Distributivity conditions and the order-skeleton of a lattice

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Distributivity conditions and the order-skeleton of a lattice"

Transcription

1 Distributivity conditions and the order-skeleton of a lattice Jianning Su, Wu Feng, and Richard J. Greechie Abstract. We introduce π-versions of five familiar conditions for distributivity by applying the various conditions to 3-element antichains only. We prove that they are inequivalent concepts, and characterize them via exclusion systems. A lattice L satisfies D 0π if a (b c) (a b) c for all 3-element antichains {a,b,c}. We consider a congruence relation whose blocks are the maximal autonomous chains and define the order-skeleton of a lattice L to be L := L/. We prove that the following are equivalent for a lattice L: (i) L satisfies D 0π, (ii) L satisfies any of the five π-versions of distributivity, (iii) the order-skeleton L is distributive. 1. Introduction Distributive lattices are perhaps the most familiar class of lattices. They may be defined via any of the following ternary relations on L: D(a,b,c) means a (b c) = (a b) (a c), D (a,b,c) means a (b c) = (a b) (a c), D m (a,b,c) means (a b) (b c) (c a) = (a b) (b c) (c a), and D 0 (a,b,c) means a (b c) (a b) c. In fact, a lattice L is distributive in case any one, and hence all, of the following equivalent conditions hold: (i) D(a,b,c) for all a,b,c L, (iii) D m (a,b,c) for all a,b,c L, (ii) D (a,b,c) for all a,b,c L, (iv) D 0 (a,b,c) for all a,b,c L. Recall that elements a, b of a lattice L are incomparable, written as a b, if they are not comparable. An antichain in L is a subset of L in which any two distinct elements are incomparable. We denote by π L the set of antichains in L and by πl n the set of n-element antichains in L, where n 1. In [8], one of us found that a π-version of distributivity proved to be of some importance in the study of when certain mappings are residuated. This motivated us to consider the π-version of each of the properties (i)-(iv), by replacing, in each case, for all a,b,c L with for all {a,b,c} πl 3. Presented by... Received...; accepted in final form Mathematics Subject Classification: Primary: 06D75. Key words and phrases: lattice, distributive lattice, π-distributive lattice, order-skeleton, residuated, exclusion systems.

2 2 J. Su, W. Feng, and R. J. Greechie Algebra univers. A lattice L is π-meet-distributive (resp. π-join-distributive) if D(a,b,c) (resp. D (a,b,c)) holds for all {a,b,c} πl 3. A lattice L is π-distributive if it is both π-meet-distributive and π-join-distributive. A lattice L satisfies the π-median law if D m (a,b,c) holds for all {a,b,c} πl 3. A lattice L satisfies D 0π if D 0 (a,b,c) holds for all {a,b,c} πl 3. We have resisted considering π-semi-distributivity because it is equivalent to semi-distributivity as defined in [4]. We observe that for a modular lattice, the five π-versions of distributivity are all equivalent to distributivity. But, in general, they are not equivalent to each other as we show in Section 3. Let C 1 and C 2 be two classes of algebras such that C 1 C 2 ; an exclusion system for C 1 C 2 is a class S C 2 C 1 such that, for L C 2, L / C 1 iff there exists S S isomorphic to a subalgebra of L. We denote by L, D, and M the classes of lattices, distributive lattices, and modular lattices, respectively. Let D 0π, D mπ, D π, D π, and D π be the classes of lattices satisfying D 0π, the π-median law, π-meet-distributivity, π-join-distributivity, and π-distributivity, respectively. RecallthatN 5 isthe 5-elementnon-modularlatticeandM 3 isthe 5-element modular non-distributive lattice. It is well known that {M 3,N 5 } is anexclusionsystemford L. InSection3, wecharacterizethefiveπ-versions of distributivity via exclusion systems; we show that [M 3,3 2 ), {L 15 }, {L 14 }, and {L 13 } are exclusion systems for D 0π L, D mπ D 0π, D π D mπ, and D π D mπ, respectively, where [M 3,3 2 ) is defined in Section 3. We study the notion of the order-skeleton L of a lattice L, which was first introduced in [8] and discussed in [9]. In Theorem2.8, we provethat L satisfies D 0π iff its order-skeleton L is distributive. Our main result, Corollary 3.6, is that L satisfies D 0π iff L satisfies any of the five π-versions of distributivity presented. In particular, if a lattice L is isomorphic to its order-skeleton, then all the five π-versions of distributivity are equivalent to distributivity. We conclude the paper by studying several other weakened distributivity conditions, giving the relation between them and our π-versions of distributivity. The authors wish to thank Dr. Jinko Kanno, Dr. Marcel Erné, and Dr. Peter Jipsen for comments which improved this paper. 2. Order-skeletons Let L be a lattice and a,b L. As usual, we write [a,b] := {x L a x b} and [a,b) := {x L a x < b}; we allow for the possibility that a b, in which case, of course, both sets are empty. Define π(a) := {b L b a}. The following definition plays an important role throughout this paper: a b means a b and π(a) = π(c) for all c [a,b] [b,a].

3 Vol. 00, XX Distributivity conditions and the order-skeleton of a lattice 3 M 3 L 1 L 2 L 13 L 3 L 4 L 5 L 14 L 6 L 7 L 8 L 15 (a) A 9-element exclusion system for D 0π L (b) Figure 1. A 12-element exclusion system for D π L Following [16], a non-empty subset S of L is called (order-)autonomous in case, for all p / S, (1) if there is an s S with s p, then x p for all x S; and (2) if there is an s S with p s, then p x for all x S. Lemma 2.1. Let L be a lattice with a,b L. The following are equivalent. (i) a b. (ii) [a,b] or [b,a] is a chain and π(a) = π(b). (iii) [a,b] or [b,a] is an autonomous chain. Proof. (i) (ii) We may assume that a b and a b. We need only to show that [a,b] is a chain. For any c,d [a,b], we have π(c) = π(a) = π(d), so that c d. It follows that [a,b] is a chain. (ii) (iii) Since π(a) = π(b), we have a b. Assume a b, so that [a,b] is a chain. Let c [a,b] and p / [a,b]. If p c, then p b. Since π(a) = π(b), we have p a. Since p / [a,b], we have p a. Thus, p x for all x [a,b]. Dually, if c p, then x p for all x [a,b]. Therefore, [a,b] is autonomous. (iii) (i) We may assume that [a,b] is an autonomous chain. Let c [a,b] and x / [a,c]. Note that, x a iff x c, and a x iff c x. Thus, x a iff x c. It follows that π(a) = π(c), so that a b. Recall that an equivalence relation θ on a lattice L is a congruence relation iff for any a,b,c L, a θ b implies that (a c) θ (b c) and (a c) θ (b c) (cf. [5]). Lemma 2.2. The relation defined on a lattice L is a congruence relation.

