. Suppose µ is super-atomless. Then there is a function g: Ω X such that (a) g is measurable; (b) Ω X ϕ j(ω,x)d f (ω)(x)dµ(ω) = Ω ϕ j(ω,g(ω))dµ(ω) for all j J.

8 8 Michael Greinecker, Konrad Podczeck Proof The σ-algebra on Ω X generated by the countable family ϕ j j J of realvalued functions is countably generated. It follows from Lemma 4 that Σ has a countably generated sub-σ-algebra Σ 1 such that all these functions are Σ 1 B(X)- measurable. By Lemma 6, there exists a sub-σ-algebra Σ 2 that is independent of Σ 1 and on which µ is atomless. The claim now follows from Theorem 1 in conjunction with Lemma 1. As was pointed out in Wang and Zhang (2012), in a context like that of Theorem 2 there must actually exist uncountably many purifications. This may also be seen from our proof: If Σ i i I is any countable and independent family of sub-σ-algebras of Σ such that each Σ i is countably generated and independent of Σ 1, and such that µ is atomless on each Σ i, then Lemma 6 applied to Σ 1 i I Σ i gives another countably generated sub-σ-algebra of Σ, say Σ +, such that Σ + is independent of Σ 1 and each Σ i, and such that µ Σ + is again atomless. Now such a Σ + leads to another function w as used to construct g in the proof of Theorem 1, and leads thus to another purification in the context of Theorem 2. It is sometimes useful to have purifications that satisfy additional constraints. For example, actions available to a player in a Bayesian game might be type-dependent and then we want only purified strategies that are actually feasible. The following theorem allows for such constraints. 5 In this theorem, G Γ denotes the graph of the correspondence Γ. Theorem 3 Let (Ω,Σ, µ) be a probability space, let X be a Souslin space, and let Γ : Ω 2 X be a correspondence which admits a measurable selection and such that G Γ Σ B(X). Let f : Ω M (X) be a measurable map such that µ (ιω, f )(G Γ ) = 1. Endow G Γ with the subspace-σ-algebra defined from Σ B(X). Let J be a countable set, and for each j J let ϕ j : Γ R be a measurable map such that for some integrable ρ j : Ω R +, sup x Γ (ω) ϕ j (ω,x) ρ j (ω) for almost all ω Ω. Suppose µ is super-atomless. Then there is a g: Ω X such that (a) g is a measurable selection of Γ ; (b) Ω X ϕ j(ω,x)d f (ω)(x)dµ(ω) = Ω ϕ j(ω,g(ω))dµ(ω) for all j J. Remark 1 Sufficient conditions for the existence of a measurable selection as required in this theorem are for example that (Ω,Σ, µ) is complete and Γ is nonemptyvalued (Castaing and Valadier 1977, Theorem III.22), or that X is Polish and that Γ is a measurable correspondence with closed and nonempty values (Castaing and Valadier 1977, Theorem III.8). Proof of Theorem 3 For all j J, extend φ j to all of Ω X, setting φ j (ω,x) = 0 for (ω,x) / Γ. We can now use Theorem 2 to obtain a measurable function g : Ω X such that (b) and in addition Ω X 1 GΓ dµ (ιω, g) = 1 GΓ dµ (ιω, f ) Ω X 5 This result generalizes Theorem 15 in Carmona and Podczeck (2013), which is used there for purifying mixed equilibria in games with a continuum of players.

9 Liapounoff s theorem in Banach spaces 9 holds. By hypothesis, 1 GΓ dµ (ιω, f ) = µ (ιω, f )(Γ ) = 1, and it follows that there is N Σ with µ(n) = 0 such that g(ω) Γ (ω) for all ω Ω\N. Let s : Ω X be a measurable selection of Γ. Define g : Ω X by { g(ω) if ω Ω\N g(ω) = s(ω) if ω N. Then g is a measurable selection of Γ. Since g = g almost surely, the integrals in (b) will be unchanged if we replace g by g. 4 Purification in games with private information In this section, we prove a general purification theorem for games with private information. Our model is a slight modification of the extremely elegant framework in Aumann (1974). The main difference is that we allow for state dependent preferences and assume that all players have the same prior. 6 There is a finite set N of players and a probability space (Ω,Σ, µ) of states of the world with µ being the common prior of all players. For each player i N, there is an action space A i which is a Souslin space. Let A = i N A i. Each player i N has a bounded and measurable utility function u i : Ω A R. 7 The information of player i N is given by a sub-σ-algebra I i Σ. The idea is that nature picks a state according to µ and then every player is informed about the events in her σ-algebra that contain the state. Players receive private information about the state and then choose their actions. A mixed strategy of i N is a I i -measurable function m i : Ω M (A i ). A pure strategy of i N is a I i -measurable function p i : Ω A i. Clearly, we may treat pure strategies as degenerate mixed strategies. We assume the following: (A) There are families P i i N and S i i N of sub-σ-algebras of Σ such that: (i) I i = P i S i for each i N. (ii) For each i N, S i is independent of j i S j. (iii) µ S i is super-atomless for each i N. (iv) P i is countably generated for each i N. We think of S i as the secret private information of player i, and of P i as the part of her information other players may be informed about. But S i may not be completely secret. It is not possible to infer anything about S i from the pooled secret information of other players j i S i, but we allow for any dependence between S i and the P j. In particular, every countable family of Borel measurable numerical signals a player receives about the information of another player is admissible. In Loeb and Sun (2006) and Khan and Zhang (2012) it is required that all private information is mutually independent conditional on a countably valued random variable. We 6 For equilibrium existence results in the framework of states of nature instead of the formulation in terms of types, see Yannelis and Rustichini (1991). 7 We actually never use boundedness, but it ensures that expected utility is well defined. Clearly, weaker assumptions would do.

10 10 Michael Greinecker, Konrad Podczeck made our independence assumption on the S i in unconditional form because there is no sensible notion of a random variable we should condition on. We make no assumptions on the utility functions, they can depend in arbitrary ways on both actions and states. In contrast, in Loeb and Sun (2006) and Khan and Zhang (2012) it is required that payoffs depend only on private information and some countably valued random variable. The reason why we can work with very weak independence assumptions is the following Lemma. Intuitively, it says that if µ is super-atomless on a σ-algebra independent of another σ-algebra, then a large number of events in the former σ-algebra remain independent of the latter after conditioning on an arbitrary countably generated σ-algebra. Lemma 7 Let (Ω,Σ, µ) be a probability space, and F 1, F 2, P sub-σ-algebras of Σ. Suppose that F 1 and F 2 are independent, that µ F 2 is super-atomless, and that P is countably generated. Then there is a sub-σ-algebra F 3 F 2 such that F 3 and F 1 P are independent and such that µ F 3 is super-atomless Proof ) By Lemma 5 there is an uncountable ( independent ) family E i i I in F 2 with µ(e i = 1/2 for each i I. Let F = σ Ei i I,F 1. Let C P be a countable algebra generating P, and for each C C let h C be a conditional expectation of C on F. Let H F be a countably generated sub-σ-algebra such that each h C is H -measurable. There is a countable J I such that H σ ( ) E i i J,F 1. Set H = I\J, let F3 = σ ( ) E i i H, and let F4 = σ ( ) E i i J,F 1. Observe that F3 and F 4 are independent (use Fremlin 2010, 272F and 272K). In particular, therefore, G h = µ(g) Ω h whenever G F 3 and h is F 4 -measurable. Pick any G F 3, F F 1 and C C. By the last sentence of the previous paragraph, as both H F 4 and F 1 F 4, we have h C = 1 F h C = µ(g) 1 F h C = µ(g)µ(f C) G F G where the last equality holds because F F and h C is a conditional expectation of C on F. On the other hand, by this property of h C, as also G F F, h C = µ(g F C). G F It follows that each G F 3 is independent of the intersection of any two elements of F 1 C. Now by a monotone class argument, it follows that each G F 3 is independent of every element of σ ( F 1 C ), i.e., F 3 and σ ( F 1 C ) are independent. Finally, just note that σ ( F 1 C ) = F 1 P. Before we can state and prove our main theorem, we introduce another Lemma, which is a variant of Theorem 1. The proof can be found in an appendix. Lemma 8 Let (Ω,Σ, µ) be a probability space, let Σ 1, Σ 2, I be sub-σ-algebras of Σ, let X, Y be Souslin spaces, and let f x : Ω M (X) a I -measurable function. Suppose that Σ 1 and Σ 2 are independent, that Σ 2 I, and that µ Σ 2 is atomless. Then there is a I -measurable map g x : Ω X such that whenever f y : Ω M (Y ) is Σ 1 -measurable, then µ (ιω, f y,g x ) and µ (ιω, f y, f x ) agree on Σ 1 B(Y ) B(X). Ω

