On Strictly Positive Modal Logics with S4.3 Frames

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "On Strictly Positive Modal Logics with S4.3 Frames"

Transcription

1 On Strictly Positive Modal Logics with S4.3 Frames Stanislav Kikot Birkbeck, University of London, U.K. Agi Kurucz King s College London, U.K. Frank Wolter University of Liverpool, U.K. Michael Zakharyaschev Birkbeck, University of London, U.K. Abstract We investigate the lattice of strictly positive (SP) modal logics that contain the SP-fragment of the propositional modal logic S4.3. We are interested in Kripke (in)completeness of these logics, their computational complexity, as well as the definability of Kripke frames by means of SP-implications. We compare the lattice of these SP-logics with the lattice of normal modal logics above S4.3. We also consider global consequence relations for SP-logics, focusing on definability and Kripke completeness. Keywords: strictly positive modal logic, meet-semilattices with monotone operators, Kripke completeness, definability, decidability. 1 Introduction The lattice NExtS4.3 of propositional normal modal logics containing S4.3 is a rare example of a non-trivial class of well-behaved modal logics. Indeed, all of them are finitely axiomatisable, have the finite model property [6,10], and are decidable in conp [22]. Although Fine [10] complained that the full lattice [of these logics] is one of great complexity, its structure is perfectly understandable (though difficult to depict) if one recalls the fact [7] that every L NExtS4.3 can be axiomatised by Jankov (aka characteristic or frame) formulas for finite linear quasi-ordered frames. In this paper, our concern is the fragment of the modal language that comprises implications σ τ, where σ and τ are strictly positive modal formulas [3]

2 2 On Strictly Positive Modal Logics with S4.3 Frames constructed from variables using,, and the constant. We call such implications SP-implications. A natural algebraic semantics for SP-implications is given by meet-semilattices with monotone operators (SLOs, for short) [21,2,16]. We denote the corresponding syntactic consequence relation by SLO and call any SLO -closed set of SP-implications an SP-logic. The lattice of varieties of SLOs validating the SP-implicational S4 axioms p p and p p (closure SLOs) was studied by Jackson [15] (see also [9]). Jackson showed, in particular, that the SP-fragment P S4 of S4 is complex in the sense that each closure SLO can be embedded into the full complex algebra of some Kripke frame for S4. It follows that the SP-logic given by {p p, p p} is (Kripke) complete in the sense that its SP-implicational SLO -consequences coincide with those over Kripke frames, that is, with P S4. On the other hand, it is shown in [16] that the SP-extension of P S4 with (p q) (p r) (p q r) (wcon) is not complex; yet, it is complete and axiomatises the SP-fragment P S4.3 of S4.3. Both P S4 and P S4.3 are decidable in polynomial time [1,21,16]. Our aim here is to investigate SP-logics above P S4.3 focusing on completeness, definability (of Kripke frames) and computational complexity and compare them with classical modal logics above S4.3. Our first important observation is that, unlike classical modal formulas, a randomly chosen SP-implication will most probably axiomatise an incomplete SP-extension of P S4.3. Such are, for example, p q and p q (p q). In Section 3, we construct infinite sequences of SP-logics sharing the same two-point frames. But the main result of this paper is that we do identify all complete SP-logics above P S4.3. Over S4.3 frames, modal formulas define exactly those frame classes that are closed under cofinal subframes [10,23]. On the other hand, over P S4, SPimplications are capable of defining only FO-definable classes closed under subframes [16] (which implies that frames for any proper extension of P S4.3 are of bounded depth). In Section 4, we show that all FO-definable subframe-closed classes of S4.3-frames are SP-definable. We also give finite axiomatisations of these SP-definable classes by means of SP-analogues of subframe formulas [11,23], and prove that each of the resulting SP-logics is decidable in polynomial time. In Section 5, we investigate the lattice Ext + P S4.3 of SP-logics containing P S4.3 by comparing it with the lattice NExtS4.3. Following [4], we consider two maps: one associates with every modal logic L its SP-fragment π(l), the other one associates with every SP-logic P the modal logic µ(p ) = S4.3 P. We give a frame-theoretic characterisation of π and show that each π 1 (P ) has a greatest element. On the other hand, as follows from Section 3, µ 1 (L) often contains infinitely many incomplete logics. In Section 6, we consider rules ϱ = ι1,...,ιn ι of SP-implications. In modal logics above S4, ϱ is expressed by the formula (ι 1 ι n ) ι. We show that a class of S4.3-frames is modally definable iff it is definable by SP-rules. An SP-logic is complete w.r.t. SP-rules iff it is complex [16]. We show that the

3 Kikot, Kurucz, Wolter, Zakharyaschev 3 only SP-logics in Ext + P S4.3 complete w.r.t. SP-rules are P S5 and the logic of the singleton cluster. These are also the only complete SP-logics for which deciding valid SP-rules is in polynomial time. We make a step towards axiomatising SPrules by giving axiomatisations for the n-element clusters, n > 1. 2 Preliminaries We assume that the reader is familiar with basic notions of modal logic and Kripke semantics [7]. In particular, M, w = ϕ means that ϕ holds at world w in Kripke model M, and F = ϕ says that ϕ is valid in Kripke frame F. We write C = ϕ, for a class C of frames, if ϕ is valid in every F C. We denote SP-implications by ι = (σ τ) and refer to σ, τ as terms. By regarding ι as the equality σ τ = σ, we can naturally evaluate it in SLOs, i.e., structures A = (A,,, ), where (A,, ) is a semilattice with top element and (a b) b = (a b), for any a, b A. We write A = ι to say that σ τ = σ holds in A under any valuation. For a set P {ι} of SP-implications, we write P = SLO ι if A = ι for every SLO A validating all implications in P. We denote by P [A] the set of SP-implications ι for which A = ι. Since equational consequence can be characterised syntactically by Birkhoff s equational calculus [5,13], it is readily seen that P = SLO ι iff P SLO ι, where P SLO ι means that there is a sequence (derivation) ι 0,, ι n = ι, with each ι i being a substitution instance of a member in P or one of the axioms p p, p, p q q p, p q p, or obtained from earlier members of the sequence using one of the rules σ τ τ ϱ, σ ϱ σ τ σ ϱ σ τ ϱ, σ τ σ τ (see also the Reflection Calculus RC of [2,8]). We say that SP-implications ι and ι are P -equivalent, if P {ι} SLO ι and P {ι } SLO ι. For any class C of Kripke frames, the set of modal formulas (with full Booleans) validated by the frames in C is called the modal logic of C and denoted by L[C]; the restriction of L[C] to SP-implications is called the SP-logic of C and denoted by P [C]. For finite C = {F 1,, F n }, we write L[F 1, F n ] and P [F 1,, F n ], respectively. For any set Φ of modal formulas, Fr(Φ) is the class of frames validating Φ. Every Kripke frame F = (W, R) gives rise to a SLO F = (2 W,, W, + ) where + X = {w W R(w, v) for some v X}, for X W (that is, F is the (,, )-type reduct of the full complex algebra of F [12]). As Kripke models over F and valuations in the algebra F are the same thing, we always have P [F] = P [F ]. S4.3 is the modal logic whose rooted Kripke frames are linear quasi-orders F = (W, R), i.e., R is a reflexive and transitive relation on W with xry or yrx, for any x, y W. From now on, we refer to rooted frames for S4.3 as simply

4 4 On Strictly Positive Modal Logics with S4.3 Frames frames. A cluster in F is any set of the form C(x) = {y W xry & yrx}. If W ω and the number of clusters in F is finite, we write F = (m 1,, m n ), 1 m i ω, to say that the ith cluster in F (starting from the root) has m i points. In this case, we also say that F is of depth n and write d(f) = n. A linear order with n points is denoted by L n. We call frame F = (W, R) a subframe of a frame F = (W, R ) and write F F if W W and R is the restriction of R to W. A subframe F of F is proper if W is a proper subset of W. We say that F is a cofinal subframe of F and write F F if F G and, for any x W and y W with xr y, there is z W with yr z. (As we only deal with frames for S4.3, F F iff F is a p-morphic image of F.) The normal extension L of S4.3 with a set Φ of modal formulas is denoted by L = S4.3 Φ; NExtS4.3 = {S4.3 Φ Φ is a set of modal formulas}. The minimal SP-logic P containing P S4.3 and a set Φ of SP-implications is denoted by P = P S4.3 + Φ; Ext + P S4.3 = {P S4.3 + Φ Φ is a set of SP-implications}. Given P and ι, we write P = Kr ι iff ι P [Fr(P )]. It is easy to see that P SLO ι always implies P = Kr ι. We call P complete if the converse also holds for every ι. As shown in [16], P S4.3 is complete and Fr(P S4.3 ) = Fr(S4.3). The picture below gives examples of SLOs for P S4.3 by Hasse diagrams where vertices represent (closed) elements a with a = a and vertices represent elements a with a > a. Note that, for each element a, a is the (unique) smallest element b with b > a. d e a b c a 1 a 2 a n C 1 g g E n 3 Incomplete SP-logics Axiomatising even very simple frames by SP-implications turns out to be a challenging problem because many natural and innocuously looking axiomcandidates will most probably give incomplete SP-logics. For instance, let σ n (p, q) = ( p ( q (p ) ). }{{} used n times, 1 n < ω Consider the following SP-implications (the reader may find it useful to compare them with the SP-implications defined in the next section): ι 2 fun = (p q) (p r) (q r) (p q r), (1) ɛ 1 = p q ( p q), (2) ɛ 2 = (p q) (p r) (q r) ( p (q r) ), (3)