4 4 J. Su, W. Feng, and R. J. Greechie Algebra univers. Proof. First, we claim that is an equivalence relation. The reflexivity and symmetry follow directly from the definition. The transitivity follows from the fact that the subsets of autonomous chains are autonomous chains and the union of two autonomous chains having a non-empty intersection is an autonomous chain. Now, we show that is a congruence relation. Let a,b,c L and suppose that a b. Since a b, we may assume that a b. We shall argue that a c b c by the following two cases. Case 1. Suppose that a c. Since π(a) = π(b), we have b c. Thus, {a,b,c} is a chain. If c a b, then a c = a b = b c. If a c b, then a c = c b = b c. If a b c, then a c = c c = b c. Therefore, in all cases, a c b c. Case 2. Suppose that a c. Since a b, we have a c b c. By Lemma 2.1, [a,b] is an autonomous chain. Since a a c, we have b a c, so that b c a c. Thus, a c = b c, and therefore, a c b c. By a dual argument, we have a c b c. Therefore, is a congruence relation. Define [a] := {b a b } and L := L/ = {[a] a L }. We call the quotient lattice L; L, L the order-skeleton of L. (The order-skeleton of a poset is introduced in [8].) Lemma 2.3. Let L be a lattice with a,b L. Then (i) [a] L [b] iff there exist a 1 [a] and b 1 [b] such that a 1 b 1 ; (ii) [a] < L [b] iff a < b and [a] [b]; (iii) [a] L [b] exists and equals [a b]; (iv) [a] L [b] exists and equals [a b]; (v) a b iff [a] L [b]; and (vi) π(a) = π(b) iff π L([a]) = π L([b]). Proof. (i), (ii), (iii), and (iv) follow directly from the fact that is a congruence relation (cf. [5]). Also, (v) follows from (i) and the definition of, and (vi) follows from (v). For a lattice L with a L, the element a is join-reducible if there exist b,c < a such that a = b c. A meet-reducible element is defined dually. An element a is doubly-reducible if it is both join-reducible and meet-reducible. Note that under this definition, 0 is not join-reducible and 1 is not meetreducible. For convenience of notation, we use a,b,c for elements in L and x,y,z for elements in L. The following lemma ensures that there is at most one joinreducible (resp., meet-reducible) element of L in each [a] L. Lemma 2.4. Let L be a lattice with a L and x L. (i) If a is join-reducible in L, then [a] exists and [a] = a. (ii) If x is join-reducible in L, then x exists and x x.

5 Vol. 00, XX Distributivity conditions and the order-skeleton of a lattice 5 (iii) If a is meet-reducible in L, then [a] exists and [a] = a. (iv) If x is meet-reducible in L, then x exists and x x. Proof. By duality, we need only prove (i) and (ii). (i) Let a L be join-reducible. We need only show that a is the lower bound of [a]. There exist b,c L such that b c and a = b c. Since b c and a c, we have [a] [b]. By Lemma 2.3 (i), we have [b] L [a], so that [b] < L [a]. Let u [a]. By Lemma 2.3 (ii), b < u. Similarly, c < u. Hence, a = b c u. (ii) Since x is join-reducible in L, there exist b,c L such that [b],[c] < L x and x = [b] L [c]. By Lemma 2.3 (ii), for all a x, we have b,c < a, so that b c a. By Lemma 2.3 (iii), x = [b c], so b c x. Therefore b c is the smallest element in x, i.e., x = b c x. Lemma 2.5. Let L be a lattice with x L. Then (i) x is a maximal autonomous chain in L; (ii) L := ( L) = {{x} x L}, i.e., L is equality on L. (iii) L = L iff L = {{a} a L}. Proof. (i) Let x L. For any b,c x, we have b c, so that b c; hence x is a chain. Let p / x and b,c x. If b p, then by Lemma 2.1, we have [b,c] or [c,b] is autonomous, so that c p. Similarly, p b implies p c. Hence, x is autonomous. We now show that x is maximal. Let S L be an autonomous chain containing x. For a x and s S, we have that [a,s] or [s,a] is autonomous, so that by Lemma 2.1, a s. Thus, S [a] = x, i.e., x is a maximal autonomous chain. (ii) Let x,y L and x L y. Since x L y, we may assume that x L y, and hence, there exist a x and b y such that a b. For any c L with a c b, we have x L [c] L y. Thus, π L(x) = π L([c]), and hence, by Lemma 2.3 (vi), π(a) = π(c). It follows that a b, so that x = y. Therefore, x = {x}. (iii) If L = {{a} a L}, then the function a [a] is easily seen to be an isomorphism. For the converse, assume that L = L via the isomorphism f: L L. Let a,b L with a b. We may assume that a b. Since f is an isomorphism, we have f(a) L f(b). Let x be an arbitrary element in [f(a),f(b)] and let c := f 1 (x). We have c [a,b], and thus, π(c) = π(a) since a b. Since f is an isomorphism, we have π L(x) = π L(f(a)). Therefore, by definition, f(a) L f(b). By (ii), we have f(a) = f(b), so that a = b. Therefore, is equality on L, and L = {{a} a L}. Let L and K be two lattices. Recall that a (lattice-)embedding f: L K is a one-to-one homomorphism from L to K. L is (lattice-)embeddable in K if there exists an embedding from L into K. The following lemma utilizes the Axiom of Choice. Lemma 2.6. Let L be a lattice. Consider the following conditions. (i) Every doubly-reducible element in L is a singleton subset of L.

