Author s address: Robert Wilson Stanford Business School, Stanford CA USA. Tel: , Fax: Internet:

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Author s address: Robert Wilson Stanford Business School, Stanford CA USA. Tel: , Fax: Internet:"

Transcription

1 Author s address: Robert Wilson Stanford Business School, Stanford CA USA. Tel: , Fax: Internet: RW@yen.stanford.edu

2 Admissibility and Stability Robert Wilson 1 1 Stanford University, Stanford CA 94305, USA Abstract: Admissibility is a useful criterion for selecting among equilibria, but I argue that enforcing admissibility dilutes the power of stability criteria to select among equilibrium components, and this accounts for anomalous examples of stable sets. Therefore, admissibility should be invoked only when selecting equilibria within a component that is immune to payoff perturbations. Keywords: Game theory, stability, admissibility, payoff perturbations The purpose of this essay is to examine the role of admissibility in formulating criteria for stability of equilibria. Recall that admissibility excludes an equilibrium that uses a dominated pure strategy. In particular, each pure strategy used (i.e., with positive probability) must be a best response to some completely mixed strategy. Reinhard Selten s (1975) criterion of perfection ensures admissibility by requiring that a pure strategy is used only if it is a best response to a sequence of completely mixed strategies. Admissibility was adopted subsequently by Kohlberg and Mertens (1986) and Mertens (1989) as a primary desideratum in their identification of stable sets of equilibria. My thesis here is that admissibility plays two roles, only the first of which advances the program of defining stability for games in extensive form. The first role is that in selecting among equilibria within a component, admissibility strengthens the criterion of stability. However, in its second role in selecting among equilibrium components, admissibility weakens the criterion of stability as examples will illustrate. I argue, therefore, that admissibility criteria should be deleted when selecting among equilibrium components; that is, the selected components should be essential, in the sense that they are stable with respect to all perturbations of normal-form payoffs. This lends credence to Kohlberg and Mertens original definitions of hyperstable and fully stable sets of equilibria, provided they are restricted to lie in essential components. It suggests modifying Mertens (1989) homological definition of stability to invoke payoff perturbations rather than strategy perturbations. 1

3 Section 1 summarizes technical aspects that are the basis in Section 2 for a comparison of stability criteria derived from perturbations of strategies and payoffs. All examples are collected in the Appendix. For a general survey of this topic see van Damme (1991). 1 Background To simplify, we consider only games in extensive form with two players, called I and II. Each player has a finite number of pure strategies; each has perfect recall; and all the data of the game are common knowledge. Thus the normal form of a game has two matrices with rows labeled by I s pure strategies and columns labeled by II s pure strategies. For each pair of their pure strategies, the corresponding entry in one matrix describes I s payoff, and in the other matrix II s payoff, each expressed in terms of that player s von Neumann-Morgenstern utility. We use u k to denote player k s payoff ij from I s pure strategy i and II s pure strategy j. Recall that each pure strategy assigns a feasible action to each information set of that player; that is, to each event in which that player takes an action. Each player s feasible strategies are his mixed strategies, i.e., the probability distributions over his pure strategies. If I uses the strategy x =(x i ) and II uses the strategy y =(y j ),where x 0 and Pi x i = 1 and similarly for y,thenk s expected payoff is PiPj x iu k y ij j. A Nash equilibrium is a pair (x; y) of strategies for the two players such that each player uses only pure strategies that are optimal responses to the other player s strategy; that is, x i X X > 0 only if u I y ij j =max u Ì y j j ; ` and similarly for player II. j Selten (1965, 1975) argued convincingly that only a subset of the Nash equilibria predicts behaviors by rational players. He proposed restricting equilibria to those that are perfect. One version of his 1975 (normal-form) definition says that an equilibrium (x; y) is perfect if it is the limit of a sequence of completely mixed strategies (i.e., every pure strategy is used), say (x h ;y h ) 0 converging to (x; y), suchthat x i X X > 0 only if u I =max ij yh u Ì j j yh ; j ` j and similarly for player II. Because each used pure strategy is an optimal response to a completely mixed strategy, it must be undominated. A perfect equilibrium therefore satisfies admissibility. 2 j j

4 One interpretation of Selten s construction is that each strategy used in a perfect equilibrium must remain optimal against some tremble by the other player; that is, small probabilities of using strategies that the equilibrium predicts will otherwise be unused. His other, equivalent definition emphasizes this aspect: an equilibrium (x; y) of a game G is perfect if there is a sequence (x h ;y h ; G h ) converging to (x; y; G), for which each (x h ;y h ) is an equilibrium of the perturbed game G h. In this version, G h is the strategy perturbation of G obtained by adjoining the constraints x h h and y h h,where ( h ; h ) 0 and lim h!1( h ; h ) = 0. This interpretation in terms of perturbations of the game had a profound effect on the subsequent development of theories of equilibrium refinements. The prominent feature of Selten s formulation is that it considers perturbations of mixed strategies. This approach was well-adapted to the specification of Kreps and Wilson s (1982) definition of sequential equilibrium, adapted from Selten s 1965 definition of subgame-perfect equilibrium, to address the games without proper subgames that motivate Selten s 1975 article. This criterion imposes the requirement of sequential rationality; that is, at each information set a player s continuation strategy is optimal with respect to a probability distribution (over possible histories) consistent with the game and Bayes Rule. A perfect equilibrium meets this requirement, using the limit of the conditional probabilities induced by the sequence of perturbed games. The perfect equilibria are therefore the sequential equilibria satisfying a strong form of admissibility. 1 Indeed, in generic extensive games the sets of perfect and sequential equilibria coincide (Blume and Zame, 1994). One version of this fact is that allowing all perturbations of payoffs (rather than strategies) produces exact coincidence between the resulting weakly perfect equilibria and the sequential equilibria. The different style of reasoning involved in using payoff perturbations to select equilibria is illustrated in the Appendix via the well-known Beer-Quiche game. In their study of hyperstability, Kohlberg and Mertens allowed all perturbations of normal-form payoffs. As they recognized, this enlarges the set of allowed perturbations. Each perturbation of strategies has the same net effect as a corresponding perturbation 1 Admissibility and normal-form perfection of equilibria are equivalent in two-person games. The analogous extensive-form definition of perfection allows use of dominated strategies. In Mertens (1995) example, the dominant-strategy equilibrium is not extensiveform perfect, and remarkably, every extensive-form perfect equilibrium uses a dominated strategy. Similar examples led van Damme (1984) to propose an alternative definition of quasi-perfection. 3

5 of payoffs. This can be seen by interpreting the trembles as chance moves whose small probabilities perturb the expected payoffs from each pure strategy specifying intended actions at information sets. Kohlberg and Mertens advanced Selten s agenda towards identifying essential or strictly perfect equilibria, those immune to all perturbations in a neighborhood of the game, not just a single sequence of strategy perturbations. Because such ideal equilibria need not exist, this step required reconsideration of the unit of analysis. 2 They demonstrated that each game s equilibria are partitioned into a finite number of closed connected components; and for generic extensive-form games, equilibria in the same component have the same outcomes, namely, they differ only off the equilibrium path and therefore their probability distributions over histories are the same. Combining these two results indicates that an equilibrium outcome immune to payoff perturbations is identified generically by a component that is essential; that is, every nearby game has an equilibrium near the component. 3 They also proved that every game has essential components. 4 Moreover, some are invariant in the sense that they are essential in every game with the same reduced normal form obtained by deleting redundant strategies (those strategies whose payoffs for all players are convex combinations of other strategies payoffs). Kohlberg and Mertens showed that an invariant essential component has several desirable properties. Invariance: Because an invariant component depends only on the reduced normal form, it does not depend on which among the many strategically equivalent extensive forms is used. Backward Induction: It contains perfect and even proper equilibria. 5 Such equilib- 2 Kohlberg and Mertens (1986, Appendix D) show that an equilibrium that is extensiveform perfect in every extensive game with the same reduced normal form is strictly perfect, provided all best responses are used. For many interesting games, however, this proviso is not satisfied. 3 Genericity is mostly immaterial here because a nongeneric case has a component that is the union of components induced by nearby games; a case where none of these subcomponents is essential would be doubly rare. 4 That such a component exists follows from their demonstration that the projection of the graph of the Nash equilibrium correspondence is homotopic to a homeomorphism. This is called the rubber sphere theorem, because it shows that when the space of games is mapped onto the surface of a sphere via a one-point compatification, the equilibrium graph is mapped to a deformation of a sphere of larger radius. Consequently, above every game lies a component for which every nearby game has an equilibrium nearby. 5 To be proper, the sequence justifying a perfect equilibrium must assign a probability of lower order to one pure strategy that is inferior to another (Myerson, 1978). 4

