MISTAKES IN COOPERATION: THE STOCHASTIC STABILITY OF EDGEWORTH S RECONTRACTING*

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "MISTAKES IN COOPERATION: THE STOCHASTIC STABILITY OF EDGEWORTH S RECONTRACTING*"

Transcription

1 The Economic Journal, 118 (October), Published by Blackwell Publishing, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA. MISTAKES IN COOPERATION: THE STOCHASTIC STABILITY OF EDGEWORTH S RECONTRACTING* Roberto Serrano and Oscar Volij We analyse a dynamic trading process of coalitional recontracting in an exchange economy with indivisible goods, where agents may make mistakes with small probability. According to this process, the resistance of a transition from one allocation to another is a function of the number of agents who make mistakes and of the seriousness of each mistake. If preferences are always strict, the unique stochastically stable state is the competitive equilibrium allocation. In economies with indifferences, non-core cycles are sometimes stochastically stable, while some core allocations are not. The robustness of these results is confirmed in a weak coalitional recontracting process Edgeworth s Recontracting Process The question of what outcomes will arise in decentralised trade amongst arbitrary groups of agents dates back to Edgeworth (1881). Edgeworth argued that these outcomes consist of the set of Ôfinal settlementsõ, which is referred to as the core, i.e., the set of allocations Ôwhich cannot be varied with advantage to all the contracting partiesõ. Although this definition of Ôfinal settlementsõ applies to a static exchange economy, Edgeworth motivates them using a description of a recontracting process that is inherently dynamic. This process received elegant formalisations in the analysis of Feldman (1974) and Green (1974) where it was shown that under certain assumptions on the economy, Edgeworth s recontracting process converges to a core allocation. 1 In the present article we formalise Edgeworth s recontracting process in a way similar to those of Feldman (1974) and Green (1974), except for two differences: (1) agents make ÔmistakesÕ in their decisions 2 and (2) the process is applied to the class of housing economies introduced by Shapley and Scarf (1974). One feature of these economies is that, since their set of feasible allocations is finite, they do not satisfy some of the Feldman-Green conditions. As a result, in these economies Feldman s and Green s recontracting systems, as well as ours, fail to converge to core allocations. Indeed, in our specification of the dynamics, along with the core allocations, some long-run predictions recurrent classes arise which consist solely of * We thank Bob Aumann, Geoffroy de Clippel, Leonardo Felli, Philippe Jehiel, Michihiro Kandori, Eric Maskin, Indra Ray and two anonymous referees for useful suggestions. Serrano acknowledges support from Fundacion Banco Herrero, Universidad Carlos III, NSF grant SES and Deutsche Bank, and thanks Universidad Carlos III and CEMFI in Madrid and the Institute for Advanced Study in Princeton for their hospitality. 1 Another aspect of the relationship between dynamics and the core is provided by the literature on the extensive-form non-cooperative implementation of the core, e.g., Perry and Reny (1994) and Dagan et al. (2000). 2 Indeed, papers in cooperative game theory have no mistakes. We shall depart from this noble tradition. [ 1719 ]

2 1720 THE ECONOMIC JOURNAL [ OCTOBER non-core allocations. 3 One way to deal with this emergence of a large number of recurrent classes is to use refinement techniques, which can be accomplished by adding mistakes and applying the concept of stochastic stability. Moreover, the consideration of mistakes captures a realistic aspect of decision making Stochastic Stability in Economic Models This article applies the concept of stochastic stability to the non-strategic context of a private ownership economy. Stochastic stability was first used in game theory by Kandori et al. (1993) and Young (1993), who applied it to 2 2 games as a selection device. 4 Since then it has been applied successfully to a wide variety of models (Young, 1998). The concept of stochastic stability belongs to the ÔevolutionaryÕ approach to explaining the emergence of equilibria, conventions or social norms. 5 In this approach, agents are not fully rational but ÔprogrammedÕ to behave in a fixed way until they are replaced by other agents who are better prepared to face their environment, or by unlikely mutations. In the usual application of stochastic stability to non-cooperative games one fixes a one-shot game in normal form (strategy sets and payoff functions) played by myopic players and one specifies a stochastic process to describe how players choose their strategies in each period. The process consists of three forces: inertia, selection and randomness. Inertia is the driving force that acts most of the time: typically players automatically repeat what they played in the last period, or copy the strategy played by their immediate ancestors playing the game. At times, however, the system is affected by selection: a player may want to put some thought into his strategy, for example by choosing it as a best response to a representative sample of past history. Finally, randomness further perturbs the system in the form of mutations or experimentation in playersõ choices. A natural question that then arises is what strategies are most likely to be played in the long run. These strategies are called stochastically stable and have been shown to have interesting properties; see, for example, Kandori et al. (1993) and Young (1993). In this article we similarly consider a one-shot exchange economy (preferences and endowments) with myopic agents, which is repeated over time. We are interested in the evolution of the allocations when they follow a stochastic process that is composed of the three forces discussed above. The main force, within which the other two are embedded, can be seen as a flow of inertia. In each period the agents take their fixed initial endowments and trade them for a given consumption bundle, repeating the pattern of trade of the previous period. These bundles constitute a status quo allocation which is consumed every period, unless something disturbs the system. Inertia is interrupted by a process of selection, based on coalitional recontracting. That is, in each period a coalition is chosen with some small probability, and it has the 3 This should be compared to the results obtained within the two-sided matching model introduced by Gale and Shapley (1962). Roth and Vande Vate (1990), for instance, show that from any initial matching, there is always a path of blocking pairs leading to a matching in the core. 4 This methodology, based on the techniques developed for stochastic dynamical systems by Freidlin and Wentzell (1984), was first applied to evolutionary biology by Foster and Young (1990). 5 Other references for evolutionary game theory in general are Weibull (1995), Vega-Redondo (1996), Samuelson (1997) and Young (1998).

3 2008] EDGEWORTH S RECONTRACTING PROCESS 1721 opportunity to reallocate its resources in a way that makes its members better off. If they find one such reallocation, they carry it out, thus sending the economy to a new status quo allocation, which will be repeated each period until the next disturbance takes place. Finally, randomness is represented by a process of mistakes. When a coalition is selected to look for a profitable recontract, there is a small probability that some of its members will agree to a reallocation that makes them worse off. This persistent randomness ensures that the system does not get stuck at any given state. Instead, it keeps transiting all the time from one state to the next. Stochastic stability then identifies those states (allocations, in this case) that are visited by the system a positive proportion of time in the very long run. Fixing the preferences and endowment of the economy allows us to compare the stochastically stable allocations to the ones prescribed by classical solution concepts, such as the core or competitive equilibrium. Therefore, our goal is to identify those allocations that will be visited by Edgeworth s recontracting process a significant proportion of time in the long run if mistakes are small probability events that all agents may make all the time Summary of Results We present two kinds of results. First, under certain conditions, stochastic stability will serve as a powerful refinement tool and provide a new foundation of competitive outcomes. And second, more generally, stochastic stability will highlight that some solution concepts, such as the core, might be lacking an aspect of coalitional interactions that stochastic dynamics may help to capture. To be more precise, when we analyse the recontracting process free of mistakes, each core allocation constitutes an absorbing state and, in addition to them, subsets of noncore allocations constitute non-singleton recurrent classes. However, when mistakes are introduced into the model our results will depend on the class of economies under consideration. In economies where all preferences are strict, we are able to obtain a remarkable refinement of the set of recurrent classes by perturbing the system with mistakes. Theorem 1 states that the unique stochastically stable state of the recontracting process with mistakes is the competitive allocation, provided that serious mistakes (those by which agents end up worse off) are sufficiently more costly than minor ones (those by which agents end up neither worse nor better off). This result relies on the property of Ôglobal dominanceõ of the competitive allocation in economies with no indifferences, as identified by Roth and Postlewaite (1977). Global dominance states that for every feasible allocation, there exists a coalition whose members can (weakly) improve upon the status quo by using their competitive bundles. This property is of course confined to the housing market setting and cannot be extended to general economies. Nonetheless, the housing market is of interest and within this setting our result provides a new foundation for competitive allocations. 6 In contexts closer to a social choice model, where only preferences and not the endowments are part of the primitives, Ben-Shoham et al. (2004) and Kandori et al. (2008) explore related models that use mistakes in decision making or random utility maximisation.