6 6 J. Su, W. Feng, and R. J. Greechie Algebra univers. (ii) There exists an embedding β: L L such that β(x) x for every x L. (iii) L is embeddable in L. (iv) The cardinality of the set of doubly-reducible elements in L equals the cardinality of the set of doubly-reducible elements in L. Then (i) (ii) (iii) (iv). In particular, if L contains finitely many doubly-reducible elements, then the four conditions are equivalent to each other. Proof. (i) (ii) Assume that every doubly-reducible element in L is a singleton subset of L. Note that, by Lemma 2.4, if x is join-reducible (resp. meet-reducible) in L, then x (resp. x) exists and x x (resp. x x). By assumption, if x is doubly-reducible in L, then x = x. Thus, there exists a selection function β: L L such that (1) β(x) x, (2) if x is join-reducible, then β(x) = x, and (3) if x is meet-reducible, then β(x) = x. It is easy to see that β: L L is one-to-one. We now show that β is a homomorphism. Let [a],[b] L. If [a] L [b], then β([a] L[b]) = β([a]) β([b]). If [a] L [b], then both [a] L[b] and a b are join-reducible, so that by Lemma 2.3 (iii) and Lemma 2.4, β([a] L [b]) = β([a b]) = [a b] = β([a]) β([b]). Dually, we have β([a] L [b]) = β([a]) β([b]). Therefore, β is an embedding. (ii) (i) Let β: L L be an embedding such that β(x) x for every x L. Let x L be a doubly-reducible element. Since x is join-reducible in L, there exist y,z L such that y L z and x = y Lz. By Lemma 2.3 (v), β(y) β(z), so that β(x) = β(y) β(z) is join-reducible in L. By Lemma 2.4, β(x) = x. Dually, β(x) = x, so that x = x, i.e., x is a singleton subset of L. (ii) (iii) This is trivial. (iii) (iv) Let f: L L be an embedding. Let c L and c L be the cardinality ofthe doubly-reducibleelementsin Land Lrespectively. Note thatf mapsthe doubly-reducible elements in L to the doubly-reducible elements in L, so that c L c L. Also note that every doubly-reducible element a L corresponds to a doubly-reducible element [a] L, so that c L c L. Therefore, c L = c L. Now assume that L contains finitely many doubly-reducible elements. (iv) (i) Suppose that x is doubly-reducible in L but not a singleton subset of L. Since every doubly-reducible element a L corresponds to a doublyreducible element [a] L, we have c L c L. Also note that there is no doubly-reducible element in L that corresponds to x. It follows that c L < c L which contradicts (iv). Note that (i), (iii), and (iv) are not in general equivalent to each other. For example, let L be the horizontal sum of L 15 with countably many copies of the 3 2. Then L is the horizontal sum of countably many copies of the 3 2. Therefore L is embeddable in L, but L contains a horizontal summand isomorphic to L 15 so that L contains a doubly-reducible element which is not a singleton subset of L, i.e., (iii) (i). Now let M be the vertical sum of

7 Vol. 00, XX Distributivity conditions and the order-skeleton of a lattice 7 two 2 2 so that there is a bi-reducible element in M. Let Q be the horizontal sum of L 15 with countably many copies of M. In this example, both Q and Q have countably many bi-reducible elements, but Q is not embeddable in Q, i.e., (iv) (iii). Define a pentagon in a lattice L to be a quintuple a,b,c,u,v such that a,b,c,u,v L and v < b < a < u, c a = v, c b = u. Lemma 2.7. Let L be a lattice. If L is non-modular, then L contains a pentagon x,y,z,u,v and there exists an element w L such that either (i) x = y L w and {w,y,z} π 3 L; or (ii) y = x L w and {w,x,z} π 3 L. Proof. Suppose that L contains a pentagon x 1,y,z,u,v. Since x 1 L y, there exists x 2 L such that y < L x 2 L x 1 and π(y) π(x 2 ). Note that, x 2,y,z,u,v is a pentagon. Since π(y) π(x 2 ), we have either (i ) w L with w L y and w L x 2, or (ii ) w L with w L x 2 and w L y. By duality, we may assume that (i ) holds. Since y L x 2 and y L w, we have x 2 L w. Since x 2 L w and w L x 2, we have w L x 2. Let x = y L w. We have y < L x L x 2, and thus, x,y,z,u,v is a pentagon. Since w L y and x L z = v L y, we have w L x L z. Since w L x L z and w L x, we have w L z. Since w L x and z L x, we have z L w. Thus, w L z, and {w,y,z} π 3 L. Therefore, (i) holds. In the dual case (ii ), (ii) holds. Theorem 2.8. Let L be a lattice. The following are equivalent. (i) L satisfies D 0π. (ii) L satisfies D 0π. (iii) L is distributive. Proof. First, we prove that (i) and (ii) are equivalent. (i) (ii) If L satisfies D 0π, then {[a],[b],[c]} π 3 L implies {a,b,c} π 3 L and [a] L([b] L[c]) = [a (b c)] L [(a b) c] = ([a] L[b]) L[c], sothat Lsatisfies D 0π. Now we assume that L does not satisfy D 0π. Then {a,b,c} π 3 L such that a (b c) (a b) c. Let d = a (b c) and e = (a b) c, so that d e. Since {a,b,c} π 3 L, we have {[a],[b],[c]} π3 L. Since d a, c e, and c a, we have e d. Thus, d e. It follows, [d] L [e]. Since [a] L ([b] L [c]) = [d] L [e] = ([a] L [b]) L [c], we have D 0 ([a],[b],[c]) does not hold. Thus, L does not satisfy D 0π. Now we prove that (ii) and (iii) are equivalent. (ii) (iii) Assumethat Lisdistributive. Forany{x,y,z} π 3 L, x L(y Lz) = (x Ly) L(x Lz) L (x Ly) Lz. Thus, LsatisfiesD 0π. Nowwemayassume that L is not distributive. Then L contains a sublattice isomorphic to M 3 or N 5. It is easy to verify that M 3 does not satisfy D 0π. We may assume that L containsapentagon x,y,z,u,v. ByLemma2.7,wemayassumethat w L such that x = y Lw and {w,y,z} π 3 L. Since w Lz L x Lz = v L y, we have w L(z Ly) = w L y = (w Lz) Ly, i.e., L does not satisfy D 0π.