5 Kikot, Kurucz, Wolter, Zakharyaschev 5 ϕ = (p q) (p r) (q r) ( p (q r) ), (4) β n = σ n (p, q) σ n (q, p) (p q), (5) γ n = σ n+1 (p, q) (p q), = σ n+1 (p, q) σ n+1 (q, p). δ n Figure 1 describes inclusions between the SP-logics above P 2 fun = P S4.3 + ι 2 fun axiomatised by these SP-implications. Using results from [15] and Claim 3.1 below, it is not hard to see that all of the depicted inclusions are proper. P [(2)] = P 2 fun + ɛ 1 P [(2), L 2 ] = P 2 fun + ϕ P [L 2 ] = Pfun 2 + ɛ 2 + β 2 Pfun 2 + β 2 Pfun 2 + ɛ 2 Pfun 2 + δ 2 P 2 fun + δ 3 Pfun 2 + γ 2 Pfun 2 + β 3 Pfun 2 + γ 3 Pfun 2 + β 4 Pfun 2 + γ 4 P 2 fun + δ 4 P 2 fun = P S4.3 + ι 2 fun Fig. 1. Complete and incomplete SP-logics above P 2 fun = P S4.3 + ι 2 fun. The only complete SP-logics in the picture are shown by (that they are axiomatised by the indicated SP-implications follows from [15]; see also Theorem 4.4 below). On the other hand, it is not hard to check that, for each SP-logic P in Fig. 1, if P is below P [(2), L 2 ] then the rooted frames for P are L 1, (2), L 2, and if P is below P [L 2 ] but not below P [(2), L 2 ] then the rooted frames for P are L 1, L 2. Therefore, all SP-logics shown by + in the picture are incomplete. Claim 3.1 (i) Pfun 2 +ɛ 2 = SLO ϕ and Pfun 2 +ɛ 2 = SLO β 2, (ii) Pfun 2 +β 2 = SLO ɛ 2, (iii) Pfun 2 + γ n = SLO β n, (iv) Pfun 2 + β n+1 = SLO δ n, (v) Pfun 2 + δ n = SLO β n+1. Proof. Claim (i) can be shown by the SLO A 2 in Fig. 3 (in the appendix), (ii) by A 3, (iii) by C n, (iv) by B n, and (v) by D n. The frames for the incomplete SP-logics above have at most 2 points. Similar incomplete SP-logics can clearly be defined for more complex frames, which makes the lattice Ext + P S4.3 much more involved compared to NExtS Axiomatising frame classes by SP-implications As any SP-implication ι is a Sahlqvist formula, Fr(ι) is FO-definable [20]. As shown in [16], the class of reflexive and transitive frames validating ι is closed under subframes. Using the results from [11,23] on FO-definable subframe logics, we obtain the following theorem (which can be readily proved directly):

6 6 On Strictly Positive Modal Logics with S4.3 Frames Theorem 4.1 For every ι / P S4.3, there exists n < ω such that Fr(ι) is closed under subframes and any frame in Fr(ι) is of depth < n. Thus, for any SP-logic P Ext + P S4.3, either P = P S4.3 or Fr(P ) is of bounded depth. Recall from [11,23] that, for any finite frame F, there are modal formulas α(f) and α (F), called the subframe and cofinal subframe formulas for F, respectively, such that, for any frame G, G = α(f) iff F G, G = α (F) iff F G. In fact, any L NExtS4.3 can be represented in the form L = S4.3 α (F 1 ) α (F m ), for some F i. If C is an FO-definable class of frames closed under subframes and N < ω is the maximal depth of frames in C, then there exist frames F 1,, F m of depth N such that L[C] = S4.3 α(l N+1 ) α(f 1 ) α(f m ). (6) Note that S4.3 α(f) = S4.3 α (F) α (F ), where F is obtained from F by adding a single-point cluster on top of F, and that S4.3 α(l n ) = S4.3 α (L n ). Our aim now is (i) to construct SP-analogues κ N (F) of the subframe formulas α(f) such that G = κ N (F) iff G is of depth N and G = α(f); and (ii) to prove that the κ N (F) axiomatise all complete SP-logics. Let F = (n 1,, n f ) be a finite frame with f N < ω. We begin by defining an SP-implication ι N (F) as follows. First, we take the terms τ(f) = ( P1 ( P2 ( P f ) )), (7) where the P i are pairwise disjoint sets of variables with P i = n i, for i f. Next, denote by Σ N (F) the set of all terms of the form ( Q1 ( Q2 ( Q N ) )), where there exist 1 = x 1 < x 2 < < x f+1 = N + 1 such that: for any i and j, if x i j < x i+1 then Q j P i and Q j P i 1, (8) there is i such that Q j = P i 1 for any j with x i j < x i+1. (9) (Note that =, so when some Q j =, the corresponding term in Σ N (F) is P S4 -equivalent to a term of modal depth < N.) It is not hard to see that Σ N (F) (max i P i + 1) N, and so Σ N (F) is polynomial in F. (10) Finally, we set ι N (F) = σ τ(f). σ Σ N (F)

7 Kikot, Kurucz, Wolter, Zakharyaschev 7 For example, ι 1 ((n)) is Q {p 1,...,p n} Q =n 1 Q (p 1 p n ), defining (n 1)-functionality (in particular, ι 1 ((3)) is ι 2 fun in (1)). For every m n, the SP-implication ι m (L n ) is (P S4 -equivalent to) n i=1 [ ( p 1 p 2 [ ( p i 1 [p i+1 ( p n ) ] ) ])] ( p 1 ( p 2 ( p n ) )), defining the property of having depth < n. In particular, ι n (L n ) is ɛ n 1 in (2) (3) for n = 2, 3; ι 2 ((1, 2)) is ϕ in (4), and ι 2 ((2)) is β 2 in (5). In order to define κ N (F), we require the following: Claim 4.2 [15, Lemma 7.7] For any finite set Φ of SP-implications, there is a single SP-implication ι Φ such that P S4 + Φ = P S4 + ι Φ. Now, we set κ N (F) = ι {ι N+1 (L N+1 ),ι N (F)}. Observe that ι n (L n ) is P S4 -equivalent to ι n+1 (L n+1 ), and so κ n (L n ) = ι n (L n ). Theorem 4.3 For any finite S4.3-frame F, any N with d(f) N < ω, and any S4.3-frame G, we have G = κ N (F) iff G is of depth N and G = α(f). Proof. It suffices to show that (i) if F G then G = ι N (F); and (ii) if d(g) N and F G then G = ι N (F). (i) Let F = (n 1,, n f ) and F G. Then there exist clusters (ζ 1 ),, (ζ f ) in G such that (ζ 1,, ζ f ) is a subframe of G and ζ i n i, for i f. We define a model M based on G in the following way. For each i f, take n i distinct points from (ζ i ) and let each validate f j=1 P j \ {p} for each different p P i. All other points in G validate no variables. Then it is easy to see that M, r = ι N (F) for any r in the root cluster of G. (ii) is proved by induction on the pair (d(f), N) for N d(f). To begin with, we claim that if (n) (ζ) for some n < ω, then (ζ) = ι 1 ((n)). Indeed, in this case, ζ < n. Suppose τ((n)) = P 1 for some set P 1 of variables with P 1 = n. Let M be a model on (ζ) such that the left-hand side of ι 1 ((n)) holds at some point in M. Then, for each of the n-many (n 1)-element subsets Q of P 1, Q is in Σ 1 ((n)), and so there is x Q (ζ) with M, x Q = Q. By the pigeonhole principle, there is x (ζ) with M, x = P 1. Now suppose inductively that, for all F and N d(f ), if either d(f ) < f or N < N, then G = ι N (F ) for every G with d(g) N and F G. Let F = (n 1,, n f ), N f, G = (ζ 1,, ζ g ), for some g N, and F G. Suppose M is a model over G such that M, r = σ, for some root r in G. (11) σ Σ N (F)

8 8 On Strictly Positive Modal Logics with S4.3 Frames Take the term τ(f) from (7) and consider two cases: Case 1: g < f. Then there is j g such that, for all i f, M, x i = P i for some x i (ζ j ). Indeed, suppose otherwise. For any j g, take some i j f with M, x = P ij for any x (ζ j ). However, as g < f, there is σ Σ N (F) with P S4 SLO σ δ for δ = ( P i1 ( P i2 ( P ig ) )), and so M, r = δ by (11), which is a contradiction. Case 2: f g N. As P S4 SLO σ P f for some σ Σ N (F), by (11) there is x with M, x = P f. Let We show that m = max{j M, x = P f for some x (ζ j )}. M, y = P 1 ( P2 ( P f 1 ) ), for some j m, y (ζ j ). (12) Indeed, two cases are possible. (2.1): ζ j < n f for every j with m < j g. Suppose (12) does not hold. Since for any sequence (Q m+1,, Q g ) of (n f 1)-element subsets of P f, we have σ Σ N (F) with P S4 SLO σ δ for the term δ = ( P1 ( P f 1 ( Qm+1 ( Q g ) ))), M, r = δ follows by (11). Therefore, there is j with m < j g such that for each of the n f -many (n f 1)-element subsets Q of P f, we have M, x Q = Q for some x Q (ζ j ), and so M, x = P f for some x (ζ j ) by the pigeonhole principle, contrary to the definition of m. (2.2) There is j such that m < j g and ζ j n f. Let F = (n 1,, n f 1 ). Then F (ζ 1,, ζ m ), and so by IH we have (ζ 1,, ζ m ) = ι m (F ). (13) For every δ Σ m (F ) of the form ( Q 1 ( Q 2 ( Q m ) )), there is some σ Σ N (F) with P S4 SLO σ δ + for the term δ + = ( Q1 ( ( Qm ( Pf ))) ). Thus, M, r = δ + by (11). Therefore, by the definition of m, there is i m such that M, x = Q 1 ( Q 2 ( Q m ) ) for some x (ζ i ), and so M, r = δ for the restriction M of M to (ζ 1,, ζ m ). By (13), we have M, r = τ(f ), and so (12) holds as required. We are now in a position to prove our main theorem on definability, completeness (axiomatisability) and computational complexity: Theorem 4.4 Let C be any first-order definable class of S4.3-frames closed under subframes and different from Fr(P S4.3 ), and let N < ω be the maximal