6 ria satisfy Selten s 1965 criterion (each strategy remains optimal in every subgame) and Kreps and Wilson s generalization to extended subgames in games with imperfect information. Proper equilibria are perfect, and therefore use only admissible strategies. Moreover, a proper equilibrium induces a sequential equilibrium in every extensive form with the same reduced normal form. Iterated Dominance: Its projection onto the equilibrium graph of a smaller game, obtained by deleting dominated strategies, contains an invariant essential component. Forward Induction: Its projection onto the equilibrium graph of a smaller game, obtained by deleting a strategy that is suboptimal at all its equilibria, contains an invariant essential component. 6 Further, within an invariant essential component is a minimal closed set (called hyperstable) with analogous properties; inside that is a minimal closed set (called fully stable) immune to perturbations of any finite set of pure or mixed strategies; and inside that is a minimal closed set (called stable) immune to perturbations of pure strategies. The latter (though omitting minimality) allows a homological definition proposed by Mertens (1989). In the next section we re-examine Kohlberg and Mertens and Mertens rejection of all these except stable sets, on the grounds that only stable sets equilibria exclude inadmissible strategies. We shall see that this has unfortunate consequences, because some stable sets reside in inessential components. This brief review omits a vast literature emanating from Selten s insights, but it includes some main themes. Extensive games require equilibrium refinements. Intuitive criteria such as admissibility, backward induction, and consistent conditional probabilities can be founded on consideration of strategy perturbations. Combining these with iterative elimination of dominated or suboptimal strategies meets further criteria, such as rationalizability (Pearce, 1984) and forward induction. To convey the scope of extensions not described above, we mention only the models of reputation effects in finitely-repeated and centipede games. These models are derived from Selten s (1978) study of the chain-store game. In repeated games (without 6 This property is motivated by games involving signaling. These games typically have multiple equilibria reflecting possible inferences from disequilibrium behaviors. The motive for forward induction insists that the conditional probabilities validating a sequential equilibrium should be zero for histories dependent on strategies that are suboptimal at every equilibrium in the component. Thus, one can prune those branches ofthegametreethatoccuronlywhensuchsuboptimalstrategiesareused. SeeBanks and Sobel (1987) and Cho and Kreps (1987). 5

7 or with stopping options), a perturbation of a strategy that repeats a particular behavior can attract imitation, leading to an equilibrium in which the perturbed strategy is the only one used, except in the last stages of the game. These models are relevant to the subsequent discussion because typically (as in the repeated chain-store and prisoners dilemma games) their striking feature is that it is a strategy that is inadmissible in the stage game that attracts imitation. 2 A Critique of Admissibility We now examine the role of admissibility in constructing equilibrium refinements such as those described above. First I suggest via examples that the known deficiencies of stable sets derive primarily from the imposition of admissibility criteria. The justification offered for admissibility is that it is a cornerstone of single-person decision theory, but this rationale applies only to selection among equilibria, not to selection among components (e.g., Kohlberg and Mertens, p. 1014; Mertens, 1989, p. 577(c)). Applying admissibility criteria to component selection is therefore misplaced. This still leaves ample latitude to select equilibria within an invariant essential component using criteria of admissibility or perfection. I conclude with cautionary remarks: in some contexts admissibility is unduly restrictive even in selecting among equilibria within an essential component. In the construction of stable sets, admissibility is ensured by allowing only strategy perturbations, rather than all payoff perturbations. This formulation might seem legitimate in view of the fact that differences between weak-perfect or sequential (justified by payoff perturbations) and perfect (justified by strategy perturbations) equilibria are nongeneric. In fact, however, the difference between the existential quantifier ( there exist perturbations yielding nearby equilibria ) used for these equilibrium selections, and the universal quantifier ( all perturbations yield nearby equilibria ) used for component selections can be substantial. In fact, generic games can have stable sets (immune to strategy perturbations) inside components that are not essential (immune to payoff perturbations). For this reason, I see no justification for restricting the allowable payoff perturbations when selecting among components. In the Appendix, three examples illustrate how the exclusion of some payoff perturbations allows implausible components to survive the criterion of stability. The first is van Damme s (1989) generic example in which there is a stable set that fails to induce an equilibrium in a subgame. Mertens (1989) revised definition produces a larger stable set that remedies this deficiency. Nevertheless, one sees easily that 6

8 these stable sets lie in an inessential component, as one can see from a simple payoff perturbation. The second example is the nongeneric game Trivial Pursuit in which there is a stable set whose outcome for one player is inferior to his stable outcome in a continuation that he has the option to elect. Again, a simple payoff perturbation suffices to eliminate this stable set lying in an inessential component. The third example is Cho and Kreps (1987) ingenious example of a stable set that motivates their conclusion that if there is an intuitive story to go with the full strength of stability, it is beyond our powers to offer it here (p. 220). But once again, a simple payoff perturbation suffices to show that this stable set resides in an inessential component. I conclude from such examples that in devising criteria for selecting among components, it is better to use all payoff perturbations. Of necessity, this approach may select essential components with equilibria using inadmissible strategies. The second step, therefore, is to use criteria such as admissibility to select, say, stable sets (or proper or perfect equilibria) within the selected component. 7 This two-step procedure was implicit in Kohlberg and Mertens original work, but unfortunately they abandoned it when they attempted to construct a definition that obtains all desirable properties in a single step. Besides the above examples, the deficiency of the single-step approach is evidenced by Mertens (1995) second example (which he calls pretty damning as to the behavior of stable sets in at least some non-generic games ) of a game with perfect information in which the unique stable set includes all admissible equilibria (which includes a twodimensional set), of which only one is subgame-perfect. Moreover, this subgame-perfect equilibrium yields the only stable outcome derived from all games in the neighborhood of payoff perturbations except those in a slice satisfying a single equality condition. Such examples indicate that a second step of selection within an essential component is inescapable. It is important to realize, however, that a two-step procedure has its own deficiencies. To illustrate, the Appendix presents a generic extensive-form game with an invariant essential component containing two stable sets (in the strong sense of Mertens 7 An example of the effectiveness of this two-step procedure even when admissibility is not an issue is van Damme s (1987, p. 119) generic extensive game with a two proper equilibria, one of which he argues is not sensible. A simple payoff perturbation suffices to show that this equilibrium s component is inessential. 7