8 8 J. Su, W. Feng, and R. J. Greechie Algebra univers. We conclude this section by observing that a simple induction proves that a lattice L is π-meet-distributive iff x ( (A {x})) = (x a) for a A {x} every finite π-set A L and x A. And the dual statement holds for π-joindistributivity. Note that this is not true when A is not finite. For example, let N 0 := N {0} and consider the lattice N 0 ;lcm,gcd. Note that 0 is the top element and 1 is the bottom element. This is a distributive lattice, and thus, a π-meet-distributive lattice. Let O be the set of all odd integers, A = O {2}, and x = 2. We have 2 ( O) = 2 0 = 2 but (2 a) = 1 = 1. a O a O 3. Exclusion systems In this section, we characterize the five π-versions of distributivity introduced in Section 1 by the exclusion systems. We observe that they are not equivalent to each other. Note that in Figure 1, L 13 is π-meet-distributive but not π-join-distributive, while L 14 is π-join-distributive but not π-meetdistributive. L 15 satisfies D 0π but does not satisfy the π-median law. Also, both L 13 and L 14 satisfy D 0π and the π-median law, but do not satisfy π- distributivity. For a lattice L with a,b,c L, we use Γ{a,b,c} to denote the sublattice of L generated by a,b,c. We write 1 K (resp. 0 K ) for the top (resp. bottom) element of a sublattice K of L. Lemma 3.1. Let L be a lattice with {a,b,c} πl 3. The following statements hold. (i) If a (b c) / {a b,a c}, then {a (b c),b,c} π 3 L. (ii) If a (b c) / {a b,a c}, then {a (b c),b,c} π 3 L. (iii) If a b < 1 Γ{a,b,c} and a c < 1 Γ{a,b,c}, then {(a b) (a c),b,c} π 3 L. (iv) If 0 Γ{a,b,c} < a b and 0 Γ{a,b,c} < a c, then {(a b) (a c),b,c} π 3 L. Proof. By duality, we need only prove (i) and (iii). (i) Let a 1 := a (b c) and assume that a 1 / {a b,a c}. Since a 1 a b and a b a 1, we have a b < a 1. Since a 1 b = a (b c) b = a b < a 1 and a 1 b = a b < b, we have a 1 b. By symmetry, a 1 c. It follows that {a 1,b,c} πl 3. (iii) Let a u := (a b) (a c). Since a a u and a b, we also have a u b. We have b a u, otherwise, b a u = (a b) (a c) a c, which implies 1 Γ{a,b,c} = a b c = a c, contradicting a c < 1 Γ{a,b,c}. Hence, a u b. By symmetry, a u c. Therefore, {a u,b,c} πl 3. Recall that D 0 (a,b,c) means a (b c) (a b) c. Dually, we can define D 0 (a,b,c) to mean (a b) c a (b c). Note that D 0 (a,b,c) = D 0(c,b,a). Lemma 3.2. Let L be a lattice with {a,b,c} π 3 L. The following statements are equivalent.

9 Vol. 00, XX Distributivity conditions and the order-skeleton of a lattice 9 (i) D 0 (a,b,c) holds. (ii) c (a (b c)) = (a b) c. (iii) a (b c) = a (c (a b)). (iv) {a (b c),b,(a b) c} / π 3 L. Proof. It is easy to see that (i), (ii), and (iii) are equivalent. It is trivial that (i) implies (iv). We need only to show that (iv) implies (i). Let a 1 := a (b c) and c 1 := (a b) c. Note that a 1 a and c c 1. Suppose that {a 1,b,c 1 } / π 3 L. We have a 1 b, b c 1, or a 1 c 1. Note that, since b a and a 1 a, we have b a 1. Therefore, if a 1 b, then since b a 1, we have a 1 < b, and thus, a 1 a b (a b) c = c 1. Similarly, since c b and c c 1, we have c 1 b. Therefore, if b c 1, then since c 1 b, we have b < c 1, and thus, a 1 = a (b c) b c c 1. Thus, we may assume that a 1 c 1. Since c c 1, a 1 a, and c a, we have c 1 a 1. Thus, a 1 c 1. Lemma 3.3. Let L be a lattice. The following conditions are equivalent. (i) L does not satisfy D 0π. (ii) {a,b,c} πl 3 such that a b c and a b c. (iii) {a,b,c} πl 3 such that a b = 0 Γ{a,b,c} and b c = 1 Γ{a,b,c}. Proof. Let a 1 := a (b c) and c 1 := (a b) c. Note that a 1 a and c c 1. (i) (ii) Since L does not satisfy D 0π, {a,b,c} π 3 L such that a 1 c 1. By Lemma 3.2 (iv), {a 1,b,c 1 } π 3 L. Thus, a 1 b = a b (a b) c = c 1. Similarly, a 1 b c 1. (ii) (iii) It is trivial. (iii) (i) a (b c) = a c = (a b) c, i.e., D 0 (a,b,c) does not hold. As mentioned in the introduction, distributivity implies D 0π, but D 0π does not imply distributivity. Moreover, for {a,b,c} πl 3, if either D(a,b,c) or D (c,b,a) holds, then D 0 (a,b,c) holds. But the converse is not true. Figure 2 is an example of a lattice satisfying D 0π, but not D(a,b,c) or D (c,b,a) (this can be verified by applying the above lemma). The following lemma is well known. Lemma 3.4. {M 3 } is an exclusion system for D M. In [6], the following lemma is proved. Lemma 3.5. Let L be a lattice containing a pentagon a,b,c,u,v and an element d such that a = b d and {b,c,d} πl 3. Then L contains a sublattice isomorphic to L 1, L 3, L 4, L 6, L 7, or L 8. We follow the notation from [14, 11, 12]. Note that M 3, L 1, L 2, L 3, L 4, L 5, L 13, L 14 and L 15 are subdirectly irreducible lattices and each L i is the order-skeleton of the corresponding lattice L i for i = 6,7,8 as found in these references. Note that L 1 and L 2 are dual; L 4 and L 5 are dual. By Lemma 2.7, Lemma 3.5 and its dual, and the fact that the eight lattices L 1,L 2,L 3,L 4,L 5, L 6, L 7, and L 8 are not modular, we have the following corollary.