4 1722 THE ECONOMIC JOURNAL [ OCTOBER The conclusions of our analysis are quite different for the more general case of economies with indifferences, where we obtain non-competitive results. We provide a series of examples to illustrate that the predictions of stochastic stability will not coincide with any of the classical solution concepts. In particular, we regard Example 5 as the other main result of the article in that it shows that non-core (and hence, noncompetitive) cycles are sometimes stochastically stable, whereas some core allocations are not. This is worth stressing for two reasons. First, when mistakes are introduced into the recontracting process the economy will frequently visit coalitionally unstable allocations. Second, entire regions of the core will be reached a zero proportion of time in the very long run. This suggests that there is a different level of ÔdecentralisationÕ behind each core allocation. Whereas some allocations may arise as a result of a simple sequence of trade and are therefore easy to reach, others will require complicated transactions and, hence, will not be reached as easily. As a robustness check of our results, we also study a second process based on weak coalitional recontracting. We find that the stochastic stability criterion always selects a non-empty subset of competitive allocations when the unperturbed process contains only singleton recurrent classes (in particular, in economies with only strict preferences, the competitive allocation is the unique recurrent class of this unperturbed process). If the mistake-free process exhibits also non-singleton recurrent classes, however, stochastic stability is compatible with the appearance of cycles containing non-competitive allocations Recontracting with Mistakes and Edgeworth s Tradition In this subsection we argue that our process of recontracting with mistakes is a faithful formalisation of the recontracting process envisioned by Edgeworth. In particular, we devote special attention to the issue of the timing of consumption. Our model has several features that deserve emphasis: 1 There is a static exchange economy. 2 This economy is repeated over time. 3 In each period trade results in a potentially different allocation and the resulting bundles are, presumably, consumed. When Edgeworth describes the process of contracting and recontracting, it is clear that he has a static exchange economy in mind:...the disposition and circumstances of the parties are assumed to remain throughout constant. (Edgeworth, 1925, p. 313.) In this context, the recontracting process consists of a series of...agreements [that] are renewed or varied many times. (Edgeworth, 1925, p. 314.) Note that the renewal of contracts is consistent with a market that takes place periodically over time. This is also suggested by the fact that Edgeworth chose the labour market to exemplify his concepts. Workers and entrepreneurs show up in the market every period with the same endowment and preferences. In particular, entrepreneurs

5 2008] EDGEWORTH S RECONTRACTING PROCESS 1723 do not sell the labour units that they bought in the previous period. The renewal of contracts is also consistent with the landlord-tenant relationship, another example mentioned by Edgeworth (see below). Further, in his Mathematical Psychics (see page 17, for instance), Edgeworth uses the expression Ôdealers in commodity xõ and Ôdealers in commodity yõ to refer to the economic agents, emphasising the persistence of the property rights based on the initial endowment allocation. Edgeworth is interested in the Ôfinal settlementsõ. According to Edgeworth a Ôfinal settlementõ consists of a set of agreements which cannot be varied with advantage to all the recontracting parties. (Edgeworth, 1925, p. 314.) The market presumably reaches a final settlement after going through various ÔsettlementsÕ or Ôtemporary equilibriaõ. Edgeworth, however, is not clear as to whether consumption takes place at each temporary equilibria or only at a final settlement. Indeed, when he explains the meaning of recontracting (or blocking, in the modern economist s jargon) he gives two examples which point to different directions concerning the issue of the timing of consumption (emphasis in the original): Thus an auctioneer having been in contact with the last bidder (to sell at such a price if no higher bid) recontracts with a higher bidder. So a landlord on expiry of lease recontracts, it may be, with a new tenant. (Edgeworth, 1881, p. 17.) In the first example there is no transaction (and a fortiori no consumption) between the auctioneer and the last bidder, due to the appearance of a higher bidder. In the second example, in contrast, there is a transaction every period between a landlord and a tenant that leads to consumption. Here, although each period s contract is just a settlement, it is not necessarily a final one. Edgeworth proposed the core as an alternative to the competitive equilibrium allocations, identified several years earlier by Walras (1874). He found that most of the times the core was indeterminate as a solution concept, since it prescribes a large set of final settlements. This contrasted with the more determinate concept due to Walras (which was believed to be unique). For this reason, Edgeworth was especially interested in this question of uniqueness of the core and was the first to notice the connection between the core and competitive allocations in large economies. 7 For Edgeworth s main purpose, the timing of consumption is irrelevant. One can interpret his temporary equilibria, very much in the competitive tattonement tradition, as agreements that are not carried out but which are intermediate steps leading to a final settlement; and alternatively, one can interpret his settlements as agreements that are carried out each period without affecting the Ôdisposition and circumstancesõ of the parties for the next period. Edgeworth s comparison of the core to Walras s equilibrium can be understood adopting either interpretation. 7 This observation gave rise to the important core convergence/equivalence literature (Debreu and Scarf, 1963; Aumann, 1964) as one of the leading game theoretic justifications of competitive equilibrium. See Anderson (1992) and Aumann (1987) for surveys. Although the robustness of the equivalence result is remarkable, several violations thereof have been identified, from which one can learn the role of certain frictions in markets. These references include Anderson and Zame (1997) for infinite dimensional commodity spaces, Manelli (1991) for instances of non-monotonicity in preferences, and Serrano et al. (2001) for asymmetric information.

6 1724 THE ECONOMIC JOURNAL [ OCTOBER However, when one focuses on the dynamic process of recontracting, the interpretation of the states of the system gains importance. The dynamic systems proposed by Feldman (1974) and Green (1974), since they do not have random perturbations, may potentially (and in fact, they actually do) converge to an absorbing state. Therefore they are consistent with an interpretation in which consumption only takes place after convergence is achieved. In our model, when agents make random mistakes, the system has no absorbing states. Therefore an interpretation more in line with the landlord tenant example, in which there are transactions and consumption every period, is more appropriate. There is yet another conceptual advantage to our approach. Essential to Edgeworth s recontracting process is the idea that any individual is free to contract and recontract without the consent of third parties. However, note that within the first interpretation there is no consumption until all agents reach an agreement. That is, no one can consume until it is certain that every agent has reached a final settlement. In fact, it may well be the case that along the path toward the final settlement, some agents hold bundles that are strictly preferred to the bundle that is consumed by them at any final settlement. Postponing consumption until the very end seems to contradict the spirit of recontracting without the consent of others. If one can recontract without the permission of others, then it would appear that one should be able also to consume without their consent. 0.5 Plan of the Article The article is organised as follows. Section 1 is concerned with preliminaries: the model and basic definitions, the unperturbed recontracting process, and its perturbed version with mistakes. Section 2 contains our main results. To check their robustness, Section 3 analyses an alternative model of weak recontracting and mistakes. Section 4 concludes. The proof of the main theorem appears in the Appendix. 1. Preliminaries 1.1. A Housing Economy We shall pose our questions in the context of the housing model of Shapley and Scarf (1974), namely a simple exchange economy with only indivisible goods; see Roth et al. (2004) for a recent successful application of the model. Formally, a housing economy is a 4-tuple EhN,H,( i,e i ) i2n i, where N is a finite set of individuals, H is a finite set of houses with the number of houses (jh j) being equal to the number of individuals (jn j). For each individual i 2 N, i is a complete and transitive preference relation over H, with C i denoting its associated strict preference relation and i its indifference relation. Finally, (e i ) i2n is the profile of individual endowments: each individual is endowed with one house. A coalition S of agents is a non-empty subset of N. The complement coalition of S, N ns, will sometimes be denoted by S. Afeasible allocation for coalition S is a redistribution of the coalitional endowment (e i ) i2s among the members of S. Denote the set of feasible allocations for coalition S by A S. We simply write A for A N. An allocation x 2 A is individually rational if there is no individual i 2 N for whom e i C i x i.

7 2008] EDGEWORTH S RECONTRACTING PROCESS 1725 An allocation x 2 A is a core allocation if there is no coalition S and no feasible allocation for S, y 2 A S, such that y i C i x i for all i 2 S. An allocation x 2 A is a strong core allocation if there is no coalition S and no feasible allocation for S, y 2 A S, such that y i C i x i for all i 2 S and y j C j x j for some j 2 S. An allocation x 2 A is a competitive allocation if there exist positive competitive equilibrium prices p such that for all i 2 Np xi ¼ p ei, and for all i 2 N and for all h 2 H, h C i x i implies p h > p ei. It has been shown (Shapley and Scarf, 1974) that an allocation x is competitive if and only if it can be obtained as a result of trading cycles. That is, if and only if there exists a partition of the set of agents fs 1,S 2,...,S m g such that for every k ¼ 1,2,...,m, x Sk 2 A Sk ; and for every j 2 S k ; x j j x i for every i 2 S k [...S m : In words, the agents in S 1 redistribute their endowments and get their most preferred houses; the agents in S 2 redistribute their endowments and get their most preferred houses out of the endowments of S 2 [...S m, and so forth. In the following subsections, we shall define two Markov processes for any given housing economy, one being a perturbation of the other. The states of the process are the allocations of the housing economy. In each period a coalition of agents is selected at random and the system moves from one state to another when the matched agents recontract. In the unperturbed Markov process M 0 of Subsection 1.2, agents do not make mistakes in their coalitional meetings: they sign a contract if and only if there is a strictly beneficial coalitional recontracting opportunity. In the perturbed process M of Subsection 1.3, agents will make mistakes with a small probability and sign a contract with a coalition even when they do not improve as a result. In Section 3 we study Markov trading processes in which coalitions can find a weak (rather than strict) coalitional recontracting move. It is often the case that an unperturbed Markov process (and it will certainly be the case for M 0 ) has many long-run predictions recurrent classes and thus many stationary or invariant distributions. As such, the long-run behaviour of the system crucially depends on the initial state. On the other hand, for each small >0, the perturbed process M is ergodic, which implies that it has a unique stationary distribution, denoted by l. This stationary distribution, which is independent of the initial state, represents the proportion of time that the system will spend on each of its states in the long run. It also represents the long-run probability that the process will be at each allocation. In order to define the stochastically stable states, which are our objects of interest, we check the behaviour of the stationary distribution l as goes to 0. It is known that lim!0 l exists and further that it is one of the stationary distributions of the unperturbed process M 0. The stochastically stable states of the system M are defined to be those states that are assigned positive probability by this limit distribution. We are interested in identifying these allocations because they are the ones that are expected to be observed in the long run Ômost of the timeõ An Unperturbed Recontracting Process Consider the following unperturbed Markov process M 0, adapted from Feldman (1974) and Green (1974). In each period t, if the system is at the allocation x(t), one