11 Liapounoff s theorem in Banach spaces 11 Our purification theorem shows that a player s mixed strategy can be replaced by a pure strategy that depends in exactly the same way as the given mixed strategy on all events that determine payoffs, action distributions, and shared information. Strategically, they are essentially indistinguishable: Theorem 4 (a) There is a countably generated sub-σ-algebra Σ of Σ such that u i is Σ B(A)-measurable for all i N and i P i Σ. (b) For any player i N and any mixed strategy m i of i, there is a pure strategy p i such that given any profile m j j i of mixed strategies of the other players, the joint distributions of ( ι Ω, m j j N ) and ( ιω, p i,m j j i ) agree on Σ B(A). Proof By Lemma 4, for each player i N there is a countably generated σ-algebra Σ i Σ such that u i is Σ i B(A)-measurable. Set Σ = i N Σ i i P i, so that Σ is as required in (a). Fix any player i and any mixed strategy m i of i. Let Σ 1 = Σ j is j. By Lemma 7 and condition (A), there is a σ-algebra Σ 2 I i which is independent of Σ 1 and such that µ Σ 2 is atomless. Note that any strategy m j of any player j i must be Σ 1 -measurable. The claim now follows from Lemma 8, substituting I i for I, m i for f x, and j i m j for f y, noting that B(A) = j I B(A j ), as all the spaces A j are Souslin. We have formulated Theorem 4 in terms of a single player to make clear that mixed and pure best replies materially coincide in our framework, but it is of course straightforward to purify strategy profiles. By purifying strategies in a profile one player at a time, it follows from Theorem 4 by a straightforward induction argument that every mixed strategy profile can be replaced by a pure strategy profile that gives rise to the same joint distribution over realized payoffs and action profiles, even when some players deviate from the profile. In particular, every Nash equilibrium can be purified. Now theorem 4 guarantees that not only the distributions of action profiles and the distributions over realized payoffs coincide for the purified and the original strategies, but also the joint distributions of action profiles and realized payoffs of these two strategies. Our notion of purification is therefore stronger than the notion of strong purification introduced in Khan et al (2006). The remarkable part of our proof is that it depends on player i being able to condition on events in a σ-algebra that is completely payoff-irrelevant 8, independent of the private information of everyone else, and rich enough that µ is atomless on it. In short, she is using a secret roulette wheel. It is worth pointing out that this does not hold when private information is merely assumed to be atomless and action spaces are countable. In that case, u i might well generate I i B(A). 8 Fu has drawn attention to differences between information that is payoff-relevant and other forms of information, and used this to obtain a purification result in the classical finite-action setting in Fu (2008). He takes the categorization of forms of information to be basic. In our view, payoff-relevance should be derived from the structure of the payoff-functions as we do here.

12 12 Michael Greinecker, Konrad Podczeck 5 Saturation revisited The following saturation principle was introduced in Hoover and Keisler (1984) and used as a basis for proving a purification result in Loeb and Sun (2009): A probability space (Ω,Σ, µ) is saturated if for any two Polish spaces X and Y, any probability measure ν M (X Y ), and any random variable φ : Ω X with distribution equal to the X-marginal of ν, there exists a random variable ψ : Ω Y such that (φ,ψ) has distribution ν. It was shown implicitly in Hoover and Keisler (1984) and more explicitly in Fajardo and Keisler (2002, Theorem B.7) that a probability space is saturated if and only if it is super-atomless. 9 Actually, saturation can be seen as a form of automatic purification. We first relate the saturation principle, strengthened to Souslin spaces, to independent randomization by employing Theorem 1, in order to show what happens in the background when saturation is employed as a black box. Closely related to the material in this section is Lemma 4 in Hoover and Keisler (1984), which is proven using methods from Maharam (1942). Proposition 1 Let (Ω,Σ, µ) be a probability space, let X and Y be Souslin spaces, let ν M (X Y ) and let φ : Ω X be a random variable with distribution equal to the X-marginal ν X of ν. Suppose there exists a sub-σ-algebra Σ 2 of Σ on which µ is atomless and such that Σ 2 is independent of the σ-algebra generated by φ. Then there exists a random variable ψ : Ω Y such that (φ,ψ) has distribution ν. Proof Since regular conditional probabilities are guaranteed to exist in Souslin spaces (Bogachev 2007, Corollary ) and the product of Souslin spaces is again a Souslin space (Bogachev 2007, Lemma 6.6.5(iii)) there exists a measurable function r : X M (Y ) such that (ι X,r) has distribution ν when we endow X with the marginal measure ν X. Let Σ 1 be the σ-algebra generated by φ. Let f = r φ. We can now take ψ to be the g guaranteed to exist by Theorem 1. Then the distribution of (ι Ω,ψ) restricted to Σ 1 B(Y ) coincides with the distribution of (ι Ω,r φ) restricted to Σ 1 B(Y ). Since φ is Σ 1 -measurable, the distribution of (ι Ω,φ,ψ) restricted to Σ 1 B(X) B(Y ) coincides with the distribution of (ι Ω,φ,r φ) restricted to Σ 1 B(X) B(Y ). For let A B C be a rectangle in Σ 1 B(X) B(Y ). We have µ (ιω,φ,ψ)(a B C) = µ (ιω,ψ)( A φ 1 (B) C ) = µ (ιω,r φ)( A φ 1 (B) C ) = µ (ιω,φ,r φ)(a B C). As B(X) B(Y ) equals B(X Y ), (φ,ψ) has distribution ν. The following proposition shows that joint applications of Theorem 1 and Lemma 6 could be based on saturation directly. We therefore think of saturation as a form of automatic purification. Proposition 2 Let (Ω,Σ, µ) be a saturated probability space, Σ 1 a countably generated sub-σ-algebra, X a Souslin space and f : Ω M (X) be Σ 1 - measurable. Then there exists a function g : Ω X such that the restriction of µ (ιω,g) to Σ 1 B(X) coincides with the restriction of µ (ιω, f ) to Σ 1 B(X). 9 The more involved notion of saturation for adapted stochastic processes introduced in Hoover and Keisler (1984) gives rise to a much more restricted class of probability spaces.