10 10 J. Su, W. Feng, and R. J. Greechie Algebra univers. a b c Figure 2. A lattice L satisfying D 0π but satisfying neither D(a,b,c) nor D (c,b,a). Corollary 3.6. Let L be a lattice. The order-skeleton L is modular iff L contains no sublattice isomorphic to L 1,L 2,L 3,L 4,L 5, L 6, L 7, or L 8. Note that the lattices M 3,L 1,L 2,L 3,L 4,L 5, L 6, L 7, and L 8 satisfy the condition (i) in Lemma 2.6. Therefore, we have the following corollary. Corollary 3.7. For F {M 3,L 1,L 2,L 3,L 4,L 5, L 6, L 7, L 8 }, if L contains a sublattice isomorphic to F, then L contains a sublattice isomorphic to F. Let L F ; be the poset of all finite lattices with the ordering defined by order-embedding, i.e., L 1 L 2 iff there exists a one-to-one mapping f: L 1 L 2 such that x y iff f(x) f(y) for all x,y L 1. We define the half open interval in L F by [L 1,L 2 ) := {L L F : L 1 L < L 2 }. One can verify that [M 3,3 2 ) = {M 3,L 1,L 2,L 3,L 4,L 5, L 6, L 7, L 8 }. We now characterize the condition D 0π. Theorem 3.8. [M 3,3 2 ) is an exclusion system for D 0π L. Proof. It is easy to verify that the nine lattices in [M 3,3 2 ) do not satisfy D 0π. We argue that, if L does not satisfy D 0π, then L contains a sublattice isomorphic to a lattice in [M 3,3 2 ). Suppose that L does not satisfy D 0π. By Theorem 2.8, L is not distributive. If L is modular, then by Lemma 3.4, it contains a sublattice isomorphic to M 3. If L is non-modular, then by Corollary 3.6, it contains a sublattice isomorphic to one of L 1,L 2,L 3,L 4,L 5, L 6, L 7, L 8. Hence, by Corollary 3.7, L contains a sublattice isomorphic to one of M 3,L 1,L 2,L 3,L 4,L 5, L 6, L 7, L 8. Recall that a lattice L satisfies the π-median law iff D m (a,b,c) holds for all {a,b,c} π 3 L. For convenience of notation, for a,b,c L, define a u := (a b) (a c), b u := (a b) (b c), and c u := (a c) (b c). Dually, define

11 Vol. 00, XX Distributivity conditions and the order-skeleton of a lattice 11 a l := (a b) (a c), b l := (a b) (b c), and c l := (a c) (b c). Also, define m u := (a b) (b c) (c a) and m l := (a b) (b c) (c a). It is easy to verify that the nine lattices in [M 3,3 2 ) do not satisfy the π-median law, so that D mπ D 0π. Lemma 3.9. Let L be a lattice and L = 3 2. If L does not satisfy the π-median law, then L 15 is embeddable in L. Proof. Note that L = 3 2 is generated by its 3-element antichain. Since L does not satisfy the π-median law, there exists {a,b,c} π 3 L such that D m(a,b,c) does not hold. Since {[a],[b],[c]} π 3 L, we have L = Γ L{[a],[b],[c]}. Without loss of generality, we may assume that [a] and [c] are complements in L. Since D m (a,b,c) does not hold, we have m l = (a b) (b c) (c a) < (a b) (b c) (c a) = m u. Since m l = b l b b u = m u and m l m u, we have [m l ] = [b] = [m u ]. Consider the inverse image of : L L in L, one can verify that {0,1,a,b u,b l,c,a b,b c,a b,b c} = L 15. Lemma {L 15 } is an exclusion system for D mπ D 0π. Proof. It is easy to verify that L 15 does not satisfy the π-median law. Now assume that L satisfies D 0π, but does not satisfy the π-median law. There exists {a,b,c} πl 3 such that D m(a,b,c) does not hold, so that m l < m u. We claim that at least two of a, b, and c are incomparable with m u. Otherwise, we may assume that m u a and m u b. If m u a and m u b, then m u a b m l, contradicting m l < m u. If a < m u and b < m u, then a m l and b m l, so that m u a b m l, contradicting m l < m u. If a m u and m u b, then a b, contradicting a b. If b m u and m u a, then b a, contradicting a b. Therefore, two of a, b, and c are incomparable with m u. We may assume that m u a and m u b, so that {a,b,m u } πl 3. By Theorem 2.8, L is distributive, so that m l m u. Observe that a b m u a b, i.e., a and b are complement elements in Γ{a,b,m u }. One can verify that Γ L{[a],[b],[m u ]} = 3 2, so that by Lemma 3.9, L 15 is a sublattice of L. By Theorem 3.8 and Lemma 3.10, we have the following theorem. Theorem [M 3,3 2 ) {L 15 } is an exclusion system for D mπ L. It is easy to verify that the ten lattices in [M 3,3 2 ) {L 15 } are not π-meetdistributive, so that D π D mπ. Lemma {L 14 } is an exclusion system for D π D mπ. Proof. ItiseasytoverifythatL 14 isnotπ-meet-distributive. Nowassumethat L satisfies the π-median law, but does not satisfy the π-meet-distributivity. There exists {a 1,b,c} π 3 L such that D(a 1,b,c) does not hold. Let a := a 1 (b c). Since a 1 b (a 1 b) (a 1 c) < a 1 (b c) = a, we have a a 1 b. By symmetry, a a 1 c. By Lemma 3.1 (i), {a,b,c} π 3 L. We have (a b) (a c) = (a 1 b) (a 1 c) < a 1 (b c) = a (b c), i.e., D(a,b,c) does not hold. Let F = Γ{a,b,c}. We have b c = a b c = 1 F.