9 Kikot, Kurucz, Wolter, Zakharyaschev 9 depth of frames in C. Then there is a finite set F C of frames of depth N such that the following conditions hold for the SP-logic { P S4.3 + {κ N (F) F F C }, if F C, P C = P S4.3 + κ N+1 (L N+1 ), otherwise: (i) C = Fr(P C ). (ii) P C is Kripke complete, and so P [C] = P C. (iii) P C is decidable in PTime. Proof. Let F C = {F 1,, F m }, where the frames F i are supplied by (6). Then, for any frame G of depth N, we have G C iff F G for any F F C. (i) is a straightforward consequence of Claim 4.2 and Theorem 4.3. (ii) By an F C -normal form we mean any term of the following form: ( P 1 ( P 2 ( P k ) )) where k N and each P i is a finite set of variables such that there is no F F C with F ( P 1, P 2,, P k ). (We do not require that the P i are disjoint.) For a set Σ of terms, let var(σ) be the set of propositional variables in Σ. We write var(σ) for var ( {σ} ). Claim For every term σ, there is a set N σ of F C -normal forms such that var(n σ ) = var(σ), N σ is polynomial in the size of σ, and ( P S4.3 + ι N+1 (L N+1 ) + {ι N (F) F F C } SLO σ ). ϱ N σ ϱ Proof. We proceed via a series of steps (a) (c). (a) As shown in [16, Claim 48.1]), by wcon, σ is P S4.3 -equivalent to a conjunction of terms of the form ( Q 1 ( Q 2 ( Q k ) )), where k < ω and each Q i is a finite set of variables. Each such term describes a full linear branch in the term tree of σ, and so (p1) each k is polynomial in the size σ of σ; (p2) each Q i of each term is polynomial in σ ; and (p3) the overall number of terms we obtain this way is polynomial in σ. (b) By ι N+1 (L N+1 ), we can take k N in (a). By (10) and (p1) (p3), the number of terms we thus obtain is polynomial in σ, so we are done if F C =. (c) Let F C. We claim that each term in (b) is P S4 + {ι N (F) F F C }- equivalent to a conjunction of F C -normal forms. Indeed, observe first that if ι N (F) = (σ τ) then P S4 SLO τ σ always holds. Now suppose χ = ( Q 1 ( Q 2 ( Q k ) )) for k N and finite sets Q i of variables with F ( Q 1, Q 2,, Q k ) for some F F C. Clearly, we may assume that d(f) = k. Let F = (n 1,, n k ) and n i Q i for i k. For i k, let P i = {p i 1,, p i n i } be the variables in

10 10 On Strictly Positive Modal Logics with S4.3 Frames ι N (F) and Q i = {q1, i, q Q i i }. We take the following substitution instance of ι N (F): for any i k and j n i 1, we substitute qj i for pi j, and qi n i q Q i i for p i n i. Then, by (8) and (9), χ is equivalent to a conjunction of terms of the form ( R 1 ( R 2 ( R l ) )) for some l N such that (n1) for every i = 1,, l there is some j i k with R i Q ji ; (n2) there is j k such that R i < Q j, for every i with j i = j. If a term ϑ of this form is not an F C -normal form, then again there is some F F C such that d(f ) = l and F ( R 1, R 2,, R l ). Thus, we can continue with applying ι N (F ) to ϑ. By (n1) and (n2), sooner or later the procedure stops and we obtain a set of F C -normal forms. In fact, by (10) and (p1) (p3), both the number of necessary steps and the number of terms we obtain in each step are polynomial in σ. Claim For every finite set Σ {ξ} of F C -normal forms such that var(σ) var(ξ), if P S4 SLO Σ ξ then G = Σ ξ, for some G C. Proof. Suppose ξ = ( P 1 ( P 2 ( P k ) )) where k N, and each P i is a finite set of variables such that there is no F F C with F ( P 1, P 2,, P k ). Then ( P 1, P 2,, P k ) C. By P S4, we may assume that neither P i P i+1 nor P i+1 P i for any i = 1,, k. Let M be the following model over ( P 1, P 2,, P k ) : for each i = 1,, k, let each point in ( P i ) validate k j=1 P j \ {p} for each different p P i. Let χ be any F C -normal form such that var(χ) var(ξ). Then χ is of the form ( R 1 ( R 2 ( R l ) )) for some l N, R i k j=1 P j for i l. If P S4 SLO χ ξ then there is no subsequence (R i1,, R i k ) of (R 1,, R l ) with P j R ij for j k. Thus, it is not hard to check that M, r = χ for any root r. As we clearly have M, r = ξ, it follows that M, r = Σ ξ for any set Σ of F C -normal forms with var(σ) = var(ξ) and P S4 SLO Σ ξ. Now the proof of (ii) can be completed as follows. Suppose P C = Kr σ τ. It is not hard to show [15, Lemma 5.1] that σ τ is P S4 -equivalent to σ τ and we may also assume that var(σ) = var(τ). Thus by Claim 4.4.1, we have P C = Kr χ χ N σ ϑ N τ ϑ. and so P C = Kr χ N σ χ ϑ, for every ϑ N τ. Again, it is not hard to show [15, Lemma 5.1] that we may assume that var(n σ ) var(ϑ). Therefore, by (i) and Claim 4.4.2, P S4 SLO χ N σ χ ϑ, for every ϑ N τ, and so P S4 SLO χ χ N σ ϑ N τ ϑ. By the completeness of P S4 and Claim 4.4.1, we obtain that P C SLO σ τ. (iii) follows from Claims and 4.4.2, and the tractability of P S4.

11 Kikot, Kurucz, Wolter, Zakharyaschev 11 5 Modal logics vs. SP-logics The set NExtS4.3 ordered by forms a distributive lattice, a pseudo-boolean algebra, to be more precise [19]. On the other hand, as follows from [15, Proposition 5.11], the lattice Ext + P S4.3 is not even modular because it contains the pentagon N 5 lattice; see Fig. 1. Following [4], we compare these two lattices of logics using the map π : NExtS4.3 Ext + P S4.3, which gives the SP-fragment π(l) of any modal logic L, and the map µ: Ext + P S4.3 NExtS4.3, which gives the modal extension µ(p ) = S4.3 P of any SP-logic P. We call L a modal companion of π(l), and P an SP-companion of µ(p ). It was observed in [4] that µ and π are monotone and form a Galois connection: µ(p ) L iff P π(l). In this section, we obtain answers to some open questions from [4] in the context of NExtS4.3 and Ext + P S4.3. First, we give a characterisation of those SP-logics that have modal companions (which actually holds for all multi-modal SP-logics). Theorem 5.1 An SP-logic P has a modal companion iff P is complete. Proof. ( ) If π(l) = P and ι / P, then ι / S4.3 P, and so, by Sahlqvist completeness, there is a Kripke frame for P refuting ι, as required. ( ) It is readily seen that, if P is complete, then S4.3 P is its modal companion. Next, we give a frame-theoretic characterisation of modal companions of any complete SP-logic in Ext + P S4.3, which consists of two parts. The first part describes the set π 1 (P S4.3 ) of modal companions of P S4.3 and shows that it comprises exactly the logics in NExtS4.3 that have frames of unbounded depth. We say that such logics are of slice ω. Theorem 5.2 For any modal logic L NExtS4.3, we have π(l) = P S4.3 iff L Grz.3 = S4.3 α((2)). Thus, Grz.3 is the greatest companion of P S4.3. Proof. ( ) If L Grz.3, then α(l n ) L, for some n < ω. By Theorem 4.3, it follows that κ n (L n ) L, contrary to π(l) = P S4.3. ( ) Suppose there is ι π(l) \ P S4.3. By Theorem 4.1, there is n < ω such that L n = ι, which is impossible since L n = Grz.3. In other words, π 1 (P S4.3 ) comprises S4.3 and all those (infinitely many) logics in NExtS4.3 whose classes of frames are not FO-definable. By a standard Löwenheim Skolem Tarski argument, if C is FO-definable, then both L[C] and P [C] are determined by the countable frames in C. So the remaining logics can be classified according to the depth of their countable frames. (This classification was suggested in [14,18].) We say that a modal logic L is of slice n (0 < n < ω) if L n = L but L n+1 = L. Within NExtS4.3, the logics L of slice n form the infinite interval S4.3 α(l n+1 ) = L[(ω,, ω)] L L[L }{{} n ] = S4.3 α(l n+1 ) α ( (2) ). n In particular, the logics L of slice 1 form the (infinite) interval S5 L L[L 1 ]. (It is shown in [18] that all logics of finite slices above S4 are locally finite.)