9 definition) and two proper equilibria, reflecting the fact that its projection map (from its neighborhood in the equilibrium graph to the space of games) has degree 2. Neither of these stable sets is immune to payoff perturbations, even though they reside in a component that is immune. We turn now to the selection of equilibria within an (invariant) essential component and ask: Are the strategy perturbations the best set to invoke in selecting among equilibria? Clearly, Selten s pure-strategy perturbations are a minimal set sufficient to ensure admissibility and consistency. 8 On these grounds one can say that Selten s construction is exactly right. On the other hand, I think it is prudent to realize that admissibility is justified only if one is quite sure about the validity of some particular extensive form of the game. As Fudenberg, Kreps, and Levine (1988) prove, every pure-strategy equilibrium is the limit of strict equilibria of nearby elaborations ; that is, games in which players may have differing information about which perturbation applies. Fudenberg and Maskin (1986), Myerson (1986), van Damme (1987) illustrate particular examples. Further, Bagwell (1995) provides an example in which perturbations of the observability of actions induce payoff perturbations that justify an inadmissible equilibrium in the unique essential component containing the subgame-perfect equilibrium. Bagwell s Stackelberg game is described in the Appendix. In all these cases, the inadmissible equilibria are justified by payoff perturbations, but not by strategy perturbations. 3 Conclusion In sum, I see no harm and substantial advantages to selecting invariant essential components based on consideration of all payoff perturbations. Doing so eliminates anomalous stable sets in the known examples. As a second step, one can select a stable set or a proper or perfect equilibrium within the essential component, provided there is assurance that admissibility is an appropriate criterion. This second step is problematic, however, whenever potentially relevant perturbations of the extensive form generate payoff perturbations not induced by strategy perturbations. 8 These comments apply to normal-form perturbations; for extensive-form versions, one can also use the perturbations used by van Damme (1984) to define quasi-perfection. A somewhat larger set that includes mixed-strategy perturbations is apparently a nearly maximal set ensuring admissibility. One subset of mixed-strategy perturbations ensuring admissibility is used by Kohlberg and Mertens (1986, p. 1025) to construct proper equilibria; however, they show by example (p. 1026, Fig. 9) that the full set fails to ensure admissibility. 8

10 Acknowledgement: Research support was provided by NSF grant SES Srihari Govindan, John Hillas, and Eric van Damme kindly pointed out errors in a previous draft. 9

11 References Bagwell, Kyle (1995), Commitment and Observability in Games, Games and Economic Behavior, 8: Banks, Jeffrey, and Joel Sobel (1987), Equilibrium Selection in Signaling Games, Econometrica, 55: Blume, Lawrence, and William Zame (1994), The Algebraic Geometry of Perfect and Sequential Equilibrium, Econometrica, 62: Cho, In-Koo, and David Kreps (1987), Signaling Games and Stable Equilibria, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 102: Fudenberg, Drew, David Kreps, and David Levine (1988), On the Robustness of Equilibrium Refinements, Journal of Economic Theory, 44: Fudenberg, Drew, and Eric Maskin (1986), The Folk Theorem in Repeated Games with Discounting and with Incomplete Information, Econometrica, 54: Kohlberg, Elon, and Jean-François Mertens (1986), On the Strategic Stability of Equilibria, Econometrica, 54: Kreps, David (1990), A Course in Economic Theory. Princeton:PrincetonUniversityPress. Kreps, David, and Robert Wilson (1982), Sequential Equilibria, Econometrica, 50: Mertens, Jean-François (1989), Stable Equilibria A Reformulation, Mathematics of Operations Research, 14: Mertens, Jean-François (1995), Two Examples of Strategic Equilibrium, Games and Economic Behavior, 8: Myerson, Roger (1978), Refinement of the Nash Equilibrium Concept, International JournalofGameTheory,7: Myerson, Roger (1986), Multistage Games with Communication, Econometrica, 54: Pearce, David (1984), Rationalizable Strategic Behavior and the Problem of Perfection, Econometrica, 52: Selten, Reinhard (1965), Spieltheoretische Behandlung eines Oligopolmodells mit Nachfragetragheit, Zeitschrift fur die gesamte Staatswissenschaft, 121: Selten, Reinhard (1975), Re-examination of the Perfectness Concept for Equilibrium Points in Extensive Games, International Journal of Game Theory, 4: Selten, Reinhard (1978), The Chain-Store Paradox, Theory and Decision, 9:

12 van Damme, Eric (1984), A Relation between Perfect Equilibria in Extensive-Form Games and Proper Equilibria in Normal-Form Games, International Journal of Game Theory, 13: van Damme, Eric (1987), Stability and Perfection of Nash Equilibria. Berlin: Springer-Verlag. van Damme, Eric (1989), Stable Equilibria and Forward Induction, Journal of Economic Theory, 48: van Damme, Eric (1991), Refinements of Nash Equilibrium, in J.J. Laffont (1992), Advances in Economic Theory: Sixth World Congress. New York: Cambridge University Press. 11

13 Appendix Examples Example 1: The Beer-Quiche Game The distinction between strategy and payoff perturbations is immaterial in generic cases. To illustrate, Figure 1 shows a version of Kreps Beer-Quiche game (1990, p. 465; Kohlberg and Mertens, 1986, p. 1031). In this game, player I chooses Left or Right and then player II chooses Across or Up; however, only I knows whether chance has chosen the payoffs along the Top or Bottom (with probabilities p and 1 0 p,where 0 < p < 1=2). The stable component contains the pure strategy equilibrium in which I surely chooses Left, and II chooses Up after Left and Across after Right. The unstable component is reversed: I surely chooses Right, and II chooses Across after Left and Up after Right. The latter violates forward induction because I s unused strategy that chooses Left after Top and Right after Bottom is suboptimal in that component; if it is deleted then II s action after Left becomes suboptimal, and if that is revised then I surely prefers Left. In terms of strategy perturbations this conclusion is evident because II s strategy cannot be optimal whenever the conditional probability of a deviation to Left is less after Top than Bottom. In terms of payoff perturbations the reasoning is altered: a perturbation that makes II s unused optimal strategy (i.e., Up invariably) superior requires II to use this strategy exclusively, in which case I prefers Left after Bottom. 9 Example 2: van Damme s Game Figure 2 depicts the generic extensive-form game studied by van Damme (1989) in which player I initially chooses either Up or to play a simultaneous-move subgame with player II. This game has a stable set with the payoff (2,2) obtained when player I chooses Up. This outcome cannot arise from an essential component: a negative perturbation of II s payoff from (Up, Middle) yields a game in which no equilibrium uses Up. The effect of suchaperturbationonii sbest-responseregionswithinthesimplexofi sstrategiesis shown in Figure 3. 9 Other than the implicit corollary seemingly implied by the elaborate proof in Kreps and Wilson (1982, strengthened by the results of Blume and Zame, 1994) of the generic coincidence of perfect and sequential equilibria, I know no direct demonstration of the generic equivalence of these two styles of reasoning. 12

14 From his study of this game, van Damme argued that the outcome Up violates a plausible interpretation of forward induction; moreover, no equilibrium in a minimal stable set induces an equilibrium in the subgame after I chooses Right. Mertens (1989) definition provides a larger stable set that does include subgame equilibria. Even so, it is stable with respect to strategy perturbations but not payoff perturbations. Example 3: Trivial Pursuit Figure 4 depicts the game Trivial Pursuit. In the continuation after player II initially chooses Right, were this known to I, I s strictly dominant strategy is Up, ensuring a payoff of 1, and the unique stable payoffs are (1,2). Now consider the full game with the parameter satisfying 0 <d<1. This adds an initial move (Up) by II from which he gets a certain payoff of 1 and I gets less both of which are inferior to their payoffs from the stable outcome after Right were it anticipated by I. However, there is a stable set in which all equilibria require both players to randomize their initial choices including a positive probability of Up initially by II. This stable set is not in the essential component, however, because every negative perturbation of either of II s payoffs from Up yields a game in which II surely chooses Right initially, as shown in Figure 5. This game is nongeneric only to the extent that II s payoffs from Up initially are replicated by a mixture of his payoffs from Right, so Up is a redundant strategy for II. Nevertheless, the normal form of this game cannot be reduced by deleting Up, because I s payoffs are affected. Example 4: Cho and Kreps Signaling Game Figure 6 depicts graphically the relevant data for a signaling game like Example 1 except that there are three types of player I and player II has three actions. They consider an equilibrium outcome in which all types of I choose Right (R). In the figure, the left simplex comprises II s possible beliefs about I s type after observing I s alternative action Left (L), and shows its partition into II s best response regions. The right simplex shows the partition of II s simplex of behavioral strategies after Left into I s best response regions; e.g., at the top the notation (L,R,R) indicates that types 1, 2, and 3 prefer Left, Right, and Right respectively if II is sufficiently likely to choose his Action 1 after Left. Cho and Kreps (1987) show that this configuration enables the outcome from the specified equilibrium [in which I uses the strategy (R,R,R)] to be stable. One sees easily, however, that this equilibrium is in an inessential component. A positive payoff perturbation of any one of II s optimal strategies ensures that it must be used exclusively, in which 13