13 Liapounoff s theorem in Banach spaces 13 Proof As Σ 1 is countably generated, there is a measurable map φ : Ω {0,1} N such that Σ 1 is the σ-algebra generated by φ. Let ν be the distribution of (φ, f ). By saturation, there is a measurable function g : Ω X such that (φ,g) has distribution ν. But this implies that the restriction of µ (ιω,g) to Σ 1 B(X) coincides with the restriction of µ (ιω, f ) to Σ 1 B(X). Indeed, let A Σ 1 and B B(X). Because φ generates Σ 1, there is a Borel set C B ( {0,1} N) such that A = φ 1 (C). Now µ (ιω,g)(a B) = µ(φ 1 (C) g 1 (B)) = ν(c B). As ν(c B) = µ (φ, f ) (C B) = µ (ιω, f )( φ 1 (C) B ) = µ (ιω, f )(A B), the result follows. 6 The scope of our approach An approach to purification that is mathematically close to ours is followed in He and Sun (2014). That paper gives a sufficient condition for purification in Bayesian games with general compact metrizable action spaces, but payoffs are allowed to depend on only a player s own type, there is no public information, and players type distributions are required to be independent. The condition used is that paper is that the measure on the private information is "relatively diffuse" with respect to a countably generated σ-algebra with respect to which a player s payoff-function is measurable. This relative diffuseness condition can be shown to be equivalent to there being an independent sub-σ-algebra on which the measure of private information is atomless; see He, Sun, and Sun (2013, Proposition 1). The actual purification is then based on a result from Hoover and Keisler (1984), which is analogous to our Proposition 2. The resulting form of purification is essentially equivalent to our form of purification, but defined in terms of certain conditional expectations. Even though it is not the focus of this paper, our approach has an obvious application to the theory of large games. In particular, it illuminates the relation between the first proofs of the existence of pure strategy Nash equilibrium for games with a super-atomless space of players and general compact metrizable action spaces in the individualistic framework of Schmeidler (1973). Existence has already been proven for distributional equilibria in Mas-Colell (1984), where equilibria are certain joint distributions on actions and payoffs. The result of Mas-Colell has been used in both Carmona and Podczeck (2009) and Keisler and Sun (2009) to prove the existence of a pure strategy Nash equilibrium in the individualistic framework. Taking a disintegration of a distributional equilibrium gives immediately rise to a mixed strategy equilibrium in the individualistic framework. Carmona and Podczeck purify such a mixed strategy equilibrium using the super-nonatomicity of the space of players. Keisler and Sun on the other hand apply the saturation property directly to the distributional equilibrium to obtain an equilibrium in pure strategies. But Proposition 1 and its proof show that these approaches are essentially the same. For large games, an essentially necessary and sufficient condition for the existence of a pure strategy Nash equilibrium in the individualistic framework has been established in He, Sun, and Sun (2013). This condition requires that there exists a sub-σ-algebra in the space of players that is independent of that generated by the characteristics of the players. Since this amounts exactly to our condition for purifi-

14 14 Michael Greinecker, Konrad Podczeck cation in Theorem 1, the problem in establishing existence is really just a problem of going from mixed to pure strategy equilibria. 7 What do super-atomless probability spaces represent? There are two justifications for the assumption that the private information is superatomless or, in large games, that the space of players is super-atomless. One is philosophical, and one pragmatic. Let us assume that a player receives private signals lying in the unit interval [0,1]. Now, for which subsets of the unit interval do we want to be able to assign a probability? A common view is that one ideally wants to assign a probability to all subsets and merely refrains from doing so for technical reasons. However, it follows from an old theorem of Ulam that under the continuum hypothesis every probability measure defined on all subsets of the unit interval must be supported on countably many atoms; see Fremlin (2006, Corollary 419G). So it is consistent with the usual axioms of set theory that there is no atomless probability measure defined on all subsets of the unit interval. But one can discuss the set theoretic implications of the assumption that an atomless probability measure defined on all subsets of the unit interval exists. In that case, it follows from an extremely deep result of Gitik and Shelah that such a probability space must be super-atomless, see Fremlin (2008, 543E). In this respect, super-atomless measures represent the idea that all subsets of the unit interval are measurable in a better way than, say, Lebesgue measure. Since every Borel probability measure on a Polish space can be extended to a super-atomless probability measure, see Podczeck (2009, Appendix), we merely allow more sets to be measurable when working with super-atomless probability spaces. There is also a pragmatic justification for using super-atomless probability spaces. If action spaces are finite, we can take atomless private information to be very finegrained information relative to the size of the action space. Under strong independence assumptions, purification is possible in this setting as the classic purification results show. If we allow for compact metric spaces as models of a very large number of not too diverse actions, we should represent relatively fine grained information so that purification is still possible. This is exactly the case when information is represented by a super-atomless probability space. Similarly, in large applied games, as in many economic models in general, it is often assumed that players face individual uncertainty that is sufficiently diluted in the aggregate so that an exact law of large numbers holds. It follows from Podczeck (2010, Theorem 3) that formalizing this idea coherently requires the space of players to be super-atomless. The general point is that many properties that we are familiar with from the finite case, or that are intuitively reasonable, hold only when working with super-atomless probability spaces. 8 Conclusion The intuition behind our results is very simple: A super-atomless probability space contains a very large number of nontrivial independent events, but only a small num-

15 Liapounoff s theorem in Banach spaces 15 ber of events are important in determining the payoffs being realized and the actions being played. So a lot of events serve no relevant function and can be used as randomization devices. This rich supply of independent events makes purification with super-atomless spaces qualitatively different from purification with arbitrary atomless spaces of private information and finite or countably infinite action spaces. It is the rich supply of independent events in a super-atomless probability space that allows for a lot of constructions not available for general atomless probability spaces. One of the most striking consequences of this richness for economic applications is the existence of nontrivial jointly measurable processes that allow for enough independence to guarantee an exact law of large numbers as provided in Sun (2006) to hold. Such processes were shown to exist in Sun (2006) by nonstandard methods. General existence results were given in Podczeck (2010), where explicit use of the rich independence structure of super-atomless probability spaces is made. Aumann took the crucial step of incorporating the randomization devices, usually assumed to be working in the background, into the description of a game. This gives a new perspective on the general theme of purification: Purification is about the identification of randomization devices within a player s private information. Superatomless probability spaces are simply the easiest case, the point itself is general. Appendix Proof of Lemma 8 As in the proof of Theorem 1, choose a Σ 2 -measurable map w: Ω [0,1] so that µ w = λ, and by Lemma 3, choose a I B measurable h: Ω [0,1] X so that f x (ω)(b x ) = λ(h(ω, ) 1 (B x )) for each B x B(X) and each ω Ω. Let g x = h (ι Ω,w) and note that g x is I -measurable, as Σ 2 I. Now pick any Σ 1 -measurable function f y : Ω M (Y ). Note that by Lemma 2, µ (ιω, f y,w) Σ 1 B(Y ) B = ( µ (ιω, f y ) Σ 1 B(Y ) ) λ. Now given any rectangle A B y B x Σ 1 B(Y ) B(X), we can calculate as follows, where the sixth equality follows by Fubini s theorem, the seventh by the generalized version of Fubini s theorem, and where h: Ω Y [0,1] X is given