8 1726 THE ECONOMIC JOURNAL [ OCTOBER coalition is chosen according to an arbitrary distribution which assigns positive probability to each coalition. Suppose coalition S is chosen. (i) If there exists an S-allocation y S 2 A S such that y i C i x i (t) for all i 2 S, the coalition moves with positive probability to one of such y S in that period. Then, the new state is either xðt þ 1Þ ¼ðy S ; x S ðtþþ if x S ðtþ 2A S ; or (ii) Otherwise, x(t þ 1) ¼ x(t). xðt þ 1Þ ¼ðy S ; e S Þ if x S ðtþ j2 A S : The interpretation of the process is one of coalitional recontracting. Following a status quo x(t), a coalition can form and modify the status quo if all members of the coalition improve as a result. When this happens, upon coalition S forming, the complement coalition N ns continues to have the same houses as before if this is feasible for them. Otherwise, N ns breaks apart and each of the agents in it receives his individual endowment. 8 If after coalition S forms all its agents cannot find any strict improvement, the original status quo persists A Perturbed Recontracting Process Next we introduce the perturbed Markov process M for an arbitrary small 2 (0,1), a perturbation of M 0. Suppose the state of the system is the allocation x and that coalition S meets. We shall say that a member of S makes a ÔmistakeÕ when he signs a contract that either leaves him indifferent to the same house he already had or he becomes worse off upon signing. Each of the members of S may make one of these ÔmistakesÕ with a small probability, as a function of >0, independently of the others. Specifically, for a small fixed 2 (0,1), we shall postulate that an agent s probability of agreeing to a new allocation that leaves him indifferent is, while the probability of agreeing to an allocation that makes him worse off is k for a sufficiently large positive integer k. That is, the latter mistakes are much less likely than the former, while both are rare events in the agent s decisionmaking process. 9 Before we define the perturbed process, we need some notation and definitions. Consider an arbitrary pair of allocations z and z 0. Let T(z, z 0 ) be the set of coalitions such that, if chosen, can induce the perturbed system to transit from z to z 0 in one step. Note that it is always the case that T(z, z 0 ) is non-empty, since N 2 T(z, z 0 ) for any z and z 0. 8 Our treatment of the complement coalition constitutes a small difference with respect to the processes in Feldman (1974) and Green (1974): in these papers, when recontracting happens, the complement coalition is sent back always to their individual endowments in Feldman (1974), or to a Pareto efficient allocation of their resources in Green (1974). Our results are robust to different specifications; for instance, if only those agents in N ns who are directly or indirectly affected by the reallocation proposed by S are sent to their initial endowments, while the rest of the economy stays put. 9 Following Bergin and Lipman (1996), the results will depend on the specification of these probabilities. Our results are robust to any specification where a transition that makes an agent worse off is less likely than one in which the only frictions are indifferences.

9 2008] EDGEWORTH S RECONTRACTING PROCESS 1727 In the direct transition from z to z 0 and for each S 2 T(z,z 0 ), define the following numbers: n I ðs; z; z 0 Þ¼jfi 2 S : z i i zi 0 gj; n W ðs; z; z 0 Þ¼jfi 2 S : z i i zi 0 gj; nðs; z; z 0 Þ¼kn W ðs; z; z 0 Þþn I ðs; z; z 0 Þ: Here n I (S, z, z 0 ) is the number of individuals in S that are indifferent between allocations z and z 0. Similarly, n W (S, z, z 0 ) is the number of members of S that make a mistake by agreeing to move from z to z 0, worse for them. Finally, n(s, z, z 0 ) is the weighted number of mistakes that are made in the transition from z to z 0, where k > 1 is the weight given to ÔseriousÕ mistakes relative to those that lead to just indifference. In the perturbed Markov process M the transition probabilities are calculated as follows. Suppose that the system is in allocation z. All coalitions are chosen with a fixed positive probability. Assume coalition S is chosen. If S j2 T(z, z 0 ), then S moves to z 0 with probability 0. If S 2 T(z, z 0 ) and n(s, z, z 0 ) > 0, then coalition S agrees to move to z 0 with probability n(s,z,z0).ifs 2 T(z, z 0 ) and n(s, z, z 0 ) ¼ 0, coalition S moves to those z 0 with some (possibly state-dependent) probability d, where 0 < d < 1/jAj. For all 2 (0,1) small enough, the system M is a well-defined irreducible Markov process, i.e., one can go from any allocation to any other one with positive probability in a finite number of periods. As such, it has a unique invariant distribution. This distribution is a good estimate of the probability that the system is in each of the allocations in the long run. We are interested in the limit of the corresponding invariant distributions as tends to 0. More precisely, our focus will be on the allocations that are assigned positive probability by this limiting distribution. These allocations are called stochastically stable allocations. In order to obtain our results, we will use the techniques developed by Kandori et al. (1993) and Young (1993). But before that, we need some additional definitions. Note that by the definition of the perturbed Markov process M, for every two allocations z and z 0, the direct transition probability l z,z 0() converges to the limit transition probability l z,z 0(0) of the unperturbed process M 0 at an exponential rate. In particular, for all allocations z, z 0 such that l z,z 0(0) ¼ 0, the convergence is at a rate r(z, z 0 ) ¼ min S2T(z,z 0 )kn W (S, z, z 0 ) þ n I (S, z, z 0 ), that is, the weighted number of mistakes associated with the most likely direct transition. We call the value r(z, z 0 )the resistance of the direct transition from allocation z to allocation z 0. For any two allocations z, z 0,a(z, z 0 )-path is a sequence of allocations n ¼ (i 0,i 1,...,i m ) such that i 0 ¼ z, i m ¼ z 0. The resistance of the path n is the sum of the resistances of its transitions. We seek to find the path of least resistance between any two allocations. Let Z 0 ¼fE 0, E 1,..., E Q g be the set of recurrent classes of the unperturbed process M 0 each recurrent class E j is a set of states with the property that if the process M 0 reaches a state in the class, it will never get out of that class. Consider the complete directed graph with vertex set Z 0. We want to define the resistance of each one of the edges in this graph. For this, let E i and E j be two elements of Z 0. The resistance of the edge (E i,e j ) in the graph, r(e i, E j ), is the minimum resistance over all the resistances of the (z i, z j )-paths, where z i 2 E i and z j 2 E j. A spanning tree rooted at E j,orane j -tree, is a set of directed edges such that from every recurrent class different from E j, there is a

10 1728 THE ECONOMIC JOURNAL [ OCTOBER unique directed path in the tree to E j. The resistance of an E j -tree is the sum of the resistances of its edges. The stochastic potential of the recurrent class E j is the minimum resistance attained by an E j -tree: it captures the smallest friction to get to class E j from any of the other recurrent classes. As shown in Young (1993), the set of stochastically stable states of the perturbed process M consists of those states belonging to the recurrent classes with minimum stochastic potential. 2. Main Results Let us begin by analysing the long-run predictions of the unperturbed process M 0.Itis clear that the absorbing states of this unperturbed process are precisely the core allocations of the economy. However, the absorbing states are not the only recurrent classes of M 0, as shown by the following example. Example 1. Let N ¼ f1, 2, 3g and denote by the individual endowment allocation (e 1, e 2, e 3 ). Let the agentsõ preferences be as follows: e 3 1 e 2 1 e 1 ; e 1 2 e 3 2 e 2 ; e 2 3 e 1 3 e 3 : Consider the following three allocations: x ¼ (e 1, e 3, e 2 ), y ¼ (e 2, e 1, e 3 ) and z ¼ (e 3, e 2, e 1 ). These three allocations constitute a recurrent class: if the system is at x, the state changes only when coalition f1, 2g meets, yielding y. At y, the system can move only to z, when coalition f1, 3g meets. Finally, the system will move out of z only by going back to x, when coalition f2, 3g meets. Note that the unique competitive allocation w ¼ (e 3, e 1, e 2 ) also constitutes a singleton recurrent class. We can prove the following result, which characterises the recurrent classes of the unperturbed process M 0 : Proposition 1. The recurrent classes of the unperturbed recontracting process M 0 take the following two forms: (i ) Singleton recurrent classes, each of which contains each core allocation. (ii ) Non-singleton recurrent classes: in each of which, the allocations are individually rational but are not core allocations. Proof. It is clear that each core allocation constitutes an absorbing state of M 0 and that every absorbing state must be a core allocation. For the second form of recurrent class, note that, by construction of the system, no state in a recurrent class can ever be non-individually rational: if at some state x in which e i C i x i the coalition fig is chosen, then, the system moves to the individual endowment e, never to return to a nonindividually rational allocation. It is also clear that each of the states in the recurrent class cannot be absorbing, i.e., cannot be a core allocation. Thus, each core allocation is an absorbing state of the unperturbed Markov process M 0 and, in principle, there may be additional non-singleton recurrent classes, such as