15 case the corresponding type prefers Left. For instance, a positive payoff perturbation of Action 1 requires that II uses only Action 1 in response to Left, but then I s Type 1 prefers Left. Example 5: The Game Figure 7 depicts the generic extensive-form game, and Figure 8 shows the players best responses. The component in which I uses only strategy a is invariant and essential; in fact the projection from its neighborhood has degree 2. The degree is reflected in the presence of the two proper equilibria where II uses e or f, each of which is contained in a Mertens-stable set: the interval [e,de] or the interval [f,df]. Neither of these stable sets is immune to payoff perturbations. For instance, those perturbed games with two equilibria near f and def have no equilibria near [e,de]. Example 6: Bagwell s Stackelberg Game This example illustrates that even in the games of perfect information that motivate Selten s 1965 criterion of subgame perfection, the sole essential component can contain inadmissible equilibria justified as the limits of equilibria of nearby games with imperfect observability. Figure 9 displays the extensive form of Bagwell s (1995) Stackelberg game. First I chooses Up or Down, then chance reveals up or down to II (with a probability p of an erroneous report), and then II chooses Up or Down. If the error probability is zero then this is a game with perfect information: the unique subgame-perfect equilibrium has I choosing Up and II choosing Up after up and Down after down. This subgame equilibrium lies in the unique essential component that requires II to choose Down after down with conditional probability at least one-half. (The inessential component has I choosing Down and then II choosing Down, provided II s conditional probability of Down after up is at least one-half.) However, any perturbation that allows a positive probability of erroneous reports has only one equilibrium close to the essential component, and the equilibrium it is close to is not the perfect equilibrium, but rather the inadmissible equilibrium where II mixes equally between Up and Down after down. This is a robust feature of games with imperfectly observed actions. The important feature of the observability perturbation above is that it induces a payoff perturbation that cannot be mimicked by a strategy perturbation. Indeed, a perturbationofi sstrategiesiscapableofexcludingonlythedominatedstrategiesof II that choose Up invariably or Down invariably. In contrast, the payoff perturbation induced by a positive error probability is one that makes these strategies undominated. 14

16 Unlike strategy perturbations, which envision nonrational trembles, payoff perturbations account for slight chances of inaccurate observations. This is similar to the effect of reputational considerations in repeated games, where again the relevant perturbation is one that converts a dominated strategy into an undominated strategy. 15

17 2,0 3,0 0,1 I 1,1 p II II 1,0 3,1 2,1 I 1-p 0,0 Figure 1: The Beer-Quiche game. 16

18 2,2 Up I II Left Middle Right Top 0,0 3,2 0,3 I Bottom 3,3 0,2 3,0 Figure 2: Van Damme s example of a generic game with a stable set in an inessential component. 17

19 I s Strategies II s Best Responses Up II s Strategies I s Best Responses Middle Top Up Left Middle Right Bottom Bottom Top Left Right Dashed boundaries show effects of perturbing II s payoff, leaving only the equilibrium (Bottom, Left). Figure 3: Van Damme s example depicted graphically, showing the effect of perturbing player II s payoff. 18

20 0,1 1,2 d,1 1,0 I II 0,0 Up II Right 0,2 Figure 4: The game Trivial Pursuit with a stable set in an inessential component. 19

21 I s Strategies II s Best Responses II s Strategies I s Best Responses Up Right-Up Up Right-Right Right Up Right Up A negative perturbation of II s payoff from Up leaves only the equilibrium (Up, Right-Up). Right-Up Right-Right Figure 5: The best-responses for Trivial Pursuit, showing a perturbation of II s payoff from Up that eliminates the inessential component. 20

22 II s beliefs after I chooses L II s best action after I chooses L II s behavioral strategy after L I s best responses Type 1 Action 1 (L,R,R) Action 1 (R,R,R) 3 2 (R,L,R) (R,L,L) (R,R,L) Type 2 Type 3 Action 2 Action 3 Figure 6: The data for Cho and Kreps example of a stable set in an inessential component. 21

23 a 3,6 4,3 d e I II b 1,1 f 2,4 Player I II c 2,4 1,1 Figure 7: The generic extensive-form game. 22

24 a d c b (de) (def) (df) f d e a b c e f Figure 8: The players best-response correspondences for the game. 23

25 5,2 5,2 Up Up 3,1 Down 1-p p up down Down 3,1 Up II I II 6,3 6,3 Down 4,4 p up 1-p down 4,4 Figure 9: Bagwell s Stackelberg game with imperfect observation by II of I s action. 24

CHARACTERIZATIONS OF STABILITY

CHARACTERIZATIONS OF STABILITY CHARACTERIZATIONS OF STABILITY Srihari Govindan and Robert Wilson University of Iowa and Stanford University 1 Motive for Equilibrium Selection The original Nash definition allows 1. Multiple equilibria

More information

SUFFICIENT CONDITIONS FOR STABLE EQUILIBRIA. 1. Introduction

SUFFICIENT CONDITIONS FOR STABLE EQUILIBRIA. 1. Introduction SUFFICIENT CONDITIONS FOR STABLE EQUILIBRIA SRIHARI GOVINDAN AND ROBERT WILSON Abstract. A refinement of the set of Nash equilibria that satisfies two assumptions is shown to select a subset that is stable

More information

Uniqueness of the index for Nash equilibria of two-player games 3

Uniqueness of the index for Nash equilibria of two-player games 3 Uniqueness of the index for Nash equilibria of two-player games 3 Srihari Govindan 1 and Robert Wilson 2 1 Economics Department, University of Western Ontario, London, Ontario N6A 5C2, Canada 2 Business

More information

ON FORWARD INDUCTION

ON FORWARD INDUCTION Econometrica, Submission #6956, revised ON FORWARD INDUCTION SRIHARI GOVINDAN AND ROBERT WILSON Abstract. A player s pure strategy is called relevant for an outcome of a game in extensive form with perfect

More information

RESEARCH PAPER NO AXIOMATIC THEORY OF EQUILIBRIUM SELECTION IN SIGNALING GAMES WITH GENERIC PAYOFFS. Srihari Govindan.

RESEARCH PAPER NO AXIOMATIC THEORY OF EQUILIBRIUM SELECTION IN SIGNALING GAMES WITH GENERIC PAYOFFS. Srihari Govindan. RESEARCH PAPER NO. 2000 AXIOMATIC THEORY OF EQUILIBRIUM SELECTION IN SIGNALING GAMES WITH GENERIC PAYOFFS Srihari Govindan Robert Wilson September 2008 This work was partially funded by a National Science

More information

Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium

Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium Zeynel Harun Alioğulları Mehmet Barlo February, 2012 Abstract This study argues that Nash equilibria with less variations in players best responses are more appealing.