16 16 Michael Greinecker, Konrad Podczeck by setting h(ω,y,r) = h(ω,r), and δ is used to denote a Dirac measure: µ (ιω, f y,g x )(A B y B x ) = f y (ω)(b y )δ gx (ω)(b x )dµ(ω) A = f y (ω)(b y )δ h(ω,w(ω)) (B x )dµ(ω) A = f y (ω)(b y )δ (ιω (ω),w(ω))(h 1 (B x ))dµ(ω) A = f y (ω)(b y )δ ιω (ω)) δ w(ω) (h 1 (B x ))dµ(ω) A = µ (ιω, f y,w) Σ 1 B(Y ) B ( h 1 (B x ) (A B y [0,1]) ) = ( µ (ιω, f y ) Σ 1 B(Y ) ) λ ( h 1 (B x ) (A B y [0,1]) ) = λ(h(ω, ) 1 (B x ))dµ (ιω, f y ) A B y = f y (ω)(b y )λ(h(ω, ) 1 (B x ))dµ(ω) A = f y (ω)(b y ) f x (ω)(b x )dµ(ω) A = µ (ιω, f y, f x )(A B y B x ). References Aumann RJ (1964) Mixed and behavior strategies in infinite extensive games. In: Advances in Game Theory, Princeton Univ. Press, Princeton, N.J., pp Aumann RJ (1974) Subjectivity and correlation in randomized strategies. J Math Econom 1(1):67 96 Balder EJ (1988) Generalized equilibrium results for games with incomplete information. Math Oper Res 13(2): , DOI /moor , URL Balder EJ (2008) Comments on purification in continuum games. International Journal of Game Theory 37(1):73 92, DOI /s , URL s Bogachev VI (2007) Measure theory. Vol. I, II. Springer-Verlag, Berlin, DOI / , URL Carmona G, Podczeck K (2009) On the existence of pure-strategy equilibria in large games. J Econom Theory 144(3): , DOI /j.jet , URL j.jet Carmona G, Podczeck K (2013) Existence of Nash equilibrium in games with a measure space of players and discontinuous payoff functions, mimeo Castaing C, Valadier M (1977) Convex analysis and measurable multifunctions. Lecture Notes in Mathematics, Vol. 580, Springer-Verlag, Berlin Dvoretzky A, Wald A, Wolfowitz J (1950) Elimination of randomization in certain problems of statistics and of the theory of games. Proc Nat Acad Sci U S A 36: Dvoretzky A, Wald A, Wolfowitz J (1951) Elimination of randomization in certain statistical decision procedures and zero-sum two-person games. Ann Math Statistics 22:1 21 Fajardo S, Keisler HJ (2002) Model theory of stochastic processes, Lecture Notes in Logic, vol 14. Association for Symbolic Logic, Urbana, IL Fremlin DH (2006) Measure theory. Vol. 4: Topological measure spaces. Part I, II. Corrected second printing of the 2003 original., corrected second printing of the 2003 original edn. Colchester: Torres Fremlin

17 Liapounoff s theorem in Banach spaces 17 Fremlin DH (2008) Measure theory. Vol. 5: Set-theoretic measure theory. Part I, II. Colchester: Torres Fremlin Fremlin DH (2010) Measure theory. Vol. 2: Broad foundations. Torres Fremlin, Colchester Fu H (2008) Mixed-strategy equilibria and strong purification for games with private and public information. Economic Theory 37(3): , DOI /s , URL org/ /s Govindan S, Reny PJ, Robson AJ (2003) A short proof of Harsanyi s purification theorem. Games Econom Behav 45(2): , DOI /S (03) , URL /S (03) , special issue in honor of Robert W. Rosenthal Grant S, Meneghel I, Tourky R (2013) Savage games, Harsanyi JC (1973) Games with randomly disturbed payoffs: a new rationale for mixed-strategy equilibrium points. Internat J Game Theory 2(1):1 23 He W, Sun X (2014) On the diffuseness of incomplete information game. Journal of Mathematical Economics (0):, DOI URL sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/s He W, Sun X, Sun Y (2013) Modeling infinitely many agents, mimeo Hoover DN, Keisler HJ (1984) Adapted probability distributions. Trans Amer Math Soc 286(1): , DOI / , URL Keisler HJ, Sun Y (2009) Why saturated probability spaces are necessary. Adv Math 221(5): , DOI /j.aim , URL Khan MA, Rath KP (2009) On games with incomplete information and the Dvoretsky-Wald-Wolfowitz theorem with countable partitions. J Math Econom 45(12): , DOI /j.jmateco , URL Khan MA, Zhang Y (2012) On sufficiently diffused information and finite-player games with private information. Tech. rep., working paper, Johns Hopkins University Khan MA, Rath KP, Sun Y (1999) On a private information game without pure strategy equilibria. J Math Econom 31(3): , DOI /S (97) , URL /S (97) Khan MA, Rath KP, Sun Y (2006) The Dvoretzky-Wald-Wolfowitz theorem and purification in atomless finite-action games. Internat J Game Theory 34(1):91 104, DOI /s , URL Lindenstrauss J (1966) A short proof of Liapounoff s convexity theorem. J Math Mech 15: Loeb P, Sun Y (2006) Purification of measure-valued maps. Illinois J Math 50(1-4): (electronic), URL Loeb P, Sun Y (2009) Purification and saturation. Proc Amer Math Soc 137(8): , DOI / S , URL Maharam D (1942) On homogeneous measure algebras. Proc Nat Acad Sci U S A 28: Mas-Colell A (1984) On a theorem of Schmeidler. J Math Econom 13(3): , DOI / (84) , URL Meneghel I, Tourky R (2013) A fixed point theorem for closed-graphed decomposable-valued correspondences. ArXiv e-prints Milgrom PR, Weber RJ (1985) Distributional strategies for games with incomplete information. Math Oper Res 10(4): , DOI /moor , URL Morris S (2008) Purification. In: Durlauf SN, Blume LE (eds) The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke Podczeck K (2009) On purification of measure-valued maps. Econom Theory 38(2): , DOI /s , URL Podczeck K (2010) On existence of rich Fubini extensions. Econom Theory 45(1-2):1 22, DOI / s , URL Radner R, Rosenthal RW (1982) Private information and pure-strategy equilibria. Math Oper Res 7(3): , DOI /moor , URL Rustichini A (1993) Mixing on function spaces. Econom Theory 3(1): , DOI / BF , URL Schmeidler D (1973) Equilibrium points of nonatomic games. J Statist Phys 7: Sun Y (2006) The exact law of large numbers via Fubini extension and characterization of insurable risks. J Econom Theory 126(1):31 69, DOI /j.jet , URL /j.jet

EXISTENCE OF PURE EQUILIBRIA IN GAMES WITH NONATOMIC SPACE OF PLAYERS. Agnieszka Wiszniewska Matyszkiel. 1. Introduction

EXISTENCE OF PURE EQUILIBRIA IN GAMES WITH NONATOMIC SPACE OF PLAYERS. Agnieszka Wiszniewska Matyszkiel. 1. Introduction Topological Methods in Nonlinear Analysis Journal of the Juliusz Schauder Center Volume 16, 2000, 339 349 EXISTENCE OF PURE EQUILIBRIA IN GAMES WITH NONATOMIC SPACE OF PLAYERS Agnieszka Wiszniewska Matyszkiel

More information

WHY SATURATED PROBABILITY SPACES ARE NECESSARY

WHY SATURATED PROBABILITY SPACES ARE NECESSARY WHY SATURATED PROBABILITY SPACES ARE NECESSARY H. JEROME KEISLER AND YENENG SUN Abstract. An atomless probability space (Ω, A, P ) is said to have the saturation property for a probability measure µ on

More information

Pure-strategy Nash equilibria in nonatomic games with infinite-dimensional action spaces

Pure-strategy Nash equilibria in nonatomic games with infinite-dimensional action spaces Pure-strategy Nash equilibria in nonatomic games with infinite-dimensional action spaces Xiang Sun Yongchao Zhang Submitted: August 28, 22. Revised and Resubmitted: December 27, 22 Abstract his paper studies

More information

Puri cation 1. Stephen Morris Princeton University. July Economics.