11 2008] EDGEWORTH S RECONTRACTING PROCESS 1729 that shown in Example 1. Note also that as soon as the economy has more than one core allocation, the system M 0 has many stationary distributions. This multiplicity of long-run predictions justifies the consideration of the perturbed process based on mistakes, whose results we shall report next Economies with Strict Preferences In this subsection we shall assume that for every agent i 2 N the preference relation i is antisymmetric, which implies that all indifference sets are singletons: for all i 2 N, h i h 0 if and only if h ¼ h 0. Making this assumption, Roth and Postlewaite (1977) proved the following result: Lemma 1. Let E be a housing economy where all preferences are strict. Then, (i ) There is a unique competitive allocation w. (ii ) The allocation w is the only strong core allocation. (iii ) Global dominanceõ of w: For every allocation x 2 A, x 6¼ w, there exists a coalition S such that w S is feasible for S and satisfies w i i x i for all i 2 S and w j C j x j for some j 2 S. Lemma 1 will be useful in proving our first main result, which we state as follows: Theorem 1. Let E be a housing economy where all preferences are strict. Suppose that k > jn j 2. Then, the unique stochastically stable allocation of the perturbed recontracting process with mistakes M is the competitive allocation w. The proof of Theorem 1 is in the Appendix. It combines the different parts of Lemma 1. Specifically, its parts (ii) and (iii) imply that the competitive allocation w is a strong dynamic attractor in the trading process with mistakes. Theorem 1 provides a remarkable refinement of the set of long-run predictions of the unperturbed process, as identified in Proposition Economies with Indifferences In this subsection we explore how the stochastic process of recontracting with mistakes, M, performs over the class of economies that allow non-singleton indifference sets for some agents. Over this larger class of economies, Proposition 1 still holds. However, the conclusions of Lemma 1 do not extend. First, although existence is guaranteed, there may be multiple competitive allocations. Second, the strong core may also contain multiple allocations, while it may sometimes be empty. Third, the Ôglobal dominanceõ property of competitive allocations as specified in Lemma 1, part (iii), is also lost. In economies with only strict preferences, the competitive allocation correspondence and the strong core coincide and, under our assumption on k, the same allocation is the only one that passes the test of stochastic stability. It is convenient, therefore, to examine the larger class of economies to disentangle the different forces at work in the selection of the stochastically stable allocations. We find that the recontracting system with mistakes gives rise to complicated dynamics and no general result of equivalence

12 1730 THE ECONOMIC JOURNAL [ OCTOBER can be established. Therefore, we learn that the paths of least resistance followed in our stochastic dynamic analysis are not intrinsically associated with the strong core property or with the competitive property of allocations. We present four examples. We arrange them by increasing difficulty and relevance. Indeed, we regard Example 5 as the other main result of the article. In some of these examples, one agent has a completely flat indifference map but this is only for simplicity of exposition. Also, in the examples we shall use the notation z! r S z0 to express that the transition of least resistance from z to z 0 takes place through coalition S with a resistance r. We begin by showing that the set of stochastically stable allocations is not the strong core. As just mentioned, the strong core may be empty in these economies, while stochastic stability always selects at least one allocation; but even when the strong core is non-empty, one can generate examples where it does not coincide with the set of stochastically stable states of M. Example 2. In this example, a non-empty strong core is strictly contained in the set of stochastically stable allocations. Let N ¼f1,2g and agentsõ preferences be described as follows: e 1 1 e 2 ; e 1 2 e 2 : In this economy there are two allocations, both of which are competitive, but only the one resulting from trade is in the strong core. Note that both allocations are stochastically stable: ðe 1 ; e 2 Þ! 1 N ðe 2; e 1 Þ and ðe 2 ; e 1 Þ! 1 f1g ðe 1; e 2 Þ. The next example shows that the set of stochastically stable allocations may be a strict subset of the strong core and of the set of competitive allocations. Example 3. Let N ¼f1, 2, 3g and the agentsõ preferences be given by: e 1 1 e 2 1 e 3 ; e 1 2 e 3 2 e 2 ; e 1 3 e 2 3 e 3 : In this economy, all allocations except the initial endowment allocation are competitive and belong to the core. The strong core consists of the following three allocations: (e 2, e 3, e 1 ), (e 3, e 1, e 2 ) and (e 1, e 3, e 2 ). The unique stochastically stable allocation is x ¼ (e 1, e 3, e 2 ). To see that x is the only allocation with minimum stochastic potential, one can construct an x-tree as follows. First, we note that the only recurrent classes of M 0 are the five absorbing states corresponding to each competitive allocation. Next, note that to go from (e 2, e 3, e 1 ) to x can be done with a resistance of 1 (only one indifference): ðe 2 ; e 3 ; e 1 Þ! 1 f1g ðe 1; e 2 ; e 3 Þ! 0 f2;3g x. The same goes for the transition (e 3, e 1, e 2 )tox: ðe 3 ; e 1 ; e 2 Þ! 1 f1g ðe 1; e 2 ; e 3 Þ! 0 f2;3g x. As for the other transitions, we have ðe 3 ; e 2 ; e 1 Þ! 1 f2;3g x and ðe 2; e 1 ; e 3 Þ! 1 f2;3g x. Therefore, the resistance of this x-tree is 4 and one cannot build a cheaper tree than that. On the other hand, to get out of x, the resistance will always be at least 2, i.e., at least two indifferences, which implies that in constructing a tree for any of the other recurrent classes its resistance must be at least 5.

13 2008] EDGEWORTH S RECONTRACTING PROCESS 1731 Our next example illustrates the only substantive difference in results between the recontracting process M and its counterpart based on weak recontracting that will be studied in the following Section. Specifically, we now construct an economy for which all recurrent classes of M 0 are singletons and where the set of stochastically stable allocations of M contains an allocation that is not competitive. Example 4. Let N ¼f1, 2, 3, 4g and let the agentsõ preferences be described as follows: e 1 1 e 3 1 e 4 1 e 2 ; e 1 2 e 4 2 e 3 2 e 2 ; e 2 3 e 1 3 e 3 3 e 4 ; e 2 4 e 3 4 e 4 4 e 1 : One can check that there are four competitive allocations: w 1 ¼ (e 3, e 4, e 1, e 2 ), w 2 ¼ (e 1, e 4, e 3, e 2 ), w 3 ¼ (e 4, e 1, e 3, e 2 ), and w 4 ¼ (e 3, e 1, e 2, e 4 ). In addition, there are three other core allocations that are not competitive: y 1 ¼ (e 1, e 4, e 2, e 3 ), y 2 ¼ (e 4, e 1, e 2, e 3 ), and y 3 ¼ (e 4, e 3, e 1, e 2 ). Since Proposition 1 also applies to the economies considered in this subsection, it follows that each of these seven allocations constitutes an absorbing state of M 0. Further, it can be checked that there are no additional recurrent classes. Apart from the seven core allocations, the only absorbing states of M 0, there are four more individually rational allocations. One is e ¼ (e 1, e 2, e 3, e 4 ) - the initial endowment allocation - and the other three are x 1 ¼ (e 1, e 3, e 2, e 4 ), x 2 ¼ (e 3, e 2, e 1, e 4 ) and x 3 ¼ (e 4, e 2, e 1, e 3 ). It can be checked that from each of these four allocations one can go with zero resistance to one of the core allocations. Consider now the following fy 1 g-tree comprising the following edges: w 1! y 1, w 2! w 1, w 3! w 1, w 4! w 2, y 2! w 2, y 3! y 1. We check next that each of these edges has resistance 1 (corresponding to a transition with only one indifference), thereby implying that the tree has minimum stochastic potential. These transitions can be detailed as follows: w 1! 1 f1g e!0 f2;3;4g y 1; w 2! 1 f1;3g x 2! 0 f2;4g w 1; w 3! 1 f1;3g x 2! 0 f2;4g w 1; w 4! 1 f2;4g w 2; y 2! 1 f2;4g w 2; y 3! 1 f1g e!0 f2;3;4g y 1: Thus, y 1 is stochastically stable, although it is not a competitive allocation. It is not in the strong core either; indeed, the strong core is empty in this economy.

14 1732 THE ECONOMIC JOURNAL [ OCTOBER The next example shows that in a dynamic model where agents may make mistakes in decision making, the core may not agree with the set of states that are visited by the process a positive proportion of time. In contrast, some non-core allocations may fare better in this sense than some core allocations. Example This example, an outgrowth of Example 1, shows that a cycle of noncore allocations may be stochastically stable, at the same time as some core allocations having higher stochastic potential. Let N ¼f1, 2, 3, 4g, and let the agentsõ preferences be as follows: e 4 1 e 3 1 e 2 1 e 1 ; e 1 2 e 3 2 e 2 2 e 4 ; e 2 3 e 1 3 e 3 3 e 4 ; e 1 4 e 2 4 e 3 4 e 4 : Consider the following three allocations: x ¼ (e 1, e 3, e 2, e 4 ), y ¼ (e 2, e 1, e 3, e 4 ) and z ¼ (e 3, e 2, e 1, e 4 ). Since agent 4 cannot strictly improve, he cannot be part of any blocking coalition. In fact, as in Example 1, these three allocations constitute a recurrent class: if the system is at x, the state changes only when coalition f1, 2g meets, yielding y. Aty, the system can move only to z, when coalition f1, 3g meets. Finally, the system will move out of z only by going back to x, when coalition f2, 3g meets. That is, x! 0 f1;2g y!0 f1;3g z!0 f2;3g x. The core consists of the following five allocations: c 1 ¼ (e 3, e 1, e 2, e 4 ), c 2 ¼ (e 4, e 1, e 2, e 3 ), c 3 ¼ (e 4, e 1, e 3, e 2 ), c 4 ¼ (e 4, e 3, e 1, e 2 ) and c 5 ¼ (e 4, e 3, e 2, e 1 ). It is easy to see that these five absorbing states i.e., the core allocations and the cycle are the only recurrent classes of the unperturbed system: the twelve allocations where e 4 is allocated to either agent 2 or agent 3 are not even individually rational. And from each of the remaining four allocations, one gets to one of the already identified recurrent classes with 0 resistance: a 1 ¼ðe 1 ; e 2 ; e 3 ; e 4 Þ! 0 f1;2;3g c 1, a 2 ¼ðe 2 ; e 3 ; e 1 ; e 4 Þ! 0 f1;2;3g c 1, a 3 ¼ðe 4 ; e 2 ; e 1 ; e 3 Þ! 0 f2;3g x and a 4 ¼ðe 4 ; e 2 ; e 3 ; e 1 Þ! 0 f2;3g c 5. Let E ¼ fx, y, zg be the non-singleton recurrent class consisting of non-core allocations. Next, we construct an E-tree and show that it has minimum stochastic potential. This tree must have five edges, coming out of each of the five core allocations. We detail the transitions below: c 1! 1 f1;4g a 4! 0 f2;3g c 5; c j! 1 f4g a 1! 0 f1;2g y; for j ¼ 2; 3; 4; 5: Therefore, the class E has minimum stochastic potential. Note also that there are four competitive allocations: c 1, c 2, c 3 and c 5. Thus, the example also shows that there are non-competitive stochastically stable allocations. 10 As communicated to us by Bob Aumann, a similar story is told in the Talmud: there is a cycle of three two-person coalitions improving the status quo. The three players involved in the cycle are the two wives of a man and a third party who buys the man s estate. The cycle occurs after the man died and left his estate. The deceased agent naturally corresponds to our agent 4, who has a flat indifference map. See also Binmore (1985) for a more recent related problem.