More information

Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions

Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions by Roger B. Myerson and Philip J. Reny* Draft notes October 2011 http://home.uchicago.edu/~preny/papers/bigseqm.pdf Abstract:

More information

BACKWARD INDUCTION IN GAMES WITHOUT PERFECT RECALL

BACKWARD INDUCTION IN GAMES WITHOUT PERFECT RECALL BACKWARD INDUCTION IN GAMES WITHOUT PERFECT RECALL JOHN HILLAS AND DMITRIY KVASOV Abstract. The equilibrium concepts that we now think of as various forms of backwards induction, namely subgame perfect

More information

Economics 201A Economic Theory (Fall 2009) Extensive Games with Perfect and Imperfect Information

Economics 201A Economic Theory (Fall 2009) Extensive Games with Perfect and Imperfect Information Economics 201A Economic Theory (Fall 2009) Extensive Games with Perfect and Imperfect Information Topics: perfect information (OR 6.1), subgame perfection (OR 6.2), forward induction (OR 6.6), imperfect

More information

Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium For an important class of extensive games, a solution concept is available that is simpler than sequential equilibrium, but with similar properties. In a Bayesian extensive

More information

BELIEFS & EVOLUTIONARY GAME THEORY

BELIEFS & EVOLUTIONARY GAME THEORY 1 / 32 BELIEFS & EVOLUTIONARY GAME THEORY Heinrich H. Nax hnax@ethz.ch & Bary S. R. Pradelski bpradelski@ethz.ch May 15, 217: Lecture 1 2 / 32 Plan Normal form games Equilibrium invariance Equilibrium

More information

Perfect Conditional -Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Signals and Actions (Preliminary and Incomplete)

Perfect Conditional -Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Signals and Actions (Preliminary and Incomplete) Perfect Conditional -Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Signals and Actions (Preliminary and Incomplete) Roger B. Myerson and Philip J. Reny Department of Economics University of Chicago

More information

1 The General Definition

1 The General Definition MS&E 336 Lecture 1: Dynamic games Ramesh Johari April 4, 2007 1 The General Definition A dynamic game (or extensive game, or game in extensive form) consists of: A set of players N; A set H of sequences

More information

Equilibrium Refinements

Equilibrium Refinements Equilibrium Refinements Mihai Manea MIT Sequential Equilibrium In many games information is imperfect and the only subgame is the original game... subgame perfect equilibrium = Nash equilibrium Play starting

More information

Axiomatic Equilibrium Selection for Generic Two-Player Games

Axiomatic Equilibrium Selection for Generic Two-Player Games Stanford University From the SelectedWorks of Robert B Wilson May, 2009 Axiomatic Equilibrium Selection for Generic Two-Player Games Srihari Govindan Robert B Wilson Available at: https://works.bepress.com/wilson_robert/16/

More information

ENDOGENOUS REPUTATION IN REPEATED GAMES

ENDOGENOUS REPUTATION IN REPEATED GAMES ENDOGENOUS REPUTATION IN REPEATED GAMES PRISCILLA T. Y. MAN Abstract. Reputation is often modelled by a small but positive prior probability that a player is a behavioral type in repeated games. This paper

More information

The Local Best Response Criterion: An Epistemic Approach to Equilibrium Refinement. Herbert Gintis

The Local Best Response Criterion: An Epistemic Approach to Equilibrium Refinement. Herbert Gintis The Local est Response Criterion: An Epistemic Approach to Equilibrium Refinement Herbert Gintis February 6, 2009 Abstract The standard refinement criteria for extensive form games, including subgame perfect,

More information

Higher Order Beliefs in Dynamic Environments

Higher Order Beliefs in Dynamic Environments University of Pennsylvania Department of Economics June 22, 2008 Introduction: Higher Order Beliefs Global Games (Carlsson and Van Damme, 1993): A B A 0, 0 0, θ 2 B θ 2, 0 θ, θ Dominance Regions: A if

More information

First Prev Next Last Go Back Full Screen Close Quit. Game Theory. Giorgio Fagiolo

First Prev Next Last Go Back Full Screen Close Quit. Game Theory. Giorgio Fagiolo Game Theory Giorgio Fagiolo giorgio.fagiolo@univr.it https://mail.sssup.it/ fagiolo/welcome.html Academic Year 2005-2006 University of Verona Summary 1. Why Game Theory? 2. Cooperative vs. Noncooperative

More information

Economics 209A Theory and Application of Non-Cooperative Games (Fall 2013) Extensive games with perfect information OR6and7,FT3,4and11

Economics 209A Theory and Application of Non-Cooperative Games (Fall 2013) Extensive games with perfect information OR6and7,FT3,4and11 Economics 209A Theory and Application of Non-Cooperative Games (Fall 2013) Extensive games with perfect information OR6and7,FT3,4and11 Perfect information A finite extensive game with perfect information

More information

Conditional equilibria of multi-stage games with infinite sets of signals and actions

Conditional equilibria of multi-stage games with infinite sets of signals and actions Conditional equilibria of multi-stage games with infinite sets of signals and actions by Roger B. Myerson and Philip J. Reny Department of Economics, University of Chicago Abstract: We develop concepts

More information

WEAKLY DOMINATED STRATEGIES: A MYSTERY CRACKED

WEAKLY DOMINATED STRATEGIES: A MYSTERY CRACKED WEAKLY DOMINATED STRATEGIES: A MYSTERY CRACKED DOV SAMET Abstract. An informal argument shows that common knowledge of rationality implies the iterative elimination of strongly dominated strategies. Rationality

More information

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract Pure strategy dominance with quasiconcave utility functions Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam Abstract By a result of Pearce (1984), in a finite strategic form game, the set of a player's serially

More information

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E.

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E. Tilburg University On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E. Publication date: 1997 Link to publication General rights Copyright and

More information

Algorithms for cautious reasoning in games

Algorithms for cautious reasoning in games Algorithms for cautious reasoning in games Geir B. Asheim a Andrés Perea b October 16, 2017 Abstract We provide comparable algorithms for the Dekel-Fudenberg procedure, iterated admissibility, proper rationalizability

More information

Bargaining Efficiency and the Repeated Prisoners Dilemma. Bhaskar Chakravorti* and John Conley**

Bargaining Efficiency and the Repeated Prisoners Dilemma. Bhaskar Chakravorti* and John Conley** Bargaining Efficiency and the Repeated Prisoners Dilemma Bhaskar Chakravorti* and John Conley** Published as: Bhaskar Chakravorti and John P. Conley (2004) Bargaining Efficiency and the repeated Prisoners

More information

NTU IO (I) : Classnote 03 Meng-Yu Liang March, 2009

NTU IO (I) : Classnote 03 Meng-Yu Liang March, 2009 NTU IO (I) : Classnote 03 Meng-Yu Liang March, 2009 Kohlberg and Mertens (Econometrica 1986) We will use the term (game) tree for the extensive form of a game with perfect recall (i.e., where every player

More information

Solving Extensive Form Games

Solving Extensive Form Games Chapter 8 Solving Extensive Form Games 8.1 The Extensive Form of a Game The extensive form of a game contains the following information: (1) the set of players (2) the order of moves (that is, who moves

More information

The Index of Nash Equilibria

The Index of Nash Equilibria Equilibria in Games, Santiago, Chile January 10, 2017 Finite Normal-Form Games We consider in these lectures, the set of finite games with fixed strategy sets and parametrized by the payoff functions.