Puri cation 1. Stephen Morris Princeton University. July Economics. Puri cation 1 Stephen Morris Princeton University July 2006 1 This survey was prepared as an entry for the second edition of the New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics. In a mixed strategy equilibrium of

More information

EXTENSION OF LYAPUNOV S CONVEXITY THEOREM TO SUBRANGES

EXTENSION OF LYAPUNOV S CONVEXITY THEOREM TO SUBRANGES PROCEEDINGS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 00, Number 0, Pages 000 000 S 0002-9939(XX)0000-0 EXTENSION OF LYAPUNOV S CONVEXITY THEOREM TO SUBRANGES PENG DAI AND EUGENE A. FEINBERG (Communicated

More information

Strict Nash equilibria in Non-Atomic Games with Strict Single Crossing in Types and Actions

Strict Nash equilibria in Non-Atomic Games with Strict Single Crossing in Types and Actions Strict Nash equilibria in Non-Atomic Games with Strict Single Crossing in Types and Actions Ennio Bilancini Leonardo Boncinelli September 13, 2013 Abstract In this paper we study games where the space

More information

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007)

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω 0. Introduction David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) In its simplest form the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem for L ω1 ω states that if σ L ω1

More information

A remark on discontinuous games with asymmetric information and ambiguity

A remark on discontinuous games with asymmetric information and ambiguity Econ Theory Bull DOI 10.1007/s40505-016-0100-5 RESEARCH ARTICLE A remark on discontinuous games with asymmetric information and ambiguity Wei He 1 Nicholas C. Yannelis 1 Received: 7 February 2016 / Accepted:

More information

On Strongly Equivalent Nonrandomized Transition Probabilities

On Strongly Equivalent Nonrandomized Transition Probabilities On Strongly Equivalent Nonrandomized Transition Probabilities Eugene. Feinberg 1 and lexey B. Piunovskiy bstract Dvoretzky, Wald and Wolfowitz proved in 1951 the existence of equivalent and strongly equivalent

More information

The small ball property in Banach spaces (quantitative results)

The small ball property in Banach spaces (quantitative results) The small ball property in Banach spaces (quantitative results) Ehrhard Behrends Abstract A metric space (M, d) is said to have the small ball property (sbp) if for every ε 0 > 0 there exists a sequence

More information

UNIVERSITY OF VIENNA

UNIVERSITY OF VIENNA WORKING PAPERS Konrad Podczeck Note on the Core-Walras Equivalence Problem when the Commodity Space is a Banach Lattice March 2003 Working Paper No: 0307 DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS UNIVERSITY OF VIENNA All

More information

The Dvoretzky-Wald-Wolfowitz Theorem and Purification in Atomless Finite-action Games

The Dvoretzky-Wald-Wolfowitz Theorem and Purification in Atomless Finite-action Games he Dvoretzky-Wald-Wolfowitz heorem and Purification in tomless Finite-action Games M. li Khan, Kali P. Rath and Yeneng Sun ugust 2005 bstract In 1951, Dvoretzky, Wald and Wolfowitz (henceforth DWW) showed

More information

Payoff Continuity in Incomplete Information Games

Payoff Continuity in Incomplete Information Games journal of economic theory 82, 267276 (1998) article no. ET982418 Payoff Continuity in Incomplete Information Games Atsushi Kajii* Institute of Policy and Planning Sciences, University of Tsukuba, 1-1-1

More information

Subjective expected utility in games

Subjective expected utility in games Theoretical Economics 3 (2008), 287 323 1555-7561/20080287 Subjective expected utility in games ALFREDO DI TILLIO Department of Economics and IGIER, Università Bocconi This paper extends Savage s subjective

More information

Incentive compatibility of rational expectations equilibrium in large economies: a counterexample

Incentive compatibility of rational expectations equilibrium in large economies: a counterexample Econ Theory Bull (203) :3 0 DOI 0.007/s40505-03-000-8 SHORT PAPER Incentive compatibility of rational expectations equilibrium in large economies: a counterexample Yeneng Sun Lei Wu Nicholas C. Yannelis

More information

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract Pure strategy dominance with quasiconcave utility functions Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam Abstract By a result of Pearce (1984), in a finite strategic form game, the set of a player's serially

More information

Measure and integration

Measure and integration Chapter 5 Measure and integration In calculus you have learned how to calculate the size of different kinds of sets: the length of a curve, the area of a region or a surface, the volume or mass of a solid.

More information

Perfect Conditional -Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Signals and Actions (Preliminary and Incomplete)

Perfect Conditional -Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Signals and Actions (Preliminary and Incomplete) Perfect Conditional -Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Signals and Actions (Preliminary and Incomplete) Roger B. Myerson and Philip J. Reny Department of Economics University of Chicago

More information

SAVAGE GAMES A Theory of Strategic Interaction with Purely Subjective Uncertainty

SAVAGE GAMES A Theory of Strategic Interaction with Purely Subjective Uncertainty SAVAGE GAMES A Theory of Strategic Interaction with Purely Subjective Uncertainty SIMON GRANT, IDIONE MENEGHEL, AND RABEE TOURKY Abstract. We define and discuss Savage games, which are ordinal games that

More information

Levels of Knowledge and Belief Computational Social Choice Seminar

Levels of Knowledge and Belief Computational Social Choice Seminar Levels of Knowledge and Belief Computational Social Choice Seminar Eric Pacuit Tilburg University ai.stanford.edu/~epacuit November 13, 2009 Eric Pacuit 1 Introduction and Motivation Informal Definition:

More information

Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions

Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions by Roger B. Myerson and Philip J. Reny* Draft notes October 2011 http://home.uchicago.edu/~preny/papers/bigseqm.pdf Abstract:

More information

The Essential Equivalence of Pairwise and Mutual Conditional Independence

The Essential Equivalence of Pairwise and Mutual Conditional Independence The Essential Equivalence of Pairwise and Mutual Conditional Independence Peter J. Hammond and Yeneng Sun Probability Theory and Related Fields, forthcoming Abstract For a large collection of random variables,

More information

RSMG Working Paper Series TITLE: Savage Games. A Theory of Strategic Interaction with Purely Subjective Uncertainty. Authors:

RSMG Working Paper Series TITLE: Savage Games. A Theory of Strategic Interaction with Purely Subjective Uncertainty. Authors: 2013 TITLE: Savage Games A Theory of Strategic Interaction with Purely Subjective Uncertainty 2011 RSMG Working Paper Series Risk and Uncertainty Program Authors: Simon Grant, Idione Meneghel and Rabee

More information

HIERARCHIES OF BELIEF AND INTERIM RATIONALIZABILITY

HIERARCHIES OF BELIEF AND INTERIM RATIONALIZABILITY HIERARCHIES OF BELIEF AND INTERIM RATIONALIZABILITY JEFFREY C. ELY AND MARCIN PESKI Abstract. In games with incomplete information, conventional hierarchies of belief are incomplete as descriptions of

More information

Subgame Perfect Equilibria in Infinite Stage Games: an alternative existence proof

Subgame Perfect Equilibria in Infinite Stage Games: an alternative existence proof Subgame Perfect Equilibria in Infinite Stage Games: an alternative existence proof Alejandro M. Manelli Department of Economics Arizona State University Tempe, Az 85287-3806 Version: January 2003 Abstract

More information

Monotone equilibria in nonatomic supermodular games. A comment

Monotone equilibria in nonatomic supermodular games. A comment Monotone equilibria in nonatomic supermodular games. A comment Lukasz Balbus Kevin Reffett Lukasz Woźny April 2014 Abstract Recently Yang and Qi (2013) stated an interesting theorem on existence of complete

More information

Essential equilibria in normal-form games

Essential equilibria in normal-form games Journal of Economic Theory 145 (2010) 421 431 www.elsevier.com/locate/jet Note Essential equilibria in normal-form games Oriol Carbonell-Nicolau 1 Department of Economics, Rutgers University, 75 Hamilton

More information

Measurable Choice Functions

Measurable Choice Functions (January 19, 2013) Measurable Choice Functions Paul Garrett garrett@math.umn.edu http://www.math.umn.edu/ garrett/ [This document is http://www.math.umn.edu/ garrett/m/fun/choice functions.pdf] This note

More information

Events Concerning Knowledge

Events Concerning Knowledge Events Concerning Knowledge Edward J. Green Department of Economics The Pennsylvania State University University Park, PA 16802, USA eug2@psu.edu DRAFT: 2010.04.05 Abstract Aumann s knowledge operator

More information

5 Measure theory II. (or. lim. Prove the proposition. 5. For fixed F A and φ M define the restriction of φ on F by writing.