12 12 On Strictly Positive Modal Logics with S4.3 Frames We now characterise the modal companions of complete SP-logics properly extending P S4.3. Given the class Fr ω (P ) of all countable rooted frames for P, denote by Fr ω (P ) its smallest subclass whose closure under subframes gives Fr ω (P ). (It is not hard to see that Fr ω (P ) always exists.) Theorem 5.3 For any complete SP-logic P P S4.3, π 1 (P ) = {L NExtS4.3 Fr ω (P ) Fr ω (L) Fr ω (P )}. Thus, L[ Fr ω (P )] is the greatest modal companion of P. Proof. Suppose Fr ω (P ) Fr ω (L) Fr ω (P ) and show that π(l) = P. If ι L, then Fr ω (L) = ι, and so Fr ω (P ) = ι. By Theorem 4.1, it follows that Fr ω (P ) = ι and ι P. The implication ι P ι L is trivial. Next, we have to prove that every modal companion L of P belongs to the specified interval. It suffices to show that if L = S4.3 P α (F) is a modal companion of P, then Fr ω (P ) = α (F). Suppose otherwise and take some G Fr ω (P ) such that F G. By the construction of Fr ω (P ), we can always find a finite frame G such that F G G and G H, for any H in Fr ω (P ) different from G. But then α(g ) L, and so κ n (G ) P by Theorem 4.3, where n is the slice of P, which is impossible because G Fr ω (P ). Intuitively, L[ Fr ω (P )] saturates S4.3 P with all those formulas α (F) that do not derive any α(g) / S4.3 P. We illustrate this by a few examples. Example 5.4 (1) The SP-logic P [(ω, ω)] = P S4.3 +κ 3 (L 3 ) has only one modal companion S4.3 α(l 3 ) since (ω, ω) = α (F), for any F of depth 2. (2) The SP-logic P [(2, 1)] = P S4.3 + κ 3 ((1, 2)) + κ 3 ((3)) has two modal companions: S4.3 α(l 3 ) α ( (1, 2) ) α ( (3) ) = L[(2), (2, 1)] and its extension with α ( (2) ), i.e., L[(2, 1)]. Note that S4 α ( (2) ) = S4 p p = S4.1. (3) The companions L of P [(ω, 1)] = P S4.3 + κ 3 ((1, 2)) form the infinite interval L[(ω), (ω, 1)] = S4.3 α(l 3 ) α ( (1, 2) ) L S4.3 α(l 3 ) α ( (2) ) = L[(ω, 1)]. As follows from our results above, π maps NExtS4.3 onto the complete SP-logics in Ext + P S4.3. On the other hand, for a complete SP-logic P, there may exist Kripke incomplete logics P such that Fr(P ) = Fr(P ). All these logics form the set µ 1 (S4.3 P ). Thus, for every L NExtS4.3, the set µ 1 (L) has π(l) as its greatest element; see Fig. 4 in the appendix. We do not know whether µ 1 (L) always has a least element, whether it has non-finitely axiomatisable SP-logics, and whether there is a continuum of them. As we saw above, any SP-logic different from P S4.3 belongs to some finite slice. In Fig. 2, we show slice 1 and a part of slice 2 (to minimise clutter, we only give the frames or SLOs determining modal and SP-logics; as before, indicates incomplete SP-logics). The structure of slice 1 was detailed in [15]. As shown in [16], it has two incomplete SP-logics: P [S] and P [E 1 ], where S

13 Kikot, Kurucz, Wolter, Zakharyaschev 13 is a SLO with two elements a such that a = =, and E 1 is on p. 4. Note that µ ( P [S] ) is inconsistent, while µ 1( L[(1)] ) = { P [(1)], P [E 1 ] }. Slice 2 is much more involved. Its sublattice of Kripke complete logics comprises the SP-logics of the form P [C], where C is a finite set of frames of depth 2 at least one of which is of depth 2. As shown in Section 3, modal logics L[C] of slice 2 typically have infinitely many SP-companions in µ 1 (L); see Fig. 1. On the other hand, Example 5.4 shows SP-logics with multiple modal companions. NExtS4.3 Ext + P S4.3 µ S (1) (2) (3) (ω) π (1, 1) (2), (1, 1) (3), (1, 1) (2, 1) (ω), (1, 1) π 1 (P [(2, 1)]) (2), (2, 1) (3, 1) (2), (3, 1) (3), (3, 1) π 1 (P [(3, 1)]) (ω, 1) µ π (1) π (2) E 1 µ 1 (L[(1)]) (3) (ω) (1, 1) (2), (1, 1) (3), (1, 1) (ω), (1, 1) π (3, 1) π µ (ω, 1) µ 1 (L[(1, 1)]) µ 1 (L[(2), (1, 1)]) Fig. 2. Modal and SP-logics of slices 1 and 2. 6 SP-rules An SP-rule, ϱ, takes the form ι1,...,ιn ι, where ι 1,, ι n, ι are SP-implications. We say that ϱ is valid in a SLO A and write A = ϱ if A satisfies the quasiequation (ι 1 ι n) ι, where (σ τ) = (σ τ = σ). We identify the rule ι with ι. Given a set R of SP-rules and an SP-rule ϱ, we set R = SLO ι if A = ϱ for any SLO A validating every rule in R. We denote by R[A] the set of SP-rules that are valid in A and, for a frame F, set R[F] = R[F ]. For a class C of SLOs (or frames), we define the SP-rule logic R[C] of C as the intersection of all R[A] with A C. Clearly, there is a one-to-one correspondence between SP-rule logics and quasi-varieties of SLOs. The minimal SP-rule logic R containing P S4.3 and a set Φ of SP-rules is denoted by P S4.3 + Φ. We call R globally complete in case ϱ P S4.3 + Φ iff ϱ R[F] for any frame F validating all rules in R. If Φ is a set of SP-implications, then P S4.3 + Φ is complete whenever it is globally complete. However, the converse only holds for two non-trivial SP-logics containing P S4.3 (see appendix for the proof): Theorem 6.1 A non-trivial P Ext + P S4.3 is globally complete iff P is complex iff P {P S5, P [(1)]}.

14 14 On Strictly Positive Modal Logics with S4.3 Frames It follows that the axiomatisations of SP-logics given above do not provide axiomatisations of the corresponding SP-rule logics, except for two cases. This is in sharp contrast to normal modal logics containing S4.3 where the introduction of rules does not extend the expressive power of formulas as any rule ϱ = ι1,...,ιn ι can be equivalently expressed by the formula (ι 1 ι n ) ι. We next observe that SP-rules have sufficient expressive power to define any modally definable class of S4.3-frames: Theorem 6.2 For every finite S4.3-frame F, there is an SP-rule ϱ(f) such that, for any S4.3-frame G, we have G = ϱ(f) iff F is a p-morphic image of G. Proof. Let F = (W, R) be a finite S4.3-frame with root r. For each x W, take a variable p x and the following set F of SP-implications: p x p y if R(x, y), p x p y q if R(x, y), p x p y q for x y, p y for y in the final cluster of F. Let F ϱ(f) = p r q It is straightforward to show that ϱ(f) is as required. Corollary 6.3 A class of frames is modally definable iff it is SP-rule definable. We now return to the axiomatisation problem for SP-rule logics. The SLOs on p. 4 show that the rules from Theorem 6.2 do not axiomatise globally complete SP-rule logics. Here, we give an axiomatisation of R[(2)], which can be easily generalised to any R[(n)] with n > 2. Consider the rules ϱ 1 = (a c i), (a (c i c j ) b), 1 i j 3 a b ϱ 2 = (c 1 b), (c 2 b), (a c 1 ), (a c 2 ), (a (c 1 c 2 ) b) a b ϱ 3 = (a c 1), (a c 2 ), (c 1 b), (a (c 1 c 2 ) b), (a (a c 2 ) b) a b It is easy to see that a cluster (n) validates all the ϱ i iff n 2. Thus, restricted to the set of clusters, each rule ϱ i defines the intended class of frames. Let R (2) = P S5 + {ϱ 1, ϱ 2, ϱ 3 }. The proof of the following theorem is given in the appendix: Theorem 6.4 (i) R (2) = R[(2)]. (ii) P S5 + Φ R[(2)], for any proper subset Φ of {ϱ 1, ϱ 2, ϱ 3 }. The computational complexity of deciding R[C] has been analysed in [17]. In contrast to SP-implications, deciding SP-rules is often conp-hard. In fact, if C is a non-empty class of S4.3-frames of the form Fr(P ) for an SP-logic P Ext + P S4.3, then R[C] is in PTime iff C is the class of all clusters or a singleton cluster. Otherwise, R[C] is conp-complete.

15 Kikot, Kurucz, Wolter, Zakharyaschev 15 References [1] Baader, F., S. Brandt and C. Lutz, Pushing the EL envelope, in: Procs. of IJCAI (2005), pp [2] Beklemishev, L., Calibrating provability logic: from modal logic to reflection calculus, in: Advances in Modal Logic, vol. 9, College Publications, 2012 pp [3] Beklemishev, L., Positive provability logic for uniform reflection principles, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 165 (2014), pp [4] Beklemishev, L., A note on strictly positive logics and word rewriting systems (2015), corr abs/ [5] Birkhoff, G., On the structure of abstract algebras, Proc. Cambridge Phil. Soc. 31 (1935), pp [6] Bull, R., That all normal extensions of S4.3 have the finite model property, Zeitschrift für Mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 12 (1966), pp [7] Chagrov, A. and M. Zakharyaschev, Modal Logic, Oxford Logic Guides 35, [8] Dashkov, E., On the positive fragment of the polymodal provability logic GLP, Mathematical Notes 91 (2012), pp [9] Davey, B., M. Jackson, J. Pitkethly and M. Talukder, Natural dualities for three classes of relational structures, Algebra Universalis (2007), pp [10] Fine, K., The logics containing S4.3, Zeitschrift für Mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 17 (1971), pp [11] Fine, K., Logics containing K4, part II, Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (1985), pp [12] Goldblatt, R., Varieties of complex algebras, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 44 (1989), pp [13] Grätzer, G., Universal Algebra, Springer, 1979, 2nd edition. [14] Hosoi, T., On intermediate logics, Journal of the Faculty of Science, University of Tokyo 14 (1967), pp [15] Jackson, M., Semilattices with closure, Algebra Universalis 52 (2004), pp [16] Kikot, S., A. Kurucz, Y. Tanaka, F. Wolter and M. Zakharyaschev, Kripke completeness of strictly positive modal logics over meet-semilattices with operators, CoRR abs/ (2017). URL [17] Kurucz, A., F. Wolter and M. Zakharyaschev, Islands of tractability for relational constraints: towards dichotomy results for the description logic EL, in: Advances in Modal Logic, vol. 8 (2010), pp [18] Maksimova, L., Modal logics of finite slices, Algebra and Logic 14 (1975), pp [19] Maksimova, L. and V. Rybakov, Lattices of modal logics, Algebra and Logic 13 (1974), pp [20] Sahlqvist, H., Completeness and correspondence in the first and second order semantics for modal logic, in: Procs. of the 3rd Scandinavian Logic Symposium, 1975 pp [21] Sofronie-Stokkermans, V., Locality and subsumption testing in EL and some of its extensions, in: Advances in Modal Logic, vol. 7 (2008), pp [22] Spaan, E., Complexity of Modal Logics, Ph.D. thesis, Department of Mathematics and Computer Science, University of Amsterdam (1993). [23] Zakharyaschev, M., Canonical formulas for K4. Part II: Cofinal subframe logics, Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (1996), pp

16 16 On Strictly Positive Modal Logics with S4.3 Frames Appendix A 1 A 2 n n n B n C n D n Fig. 3. SLOs validating P 2 fun. L[ C] L[C] = L π 1 (P ) µ π µ 1 (L) P = P [C] Fig. 4. Maps π and µ.