More information

Industrial Organization Lecture 3: Game Theory

Industrial Organization Lecture 3: Game Theory Industrial Organization Lecture 3: Game Theory Nicolas Schutz Nicolas Schutz Game Theory 1 / 43 Introduction Why game theory? In the introductory lecture, we defined Industrial Organization as the economics

More information

Bayesian Games and Mechanism Design Definition of Bayes Equilibrium

Bayesian Games and Mechanism Design Definition of Bayes Equilibrium Bayesian Games and Mechanism Design Definition of Bayes Equilibrium Harsanyi [1967] What happens when players do not know one another s payoffs? Games of incomplete information versus games of imperfect

More information

Learning Equilibrium as a Generalization of Learning to Optimize

Learning Equilibrium as a Generalization of Learning to Optimize Learning Equilibrium as a Generalization of Learning to Optimize Dov Monderer and Moshe Tennenholtz Faculty of Industrial Engineering and Management Technion Israel Institute of Technology Haifa 32000,

More information

Open Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions

Open Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions Open Sequential Equilibria of Multi-Stage Games with Infinite Sets of Types and Actions By Roger B. Myerson and Philip J. Reny Department of Economics University of Chicago Paper can be found at https://sites.google.com/site/philipjreny/home/research

More information

Strongly Consistent Self-Confirming Equilibrium

Strongly Consistent Self-Confirming Equilibrium Strongly Consistent Self-Confirming Equilibrium YUICHIRO KAMADA 1 Department of Economics, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA 02138 Abstract Fudenberg and Levine (1993a) introduce the notion of self-confirming

More information

EVOLUTIONARY STABILITY FOR TWO-STAGE HAWK-DOVE GAMES

EVOLUTIONARY STABILITY FOR TWO-STAGE HAWK-DOVE GAMES ROCKY MOUNTAIN JOURNAL OF MATHEMATICS olume 25, Number 1, Winter 1995 EOLUTIONARY STABILITY FOR TWO-STAGE HAWK-DOE GAMES R. CRESSMAN ABSTRACT. Although two individuals in a biological species often interact

More information

Conservative Belief and Rationality

Conservative Belief and Rationality Conservative Belief and Rationality Joseph Y. Halpern and Rafael Pass Department of Computer Science Cornell University Ithaca, NY, 14853, U.S.A. e-mail: halpern@cs.cornell.edu, rafael@cs.cornell.edu January

More information

Basic Game Theory. Kate Larson. January 7, University of Waterloo. Kate Larson. What is Game Theory? Normal Form Games. Computing Equilibria

Basic Game Theory. Kate Larson. January 7, University of Waterloo. Kate Larson. What is Game Theory? Normal Form Games. Computing Equilibria Basic Game Theory University of Waterloo January 7, 2013 Outline 1 2 3 What is game theory? The study of games! Bluffing in poker What move to make in chess How to play Rock-Scissors-Paper Also study of

More information

Puri cation 1. Stephen Morris Princeton University. July Economics.

Puri cation 1. Stephen Morris Princeton University. July Economics. Puri cation 1 Stephen Morris Princeton University July 2006 1 This survey was prepared as an entry for the second edition of the New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics. In a mixed strategy equilibrium of

More information

The computational complexity of trembling hand perfection and other equilibrium refinements

The computational complexity of trembling hand perfection and other equilibrium refinements The computational complexity of trembling hand perfection and other equilibrium refinements Kristoffer Arnsfelt Hansen 1, Peter Bro Miltersen 1, and Troels Bjerre Sørensen 2 1 {arnsfelt,bromille}@cs.au.dk

More information

Approval Voting: Three Examples

Approval Voting: Three Examples Approval Voting: Three Examples Francesco De Sinopoli, Bhaskar Dutta and Jean-François Laslier August, 2005 Abstract In this paper we discuss three examples of approval voting games. The first one illustrates

More information

Rationalizable Partition-Confirmed Equilibrium

Rationalizable Partition-Confirmed Equilibrium Rationalizable Partition-Confirmed Equilibrium Drew Fudenberg and Yuichiro Kamada First Version: January 29, 2011; This Version: July 30, 2014 Abstract Rationalizable partition-confirmed equilibrium (RPCE)

More information

Equivalences of Extensive Forms with Perfect Recall

Equivalences of Extensive Forms with Perfect Recall Equivalences of Extensive Forms with Perfect Recall Carlos Alós-Ferrer and Klaus Ritzberger University of Cologne and Royal Holloway, University of London, 1 and VGSF 1 as of Aug. 1, 2016 1 Introduction

More information

An axiomatization of minimal curb sets. 1. Introduction. Mark Voorneveld,,1, Willemien Kets, and Henk Norde

An axiomatization of minimal curb sets. 1. Introduction. Mark Voorneveld,,1, Willemien Kets, and Henk Norde An axiomatization of minimal curb sets Mark Voorneveld,,1, Willemien Kets, and Henk Norde Department of Econometrics and Operations Research, Tilburg University, The Netherlands Department of Economics,

More information

WHEN ORDER MATTERS FOR ITERATED STRICT DOMINANCE *

WHEN ORDER MATTERS FOR ITERATED STRICT DOMINANCE * WHEN ORDER MATTERS FOR ITERATED STRICT DOMINANCE * Martin Dufwenberg ** & Mark Stegeman *** February 1999 Abstract: We demonstrate that iterated elimination of strictly dominated strategies is an order

More information

Reputations. Larry Samuelson. Yale University. February 13, 2013

Reputations. Larry Samuelson. Yale University. February 13, 2013 Reputations Larry Samuelson Yale University February 13, 2013 I. Introduction I.1 An Example: The Chain Store Game Consider the chain-store game: Out In Acquiesce 5, 0 2, 2 F ight 5,0 1, 1 If played once,

More information

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Emir Kamenica and Matthew Gentzkow University of Chicago June 2010 1 Persuasion mechanisms In this paper we study a particular game where Sender chooses a signal π whose

More information

The refined best-response correspondence in normal form games. Dieter Balkenborg, Josef Hofbauer & Christoph Kuzmics

The refined best-response correspondence in normal form games. Dieter Balkenborg, Josef Hofbauer & Christoph Kuzmics The refined best-response correspondence in normal form games Dieter Balkenborg, Josef Hofbauer & Christoph Kuzmics International Journal of Game Theory ISSN 0020-7276 Volume 44 Number 1 Int J Game Theory

More information

On Reputation with Imperfect Monitoring

On Reputation with Imperfect Monitoring On Reputation with Imperfect Monitoring M. W. Cripps, G. Mailath, L. Samuelson UCL, Northwestern, Pennsylvania, Yale Theory Workshop Reputation Effects or Equilibrium Robustness Reputation Effects: Kreps,

More information

The Intuitive and Divinity Criterion:

The Intuitive and Divinity Criterion: The Intuitive and Divinity Criterion: Interpretation and Step-by-Step Examples Ana Espínola-Arredondo School of Economic Sciences Washington State University Pullman, WA 99164 Félix Muñoz-García y School

More information

Title: The Castle on the Hill. Author: David K. Levine. Department of Economics UCLA. Los Angeles, CA phone/fax

Title: The Castle on the Hill. Author: David K. Levine. Department of Economics UCLA. Los Angeles, CA phone/fax Title: The Castle on the Hill Author: David K. Levine Department of Economics UCLA Los Angeles, CA 90095 phone/fax 310-825-3810 email dlevine@ucla.edu Proposed Running Head: Castle on the Hill Forthcoming:

More information

ESSENTIAL EQUILIBRIA. 1. Introduction

ESSENTIAL EQUILIBRIA. 1. Introduction ESSENTIAL EQUILIBRIA SRIHARI GOVINDAN AND ROBERT WILSON Abstract. The connected uniformly-hyperstable sets of a finite game are shown to be precisely the essential components of Nash equilibria. 1. Introduction

More information

Introduction to game theory LECTURE 1

Introduction to game theory LECTURE 1 Introduction to game theory LECTURE 1 Jörgen Weibull January 27, 2010 1 What is game theory? A mathematically formalized theory of strategic interaction between countries at war and peace, in federations

More information

Economics 703 Advanced Microeconomics. Professor Peter Cramton Fall 2017

Economics 703 Advanced Microeconomics. Professor Peter Cramton Fall 2017 Economics 703 Advanced Microeconomics Professor Peter Cramton Fall 2017 1 Outline Introduction Syllabus Web demonstration Examples 2 About Me: Peter Cramton B.S. Engineering, Cornell University Ph.D. Business

More information

Common Knowledge of Rationality is Self-Contradictory. Herbert Gintis

Common Knowledge of Rationality is Self-Contradictory. Herbert Gintis Common Knowledge of Rationality is Self-Contradictory Herbert Gintis February 25, 2012 Abstract The conditions under which rational agents play a Nash equilibrium are extremely demanding and often implausible.