5 Measure theory II. (or. lim. Prove the proposition. 5. For fixed F A and φ M define the restriction of φ on F by writing. 5 Measure theory II 1. Charges (signed measures). Let (Ω, A) be a σ -algebra. A map φ: A R is called a charge, (or signed measure or σ -additive set function) if φ = φ(a j ) (5.1) A j for any disjoint

More information

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Emir Kamenica and Matthew Gentzkow University of Chicago June 2010 1 Persuasion mechanisms In this paper we study a particular game where Sender chooses a signal π whose

More information

A DECOMPOSITION THEOREM FOR FRAMES AND THE FEICHTINGER CONJECTURE

A DECOMPOSITION THEOREM FOR FRAMES AND THE FEICHTINGER CONJECTURE PROCEEDINGS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 00, Number 0, Pages 000 000 S 0002-9939(XX)0000-0 A DECOMPOSITION THEOREM FOR FRAMES AND THE FEICHTINGER CONJECTURE PETER G. CASAZZA, GITTA KUTYNIOK,

More information

Robust Comparative Statics in Large Static Games

Robust Comparative Statics in Large Static Games Robust Comparative Statics in Large Static Games Daron Acemoglu and Martin Kaae Jensen Abstract We provide general comparative static results for large finite and infinite-dimensional aggregative games.

More information

Monotonic models and cycles

Monotonic models and cycles Int J Game Theory DOI 10.1007/s00182-013-0385-7 Monotonic models and cycles José Alvaro Rodrigues-Neto Accepted: 16 May 2013 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2013 Abstract A partitional model of knowledge

More information

Basic Measure and Integration Theory. Michael L. Carroll

Basic Measure and Integration Theory. Michael L. Carroll Basic Measure and Integration Theory Michael L. Carroll Sep 22, 2002 Measure Theory: Introduction What is measure theory? Why bother to learn measure theory? 1 What is measure theory? Measure theory is

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago December 2015 Abstract Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970) represent random

More information

Existence, Incentive Compatibility and Efficiency of the Rational Expectations Equilibrium

Existence, Incentive Compatibility and Efficiency of the Rational Expectations Equilibrium Existence, ncentive Compatibility and Efficiency of the Rational Expectations Equilibrium Yeneng Sun, Lei Wu and Nicholas C. Yannelis Abstract The rational expectations equilibrium (REE), as introduced

More information

More Model Theory Notes

More Model Theory Notes More Model Theory Notes Miscellaneous information, loosely organized. 1. Kinds of Models A countable homogeneous model M is one such that, for any partial elementary map f : A M with A M finite, and any

More information

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory Part V 7 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets Lebesgue Integration Theory Definition 7. (Preliminary). A measure on a set is a function :2 [ ] such that. () = 2. If { } = is a finite

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago September 2015 Abstract Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970) introduce a

More information

4 Choice axioms and Baire category theorem

4 Choice axioms and Baire category theorem Tel Aviv University, 2013 Measure and category 30 4 Choice axioms and Baire category theorem 4a Vitali set....................... 30 4b No choice....................... 31 4c Dependent choice..................

More information

Contracts under Asymmetric Information

Contracts under Asymmetric Information Contracts under Asymmetric Information 1 I Aristotle, economy (oiko and nemo) and the idea of exchange values, subsequently adapted by Ricardo and Marx. Classical economists. An economy consists of a set

More information

Online Appendices for Large Matching Markets: Risk, Unraveling, and Conflation

Online Appendices for Large Matching Markets: Risk, Unraveling, and Conflation Online Appendices for Large Matching Markets: Risk, Unraveling, and Conflation Aaron L. Bodoh-Creed - Cornell University A Online Appendix: Strategic Convergence In section 4 we described the matching

More information

On the Converse Law of Large Numbers

On the Converse Law of Large Numbers On the Converse Law of Large Numbers H. Jerome Keisler Yeneng Sun This version: March 15, 2018 Abstract Given a triangular array of random variables and a growth rate without a full upper asymptotic density,

More information

4 Countability axioms

4 Countability axioms 4 COUNTABILITY AXIOMS 4 Countability axioms Definition 4.1. Let X be a topological space X is said to be first countable if for any x X, there is a countable basis for the neighborhoods of x. X is said

More information

Lebesgue Measure on R n

Lebesgue Measure on R n CHAPTER 2 Lebesgue Measure on R n Our goal is to construct a notion of the volume, or Lebesgue measure, of rather general subsets of R n that reduces to the usual volume of elementary geometrical sets

More information

Convergence and submeasures in Boolean algebras

Convergence and submeasures in Boolean algebras Convergence and submeasures in Boolean algebras Thomas Jech e-mail: jech@math.psu.edu January 30, 2018 In memory of Bohuslav Balcar Abstract A Boolean algebra carries a strictly positive exhaustive submeasure

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago January 2016 Consider a situation where one person, call him Sender,

More information

A NOTE ON COMPARISON BETWEEN BIRKHOFF AND MCSHANE-TYPE INTEGRALS FOR MULTIFUNCTIONS

A NOTE ON COMPARISON BETWEEN BIRKHOFF AND MCSHANE-TYPE INTEGRALS FOR MULTIFUNCTIONS RESERCH Real nalysis Exchange Vol. 37(2), 2011/2012, pp. 315 324 ntonio Boccuto, Department of Mathematics and Computer Science - 1, Via Vanvitelli 06123 Perugia, Italy. email: boccuto@dmi.unipg.it nna

More information

APPROXIMATING BOCHNER INTEGRALS BY RIEMANN SUMS

APPROXIMATING BOCHNER INTEGRALS BY RIEMANN SUMS APPROXIMATING BOCHNER INTEGRALS BY RIEMANN SUMS J.M.A.M. VAN NEERVEN Abstract. Let µ be a tight Borel measure on a metric space, let X be a Banach space, and let f : (, µ) X be Bochner integrable. We show

More information

The ideal of Sierpiński-Zygmund sets on the plane

The ideal of Sierpiński-Zygmund sets on the plane The ideal of Sierpiński-Zygmund sets on the plane Krzysztof P lotka Department of Mathematics, West Virginia University Morgantown, WV 26506-6310, USA kplotka@math.wvu.edu and Institute of Mathematics,

More information

The Skorokhod reflection problem for functions with discontinuities (contractive case)

The Skorokhod reflection problem for functions with discontinuities (contractive case) The Skorokhod reflection problem for functions with discontinuities (contractive case) TAKIS KONSTANTOPOULOS Univ. of Texas at Austin Revised March 1999 Abstract Basic properties of the Skorokhod reflection

More information

Robust Comparative Statics for Non-monotone Shocks in Large Aggregative Games

Robust Comparative Statics for Non-monotone Shocks in Large Aggregative Games Robust Comparative Statics for Non-monotone Shocks in Large Aggregative Games Carmen Camacho Takashi Kamihigashi Çağrı Sağlam February 1, 2016 Abstract A policy change that involves a redistribution of

More information

Equivalence of Stochastic and Deterministic Mechanisms

Equivalence of Stochastic and Deterministic Mechanisms Equivalence of Stochastic and Deterministic Mechanisms Yi-Chun Chen Wei He Jiangtao Li Yeneng Sun September 14, 2016 Abstract We consider a general social choice environment that has multiple agents, a

More information

Definitions and Proofs

Definitions and Proofs Giving Advice vs. Making Decisions: Transparency, Information, and Delegation Online Appendix A Definitions and Proofs A. The Informational Environment The set of states of nature is denoted by = [, ],

More information

Open Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions

Open Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions Open Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions By Roger B. Myerson and Philip J. Reny Department of Economics University of Chicago Paper can be found at https://sites.google.com/site/philipjreny/home/research