17 Kikot, Kurucz, Wolter, Zakharyaschev 17 Proof of Theorem 6.1 The first equivalence is shown in [16]. For the second one, it is known from [16] that P S5 and P [(1)] are complex. Conversely, let P {P S5, P [(1)]}. Suppose first that (1, 1) Fr(P ). Then the SLO C 1 on p. 4 validates P but there is no frame F Fr(P S4.3 ) such that C 1 is embeddable into F. Thus, P is not complex. Now suppose (1, 1) Fr(P ). Then P P S5 and there exists a minimal n > 2 such that (n) Fr(P ). Then the SLO E n on p. 4 validates P but there is no frame F Fr(P ) such that E n is embeddable into F. Proof of Theorem 6.4 (ii) Take E 3 on p. 4 and A 3 and A 4 shown below: A 3 A 4 Then E 3, A 3, A 4 all validate P S5 and E 3 = ϱ 1, but E 3 = ϱ 2, ϱ 3 ; A 3 = ϱ 2, but A 3 = ϱ 1, ϱ 3 ; A 4 = ϱ 3, but A 4 = ϱ 1, ϱ 2. For (i), it suffices to provide an embedding of any SLO A with A = R (2) into F, for a union F of two-element clusters. Recall that a filter F in A is a subset of A containing and such that a F and a b imply b F and a, b F imply a b F. For a filter F in A, we set F = { a a F } and define F = (W, R) using a set X of pairs of filters in A. Let (F 1, F 2 ) X if F 1, F 2 are filters in A such that F 1 F 2 and F 2 F 1 ; if F 1 F or F 2 F for a filter F, then F 1 F or F 2 F. For any w = (F 1, F 2 ) X, take fresh 1 w and 2 w and set W = {1 w, 2 w w X }, R = {(1 w, 2 w ), (1 w, 1 w ), (2 w, 2 w ), (2 w, 1 w ) w X }. By definition, F = (W, R) is a union of two-element clusters. We now embed A into F. We show that f(a) = {1 F1,F 2 a F 1 } {2 F1,F 2 a F 2 } is an embedding. We first show that if a b, then f(a) f(b). We may assume that a b. Let F 0 be a maximal filter containing a such that b F 0. We show that there exists a pair (F 1, F 2 ) X with a F 1 and b F 1. Let M be the set of all maximal filters G in A such that G F 0 and F 0 G. Observe that there exists a filter G M containing a set X A iff (a 1 a n ) F 0 for all a 1,, a n X. It follows that, for every filter F in A with F 0 F, there exists G M with F G. We now make a case

18 18 On Strictly Positive Modal Logics with S4.3 Frames distinction according to the cardinality of M. M = 1. Let M = {G}. Then G F 0 and (F 0, G) X. We have a F 0 and b F 0, as required. M = 2. Let M = {G 0, G 1 }. We distinguish two cases: Case 1: G 0, G 1 F 0. Since neither G 0 G 1 nor G 1 G 0, we obtain G 0 F 0 and G 1 F 0. Thus, b G 0 G 1. Then we find c 1 G 0 and c 2 G 1 and a F 0 such that a (c 1 c 2) b. Then, using the condition that filters are closed under, we find c 1 G 0, c 2 G 1, and a F 0 such that c 1 b, c 2 b, a c 1, a c 2, and a (c 1 c 2 ) b. By rule ϱ 2, a b, and we have derived a contradiction as b F 0 follows. Case 2: G 1 F 0. Then G 0 F 0 as there exists at least one filter G M with G F 0. Assume first that G 0 F 0. Then b G 0. Similarly to Case 1 we thus find c 1 G 0, c 2 G 1, and a F 0 such that a c 1, a c 2, c 1 b, a (c 1 c 2 ) b, and a (a c 2 ) b. But then, by rule ϱ 3, a b, and we have derived a contradiction. Assume now that G 0 = F 0. Then (F 0, G 1 ) X. We are done as a F 0 and b F 0. M 3. Let G 0, G 1, G 2 M. Then we find a F 0, c 1 G 0, c 2 G 1, and c 3 G 2 such that a c i for 1 i 3 and a (c i c j ) b for 1 i j 3. But then a b, by rule ϱ 1, and we have derived a contradiction. We next show that f( a) = f(a) for all a A. Suppose first 1 F1,F 2 f(a). Then a F 1 or a F 2. Then a F 1. Then 1 F1,F 2 f( a), as required. Conversely, suppose 1 F1,F 2 f( a). Then a F 1. Then there exists a filter F with a F and F 1 F and F F 1. By definition, F 1 F or F 2 F. Thus 1 F1,F 2 f(a). Finally, f(a 1 a 2 ) = f(a 1 ) f(a 2 ) can we proved in a straightforward way.

On Strictly Positive Modal Logics with S4.3 Frames

On Strictly Positive Modal Logics with S4.3 Frames On Strictly Positive Modal Logics with S4.3 Frames Stanislav Kikot Department of Computer Science and Information Systems Birkbeck, University of London, U.K. Agi Kurucz Department of Informatics King

More information

De Jongh s characterization of intuitionistic propositional calculus

De Jongh s characterization of intuitionistic propositional calculus De Jongh s characterization of intuitionistic propositional calculus Nick Bezhanishvili Abstract In his PhD thesis [10] Dick de Jongh proved a syntactic characterization of intuitionistic propositional

More information

2 S. KIKOT, A. KURUCZ, Y. TANAKA, F. WOLTER, AND M. ZAKHARYASCHEV

2 S. KIKOT, A. KURUCZ, Y. TANAKA, F. WOLTER, AND M. ZAKHARYASCHEV KRIPKE COMPLETENESS OF STRICTLY POSITIVE MODAL LOGICS OVER MEET-SEMILATTICES WITH OPERATORS arxiv:1708.03403v2 [cs.lo] 11 Nov 2018 STANISLAV KIKOT, AGI KURUCZ, YOSHIHITO TANAKA, FRANK WOLTER, AND MICHAEL

More information

ALL NORMAL EXTENSIONS OF S5-SQUARED ARE FINITELY AXIOMATIZABLE

ALL NORMAL EXTENSIONS OF S5-SQUARED ARE FINITELY AXIOMATIZABLE ALL NORMAL EXTENSIONS OF S5-SQUARED ARE FINITELY AXIOMATIZABLE Nick Bezhanishvili and Ian Hodkinson Abstract We prove that every normal extension of the bi-modal system S5 2 is finitely axiomatizable and

More information

arxiv: v4 [math.lo] 6 Apr 2018

arxiv: v4 [math.lo] 6 Apr 2018 Complexity of the interpretability logic IL arxiv:1710.05599v4 [math.lo] 6 Apr 2018 Luka Mikec luka.mikec@math.hr Fedor Pakhomov pakhfn@mi.ras.ru Monday 2 nd April, 2018 Abstract Mladen Vuković vukovic@math.hr

More information

COMBINING MODAL LOGICS

COMBINING MODAL LOGICS 15 COMBINING MODAL LOGICS Agi Kurucz 1 Introduction............................................... 1 2 Fusion of modal logics.......................................... 4 2.1 Transfer results...........................................

More information

Modal and temporal logic

Modal and temporal logic Modal and temporal logic N. Bezhanishvili I. Hodkinson C. Kupke Imperial College London 1 / 83 Overview Part II 1 Soundness and completeness. Canonical models. 3 lectures. 2 Finite model property. Filtrations.