15 2008] EDGEWORTH S RECONTRACTING PROCESS 1733 However, apart from E, the only stochastically stable allocations are the four competitive allocations c 1, c 2, c 3 and c 5 : there are allocations in the core that are not visited in the long run but a zero proportion of time. In particular, it can be checked that it takes at least two indifferences to get out of other recurrent classes to go to c 4. This implies that c 4 cannot be stochastically stable. To illustrate, we construct a fc 4 g-tree as follows: c 1! 1 f1;4g a 4! 0 f2;3g c 5; c j! 1 f4g a 1! 0 f1;2g ðy 2 EÞ; for j ¼ 2; 3; 5; ðz 2 EÞ! 2 N c 4: Thus, this dynamic analysis, which sheds light on how each allocation emerges, makes a distinction among different core allocations. Some core allocations (like c 4 in the example) are actually very hard to get to, when compared to other allocations in the core or even outside of the core. The point is that the usual emphasis in the definition of the core is given to the non-existence of a coalitional blocking move, whereas the issue of how the allocation in question emerges is disregarded. Dynamics should have something to say about the matter and Example 5 is a confirmation that this is indeed the case. 3. Recontracting Based on Weak Blocking As a robustness check of our results, this Section analyses a Markov process in which transitions take place whenever there is an instance of weak coalitional blocking, instead of the strict version thereof, as was the case in the process M The Unperturbed Process Consider the following unperturbed Markov process M 0 W, which represents the Ôweak recontractingõ version of the process presented in Subsection 1.2. In each period t, the system is at the allocation x(t), and one coalition is chosen according to an arbitrary probability distribution that assigns positive probability to each coalition. Suppose coalition S is chosen. (i) If there exists an S-allocation y S 2 A S such that y i i x i (t) for all i 2 S and y j C j x j (t) for some j 2 S, the coalition moves with positive probability to some of such y S in that period. Then, the new state is either xðt þ 1Þ ¼ðy S ; x S ðtþþ if x S ðtþ 2A S ; or (ii) Otherwise, x(t þ 1) ¼ x(t). xðt þ 1Þ ¼ðy S ; e S Þ if x S ðtþ j2 A S :

16 1734 THE ECONOMIC JOURNAL [ OCTOBER The interpretation of this new process is one of weak coalitional recontracting. Following a status quo, a coalition can form and modify the status quo if at least one member of the coalition improves as a result, and if none of the other members is made worse off. Apart from this change, the process is identical to the one in Subsection 2.2. That is, when the weak coalitional recontracting move occurs, upon coalition S forming, the complement coalition N ns continues to have the same houses as before, if this is feasible for them. Otherwise, N ns breaks apart and each of the agents in it receives his individual endowment (the same comment as in footnote 8 applies here in terms of alternative specifications). If after coalition S forms, it cannot find any such weak coalitional improvement, the original status quo persists. The absorbing states of the unperturbed process M 0 W are precisely the strong core allocations of the economy. However, the absorbing states are not the only recurrent classes of M 0 W. The easiest way to see this is to note that there are economies in which the strong core is empty. We can prove the following result, similar to Proposition 1, which characterises the recurrent classes of the unperturbed process M 0 W : Proposition 2. The recurrent classes of the unperturbed weak recontracting process M 0 W take the following two forms: (i) Singleton recurrent classes, each of which contains each strong core allocation. (ii) Non-singleton recurrent classes, in each of which, the allocations are individually rational but are not strong core allocations. Proof. The proof is similar to that of Proposition 1. Thus, each strong core allocation is an absorbing state of the unperturbed Markov process M 0 W, and in principle there may be additional non-singleton recurrent classes. Note also that as soon as the economy has more than one strong core allocation, the system M 0 W has many stationary distributions. The conclusions of Proposition 2 extend to all economies where preferences are complete and transitive, with or without indifferences. One can now obtain a simple generalisation of the conclusions of Theorem 1. In fact, the competitive result is obtained even before mistakes are added to the process. Proposition 3. Let E be a housing economy where all preferences are strict. Then, the unperturbed weak recontracting process M 0 W is ergodic and the only recurrent class is the singleton consisting of the unique competitive allocation. Proof. The proof follows from the definition of the transitions in the process and from Lemma 1. Notice how, as in Theorem 1, the Ôglobal dominanceõ property of the competitive allocation in these economies makes it the only prediction of the dynamic process, this time as the strong attractor of the unperturbed system (see Example 1 for an illustration).

MISTAKES IN COOPERATION: the Stochastic Stability of Edgeworth s Recontracting. Roberto Serrano Oscar Volij. January 2003

MISTAKES IN COOPERATION: the Stochastic Stability of Edgeworth s Recontracting. Roberto Serrano Oscar Volij. January 2003 MISTAKES IN COOPERATION: the Stochastic Stability of Edgeworth s Recontracting Roberto Serrano Oscar Volij January 2003 Abstract. In an exchange economy with a finite number of indivisible goods, we analyze

More information

Contracts under Asymmetric Information

Contracts under Asymmetric Information Contracts under Asymmetric Information 1 I Aristotle, economy (oiko and nemo) and the idea of exchange values, subsequently adapted by Ricardo and Marx. Classical economists. An economy consists of a set

More information

The Coordinate-Wise Core for Multiple-Type Housing Markets is Second-Best Incentive Compatible

The Coordinate-Wise Core for Multiple-Type Housing Markets is Second-Best Incentive Compatible The Coordinate-Wise Core for Multiple-Type Housing Markets is Second-Best Incentive Compatible Bettina Klaus October 2005 Abstract We consider the generalization of Shapley and Scarf s (1974) model of

More information

Selecting Efficient Correlated Equilibria Through Distributed Learning. Jason R. Marden

Selecting Efficient Correlated Equilibria Through Distributed Learning. Jason R. Marden 1 Selecting Efficient Correlated Equilibria Through Distributed Learning Jason R. Marden Abstract A learning rule is completely uncoupled if each player s behavior is conditioned only on his own realized

More information

The Debreu-Scarf Theorem: The Core Converges to the Walrasian Allocations

The Debreu-Scarf Theorem: The Core Converges to the Walrasian Allocations The Debreu-Scarf Theorem: The Core Converges to the Walrasian Allocations We ve shown that any Walrasian equilibrium allocation (any WEA) is in the core, but it s obvious that the converse is far from

More information

On the Shapley-Scarf Economy: The Case of Multiple Types of Indivisible Goods

On the Shapley-Scarf Economy: The Case of Multiple Types of Indivisible Goods On the Shapley-Scarf Economy: The Case of Multiple Types of Indivisible Goods Hideo Konishi Thomas Quint Jun Wako April, 1997 (first version) October 1997 (revised) July 20, 2000 (second revision) file

More information

Introduction. 1 University of Pennsylvania, Wharton Finance Department, Steinberg Hall-Dietrich Hall, 3620

Introduction. 1 University of Pennsylvania, Wharton Finance Department, Steinberg Hall-Dietrich Hall, 3620 May 16, 2006 Philip Bond 1 Are cheap talk and hard evidence both needed in the courtroom? Abstract: In a recent paper, Bull and Watson (2004) present a formal model of verifiability in which cheap messages

More information

Notes on General Equilibrium

Notes on General Equilibrium Notes on General Equilibrium Alejandro Saporiti Alejandro Saporiti (Copyright) General Equilibrium 1 / 42 General equilibrium Reference: Jehle and Reny, Advanced Microeconomic Theory, 3rd ed., Pearson

More information

NOTES ON COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY AND THE CORE. 1. Introduction

NOTES ON COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY AND THE CORE. 1. Introduction NOTES ON COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY AND THE CORE SARA FROEHLICH 1. Introduction Cooperative game theory is fundamentally different from the types of games we have studied so far, which we will now refer to

More information

A finite population ESS and a long run equilibrium in an n players coordination game

A finite population ESS and a long run equilibrium in an n players coordination game Mathematical Social Sciences 39 (000) 95 06 www.elsevier.nl/ locate/ econbase A finite population ESS and a long run equilibrium in an n players coordination game Yasuhito Tanaka* Faculty of Law, Chuo

More information

Core and Top Trading Cycles in a Market with Indivisible Goods and Externalities

Core and Top Trading Cycles in a Market with Indivisible Goods and Externalities Core and Top Trading Cycles in a Market with Indivisible Goods and Externalities Miho Hong Jaeok Park December 17, 2017 Abstract In this paper, we incorporate externalities into Shapley-Scarf housing markets.