12 12 J. Su, W. Feng, and R. J. Greechie Algebra univers. Since L satisfies the π-median law, we have m l = m u. Since b c = 1 F, m u = (a b) (b c) (c a) = (a b) (a c) = a u. Since a l = (a b) (a c) < a (b c) = a 1 F = a a u and a l (b c) = (a b) (b c) (c a) = m l = m u = a u, we have 0 F < b c. Since a a u and a b, we have a u b. Since a u b and b l b, we have a u b l. Since a u b l and b l (a c) = (a b) (b c) (c a) = m l = m u = a u, we have 0 F < a c. By symmetry, 0 F < a b. By Lemma 3.1 (iv), {a l,b,c} πl 3, {a,b l,c} πl 3, and {a,b,c l } πl 3. Since b l c and c l c, we have b l c l. By symmetry, c l b l. Thus, b l c l. It follows, {a,b l,c l } πl 3. Since a a u = m u = m l = b l c l, (a b l ) (a c l ) (a b) (a c) < a = a (b l c l ), i.e., D(a,b l,c l ) does not hold. Since a b a l a and a b b l b, we have a b a l b l a b, so that a l b l = a b. Similarly, b l c l = b c and a l c l = a c. Observe that a l b l = b l c l = a l c l = m l, so that Γ{a l,b l,c l } = 2 3. Since a l a m l, we have Γ{a,b l,c l } = L 14. By Theorem 3.11, Lemma 3.12, and their dual statements, we have the following theorem. Theorem (i) [M 3,3 2 ) {L 14,L 15 }is an exclusion system for D π L. (ii) [M 3,3 2 ) {L 13,L 15 } is an exclusion system for D π L. (iii) [M 3,3 2 ) {L 13,L 14,L 15 } is an exclusion system for D π L. Remark By definition, π-distributivity implies both π-meet- and π- join-distributivity. By comparing the exclusion systems of the π-versions of distributivity, one can also see that either one of π-meet-distributivity and π-join-distributivity implies the π-median law, and the π-median law implies D 0π. In particular, π-distributivity implies D 0π. By using the exclusion systems with Theorem 2.8, we have the following corollary. Corollary Let L be a lattice. The following statements are equivalent. (i) L satisfies D 0π. (ii) L contains no sublattice isomorphic to a lattice in [M 3,3 2 ). (iii) L is distributive. (v) L is π-meet-distributive. (vii) L satisfies the π-median law. (iv) L is π-distributive. (vi) L is π-join-distributive. (viii) L satisfies D 0π. This corollary tells us that, if a lattice L is isomorphic to its own orderskeleton, then all these π-properties are equivalent to distributivity. We conclude this section by observing that no two of the properties (iii) - (viii) are equivalent for general lattices.

13 Vol. 00, XX Distributivity conditions and the order-skeleton of a lattice Motivation and related results In another paper ([9]), we study the residuated approximation to orderpreserving maps on complete lattices. A mapping between two posets is residuated if the inverse image of every principle ideal in Q is a principle ideal in L (see [2]). If the posets are complete lattices, then the mapping is residuated iff it preserves all joins. Any function f: L Q between two complete lattices dominates a largest residuated mapping, called ρ f, the residuated approximation of f. In [1], Andréka, Greechie, and Strecker introduced the shadow σ f of f in order to efficiently approximate ρ f by iterating σ f where σ f is defined by σ f (x) := {q Q x f 1 ( q)}. They proved the following theorem. Theorem 4.1. For a complete lattice Q, Q is completely distributive iff for every complete lattice L and every order-preserving mapping f: L Q, the shadow σ f is residuated. Also, Greechie and Janowitz[10, 9, 8] proved a result implying the following corollary. Corollary 4.2. Let L and Q be two complete lattices and f: L Q be an order-preserving mapping. If L is completely distributive, then σ f is residuated. Notice that both the theorem and the corollary are concerned with distributivity conditions. But even if both L and Q are non-distributive, it is still possible that the shadow is residuated. In [9], we study the structure of L in order to make the shadow σ f residuated and found the following theorem. Theorem 4.3. Let L be a lattice with no infinite chains. The following statements are equivalent. (i) σ f is residuated whenever Q is a complete lattice and f: L Q is an order-preserving mapping. (ii) L satisfies D 0π. (iii) L is distributive. This theorem motivated us to study the π-versions of distributivity and the order-skeleton of a lattice. Now we discuss the relation between the π-versions of distributivity in this paper to some weakened conditions found elsewhere [7, 13]. Note that both 2 and N 5 are π-distributive lattices, but 2 N 5 does not satisfy D 0π. Thus, by Comment 3.14, both 2 and N 5 satisfy the five π-versions of distributive conditions, but 2 N 5 does not satisfy any of these five conditions. Therefore, the five classes of lattices satisfying the various π-versions of distributivity described in this paper are not lattice varieties since they are not closed under products. A lattice L is semi-distributive whenever, for every a,b,c L, (SD1) a b = a c implies a b = a (b c); and (SD2) a b = a c implies a b = a (b c).