More information

From Syllogism to Common Sense

From Syllogism to Common Sense From Syllogism to Common Sense Mehul Bhatt Oliver Kutz Thomas Schneider Department of Computer Science & Research Center on Spatial Cognition (SFB/TR 8) University of Bremen Normal Modal Logic K r i p

More information

Canonicity and representable relation algebras

Canonicity and representable relation algebras Canonicity and representable relation algebras Ian Hodkinson Joint work with: Rob Goldblatt Robin Hirsch Yde Venema What am I going to do? In the 1960s, Monk proved that the variety RRA of representable

More information

ON MODAL LOGICS BETWEEN K K K AND S5 S5 S5

ON MODAL LOGICS BETWEEN K K K AND S5 S5 S5 ON MODAL LOGICS BETWEEN K K K AND S5 S5 S5 R. HIRSCH, I. HODKINSON AND A. KURUCZ Abstract. We prove that every n-modal logic between K n and S5 n is undecidable, whenever n 3. We also show that each of

More information

Varieties of Heyting algebras and superintuitionistic logics

Varieties of Heyting algebras and superintuitionistic logics Varieties of Heyting algebras and superintuitionistic logics Nick Bezhanishvili Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam http://www.phil.uu.nl/~bezhanishvili email: N.Bezhanishvili@uva.nl

More information

THE EQUATIONAL THEORIES OF REPRESENTABLE RESIDUATED SEMIGROUPS

THE EQUATIONAL THEORIES OF REPRESENTABLE RESIDUATED SEMIGROUPS TH QUATIONAL THORIS OF RPRSNTABL RSIDUATD SMIGROUPS SZABOLCS MIKULÁS Abstract. We show that the equational theory of representable lower semilattice-ordered residuated semigroups is finitely based. We

More information

Model Theory of Modal Logic Lecture 5. Valentin Goranko Technical University of Denmark

Model Theory of Modal Logic Lecture 5. Valentin Goranko Technical University of Denmark Model Theory of Modal Logic Lecture 5 Valentin Goranko Technical University of Denmark Third Indian School on Logic and its Applications Hyderabad, January 29, 2010 Model Theory of Modal Logic Lecture

More information

Hypersequent Calculi for some Intermediate Logics with Bounded Kripke Models

Hypersequent Calculi for some Intermediate Logics with Bounded Kripke Models Hypersequent Calculi for some Intermediate Logics with Bounded Kripke Models Agata Ciabattoni Mauro Ferrari Abstract In this paper we define cut-free hypersequent calculi for some intermediate logics semantically

More information

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Keith A. Kearnes and Greg Oman Abstract. We show that if P is an infinite poset whose proper order ideals have cardinality strictly less than P, and κ is a cardinal

More information

MONADIC FRAGMENTS OF INTUITIONISTIC CONTROL LOGIC

MONADIC FRAGMENTS OF INTUITIONISTIC CONTROL LOGIC Bulletin of the Section of Logic Volume 45:3/4 (2016), pp. 143 153 http://dx.doi.org/10.18778/0138-0680.45.3.4.01 Anna Glenszczyk MONADIC FRAGMENTS OF INTUITIONISTIC CONTROL LOGIC Abstract We investigate

More information

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year Part II Year 2018 2017 2016 2015 2014 2013 2012 2011 2010 2009 2008 2007 2006 2005 2018 60 Paper 4, Section II 16G State and prove the ǫ-recursion Theorem. [You may assume the Principle of ǫ- Induction.]

More information

Representable Cylindric Algebras and Many-Dimensional Modal Logics

Representable Cylindric Algebras and Many-Dimensional Modal Logics Representable Cylindric Algebras and Many-Dimensional Modal Logics Agi Kurucz Department of Informatics King s College London agi.kurucz@kcl.ac.uk The equationally expressible properties of the cylindrifications

More information

Axiomatisation of Hybrid Logic

Axiomatisation of Hybrid Logic Imperial College London Department of Computing Axiomatisation of Hybrid Logic by Louis Paternault Submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the MSc Degree in Advanced Computing of Imperial

More information

Stable formulas in intuitionistic logic

Stable formulas in intuitionistic logic Stable formulas in intuitionistic logic Nick Bezhanishvili and Dick de Jongh August 14, 2014 Abstract NNIL-formulas are propositional formulas that do not allow nesting of implication to the left. These

More information

A generalization of modal definability

A generalization of modal definability A generalization of modal definability Tin Perkov Polytechnic of Zagreb Abstract. Known results on global definability in basic modal logic are generalized in the following sense. A class of Kripke models

More information

Canonical models for normal logics (Completeness via canonicity)

Canonical models for normal logics (Completeness via canonicity) 499 Modal and Temporal Logic Canonical models for normal logics (Completeness via canonicity) Marek Sergot Department of Computing Imperial College, London Autumn 2008 Further reading: B.F. Chellas, Modal

More information

Technical Modal Logic

Technical Modal Logic Technical Modal Logic Marcus Kracht Fakultät LiLi Universität Bielefeld Postfach 10 01 31 D-33501 Bielefeld marcus.kracht@uni-bielefeld.de December 17, 2009 Abstract Modal logic is concerned with the analysis

More information

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.lo] 5 Mar 2007

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.lo] 5 Mar 2007 Topological Semantics and Decidability Dmitry Sustretov arxiv:math/0703106v1 [math.lo] 5 Mar 2007 March 6, 2008 Abstract It is well-known that the basic modal logic of all topological spaces is S4. However,

More information

Systems of modal logic

Systems of modal logic 499 Modal and Temporal Logic Systems of modal logic Marek Sergot Department of Computing Imperial College, London utumn 2008 Further reading: B.F. Chellas, Modal logic: an introduction. Cambridge University

More information

On the Craig interpolation and the fixed point

On the Craig interpolation and the fixed point On the Craig interpolation and the fixed point property for GLP Lev D. Beklemishev December 11, 2007 Abstract We prove the Craig interpolation and the fixed point property for GLP by finitary methods.

More information

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007)

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω 0. Introduction David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) In its simplest form the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem for L ω1 ω states that if σ L ω1

More information

Axioms of separation

Axioms of separation Axioms of separation These notes discuss the same topic as Sections 31, 32, 33, 34, 35, and also 7, 10 of Munkres book. Some notions (hereditarily normal, perfectly normal, collectionwise normal, monotonically

More information

A Remark on Propositional Kripke Frames Sound for Intuitionistic Logic

A Remark on Propositional Kripke Frames Sound for Intuitionistic Logic A Remark on Propositional Kripke Frames Sound for Intuitionistic Logic Dmitrij Skvortsov All-Russian Institute of Scientific and Technical Information, VINITI Russian Academy of Science Usievicha, 20,

More information

A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries

A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries Johannes Marti and Riccardo Pinosio Draft from April 5, 2018 Abstract In this paper we present a duality between nonmonotonic

More information

Logics above S4 and the Lebesgue measure algebra

Logics above S4 and the Lebesgue measure algebra Logics above S4 and the Lebesgue measure algebra Tamar Lando Abstract We study the measure semantics for propositional modal logics, in which formulas are interpreted in the Lebesgue measure algebra M,

More information

Tractable Extensions of the Description Logic EL with Numerical Datatypes

Tractable Extensions of the Description Logic EL with Numerical Datatypes Tractable Extensions of the Description Logic EL with Numerical Datatypes Despoina Magka, Yevgeny Kazakov, and Ian Horrocks Oxford University Computing Laboratory Wolfson Building, Parks Road, OXFORD,

More information

Madhavan Mukund Chennai Mathematical Institute

Madhavan Mukund Chennai Mathematical Institute AN INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC Madhavan Mukund Chennai Mathematical Institute E-mail: madhavan@cmiacin Abstract ese are lecture notes for an introductory course on logic aimed at graduate students in Computer

More information

Modal Logic of Forcing Classes

Modal Logic of Forcing Classes Outline CUNY Graduate Center Department of Mathematics March 11, 2016 Outline Outline 1 Outline 1 Modal Logic Background Modal Axioms K (ϕ ψ) ( ϕ ψ) T ϕ ϕ 4 ϕ ϕ.2 ϕ ϕ.3 ( ϕ ψ) [(ϕ ψ) (ψ ϕ)] 5 ϕ ϕ Modal

More information

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES ITAY NEEMAN Abstract. We present an approach to forcing with finite sequences of models that uses models of two types. This approach builds on earlier work

More information

The modal logic of forcing

The modal logic of forcing Joel David Hamkins New York University, Philosophy The City University of New York, Mathematics College of Staten Island of CUNY The CUNY Graduate Center London, August 5 6, 2011 This is joint work with

More information

Inquisitive Logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Ivano Ciardelli Floris Roelofsen

Inquisitive Logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Ivano Ciardelli Floris Roelofsen Journal of Philosophical Logic manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Inquisitive Logic Ivano Ciardelli Floris Roelofsen Received: 26 August 2009 / Accepted: 1 July 2010 Abstract This paper investigates

More information

Atom structures and Sahlqvist equations

Atom structures and Sahlqvist equations Atom structures and Sahlqvist equations Yde Venema Department of Mathematics and Computer Science Vrije Universiteit De Boelelaan 1081 1081 HV Amsterdam July 28, 1997 Abstract This paper addresses the

More information

Keywords: Boolean algebras with operators, modal logic, random graphs, canonical extension, elementary class, variety.