More information

Microeconomics. 2. Game Theory

Microeconomics. 2. Game Theory Microeconomics 2. Game Theory Alex Gershkov http://www.econ2.uni-bonn.de/gershkov/gershkov.htm 18. November 2008 1 / 36 Dynamic games Time permitting we will cover 2.a Describing a game in extensive form

More information

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7).

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). The axiomatic approach (OR 15) Nash s (1950) work is the starting point

More information

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2 6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2 Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar MIT October 14, 2009 1 Introduction Outline Mixed Strategies Existence of Mixed Strategy Nash Equilibrium

More information

Evolutionary Dynamics and Extensive Form Games by Ross Cressman. Reviewed by William H. Sandholm *

Evolutionary Dynamics and Extensive Form Games by Ross Cressman. Reviewed by William H. Sandholm * Evolutionary Dynamics and Extensive Form Games by Ross Cressman Reviewed by William H. Sandholm * Noncooperative game theory is one of a handful of fundamental frameworks used for economic modeling. It

More information

FORWARD INDUCTION AND SUNK COSTS GIVE AVERAGE COST PRICING. Jean-Pierre Ponssard. Abstract

FORWARD INDUCTION AND SUNK COSTS GIVE AVERAGE COST PRICING. Jean-Pierre Ponssard. Abstract FORWARD INDUCTION AND SUNK COSTS GIVE AVERAGE COST PRICING Jean-Pierre Ponssard Abstract This paper applies the idea of forward induction to a classical economic problem: the existence of an efficient

More information

Quantum Games Have No News for Economists 1

Quantum Games Have No News for Economists 1 Quantum Games Have No News for Economists 1 By David K. Levine 2 This version: September 1, 2005 First version: December 3, 2005 Quantum computing offers the possibility of massively parallel computing

More information

האוניברסיטה העברית בירושלים

האוניברסיטה העברית בירושלים האוניברסיטה העברית בירושלים THE HEBREW UNIVERSITY OF JERUSALEM TOWARDS A CHARACTERIZATION OF RATIONAL EXPECTATIONS by ITAI ARIELI Discussion Paper # 475 February 2008 מרכז לחקר הרציונליות CENTER FOR THE

More information

Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information

Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information Extensive Form Games with Perfect Information Levent Koçkesen 1 Extensive Form Games The strategies in strategic form games are speci ed so that each player chooses an action (or a mixture of actions)

More information

Game Theory. Georg Moser. Institute of Computer UIBK. Winter GM (Institute of Computer UIBK) Game Theory 1/19 Organisation

Game Theory. Georg Moser. Institute of Computer UIBK. Winter GM (Institute of Computer UIBK) Game Theory 1/19 Organisation OLC mputational gic Game Theory Georg Moser Institute of Computer Science @ UIBK Winter 2008 GM (Institute of Computer Science @ UIBK) Game Theory 1/19 Organisation Organisation Time and Place Thursday,

More information

4: Dynamic games. Concordia February 6, 2017

4: Dynamic games. Concordia February 6, 2017 INSE6441 Jia Yuan Yu 4: Dynamic games Concordia February 6, 2017 We introduce dynamic game with non-simultaneous moves. Example 0.1 (Ultimatum game). Divide class into two groups at random: Proposers,

More information

Introduction. 1 University of Pennsylvania, Wharton Finance Department, Steinberg Hall-Dietrich Hall, 3620

Introduction. 1 University of Pennsylvania, Wharton Finance Department, Steinberg Hall-Dietrich Hall, 3620 May 16, 2006 Philip Bond 1 Are cheap talk and hard evidence both needed in the courtroom? Abstract: In a recent paper, Bull and Watson (2004) present a formal model of verifiability in which cheap messages

More information

A Dynamic Level-k Model in Games

A Dynamic Level-k Model in Games Dynamic Level-k Model in Games Teck Ho and Xuanming Su UC erkeley March, 2010 Teck Hua Ho 1 4-stage Centipede Game 4 2 16 8 1 8 4 32 1 2 3 4 64 16 5 Outcome Round 1 2 3 4 5 1 5 6.2% 30.3% 35.9% 20.0% 7.6%

More information

Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College

Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College 2015 Course Overview 1. Bargaining 2. Hidden information and self-selection Optimal contracting with hidden information

More information

Some forgotten equilibria of the Bertrand duopoly!?

Some forgotten equilibria of the Bertrand duopoly!? Some forgotten equilibria of the Bertrand duopoly!? Mathias Erlei Clausthal University of Technology Julius-Albert-Str. 2, 38678 Clausthal-Zellerfeld, Germany email: m.erlei@tu-clausthal.de Abstract This

More information

Epsilon Ex Post Implementation

Epsilon Ex Post Implementation Epsilon Ex Post Implementation Mehmet Barlo Nuh Aygun Dalkiran February 10, 2014 Abstract We provide necessary and sufficient conditions for epsilon ex post implementation. Our analysis extends Bergemann

More information

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM Discussion Papers in Economics Discussion Paper No. 0/06 CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY by Indraneel Dasgupta July 00 DP 0/06 ISSN 1360-438 UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM

More information

Columbia University. Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series

Columbia University. Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series Columbia University Department of Economics Discussion Paper Series Equivalence of Public Mixed-Strategies and Private Behavior Strategies in Games with Public Monitoring Massimiliano Amarante Discussion

More information

J. Flesch, J. Kuipers, G. Schoenmakers, K. Vrieze. Subgame-Perfection in Free Transition Games RM/11/047

J. Flesch, J. Kuipers, G. Schoenmakers, K. Vrieze. Subgame-Perfection in Free Transition Games RM/11/047 J. Flesch, J. Kuipers, G. Schoenmakers, K. Vrieze Subgame-Perfection in Free Transition Games RM/11/047 Subgame-Perfection in Free Transition Games J. Flesch, J. Kuipers, G. Schoenmakers, K. Vrieze October

More information

Repeated Downsian Electoral Competition

Repeated Downsian Electoral Competition Repeated Downsian Electoral Competition John Duggan Department of Political Science and Department of Economics University of Rochester Mark Fey Department of Political Science University of Rochester

More information

The Limits of ESS Methodology

The Limits of ESS Methodology The Limits of ESS Methodology Simon M. Huttegger Kevin J. S. Zollman December 31, 2010 Abstract In this paper we show that there are certain limits as to what applications of Maynard Smith s concept of

More information

Aspects of Rationalizable Behaviour

Aspects of Rationalizable Behaviour Aspects of Rationalizable Behaviour Peter J. Hammond Department of Economics, Stanford University, CA 94305-6072, U.S.A. December 1991; revised April, July, and September 1992. Chapter for Frontiers of

More information

SF2972 Game Theory Exam with Solutions March 15, 2013

SF2972 Game Theory Exam with Solutions March 15, 2013 SF2972 Game Theory Exam with s March 5, 203 Part A Classical Game Theory Jörgen Weibull and Mark Voorneveld. (a) What are N, S and u in the definition of a finite normal-form (or, equivalently, strategic-form)