14 14 J. Su, W. Feng, and R. J. Greechie Algebra univers. It is easy to show that the π-version of semi-distributivity (again by applying the conditions only to {a,b,c} πl 3 ) is equivalent to semi-distributivity. Davey, Poguntke, and Rival proved that {M 3,L 1,L 2,L 3,L 4,L 5 } is an exclusion system for SD L where SD is the class of all semi-distributive lattice [4]. A lattice L is near-distributive whenever, for every a,b,c L, (ND1) a (b c) = a (b (a (c (a b)))) and (ND2) a (b c) = a (b (a (c (a b)))). As with semi-distributivity, it is not difficult to show that the π-version of near-distributivity is equivalent to near-distributivity. It is also easy to show that near-distributivity implies semi-distributivity. We now show that D 0π implies near-distributivity. Lemma 4.4. Let L be a lattice. If L satisfies D 0π, then L is near-distributive. Proof. Since near-distributivity and its π-version are equivalent, we need only to show that the π-version holds. Let {a,b,c} πl 3. By Lemma 3.2 (iii), we know that a (b c) = a (c (a b)). Let r := a (b (a (c (a b)))) be the right hand side of (ND1). Since a (c (a b)) a and a (c (a b)) b (a (c (a b))), we have a (c (a b) r. Also, we have r a (b (a (c b))) a (b (c b)) = a (b c). Therefore, a (b c) = r = a (b (a (c (a b)))), i.e., (ND1) holds. By duality, (ND2) holds. Therefore, L is near-distributive. A lattice L is almost-distributive if it is near-distributive and for every x,y,z,u,v L, (AD1) v (u c) u (c (v a)); and (AD2) v (u c ) u (c (v a )), where a = (x y) (x z), c = x (y (x z)), a = (x y) (x z), and c = x (y (x z)). Note that a is the dual of a, c is the dual of c, and (AD2) is the dual of (AD1). Lemma 4.5. Let L be a lattice. If L satisfies D 0π, then L is almost distributive. Proof. Let L be a lattice satisfying D 0π. By Lemma 4.4, L is near-distributive. Thus, by duality, we need only to show that (AD1) holds. Since L satisfies D 0π, by Theorem 2.8, L is distributive. Recall that is a congruence relation on L. In L, [a] = [(x y) (x z)] = ([x] L[y]) L([x] L [z]) = [x] L ([y] L [z]) = [x (y z)] = [c]. Thus, a c and clearly, a c. If a v, then c v and by Lemma 2.4, v a = [v a] = [v c] = v c, so that v (u c) u c = u (c (v c)) = u (c (v a)). If v a, then v (u c) v a u a = u (c (v a)). If c v, then v (u c) u c = u (c (v a)). If a v c, then v (u c) = v u v = u (c (v a)). Thus, (AD1) holds.

15 Vol. 00, XX Distributivity conditions and the order-skeleton of a lattice 15 Note that the converse of this lemma is not true. For example, L 6 is almost distributive but does not satisfy D 0π. In [15], Rose proved that for any subdirectly irreducible lattice L, L is almost distributive iff L = D[d] for some distributive lattice D and d D (see also [11, 13]). Here D[d] is the doubling construction introduced by Day [3]. Note that D[d] = D. If D = D, then the order-skeleton D[d] is isomorphic to D, and every block of the order-skeleton is a singleton subset except one block which is a doubleton subset. Recall the definition of a pentagon a,b,c,u,v preceding Lemma 2.7. The following lemma follows from the definition of the doubling construction. Lemma 4.6. Let L = D[d] for some distributive lattice D with d D. If L contains a pentagon a,b,c,u,v and θ is the smallest congruence relation that identifies a and b, then L/θ = D and θ is the congruence relation that identifies only a and b. Lemma 4.7. Let L be a π-distributive lattice with x,y,z L and L = D[d] for some distributive lattice D with d D. If L contains a pentagon a,b,c,u,v and x v = y v, then (x z) v = (y z) v. Proof. Assume that (x z) v (y z) v. Let θ be the smallest congruence relation that identifies a and b. By Lemma 4.6, L/θ is distributive, so that [(x z) v] θ = ([x] θ θ [z] θ ) θ [v] θ = ([x] θ θ [v] θ ) θ ([z] θ θ [v] θ ) = [(x v) (z v)] θ = [(y v) (z v)] θ = [(y z) v] θ. Since (x z) v θ (y z) v, we have {(x z) v,(y z) v} = {a,b} and we may assume that (x z) v = a and (y z) v = b. Sincea b,wehavex y. Notethatx a = x v = y v = y b. Since a x a = y b and a b, we have y b. Since x x a = y v and x y, we have b y. Thus, y b. Since b y b = y v y c and b c, we have y c. Since y < y b = y v y c, we have c y. Hence, y c, so that {y,b,c} πl 3. Since b y < b and a y θ b y, we have a y = b y. Since a x a = y v y c and L is π-distributive, we have a = a (y c) = (a y) (a c) = (b y) (b c) b, contradicting b < a. Therefore, (x z) v = (y z) v. Lemma 4.8. Let L be a subdirectly irreducible π-distributive lattice. If L contains a pentagon a,b,c,u,v, then u = 1 and v = 0. Proof. Let L be a subdirectly irreducible π-distributive lattice with a pentagon a,b,c,u,v. Assume that u 1 or v 0. By duality, we may assume v 0. Define a relation α on L by x α y iff x v = y v. It is easy to see that α is an equivalent relation such that for any x,y,z L with x α y, we have x z α y z and, by Lemma 4.7, x z α y z, so that α is a congruence relation. Let θ be the smallest congruence relation that identifies a and b. By Lemma 4.6, θ identifies only a and b. Note that, since a v = a b = b v, we have a α b, so that θ α. Let β be a congruence relation with β α and β θ, and suppose that c,d L with c β d. Since c θ d, we have c = d or