More information

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Keith A. Kearnes and Greg Oman Abstract. We show that if P is an infinite poset whose proper order ideals have cardinality strictly less than P, and κ is a cardinal

More information

Introduction to Topology

Introduction to Topology Introduction to Topology Randall R. Holmes Auburn University Typeset by AMS-TEX Chapter 1. Metric Spaces 1. Definition and Examples. As the course progresses we will need to review some basic notions about

More information

PROBABILITY LOGICS WITH VECTOR VALUED MEASURES. Vladimir Ristić

PROBABILITY LOGICS WITH VECTOR VALUED MEASURES. Vladimir Ristić 47 Kragujevac J. Math. 32 2009) 47-60. PROBABILITY LOGICS WITH VECTOR VALUED MEASURES Vladimir Ristić Faculty of Teacher Education, Milana Mijalkovića 14, 35000 Jagodina, Serbia e-mail: vladimir.ristic@pefja.kg.ac.yu)

More information

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Ozan Candogan, Asuman Ozdaglar and Pablo A. Parrilo January 29, 2012 Abstract Potential games are a special class of games for which many adaptive user dynamics

More information

Changing Types. Dominik Klein Eric Pacuit. April 24, 2011

Changing Types. Dominik Klein Eric Pacuit. April 24, 2011 Changing Types Dominik Klein Eric Pacuit April 24, 2011 The central thesis of the epistemic program in game theory (Brandenburger, 2007) is that the basic mathematical models of a game situation should

More information

Conservative Belief and Rationality

Conservative Belief and Rationality Conservative Belief and Rationality Joseph Y. Halpern and Rafael Pass Department of Computer Science Cornell University Ithaca, NY, 14853, U.S.A. e-mail: halpern@cs.cornell.edu, rafael@cs.cornell.edu January

More information

The Value of Information in Zero-Sum Games

The Value of Information in Zero-Sum Games The Value of Information in Zero-Sum Games Olivier Gossner THEMA, Université Paris Nanterre and CORE, Université Catholique de Louvain joint work with Jean-François Mertens July 2001 Abstract: It is not

More information

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Ozan Candogan, Asuman Ozdaglar and Pablo A. Parrilo September 6, 2011 Abstract Potential games are a special class of games for which many adaptive user dynamics

More information

Order on Types based on Monotone Comparative Statics

Order on Types based on Monotone Comparative Statics Order on Types based on Monotone Comparative Statics Takashi Kunimoto Takuro Yamashita July 10, 2015 Monotone comparative statics Comparative statics is important in Economics E.g., Wealth Consumption

More information

Chapter 1. Measure Spaces. 1.1 Algebras and σ algebras of sets Notation and preliminaries

Chapter 1. Measure Spaces. 1.1 Algebras and σ algebras of sets Notation and preliminaries Chapter 1 Measure Spaces 1.1 Algebras and σ algebras of sets 1.1.1 Notation and preliminaries We shall denote by X a nonempty set, by P(X) the set of all parts (i.e., subsets) of X, and by the empty set.

More information

MATS113 ADVANCED MEASURE THEORY SPRING 2016

MATS113 ADVANCED MEASURE THEORY SPRING 2016 MATS113 ADVANCED MEASURE THEORY SPRING 2016 Foreword These are the lecture notes for the course Advanced Measure Theory given at the University of Jyväskylä in the Spring of 2016. The lecture notes can

More information

Robust comparative statics in large static games

Robust comparative statics in large static games Robust comparative statics in large static games The MIT Faculty has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters. Citation As Published Publisher Acemoglu,

More information

FUNCTION BASES FOR TOPOLOGICAL VECTOR SPACES. Yılmaz Yılmaz

FUNCTION BASES FOR TOPOLOGICAL VECTOR SPACES. Yılmaz Yılmaz Topological Methods in Nonlinear Analysis Journal of the Juliusz Schauder Center Volume 33, 2009, 335 353 FUNCTION BASES FOR TOPOLOGICAL VECTOR SPACES Yılmaz Yılmaz Abstract. Our main interest in this

More information

arxiv:math.lo/ v1 28 Nov 2004

arxiv:math.lo/ v1 28 Nov 2004 HILBERT SPACES WITH GENERIC GROUPS OF AUTOMORPHISMS arxiv:math.lo/0411625 v1 28 Nov 2004 ALEXANDER BERENSTEIN Abstract. Let G be a countable group. We proof that there is a model companion for the approximate

More information

Integration on Measure Spaces

Integration on Measure Spaces Chapter 3 Integration on Measure Spaces In this chapter we introduce the general notion of a measure on a space X, define the class of measurable functions, and define the integral, first on a class of

More information

AN EXPLORATION OF THE METRIZABILITY OF TOPOLOGICAL SPACES

AN EXPLORATION OF THE METRIZABILITY OF TOPOLOGICAL SPACES AN EXPLORATION OF THE METRIZABILITY OF TOPOLOGICAL SPACES DUSTIN HEDMARK Abstract. A study of the conditions under which a topological space is metrizable, concluding with a proof of the Nagata Smirnov

More information

Subgame-Perfect Equilibria for Stochastic Games

Subgame-Perfect Equilibria for Stochastic Games MATHEMATICS OF OPERATIONS RESEARCH Vol. 32, No. 3, August 2007, pp. 711 722 issn 0364-765X eissn 1526-5471 07 3203 0711 informs doi 10.1287/moor.1070.0264 2007 INFORMS Subgame-Perfect Equilibria for Stochastic

More information

THEOREMS, ETC., FOR MATH 515

THEOREMS, ETC., FOR MATH 515 THEOREMS, ETC., FOR MATH 515 Proposition 1 (=comment on page 17). If A is an algebra, then any finite union or finite intersection of sets in A is also in A. Proposition 2 (=Proposition 1.1). For every

More information

Banach-Mazur game played in partially ordered sets

Banach-Mazur game played in partially ordered sets Banach-Mazur game played in partially ordered sets arxiv:1505.01094v1 [math.lo] 5 May 2015 Wies law Kubiś Department of Mathematics Jan Kochanowski University in Kielce, Poland and Institute of Mathematics,

More information

Subgame Perfect Equilibria in Stage Games

Subgame Perfect Equilibria in Stage Games Subgame Perfect Equilibria in Stage Games Alejandro M. Manelli Department of Economics Arizona State University Tempe, Az 85287-3806 August 2000 I am grateful to an associate editor and to two referees

More information

CRITICAL TYPES. 1. Introduction

CRITICAL TYPES. 1. Introduction CRITICAL TYPES JEFFREY C. ELY AND MARCIN PESKI Abstract. Economic models employ assumptions about agents infinite hierarchies of belief. We might hope to achieve reasonable approximations by specifying

More information

The Banach-Tarski paradox

The Banach-Tarski paradox The Banach-Tarski paradox 1 Non-measurable sets In these notes I want to present a proof of the Banach-Tarski paradox, a consequence of the axiom of choice that shows us that a naive understanding of the

More information

On equilibria for discontinuous games: Nash approximation schemes

On equilibria for discontinuous games: Nash approximation schemes On equilibria for discontinuous games: Nash approximation schemes Erik J. Balder, Mathematical Institute, University of Utrecht, P.O. Box 80.010, 3508 TA Utrecht, Netherlands eptember, 2001 Abstract: For

More information

THE PETTIS INTEGRAL FOR MULTI-VALUED FUNCTIONS VIA SINGLE-VALUED ONES

THE PETTIS INTEGRAL FOR MULTI-VALUED FUNCTIONS VIA SINGLE-VALUED ONES THE PETTIS INTEGRAL FOR MULTI-VALUED FUNCTIONS VIA SINGLE-VALUED ONES B. CASCALES, V. KADETS, AND J. RODRÍGUEZ ABSTRACT. We study the Pettis integral for multi-functions F : Ω cwk(x) defined on a complete

More information

SEPARABLE MODELS OF RANDOMIZATIONS

SEPARABLE MODELS OF RANDOMIZATIONS SEPARABLE MODELS OF RANDOMIZATIONS URI ANDREWS AND H. JEROME KEISLER Abstract. Every complete first order theory has a corresponding complete theory in continuous logic, called the randomization theory.