More information

Lecture Notes on Game Theory

Lecture Notes on Game Theory Lecture Notes on Game Theory Levent Koçkesen Strategic Form Games In this part we will analyze games in which the players choose their actions simultaneously (or without the knowledge of other players

More information

Stackelberg-solvable games and pre-play communication

Stackelberg-solvable games and pre-play communication Stackelberg-solvable games and pre-play communication Claude d Aspremont SMASH, Facultés Universitaires Saint-Louis and CORE, Université catholique de Louvain, Louvain-la-Neuve, Belgium Louis-André Gérard-Varet

More information

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 11: Introduction to Game Theory 3

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 11: Introduction to Game Theory 3 6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 11: Introduction to Game Theory 3 Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar MIT October 19, 2009 1 Introduction Outline Existence of Nash Equilibrium in Infinite Games Extensive Form

More information

Refinements - change set of equilibria to find "better" set of equilibria by eliminating some that are less plausible

Refinements - change set of equilibria to find better set of equilibria by eliminating some that are less plausible efinements efinements - change set of equilibria to find "better" set of equilibria by eliminating some that are less plausible Strategic Form Eliminate Weakly Dominated Strategies - Purpose - throwing

More information

Super Weak Isomorphism of Extensive Games

Super Weak Isomorphism of Extensive Games Super Weak Isomorphism of Extensive Games André Casajus Accepted for publication in Mathematical Social Sciences as of July 6 2005. (March 2005, this version: July 10, 2005, 12:13) Abstract It is well-known

More information

Generic equivalence between perfectly and sequentially rational strategic behavior

Generic equivalence between perfectly and sequentially rational strategic behavior Generic equivalence between perfectly and sequentially rational strategic behavior Xiao Luo ay, Xuewen Qian a, Yang Sun a a Department of Economics, National University of Singapore, Singapore 117570 This

More information

What is Backward Induction?

What is Backward Induction? What is ackward duction? dam randenburger y manda Friedenberg z September 9 bstract Which solution concepts satisfy backward induction (I)? We de ne a property we call it Di erence which relates the behavior

More information

NOTES ON COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY AND THE CORE. 1. Introduction

NOTES ON COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY AND THE CORE. 1. Introduction NOTES ON COOPERATIVE GAME THEORY AND THE CORE SARA FROEHLICH 1. Introduction Cooperative game theory is fundamentally different from the types of games we have studied so far, which we will now refer to

More information

Rationalizable Partition-Confirmed Equilibrium

Rationalizable Partition-Confirmed Equilibrium Rationalizable Partition-Confirmed Equilibrium Drew Fudenberg and Yuichiro Kamada First Version: January 29, 2011; This Version: May 3, 2013 Abstract Rationalizable partition-confirmed equilibrium (RPCE)

More information

COMPUTATION OF EXTENSIVE FORM EQUILIBRIA IN SEQUENCE FORM GAMES

COMPUTATION OF EXTENSIVE FORM EQUILIBRIA IN SEQUENCE FORM GAMES COMPUTATION OF EXTENSIVE FORM EQUILIBRIA IN SEQUENCE FORM GAMES Gunhaeng Lee November 12, 2017 Abstract This paper presents a modified version of a sequence form representation of a two-person extensive-form

More information

Long-Run versus Short-Run Player

Long-Run versus Short-Run Player Repeated Games 1 Long-Run versus Short-Run Player a fixed simultaneous move stage game Player 1 is long-run with discount factor δ actions a A a finite set 1 1 1 1 2 utility u ( a, a ) Player 2 is short-run

More information

Iterative Weak Dominance and Interval-Dominance Supermodular Games

Iterative Weak Dominance and Interval-Dominance Supermodular Games Iterative Weak Dominance and Interval-Dominance Supermodular Games Joel Sobel April 4, 2016 Abstract This paper extends Milgrom and Robert s treatment of supermodular games in two ways. It points out that

More information

A Bayesian Theory of Games: An Analysis of Strategic Interactions with Statistical Decision Theoretic Foundation

A Bayesian Theory of Games: An Analysis of Strategic Interactions with Statistical Decision Theoretic Foundation Journal of Mathematics and System Science (0 45-55 D DAVID PUBLISHING A Bayesian Theory of Games: An Analysis of Strategic Interactions with Statistical Decision Theoretic Foundation Jimmy Teng School

More information

Interactive epistemology in games with payoff uncertainty

Interactive epistemology in games with payoff uncertainty Research in Economics 61 (2007) 165 184 www.elsevier.com/locate/rie Interactive epistemology in games with payoff uncertainty Pierpaolo Battigalli a,, Marciano Siniscalchi b,1 a Università Bocconi, IEP

More information

Extensive games (with perfect information)

Extensive games (with perfect information) Extensive games (with perfect information) (also referred to as extensive-form games or dynamic games) DEFINITION An extensive game with perfect information has the following components A set N (the set

More information

Computing Minmax; Dominance

Computing Minmax; Dominance Computing Minmax; Dominance CPSC 532A Lecture 5 Computing Minmax; Dominance CPSC 532A Lecture 5, Slide 1 Lecture Overview 1 Recap 2 Linear Programming 3 Computational Problems Involving Maxmin 4 Domination

More information

Dominance and Admissibility without Priors

Dominance and Admissibility without Priors Dominance and Admissibility without Priors Jörg Stoye Cornell University September 14, 2011 Abstract This note axiomatizes the incomplete preference ordering that reflects statewise dominance with respect

More information

Refined best-response correspondence and dynamics

Refined best-response correspondence and dynamics Refined best-response correspondence and dynamics Dieter Balkenborg, Josef Hofbauer, and Christoph Kuzmics February 18, 2007 Abstract We study a natural (and, in a well-defined sense, minimal) refinement

More information

Robust Mechanism Design and Robust Implementation

Robust Mechanism Design and Robust Implementation Robust Mechanism Design and Robust Implementation joint work with Stephen Morris August 2009 Barcelona Introduction mechanism design and implementation literatures are theoretical successes mechanisms

More information

SEQUENTIAL EQUILIBRIA IN BAYESIAN GAMES WITH COMMUNICATION. Dino Gerardi and Roger B. Myerson. December 2005

SEQUENTIAL EQUILIBRIA IN BAYESIAN GAMES WITH COMMUNICATION. Dino Gerardi and Roger B. Myerson. December 2005 SEQUENTIAL EQUILIBRIA IN BAYESIAN GAMES WITH COMMUNICATION By Dino Gerardi and Roger B. Myerson December 2005 COWLES FOUNDATION DISCUSSION AER NO. 1542 COWLES FOUNDATION FOR RESEARCH IN ECONOMICS YALE

More information

Definitions and Proofs

Definitions and Proofs Giving Advice vs. Making Decisions: Transparency, Information, and Delegation Online Appendix A Definitions and Proofs A. The Informational Environment The set of states of nature is denoted by = [, ],

More information

Weak Robust (Virtual) Implementation

Weak Robust (Virtual) Implementation Weak Robust (Virtual) Implementation Chih-Chun Yang Institute of Economics, Academia Sinica, Taipei 115, Taiwan April 2016 Abstract We provide a characterization of (virtual) implementation in iterated

More information

Positive Political Theory II David Austen-Smith & Je rey S. Banks

Positive Political Theory II David Austen-Smith & Je rey S. Banks Positive Political Theory II David Austen-Smith & Je rey S. Banks Egregious Errata Positive Political Theory II (University of Michigan Press, 2005) regrettably contains a variety of obscurities and errors,

More information

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers September 6, 016 ONLINE APPENDIX In this Appendix we present in full additional results and extensions which are only mentioned in the paper. In the exposition

More information