More information

Coalitional stochastic stability

Coalitional stochastic stability Under revision for invited resubmission to Games & Economic Behavior. Coalitional stochastic stability Jonathan Newton November 9, 2010 Abstract This paper takes the idea of coalitional behaviour - groups

More information

Implementation of the Ordinal Shapley Value for a three-agent economy 1

Implementation of the Ordinal Shapley Value for a three-agent economy 1 Implementation of the Ordinal Shapley Value for a three-agent economy 1 David Pérez-Castrillo 2 Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona David Wettstein 3 Ben-Gurion University of the Negev April 2005 1 We gratefully

More information

First Welfare Theorem

First Welfare Theorem First Welfare Theorem Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 17, October 31 Outline 1 First Welfare Theorem 2 Preliminaries to Second Welfare Theorem Past Definitions A feasible allocation (ˆx, ŷ) is Pareto optimal

More information

Random paths to stability in the roommate problem

Random paths to stability in the roommate problem Games and Economic Behavior 48 (2004) 18 28 www.elsevier.com/locate/geb Random paths to stability in the roommate problem Effrosyni Diamantoudi, a Eiichi Miyagawa, b, and Licun Xue c a Concordia University,

More information

Algorithmic Game Theory and Applications

Algorithmic Game Theory and Applications Algorithmic Game Theory and Applications Lecture 18: Auctions and Mechanism Design II: a little social choice theory, the VCG Mechanism, and Market Equilibria Kousha Etessami Reminder: Food for Thought:

More information

Volume 31, Issue 1. A solution concept for housing market problems with externalities. Alfredo Salgado-Torres Universidad Carlos III de Madrid

Volume 31, Issue 1. A solution concept for housing market problems with externalities. Alfredo Salgado-Torres Universidad Carlos III de Madrid Volume 31, Issue 1 A solution concept for housing market problems with externalities Alfredo Salgado-Torres Universidad Carlos III de Madrid Abstract Since the core of a housing market with externalities

More information

Farsighted House Allocation

Farsighted House Allocation Farsighted House Allocation Bettina Klaus Flip Klijn Markus Walzl Working Paper 09-129 Copyright 2009 by Bettina Klaus, Flip Klijn, and Markus Walzl Working papers are in draft form. This working paper

More information

Economics 201B Second Half. Lecture 12-4/22/10. Core is the most commonly used. The core is the set of all allocations such that no coalition (set of

Economics 201B Second Half. Lecture 12-4/22/10. Core is the most commonly used. The core is the set of all allocations such that no coalition (set of Economics 201B Second Half Lecture 12-4/22/10 Justifying (or Undermining) the Price-Taking Assumption Many formulations: Core, Ostroy s No Surplus Condition, Bargaining Set, Shapley-Shubik Market Games

More information

Question 1. (p p) (x(p, w ) x(p, w)) 0. with strict inequality if x(p, w) x(p, w ).

Question 1. (p p) (x(p, w ) x(p, w)) 0. with strict inequality if x(p, w) x(p, w ). University of California, Davis Date: August 24, 2017 Department of Economics Time: 5 hours Microeconomics Reading Time: 20 minutes PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION FOR THE Ph.D. DEGREE Please answer any three

More information

Unlinked Allocations in an Exchange Economy with One Good and One Bad

Unlinked Allocations in an Exchange Economy with One Good and One Bad Unlinked llocations in an Exchange Economy with One Good and One ad Chiaki Hara Faculty of Economics and Politics, University of Cambridge Institute of Economic Research, Hitotsubashi University pril 16,

More information

Strategy-Proofness and the Core in House Allocation Problems

Strategy-Proofness and the Core in House Allocation Problems Strategy-Proofness and the Core in House Allocation Problems Eiichi Miyagawa Department of Economics, Columbia University 420 West 118th Street, New York, NY 10027 Email: em437@columbia.edu July 28, 1999

More information

Market Equilibrium and the Core

Market Equilibrium and the Core Market Equilibrium and the Core Ram Singh Lecture 3-4 September 22/25, 2017 Ram Singh (DSE) Market Equilibrium September 22/25, 2017 1 / 19 Market Exchange: Basics Let us introduce price in our pure exchange

More information

A : a b c d a : B C A E B : d b c a b : C A B D E C : d c a c : E D B C D : a d b d : A D E B C E : a b d. A : a b c d a : B C A D E

A : a b c d a : B C A E B : d b c a b : C A B D E C : d c a c : E D B C D : a d b d : A D E B C E : a b d. A : a b c d a : B C A D E Microeconomics II( ECO 50) Questions on the comprehensive exam will be chosen from the list below( with possible minor variations) CALCULATORS ARE ALLOWED Matching. Consider the Gale-Shapley marriage problem

More information

Sufficient Conditions for Weak Group-Strategy-Proofness

Sufficient Conditions for Weak Group-Strategy-Proofness Sufficient Conditions for Weak Group-Strategy-Proofness T.C.A. Madhav Raghavan 31 July, 2014 Abstract In this note we study group-strategy-proofness, which is the extension of strategy-proofness to groups

More information

Conflict Leads to Cooperation in Demand Bargaining

Conflict Leads to Cooperation in Demand Bargaining Conflict Leads to Cooperation in Demand Bargaining Kareen Rozen Yale University Abstract We consider a multilateral Nash demand game in which short-sighted players come to the bargaining table with requests

More information

On the Maximal Domain Theorem

On the Maximal Domain Theorem On the Maximal Domain Theorem Yi-You Yang April 28, 2016 Abstract The maximal domain theorem by Gul and Stacchetti (J. Econ. Theory 87 (1999), 95-124) shows that for markets with indivisible objects and

More information

Mathematical models in economy. Short descriptions

Mathematical models in economy. Short descriptions Chapter 1 Mathematical models in economy. Short descriptions 1.1 Arrow-Debreu model of an economy via Walras equilibrium problem. Let us consider first the so-called Arrow-Debreu model. The presentation

More information

1 Second Welfare Theorem

1 Second Welfare Theorem Econ 701B Fall 018 University of Pennsylvania Recitation : Second Welfare Theorem Xincheng Qiu (qiux@sas.upenn.edu) 1 Second Welfare Theorem Theorem 1. (Second Welfare Theorem) An economy E satisfies (A1)-(A4).

More information

General equilibrium with externalities and tradable licenses

General equilibrium with externalities and tradable licenses General equilibrium with externalities and tradable licenses Carlos Hervés-Beloso RGEA. Universidad de Vigo. e-mail: cherves@uvigo.es Emma Moreno-García Universidad de Salamanca. e-mail: emmam@usal.es

More information

6 Evolution of Networks

6 Evolution of Networks last revised: March 2008 WARNING for Soc 376 students: This draft adopts the demography convention for transition matrices (i.e., transitions from column to row). 6 Evolution of Networks 6. Strategic network

More information

Uniqueness, Stability, and Gross Substitutes

Uniqueness, Stability, and Gross Substitutes Uniqueness, Stability, and Gross Substitutes Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 21, November 14 Outline 1 Uniquenness (in pictures) 2 Stability 3 Gross Substitute Property Uniqueness and Stability We have dealt

More information

A Farsighted Stable Set for Partition Function Games

A Farsighted Stable Set for Partition Function Games 0 A Farsighted Stable Set for Partition Function Games Parkash Chander * August, 2015 Preliminary Draft Abstract In this paper, we introduce a concept of a farsighted stable set for a partition function

More information

INFORMATION TRANSMISSION IN COALITIONAL VOTING GAMES * Roberto Serrano 1 and Rajiv Vohra

INFORMATION TRANSMISSION IN COALITIONAL VOTING GAMES * Roberto Serrano 1 and Rajiv Vohra Working Paper 05-57 Economics Series 26 October 2005 Departamento de Economía Universidad Carlos III de Madrid Calle Madrid, 126 28903 Getafe (Spain) Fax (34) 91 624 98 75 INFORMATION TRANSMISSION IN COALITIONAL

More information

Informed Principal in Private-Value Environments

Informed Principal in Private-Value Environments Informed Principal in Private-Value Environments Tymofiy Mylovanov Thomas Tröger University of Bonn June 21, 2008 1/28 Motivation 2/28 Motivation In most applications of mechanism design, the proposer

More information

We set up the basic model of two-sided, one-to-one matching

We set up the basic model of two-sided, one-to-one matching Econ 805 Advanced Micro Theory I Dan Quint Fall 2009 Lecture 18 To recap Tuesday: We set up the basic model of two-sided, one-to-one matching Two finite populations, call them Men and Women, who want to

More information

Core. Ichiro Obara. December 3, 2008 UCLA. Obara (UCLA) Core December 3, / 22

Core. Ichiro Obara. December 3, 2008 UCLA. Obara (UCLA) Core December 3, / 22 Ichiro Obara UCLA December 3, 2008 Obara (UCLA) Core December 3, 2008 1 / 22 in Edgeworth Box Core in Edgeworth Box Obara (UCLA) Core December 3, 2008 2 / 22 in Edgeworth Box Motivation How should we interpret

More information

Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity

Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity Analyse & Kritik 29/2007 ( c Lucius & Lucius, Stuttgart) p. 163 187 Walter Bossert/Kotaro Suzumura Non-deteriorating Choice Without Full Transitivity Abstract: Although the theory of greatest-element rationalizability