More information

Blackwell s Informativeness Theorem Using Diagrams

Blackwell s Informativeness Theorem Using Diagrams Blackwell s Informativeness Theorem Using Diagrams Henrique de Oliveira 1, a Department of Economics, Pennsylvania State University, University Park, PA 16802 Abstract This paper gives a simple proof of

More information

A PROOF OF A CONVEX-VALUED SELECTION THEOREM WITH THE CODOMAIN OF A FRÉCHET SPACE. Myung-Hyun Cho and Jun-Hui Kim. 1. Introduction

A PROOF OF A CONVEX-VALUED SELECTION THEOREM WITH THE CODOMAIN OF A FRÉCHET SPACE. Myung-Hyun Cho and Jun-Hui Kim. 1. Introduction Comm. Korean Math. Soc. 16 (2001), No. 2, pp. 277 285 A PROOF OF A CONVEX-VALUED SELECTION THEOREM WITH THE CODOMAIN OF A FRÉCHET SPACE Myung-Hyun Cho and Jun-Hui Kim Abstract. The purpose of this paper

More information

Max-min (σ-)additive representation of monotone measures

Max-min (σ-)additive representation of monotone measures Noname manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Max-min (σ-)additive representation of monotone measures Martin Brüning and Dieter Denneberg FB 3 Universität Bremen, D-28334 Bremen, Germany e-mail:

More information

Boundedly complete weak-cauchy basic sequences in Banach spaces with the PCP

Boundedly complete weak-cauchy basic sequences in Banach spaces with the PCP Journal of Functional Analysis 253 (2007) 772 781 www.elsevier.com/locate/jfa Note Boundedly complete weak-cauchy basic sequences in Banach spaces with the PCP Haskell Rosenthal Department of Mathematics,

More information

II - REAL ANALYSIS. This property gives us a way to extend the notion of content to finite unions of rectangles: we define

II - REAL ANALYSIS. This property gives us a way to extend the notion of content to finite unions of rectangles: we define 1 Measures 1.1 Jordan content in R N II - REAL ANALYSIS Let I be an interval in R. Then its 1-content is defined as c 1 (I) := b a if I is bounded with endpoints a, b. If I is unbounded, we define c 1

More information

Columbia University. Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series

Columbia University. Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series Columbia University Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series Equivalence of Public Mixed-Strategies and Private Behavior Strategies in Games with Public Monitoring Massimiliano Amarante Discussion

More information

02. Measure and integral. 1. Borel-measurable functions and pointwise limits

02. Measure and integral. 1. Borel-measurable functions and pointwise limits (October 3, 2017) 02. Measure and integral Paul Garrett garrett@math.umn.edu http://www.math.umn.edu/ garrett/ [This document is http://www.math.umn.edu/ garrett/m/real/notes 2017-18/02 measure and integral.pdf]

More information

Recall that if X is a compact metric space, C(X), the space of continuous (real-valued) functions on X, is a Banach space with the norm

Recall that if X is a compact metric space, C(X), the space of continuous (real-valued) functions on X, is a Banach space with the norm Chapter 13 Radon Measures Recall that if X is a compact metric space, C(X), the space of continuous (real-valued) functions on X, is a Banach space with the norm (13.1) f = sup x X f(x). We want to identify

More information

The Index of Nash Equilibria

The Index of Nash Equilibria Equilibria in Games, Santiago, Chile January 10, 2017 Finite Normal-Form Games We consider in these lectures, the set of finite games with fixed strategy sets and parametrized by the payoff functions.

More information

A BOREL SOLUTION TO THE HORN-TARSKI PROBLEM. MSC 2000: 03E05, 03E20, 06A10 Keywords: Chain Conditions, Boolean Algebras.

A BOREL SOLUTION TO THE HORN-TARSKI PROBLEM. MSC 2000: 03E05, 03E20, 06A10 Keywords: Chain Conditions, Boolean Algebras. A BOREL SOLUTION TO THE HORN-TARSKI PROBLEM STEVO TODORCEVIC Abstract. We describe a Borel poset satisfying the σ-finite chain condition but failing to satisfy the σ-bounded chain condition. MSC 2000:

More information

VARIATIONS FOR SEPARATING CLUB GUESSING PRINCIPLES

VARIATIONS FOR SEPARATING CLUB GUESSING PRINCIPLES P max VARIATIONS FOR SEPARATING CLUB GUESSING PRINCIPLES TETSUYA ISHIU AND PAUL B. LARSON Abstract. In his book on P max [6], Woodin presents a collection of partial orders whose extensions satisfy strong

More information

(1) Consider the space S consisting of all continuous real-valued functions on the closed interval [0, 1]. For f, g S, define

(1) Consider the space S consisting of all continuous real-valued functions on the closed interval [0, 1]. For f, g S, define Homework, Real Analysis I, Fall, 2010. (1) Consider the space S consisting of all continuous real-valued functions on the closed interval [0, 1]. For f, g S, define ρ(f, g) = 1 0 f(x) g(x) dx. Show that

More information

General Topology. Summer Term Michael Kunzinger

General Topology. Summer Term Michael Kunzinger General Topology Summer Term 2016 Michael Kunzinger michael.kunzinger@univie.ac.at Universität Wien Fakultät für Mathematik Oskar-Morgenstern-Platz 1 A-1090 Wien Preface These are lecture notes for a

More information

Alvaro Rodrigues-Neto Research School of Economics, Australian National University. ANU Working Papers in Economics and Econometrics # 587

Alvaro Rodrigues-Neto Research School of Economics, Australian National University. ANU Working Papers in Economics and Econometrics # 587 Cycles of length two in monotonic models José Alvaro Rodrigues-Neto Research School of Economics, Australian National University ANU Working Papers in Economics and Econometrics # 587 October 20122 JEL:

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 10 Aug 2015

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 10 Aug 2015 NAIVELY HAAR NULL SETS IN POLISH GROUPS arxiv:1508.02227v1 [math.lo] 10 Aug 2015 MÁRTON ELEKES AND ZOLTÁN VIDNYÁNSZKY Abstract. Let (G, ) be a Polish group. We say that a set X G is Haar null if there

More information

Blackwell s Informativeness Theorem Using Category Theory

Blackwell s Informativeness Theorem Using Category Theory Blackwell s Informativeness Theorem Using Category Theory Henrique de Oliveira March 29, 2016 1 Introduction An agent faces a decision problem under uncertainty, whose payoff u (a, ω) depends on her action

More information

Math 210B. Profinite group cohomology

Math 210B. Profinite group cohomology Math 210B. Profinite group cohomology 1. Motivation Let {Γ i } be an inverse system of finite groups with surjective transition maps, and define Γ = Γ i equipped with its inverse it topology (i.e., the

More information

Methods of constructing topological vector spaces

Methods of constructing topological vector spaces CHAPTER 2 Methods of constructing topological vector spaces In this chapter we consider projective limits (in particular, products) of families of topological vector spaces, inductive limits (in particular,

More information

On the Consistency among Prior, Posteriors, and Information Sets

On the Consistency among Prior, Posteriors, and Information Sets On the Consistency among Prior, Posteriors, and Information Sets Satoshi Fukuda September 23, 2018 Abstract This paper studies implications of the consistency conditions among prior, posteriors, and information

More information