Keywords: Boolean algebras with operators, modal logic, random graphs, canonical extension, elementary class, variety. ERDŐS GRAPHS RESOLVE FINE S CANONICITY PROBLEM ROBERT GOLDBLATT, IAN HODKINSON, AND YDE VENEMA Abstract. We show that there exist 2 ℵ 0 equational classes of Boolean algebras with operators that are not

More information

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved. Topology Proceedings Web: http://topology.auburn.edu/tp/ Mail: Topology Proceedings Department of Mathematics & Statistics Auburn University, Alabama 36849, USA E-mail: topolog@auburn.edu ISSN: 0146-4124

More information

Modal systems based on many-valued logics

Modal systems based on many-valued logics Modal systems based on many-valued logics F. Bou IIIA - CSIC Campus UAB s/n 08193, Bellaterra, Spain fbou@iiia.csic.es F. Esteva IIIA - CSIC Campus UAB s/n 08193, Bellaterra, Spain esteva@iiia.csic.es

More information

Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G. Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21

Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G. Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21 Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21 Introduction These notes were originally prepared in July 1972 as a handout for a class in modern algebra taught at the Carnegie-Mellon

More information

On Jankov-de Jongh formulas

On Jankov-de Jongh formulas On Jankov-de Jongh formulas Nick Bezhanishvili Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam http://www.phil.uu.nl/~bezhanishvili The Heyting day dedicated to Dick de Jongh and

More information

DENSELY k-separable COMPACTA ARE DENSELY SEPARABLE

DENSELY k-separable COMPACTA ARE DENSELY SEPARABLE DENSELY k-separable COMPACTA ARE DENSELY SEPARABLE ALAN DOW AND ISTVÁN JUHÁSZ Abstract. A space has σ-compact tightness if the closures of σ-compact subsets determines the topology. We consider a dense

More information

SUBLATTICES OF LATTICES OF ORDER-CONVEX SETS, III. THE CASE OF TOTALLY ORDERED SETS

SUBLATTICES OF LATTICES OF ORDER-CONVEX SETS, III. THE CASE OF TOTALLY ORDERED SETS SUBLATTICES OF LATTICES OF ORDER-CONVEX SETS, III. THE CASE OF TOTALLY ORDERED SETS MARINA SEMENOVA AND FRIEDRICH WEHRUNG Abstract. For a partially ordered set P, let Co(P) denote the lattice of all order-convex

More information

The McKinsey Lemmon logic is barely canonical

The McKinsey Lemmon logic is barely canonical The McKinsey Lemmon logic is barely canonical Robert Goldblatt and Ian Hodkinson July 18, 2006 Abstract We study a canonical modal logic introduced by Lemmon, and axiomatised by an infinite sequence of

More information

Recursive definitions on surreal numbers

Recursive definitions on surreal numbers Recursive definitions on surreal numbers Antongiulio Fornasiero 19th July 2005 Abstract Let No be Conway s class of surreal numbers. I will make explicit the notion of a function f on No recursively defined

More information

REPRESENTATION THEOREMS FOR IMPLICATION STRUCTURES

REPRESENTATION THEOREMS FOR IMPLICATION STRUCTURES Wojciech Buszkowski REPRESENTATION THEOREMS FOR IMPLICATION STRUCTURES Professor Rasiowa [HR49] considers implication algebras (A,, V ) such that is a binary operation on the universe A and V A. In particular,

More information

Applied Logic. Lecture 1 - Propositional logic. Marcin Szczuka. Institute of Informatics, The University of Warsaw

Applied Logic. Lecture 1 - Propositional logic. Marcin Szczuka. Institute of Informatics, The University of Warsaw Applied Logic Lecture 1 - Propositional logic Marcin Szczuka Institute of Informatics, The University of Warsaw Monographic lecture, Spring semester 2017/2018 Marcin Szczuka (MIMUW) Applied Logic 2018

More information

Fuzzy Description Logics

Fuzzy Description Logics Fuzzy Description Logics 1. Introduction to Description Logics Rafael Peñaloza Rende, January 2016 Literature Description Logics Baader, Calvanese, McGuinness, Nardi, Patel-Schneider (eds.) The Description

More information

More Model Theory Notes

More Model Theory Notes More Model Theory Notes Miscellaneous information, loosely organized. 1. Kinds of Models A countable homogeneous model M is one such that, for any partial elementary map f : A M with A M finite, and any

More information

Generalized Pigeonhole Properties of Graphs and Oriented Graphs

Generalized Pigeonhole Properties of Graphs and Oriented Graphs Europ. J. Combinatorics (2002) 23, 257 274 doi:10.1006/eujc.2002.0574 Available online at http://www.idealibrary.com on Generalized Pigeonhole Properties of Graphs and Oriented Graphs ANTHONY BONATO, PETER

More information

A Note on Graded Modal Logic

A Note on Graded Modal Logic A Note on Graded Modal Logic Maarten de Rijke Studia Logica, vol. 64 (2000), pp. 271 283 Abstract We introduce a notion of bisimulation for graded modal logic. Using these bisimulations the model theory

More information

Logics for Compact Hausdorff Spaces via de Vries Duality

Logics for Compact Hausdorff Spaces via de Vries Duality Logics for Compact Hausdorff Spaces via de Vries Duality Thomas Santoli ILLC, Universiteit van Amsterdam June 16, 2016 Outline Main goal: developing a propositional calculus for compact Hausdorff spaces

More information

The Absoluteness of Constructibility

The Absoluteness of Constructibility Lecture: The Absoluteness of Constructibility We would like to show that L is a model of V = L, or, more precisely, that L is an interpretation of ZF + V = L in ZF. We have already verified that σ L holds

More information

Solutions to Unique Readability Homework Set 30 August 2011

Solutions to Unique Readability Homework Set 30 August 2011 s to Unique Readability Homework Set 30 August 2011 In the problems below L is a signature and X is a set of variables. Problem 0. Define a function λ from the set of finite nonempty sequences of elements

More information

Modularity in DL-Lite

Modularity in DL-Lite Modularity in DL-Lite Roman Kontchakov 1, Frank Wolter 2, and Michael Zakharyaschev 1 1 School of Computer Science and Information Systems, Birkbeck College, London, {roman,michael}@dcs.bbk.ac.uk 2 Department

More information

Abstract model theory for extensions of modal logic

Abstract model theory for extensions of modal logic Abstract model theory for extensions of modal logic Balder ten Cate Stanford, May 13, 2008 Largely based on joint work with Johan van Benthem and Jouko Väänänen Balder ten Cate Abstract model theory for

More information

Positive provability logic

Positive provability logic Positive provability logic Lev Beklemishev Steklov Mathematical Institute Russian Academy of Sciences, Moscow November 12, 2013 Strictly positive modal formulas The language of modal logic extends that

More information

Axiomatizing hybrid logic using modal logic

Axiomatizing hybrid logic using modal logic Axiomatizing hybrid logic using modal logic Ian Hodkinson Department of Computing Imperial College London London SW7 2AZ United Kingdom imh@doc.ic.ac.uk Louis Paternault 4 rue de l hôpital 74800 La Roche

More information

Existential definability of modal frame classes

Existential definability of modal frame classes Existential definability of modal frame classes Tin Perkov Polytechnic of Zagreb, Croatia tin.perkov@tvz.hr Abstract. A class of Kripke frames is called modally definable if there is a set of modal formulas

More information

SUBALGEBRAS AND HOMOMORPHIC IMAGES OF THE RIEGER-NISHIMURA LATTICE

SUBALGEBRAS AND HOMOMORPHIC IMAGES OF THE RIEGER-NISHIMURA LATTICE SUBALGEBRAS AND HOMOMORPHIC IMAGES OF THE RIEGER-NISHIMURA LATTICE Guram Bezhanishvili and Revaz Grigolia Abstract In this note we characterize all subalgebras and homomorphic images of the free cyclic

More information

On minimal models of the Region Connection Calculus

On minimal models of the Region Connection Calculus Fundamenta Informaticae 69 (2006) 1 20 1 IOS Press On minimal models of the Region Connection Calculus Lirong Xia State Key Laboratory of Intelligent Technology and Systems Department of Computer Science

More information

On the Structure of Rough Approximations

On the Structure of Rough Approximations On the Structure of Rough Approximations (Extended Abstract) Jouni Järvinen Turku Centre for Computer Science (TUCS) Lemminkäisenkatu 14 A, FIN-20520 Turku, Finland jjarvine@cs.utu.fi Abstract. We study

More information

Non-primitive recursive decidability of products of modal logics with expanding domains

Non-primitive recursive decidability of products of modal logics with expanding domains Non-primitive recursive decidability of products of modal logics with expanding domains D. Gabelaia, A. Kurucz, F. Wolter and M. Zakharyaschev Department of Computer Science King s College London Strand,

More information

Informal Statement Calculus

Informal Statement Calculus FOUNDATIONS OF MATHEMATICS Branches of Logic 1. Theory of Computations (i.e. Recursion Theory). 2. Proof Theory. 3. Model Theory. 4. Set Theory. Informal Statement Calculus STATEMENTS AND CONNECTIVES Example

More information

Equational Logic. Chapter Syntax Terms and Term Algebras

Equational Logic. Chapter Syntax Terms and Term Algebras Chapter 2 Equational Logic 2.1 Syntax 2.1.1 Terms and Term Algebras The natural logic of algebra is equational logic, whose propositions are universally quantified identities between terms built up from

More information

KRIPKE S THEORY OF TRUTH 1. INTRODUCTION

KRIPKE S THEORY OF TRUTH 1. INTRODUCTION KRIPKE S THEORY OF TRUTH RICHARD G HECK, JR 1. INTRODUCTION The purpose of this note is to give a simple, easily accessible proof of the existence of the minimal fixed point, and of various maximal fixed

More information

Standard Bayes logic is not finitely axiomatizable

Standard Bayes logic is not finitely axiomatizable Standard Bayes logic is not finitely axiomatizable Zalán Gyenis January 6, 2018 Abstract In the paper [2] a hierarchy of modal logics have been defined to capture the logical features of Bayesian belief

More information

SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS

SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS NATHAN BOWLER AND STEFAN GESCHKE Abstract. We extend the notion of a uniform matroid to the infinitary case and construct, using weak fragments of Martin s Axiom,

More information

EMBEDDING DISTRIBUTIVE LATTICES IN THE Σ 0 2 ENUMERATION DEGREES

EMBEDDING DISTRIBUTIVE LATTICES IN THE Σ 0 2 ENUMERATION DEGREES EMBEDDING DISTRIBUTIVE LATTICES IN THE Σ 0 2 ENUMERATION DEGREES HRISTO GANCHEV AND MARIYA SOSKOVA 1. Introduction The local structure of the enumeration degrees G e is the partially ordered set of the

More information

An Algebraic View of the Relation between Largest Common Subtrees and Smallest Common Supertrees

An Algebraic View of the Relation between Largest Common Subtrees and Smallest Common Supertrees An Algebraic View of the Relation between Largest Common Subtrees and Smallest Common Supertrees Francesc Rosselló 1, Gabriel Valiente 2 1 Department of Mathematics and Computer Science, Research Institute