More information

Introduction to General Equilibrium

Introduction to General Equilibrium Introduction to General Equilibrium Juan Manuel Puerta November 6, 2009 Introduction So far we discussed markets in isolation. We studied the quantities and welfare that results under different assumptions

More information

The Bargaining Set of an Exchange Economy with Discrete. Resources

The Bargaining Set of an Exchange Economy with Discrete. Resources The Bargaining Set of an Exchange Economy with Discrete Resources Murat Yılmaz and Özgür Yılmaz November 17, 2016 Abstract A central notion for allocation problems when there are private endowments is

More information

COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY: CORE AND SHAPLEY VALUE

COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY: CORE AND SHAPLEY VALUE 1 / 54 COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY: CORE AND SHAPLEY VALUE Heinrich H. Nax hnax@ethz.ch & Bary S. R. Pradelski bpradelski@ethz.ch February 26, 2018: Lecture 2 2 / 54 What you did last week... There appear

More information

Housing Markets with Indifferences: a Tale of Two Mechanisms

Housing Markets with Indifferences: a Tale of Two Mechanisms Housing Markets with Indifferences: a Tale of Two Mechanisms Haris Aziz, Bart de Keijzer Institut für Informatik, Technische Universität München, 80538 München, Germany CWI Amsterdam, 1098 XG Amsterdam,

More information

Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium

Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium Zeynel Harun Alioğulları Mehmet Barlo February, 2012 Abstract This study argues that Nash equilibria with less variations in players best responses are more appealing.

More information

First Prev Next Last Go Back Full Screen Close Quit. Game Theory. Giorgio Fagiolo

First Prev Next Last Go Back Full Screen Close Quit. Game Theory. Giorgio Fagiolo Game Theory Giorgio Fagiolo giorgio.fagiolo@univr.it https://mail.sssup.it/ fagiolo/welcome.html Academic Year 2005-2006 University of Verona Summary 1. Why Game Theory? 2. Cooperative vs. Noncooperative

More information

Advanced Microeconomics

Advanced Microeconomics Advanced Microeconomics Partial and General Equilibrium Giorgio Fagiolo giorgio.fagiolo@sssup.it http://www.lem.sssup.it/fagiolo/welcome.html LEM, Sant Anna School of Advanced Studies, Pisa (Italy) Part

More information

Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College

Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College 2015 Course Overview 1. Bargaining 2. Hidden information and self-selection Optimal contracting with hidden information

More information

A NOTE ON FUNAKI AND YAMATO S TRAGEDY OF THE COMMONS

A NOTE ON FUNAKI AND YAMATO S TRAGEDY OF THE COMMONS A NOTE ON FUNAKI AND YAMATO S TRAGEDY OF THE COMMONS LÁSZLÓ Á. KÓCZY Abstract. In the model of Funaki and Yamato (1999) the tragedy of the commons can be avoided with pessimistic players, while this does

More information

The Relation Between Implementability and the Core

The Relation Between Implementability and the Core The Relation Between Implementability and the Core Eiichi Miyagawa Department of Economics, Columbia University 420 West 118th Street, New York, NY 10027, U.S.A. em437@columbia.edu June 11, 2002 Abstract

More information

No-envy in Queueing Problems

No-envy in Queueing Problems No-envy in Queueing Problems Youngsub Chun School of Economics Seoul National University Seoul 151-742, Korea and Department of Economics University of Rochester Rochester, NY 14627, USA E-mail: ychun@plaza.snu.ac.kr

More information

SURPLUS SHARING WITH A TWO-STAGE MECHANISM. By Todd R. Kaplan and David Wettstein 1. Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel. 1.

SURPLUS SHARING WITH A TWO-STAGE MECHANISM. By Todd R. Kaplan and David Wettstein 1. Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel. 1. INTERNATIONAL ECONOMIC REVIEW Vol. 41, No. 2, May 2000 SURPLUS SHARING WITH A TWO-STAGE MECHANISM By Todd R. Kaplan and David Wettstein 1 Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel In this article we consider

More information

Title: The Castle on the Hill. Author: David K. Levine. Department of Economics UCLA. Los Angeles, CA phone/fax

Title: The Castle on the Hill. Author: David K. Levine. Department of Economics UCLA. Los Angeles, CA phone/fax Title: The Castle on the Hill Author: David K. Levine Department of Economics UCLA Los Angeles, CA 90095 phone/fax 310-825-3810 email dlevine@ucla.edu Proposed Running Head: Castle on the Hill Forthcoming:

More information

1. Introduction. 2. A Simple Model

1. Introduction. 2. A Simple Model . Introduction In the last years, evolutionary-game theory has provided robust solutions to the problem of selection among multiple Nash equilibria in symmetric coordination games (Samuelson, 997). More

More information

The core of voting games: a partition approach

The core of voting games: a partition approach The core of voting games: a partition approach Aymeric Lardon To cite this version: Aymeric Lardon. The core of voting games: a partition approach. International Game Theory Review, World Scientific Publishing,

More information

The Core can be accessed in a Bounded Number of Steps

The Core can be accessed in a Bounded Number of Steps The Core can be accessed in a Bounded Number of Steps by László Á. KÓCZY Econometrics Center for Economic Studies Discussions Paper Series (DPS) 02.18 http://www.econ.kuleuven.be/ces/discussionpapers/default.htm

More information

Representation of TU games by coalition production economies

Representation of TU games by coalition production economies Working Papers Institute of Mathematical Economics 430 April 2010 Representation of TU games by coalition production economies Tomoki Inoue IMW Bielefeld University Postfach 100131 33501 Bielefeld Germany

More information

Boundary Behavior of Excess Demand Functions without the Strong Monotonicity Assumption

Boundary Behavior of Excess Demand Functions without the Strong Monotonicity Assumption Boundary Behavior of Excess Demand Functions without the Strong Monotonicity Assumption Chiaki Hara April 5, 2004 Abstract We give a theorem on the existence of an equilibrium price vector for an excess

More information

This article appeared in a journal published by Elsevier. The attached copy is furnished to the author for internal non-commercial research and

This article appeared in a journal published by Elsevier. The attached copy is furnished to the author for internal non-commercial research and This article appeared in a journal published by Elsevier. The attached copy is furnished to the author for internal non-commercial research and education use, including for instruction at the authors institution

More information

Competitive Equilibrium

Competitive Equilibrium Competitive Equilibrium Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 16, October 26 Outline 1 Pareto Effi ciency 2 The Core 3 Planner s Problem(s) 4 Competitive (Walrasian) Equilibrium Decentralized vs. Centralized Economic

More information

Strategic Properties of Heterogeneous Serial Cost Sharing

Strategic Properties of Heterogeneous Serial Cost Sharing Strategic Properties of Heterogeneous Serial Cost Sharing Eric J. Friedman Department of Economics, Rutgers University New Brunswick, NJ 08903. January 27, 2000 Abstract We show that serial cost sharing

More information

Intro to Economic analysis

Intro to Economic analysis Intro to Economic analysis Alberto Bisin - NYU 1 Rational Choice The central gure of economics theory is the individual decision-maker (DM). The typical example of a DM is the consumer. We shall assume

More information

Exchange of indivisible goods and indifferences: the Top Trading Absorbing Sets mechanisms

Exchange of indivisible goods and indifferences: the Top Trading Absorbing Sets mechanisms Exchange of indivisible goods and indifferences: the Top Trading Absorbing Sets mechanisms Jorge Alcalde-Unzu, Elena Molis August 2009 Abstract There is a wide range of economic problems involving the

More information

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM Discussion Papers in Economics Discussion Paper No. 0/06 CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY by Indraneel Dasgupta July 00 DP 0/06 ISSN 1360-438 UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM

More information

Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory

Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory Chapter 9 Nathan Smooha Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory 9.1 Introduction In this chapter, we briefly discuss some topics in the framework of general equilibrium theory, namely

More information

ECONOMICS 001 Microeconomic Theory Summer Mid-semester Exam 2. There are two questions. Answer both. Marks are given in parentheses.

ECONOMICS 001 Microeconomic Theory Summer Mid-semester Exam 2. There are two questions. Answer both. Marks are given in parentheses. Microeconomic Theory Summer 206-7 Mid-semester Exam 2 There are two questions. Answer both. Marks are given in parentheses.. Consider the following 2 2 economy. The utility functions are: u (.) = x x 2

More information

Competition and Resource Sensitivity in Marriage and Roommate Markets

Competition and Resource Sensitivity in Marriage and Roommate Markets Competition and Resource Sensitivity in Marriage and Roommate Markets Bettina Klaus This Version: April 2010 Previous Versions: November 2007 and December 2008 Abstract We consider one-to-one matching

More information

Advanced Microeconomics

Advanced Microeconomics Advanced Microeconomics Leonardo Felli EC441: Room D.106, Z.332, D.109 Lecture 8 bis: 24 November 2004 Monopoly Consider now the pricing behavior of a profit maximizing monopolist: a firm that is the only

More information

Lecture 1. History of general equilibrium theory

Lecture 1. History of general equilibrium theory Lecture 1 History of general equilibrium theory Adam Smith: The Wealth of Nations, 1776 many heterogeneous individuals with diverging interests many voluntary but uncoordinated actions (trades) results

More information

The Consumer, the Firm, and an Economy

The Consumer, the Firm, and an Economy Andrew McLennan October 28, 2014 Economics 7250 Advanced Mathematical Techniques for Economics Second Semester 2014 Lecture 15 The Consumer, the Firm, and an Economy I. Introduction A. The material discussed

More information

A New and Robust Subgame Perfect Equilibrium in a model of Triadic Power Relations *

A New and Robust Subgame Perfect Equilibrium in a model of Triadic Power Relations * A New and Robust Subgame Perfect Equilibrium in a model of Triadic Power Relations * by Magnus Hatlebakk ** Department of Economics, University of Bergen Abstract: We present a new subgame perfect equilibrium

More information

Imitation Processes with Small Mutations

Imitation Processes with Small Mutations Imitation Processes with Small Mutations The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Fudenberg, Drew, and Lorens

More information

Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1)

Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1) Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1) Tsun-Feng Chiang* *School of Economics, Henan University, Kaifeng, China November 2, 2014 1 / 28 Primitive Notions 1.1 Primitive Notions Consumer

More information

The Core of a Strategic Game *

The Core of a Strategic Game * The Core of a trategic Game * Parkash Chander January, 2014 Abstract This paper introduces and studies the γ-core of a general strategic game. It shows that a prominent class of games admit nonempty γ-cores.