More information

Finitely generated free Heyting algebras; the well-founded initial segment

Finitely generated free Heyting algebras; the well-founded initial segment Finitely generated free Heyting algebras; the well-founded initial segment R. Elageili and J.K. Truss Department of Pure Mathematics, University of Leeds, Leeds LS2 9JT, UK e-mail yazid98rajab@yahoo.com,

More information

ON DEFINABILITY IN MULTIMODAL LOGIC

ON DEFINABILITY IN MULTIMODAL LOGIC THE REVIEW OF SYMBOLIC LOGIC Volume 2, Number 3, September 2009 ON DEFINABILITY IN MULTIMODAL LOGIC JOSEPH Y. HALPERN Computer Science Department, Cornell University DOV SAMET The Faculty of Management,

More information

Part II Logic and Set Theory

Part II Logic and Set Theory Part II Logic and Set Theory Theorems Based on lectures by I. B. Leader Notes taken by Dexter Chua Lent 2015 These notes are not endorsed by the lecturers, and I have modified them (often significantly)

More information

Lecture 11: Minimal types

Lecture 11: Minimal types MODEL THEORY OF ARITHMETIC Lecture 11: Minimal types Tin Lok Wong 17 December, 2014 Uniform extension operators are used to construct models with nice structural properties Thus, one has a very simple

More information

Vietoris bisimulations

Vietoris bisimulations Vietoris bisimulations N. Bezhanishvili, G. Fontaine and Y. Venema July 17, 2008 Abstract Building on the fact that descriptive frames are coalgebras for the Vietoris functor on the category of Stone spaces,

More information

Weak Choice Principles and Forcing Axioms

Weak Choice Principles and Forcing Axioms Weak Choice Principles and Forcing Axioms Elizabeth Lauri 1 Introduction Faculty Mentor: David Fernandez Breton Forcing is a technique that was discovered by Cohen in the mid 20th century, and it is particularly

More information

Role-depth Bounded Least Common Subsumers by Completion for EL- and Prob-EL-TBoxes

Role-depth Bounded Least Common Subsumers by Completion for EL- and Prob-EL-TBoxes Role-depth Bounded Least Common Subsumers by Completion for EL- and Prob-EL-TBoxes Rafael Peñaloza and Anni-Yasmin Turhan TU Dresden, Institute for Theoretical Computer Science Abstract. The least common

More information

A MODEL-THEORETIC PROOF OF HILBERT S NULLSTELLENSATZ

A MODEL-THEORETIC PROOF OF HILBERT S NULLSTELLENSATZ A MODEL-THEORETIC PROOF OF HILBERT S NULLSTELLENSATZ NICOLAS FORD Abstract. The goal of this paper is to present a proof of the Nullstellensatz using tools from a branch of logic called model theory. In

More information

SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS

SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS SYLVIA DURIAN Abstract. This paper develops the ordinal numbers and transfinite induction, then demonstrates some interesting applications of transfinite induction.

More information

Monodic fragments of first-order temporal logics

Monodic fragments of first-order temporal logics Outline of talk Most propositional temporal logics are decidable. But the decision problem in predicate (first-order) temporal logics has seemed near-hopeless. Monodic fragments of first-order temporal

More information

A proof of topological completeness for S4 in (0,1)

A proof of topological completeness for S4 in (0,1) A proof of topological completeness for S4 in (,) Grigori Mints and Ting Zhang 2 Philosophy Department, Stanford University mints@csli.stanford.edu 2 Computer Science Department, Stanford University tingz@cs.stanford.edu

More information

Foundations of non-commutative probability theory

Foundations of non-commutative probability theory Foundations of non-commutative probability theory Daniel Lehmann School of Engineering and Center for the Study of Rationality Hebrew University, Jerusalem 91904, Israel June 2009 Abstract Kolmogorov s

More information

3. FORCING NOTION AND GENERIC FILTERS

3. FORCING NOTION AND GENERIC FILTERS 3. FORCING NOTION AND GENERIC FILTERS January 19, 2010 BOHUSLAV BALCAR, balcar@math.cas.cz 1 TOMÁŠ PAZÁK, pazak@math.cas.cz 1 JONATHAN VERNER, jonathan.verner@matfyz.cz 2 We now come to the important definition.

More information

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic Takahiro Kato September 10, 2015 ABSTRACT. This article provides yet another characterization of Boolean algebras and, using this characterization, establishes a

More information

On Definability in Multimodal Logic

On Definability in Multimodal Logic On Definability in Multimodal Logic Joseph Y. Halpern Computer Science Department Cornell University, U.S.A. halpern@cs.cornell.edu Dov Samet The Faculty of Management Tel Aviv University, Israel samet@post.tau.ac.il

More information

The Many Faces of Modal Logic Day 3: Algebraic Semantics

The Many Faces of Modal Logic Day 3: Algebraic Semantics The Many Faces of Modal Logic Day 3: Algebraic Semantics Dirk Pattinson Australian National University, Canberra (Slides based on a NASSLLI 2014 Tutorial and are joint work with Lutz Schröder) LAC 2018

More information

Logics of n-ary Contact

Logics of n-ary Contact Sofia University St. Kliment Ohridski Faculty of Mathematics and Informatics Department of Mathematical Logic and Its Applications Master Thesis Logics of n-ary Contact Ivan Zheliazkov Nikolov M.Sc. Logics

More information

S4.3 AND HEREDITARILY EXTREMALLY DISCONNECTED SPACES. On the occasion of the one hundredth anniversary of the birth of George Chogoshvili.

S4.3 AND HEREDITARILY EXTREMALLY DISCONNECTED SPACES. On the occasion of the one hundredth anniversary of the birth of George Chogoshvili. S43 AND HEREDITARILY EXTREMALLY DISCONNECTED SPACES G BEZHANISHVILI, N BEZHANISHVILI, J LUCERO-BRYAN, J VAN MILL On the occasion of the one hundredth anniversary of the birth of George Chogoshvili 1 Abstract

More information

Axiomatizing hybrid logic using modal logic

Axiomatizing hybrid logic using modal logic Axiomatizing hybrid logic using modal logic Ian Hodkinson Department of Computing Imperial College London London SW7 2AZ United Kingdom imh@doc.ic.ac.uk Louis Paternault 4 rue de l hôpital 74800 La Roche

More information

The Countable Henkin Principle

The Countable Henkin Principle The Countable Henkin Principle Robert Goldblatt Abstract. This is a revised and extended version of an article which encapsulates a key aspect of the Henkin method in a general result about the existence

More information

LOGIC OF CLASSICAL REFUTABILITY AND CLASS OF EXTENSIONS OF MINIMAL LOGIC

LOGIC OF CLASSICAL REFUTABILITY AND CLASS OF EXTENSIONS OF MINIMAL LOGIC Logic and Logical Philosophy Volume 9 (2001), 91 107 S. P. Odintsov LOGIC OF CLASSICAL REFUTABILITY AND CLASS OF EXTENSIONS OF MINIMAL LOGIC Introduction This article continues the investigation of paraconsistent

More information

Completeness in the Monadic Predicate Calculus. We have a system of eight rules of proof. Let's list them:

Completeness in the Monadic Predicate Calculus. We have a system of eight rules of proof. Let's list them: Completeness in the Monadic Predicate Calculus We have a system of eight rules of proof. Let's list them: PI At any stage of a derivation, you may write down a sentence φ with {φ} as its premiss set. TC

More information

THE CLOSED-POINT ZARISKI TOPOLOGY FOR IRREDUCIBLE REPRESENTATIONS. K. R. Goodearl and E. S. Letzter

THE CLOSED-POINT ZARISKI TOPOLOGY FOR IRREDUCIBLE REPRESENTATIONS. K. R. Goodearl and E. S. Letzter THE CLOSED-POINT ZARISKI TOPOLOGY FOR IRREDUCIBLE REPRESENTATIONS K. R. Goodearl and E. S. Letzter Abstract. In previous work, the second author introduced a topology, for spaces of irreducible representations,

More information

A NEW PROOF OF THE MCKINSEY-TARSKI THEOREM

A NEW PROOF OF THE MCKINSEY-TARSKI THEOREM A NEW PROOF OF THE MCKINSEY-TARSKI THEOREM G. BEZHANISHVILI, N. BEZHANISHVILI, J. LUCERO-BRYAN, J. VAN MILL Abstract. It is a landmark theorem of McKinsey and Tarski that if we interpret modal diamond

More information

Semantic Characterization of Kracht Formulas

Semantic Characterization of Kracht Formulas Semantic Characterization of Kracht Formulas Stanislav Kikot Moscow State University Moscow, Vorobjovy Gory, 1 Abstract Kracht formulas are first-order correspondents of modal Sahlqvist formulas. In this

More information

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA  address: Topology Xiaolong Han Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA E-mail address: Xiaolong.Han@csun.edu Remark. You are entitled to a reward of 1 point toward a homework

More information

Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory

Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory Department of Mathematics Bachelor Thesis (7.5 ECTS) Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory Author: Dionijs van Tuijl Supervisor: Dr. Jaap van Oosten June 15, 2016 Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Preliminaries

More information

CHODOUNSKY, DAVID, M.A. Relative Topological Properties. (2006) Directed by Dr. Jerry Vaughan. 48pp.

CHODOUNSKY, DAVID, M.A. Relative Topological Properties. (2006) Directed by Dr. Jerry Vaughan. 48pp. CHODOUNSKY, DAVID, M.A. Relative Topological Properties. (2006) Directed by Dr. Jerry Vaughan. 48pp. In this thesis we study the concepts of relative topological properties and give some basic facts and

More information