More information

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Ozan Candogan, Asuman Ozdaglar and Pablo A. Parrilo September 6, 2011 Abstract Potential games are a special class of games for which many adaptive user dynamics

More information

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7).

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). The axiomatic approach (OR 15) Nash s (1950) work is the starting point

More information

PREFERENCE REVELATION GAMES AND STRONG CORES OF ALLOCATION PROBLEMS WITH INDIVISIBILITIES

PREFERENCE REVELATION GAMES AND STRONG CORES OF ALLOCATION PROBLEMS WITH INDIVISIBILITIES Discussion Paper No. 651 PREFERENCE REVELATION GAMES AND STRONG CORES OF ALLOCATION PROBLEMS WITH INDIVISIBILITIES Koji Takamiya March 2006 The Institute of Social and Economic Research Osaka University

More information

Can everyone benefit from innovation?

Can everyone benefit from innovation? Can everyone benefit from innovation? Christopher P. Chambers and Takashi Hayashi June 16, 2017 Abstract We study a resource allocation problem with variable technologies, and ask if there is an allocation

More information

Exchange of indivisible goods and indifferences: the Top Trading Absorbing Sets mechanisms

Exchange of indivisible goods and indifferences: the Top Trading Absorbing Sets mechanisms Exchange of indivisible goods and indifferences: the Top Trading Absorbing Sets mechanisms Jorge Alcalde-Unzu, Elena Molis First draft: May 2009 This version: August 2009 Abstract There is a wide range

More information

General Equilibrium and Welfare

General Equilibrium and Welfare and Welfare Lectures 2 and 3, ECON 4240 Spring 2017 University of Oslo 24.01.2017 and 31.01.2017 1/37 Outline General equilibrium: look at many markets at the same time. Here all prices determined in the

More information

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES KYOTO INSTITUTE OF ECONOMIC RESEARCH Discussion Paper No.992 Intertemporal efficiency does not imply a common price forecast: a leading example Shurojit Chatterji, Atsushi

More information

Learning, Memory, and Inertia *

Learning, Memory, and Inertia * Learning, Memory, and Inertia * Carlos Alós Ferrer E mail: Carlos.Alos Ferrer@univie.ac.at Department of Economics, University of Vienna, Hohenstaufengasse 9, A 1010 Vienna, Austria This paper explores

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago December 2015 Abstract Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970) represent random

More information

Puri cation 1. Stephen Morris Princeton University. July Economics.

Puri cation 1. Stephen Morris Princeton University. July Economics. Puri cation 1 Stephen Morris Princeton University July 2006 1 This survey was prepared as an entry for the second edition of the New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics. In a mixed strategy equilibrium of

More information

Volume of Trade and Dynamic Network Formation in Two-Sided Economies 1

Volume of Trade and Dynamic Network Formation in Two-Sided Economies 1 Volume of Trade and Dynamic Network Formation in Two-Sided Economies 1 Roland Pongou 2 and Roberto Serrano 3 This version: June 2013 Abstract: We study the long-run stability of trade networks in a two-sided

More information

Appendix of Homophily in Peer Groups The Costly Information Case

Appendix of Homophily in Peer Groups The Costly Information Case Appendix of Homophily in Peer Groups The Costly Information Case Mariagiovanna Baccara Leeat Yariv August 19, 2012 1 Introduction In this Appendix we study the information sharing application analyzed

More information

Bilateral Trading in Divisible Double Auctions

Bilateral Trading in Divisible Double Auctions Bilateral Trading in Divisible Double Auctions Songzi Du Haoxiang Zhu March, 014 Preliminary and Incomplete. Comments Welcome Abstract We study bilateral trading between two bidders in a divisible double

More information

Matching with Contracts: The Critical Role of Irrelevance of Rejected Contracts

Matching with Contracts: The Critical Role of Irrelevance of Rejected Contracts Matching with Contracts: The Critical Role of Irrelevance of Rejected Contracts Orhan Aygün and Tayfun Sönmez May 2012 Abstract We show that an ambiguity in setting the primitives of the matching with

More information

Economics 501B Final Exam Fall 2017 Solutions

Economics 501B Final Exam Fall 2017 Solutions Economics 501B Final Exam Fall 2017 Solutions 1. For each of the following propositions, state whether the proposition is true or false. If true, provide a proof (or at least indicate how a proof could

More information

The B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics

The B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics The B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics Topics Volume 9, Issue 1 2009 Article 43 Simple Economies with Multiple Equilibria Theodore C. Bergstrom Ken-Ichi Shimomura Takehiko Yamato University of California,

More information

On the Informed Principal Model with Common Values

On the Informed Principal Model with Common Values On the Informed Principal Model with Common Values Anastasios Dosis ESSEC Business School and THEMA École Polytechnique/CREST, 3/10/2018 Anastasios Dosis (ESSEC and THEMA) Informed Principal with Common

More information

Housing Markets with Indifferences: a Tale of Two Mechanisms

Housing Markets with Indifferences: a Tale of Two Mechanisms Housing Markets with Indifferences: a Tale of Two Mechanisms Haris Aziz and Bart de Keijzer Abstract The (Shapley-Scarf) housing market is a well-studied and fundamental model of an exchange economy. Each

More information

Implementation in Adaptive Better-Response Dynamics: Towards a General Theory of Bounded Rationality in Mechanisms

Implementation in Adaptive Better-Response Dynamics: Towards a General Theory of Bounded Rationality in Mechanisms Implementation in Adaptive Better-Response Dynamics: Towards a General Theory of Bounded Rationality in Mechanisms Antonio Cabrales Roberto Serrano This version: October 2010 Abstract We study the classic

More information

1 Lattices and Tarski s Theorem

1 Lattices and Tarski s Theorem MS&E 336 Lecture 8: Supermodular games Ramesh Johari April 30, 2007 In this lecture, we develop the theory of supermodular games; key references are the papers of Topkis [7], Vives [8], and Milgrom and

More information

Core equivalence and welfare properties without divisible goods

Core equivalence and welfare properties without divisible goods Core equivalence and welfare properties without divisible goods Michael Florig Jorge Rivera Cayupi First version November 2001, this version May 2005 Abstract We study an economy where all goods entering

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago September 2015 Abstract Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970) introduce a

More information

Stochastic Stability for Roommate Markets

Stochastic Stability for Roommate Markets Stochastic Stability for Roommate Markets Bettina Klaus, Flip Klijn, and Markus Walzl May 2008 Abstract We show that for any roommate market the set of stochastically stable matchings coincides with the

More information

Epsilon Ex Post Implementation

Epsilon Ex Post Implementation Epsilon Ex Post Implementation Mehmet Barlo Nuh Aygun Dalkiran February 10, 2014 Abstract We provide necessary and sufficient conditions for epsilon ex post implementation. Our analysis extends Bergemann

More information

20 GUOQIANG TIAN may cooperate and in others they may not, and such information is unknown to the designer. (2) This combining solution concept, which

20 GUOQIANG TIAN may cooperate and in others they may not, and such information is unknown to the designer. (2) This combining solution concept, which ANNALS OF ECONOMICS AND FINANCE 1, 19 32 (2000) Feasible and Continuous Double Implementation of Constrained Walrasian Allocations * Guoqiang Tian Department of Economics, Texas A&M University, College

More information

General Equilibrium. General Equilibrium, Berardino. Cesi, MSc Tor Vergata

General Equilibrium. General Equilibrium, Berardino. Cesi, MSc Tor Vergata General Equilibrium Equilibrium in Consumption GE begins (1/3) 2-Individual/ 2-good Exchange economy (No production, no transaction costs, full information..) Endowment (Nature): e Private property/ NO

More information

Stability and Segregation in Group Formation

Stability and Segregation in Group Formation Stability and Segregation in Group Formation IGAL MILCHTAICH Department of Economics, Bar-Ilan University, Ramat-Gan 52900, Israel and Managerial Economics and Decision Sciences, J. L. Kellogg Graduate

More information

CORE AND NO-TREAT EQUILIBRIUM IN TOURNAMENT GAMES WITH EXTERNALITIES

CORE AND NO-TREAT EQUILIBRIUM IN TOURNAMENT GAMES WITH EXTERNALITIES CORE AND NO-TREAT EQUILIBRIUM IN TOURNAMENT GAMES WITH EXTERNALITIES RYO MIZUNO Abstract. We consider a situation where coalitions are formed to divide a resource. As in real life, the value of a payoff

More information