16 16 J. Su, W. Feng, and R. J. Greechie Algebra univers. {c,d} = {a,b}. Since c α d, we have c = d. Therefore, β is equality, which implies that L is not subdirectly irreducible, contradicting the assumption. Theorem 4.9. Let L be a subdirectly irreducible lattice with L N 5. Then L is distributive iff L is π-distributive. Proof. Let L be a subdirectly irreducible π-distributive lattice with L N 5. ByComment3.14, LsatisfiesD 0π, andbylemma4.5, Lis almostdistributive, so that L = D[d] for some distributive lattice D and d D. Assume that L is not distributive, so that L contains a sublattice isomorphic to M 3 or N 5. Since M 3 does not satisfy D 0π, L contains a pentagon a,b,c,u,v. By Lemma 4.8, u = 1 and v = 0. Since L N 5, there exists e L such that e / {a,b,c,0,1}. We have a e, for if a < e, then a,b,c e,b (c e),0 is a pentagon, so that, by Lemma 4.8 again, 1 = b (c e) e, contradicting e 1. Similarly, e b. Since L is subdirectly irreducible, e / [b,a], so that e a and e b. Since {a,b,e,a e,a e} is a pentagon, by Lemma 4.8, a e = b e = 1 and a e = b e = 0. Let θ be the smallest congruence relation that identifies a and b. By Lemma 4.6, θ identifies only a and b. Since [c] θ = [c (a e)] θ = [(c a) (c e)] θ = [c e] θ, we have c θ c e, so that c = c e. Similarly, c = c e, so that c = e, contradicting the assumption. Theorem Let L be a subdirectly irreducible lattice. Then L is almost distributive iff L satisfies D 0π. Proof. By Lemma 4.5, D 0π implies almost distributivity. We now prove the sufficiency. Let L be a subdirectly irreducible almost distributive lattice. There exists a distributive lattice D and an element d D such that L = D[d]. Notice that the order-skeleton L = D[d] = D is distributive, by Corollary 3.15, L satisfies D 0π. In [7], Erné introduced n-zipper-distributivity and the conditions of H n where n 3. It turns out that the π-version of n-zipper-distributivity is also equivalent to n-zipper-distributivity. In Figure 3, we present a diagram indicating the implications between the various weakened distributive conditions discussed above. We observe that nothing collapses except the five π-versions of distributivity discussed in Corollary 3.15 even if a lattice L is isomorphic to its own order-skeleton. Details can be found in [17]. References [1] Andréka H., Greechie R. J., Strecker G. E.: On residuated approxiations. Categorical Methods in Computer Science With Aspects from Topology, 393, (1989) [2] Blyth T. S., Janowitz M. F.: Residuation theory. Pergamon Press, (1972) [3] Day A.: A simple solution to the word problem for lattices. Canadian Mathemtical Bulleton, 13, (1970) [4] Davey B. A., Poguntke W., Rival I.: A characterization of semi-distributivity. Algebra Universalis, 5, (1975) [5] Davey B. A., Priestley H. A.: Introduction to lattices and order. Cambridge University Press, New York (1980)

17 Vol. 00, XX Distributivity conditions and the order-skeleton of a lattice 17 meet-semi-distributivity 4-zipper-distributivity semi-distributivity meet-near-distributivity near-distributivity almost-distributivity 3-zipper-distributivity modularity D 0π H 3 π-median law π-meet-distributivity π-join-distributivity H 4 π-distributivity distributivity Figure 3. The implications between various weakened distributive conditions. [6] Davey B. A., Rival I.: Finite sublattices of three-generated lattices. Journal of Australian Mathematical Society (Series A), 21, (1976) [7] Erné M.: Weak distributive laws and their role in lattices of congruences and equational theories. Algebra Univeralis, 25, (1980) [8] Feng W.: On calculating residuated approximations and the structure of finite lattices of small width. PhD dissertation, Louisiana Tech University (2010) [9] Feng W., Su J., Greechie R. J.: On calculating residuated approximations (submitted to Algebra Universalis) [10] Greechie R. J., Janowitz M. F.: Personal Communication. [11] Jónsson B., Rival I.: Lattice varieties covering the smallest non-modular variety. Pacific Journal of Mathematics, 82, (1979) [12] Jipsen P., Rose H.: Varieties of lattices. Springer Verlag, (1992) [13] Lee J. G.: Almost distributive lattice varieties. Algebra Univeralis, 21, (1985) [14] McKenzie R.: Equational bases and nonmodular lattice varieties. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 174, 1-43 (1972) [15] Rose H.: Nonmodular lattice varieties. Memoirs of American Mathematical Society, 292 (1984) [16] Schröder B. S. W.: Ordered sets: an introduction, Birkhäuser (2002) [17] Su J.: Results in lattices, ortholattices, and graphs. PhD dissertation, Louisiana Tech University (2011) Jianning Su Program of Mathematics and Statistics, Louisiana Tech University, Ruston 71272, USA sujianning@hotmail.com Wu Feng

18 18 J. Su, W. Feng, and R. J. Greechie Algebra univers. The Center for Secure Cyberspace, Louisiana Tech University, Ruston 71272, USA Richard J. Greechie Program of Mathematics and Statistics, Louisiana Tech University, Ruston 71272, USA URL: greechie/

On the variety generated by planar modular lattices

On the variety generated by planar modular lattices On the variety generated by planar modular lattices G. Grätzer and R. W. Quackenbush Abstract. We investigate the variety generated by the class of planar modular lattices. The main result is a structure

More information

SUBLATTICES OF LATTICES OF ORDER-CONVEX SETS, III. THE CASE OF TOTALLY ORDERED SETS

SUBLATTICES OF LATTICES OF ORDER-CONVEX SETS, III. THE CASE OF TOTALLY ORDERED SETS SUBLATTICES OF LATTICES OF ORDER-CONVEX SETS, III. THE CASE OF TOTALLY ORDERED SETS MARINA SEMENOVA AND FRIEDRICH WEHRUNG Abstract. For a partially ordered set P, let Co(P) denote the lattice of all order-convex

More information

A CHARACTERIZATION OF LOCALLY FINITE VARIETIES THAT SATISFY A NONTRIVIAL CONGRUENCE IDENTITY

A CHARACTERIZATION OF LOCALLY FINITE VARIETIES THAT SATISFY A NONTRIVIAL CONGRUENCE IDENTITY A CHARACTERIZATION OF LOCALLY FINITE VARIETIES THAT SATISFY A NONTRIVIAL CONGRUENCE IDENTITY KEITH A. KEARNES Abstract. We show that a locally finite variety satisfies a nontrivial congruence identity

More information

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Keith A. Kearnes and Greg Oman Abstract. We show that if P is an infinite poset whose proper order ideals have cardinality strictly less than P, and κ is a cardinal

More information

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.gm] 21 Jan 2005

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.gm] 21 Jan 2005 arxiv:math/0501341v1 [math.gm] 21 Jan 2005 SUBLATTICES OF LATTICES OF ORDER-CONVEX SETS, I. THE MAIN REPRESENTATION THEOREM MARINA SEMENOVA AND FRIEDRICH WEHRUNG Abstract. For a partially ordered set P,

More information

10. Finite Lattices and their Congruence Lattices. If memories are all I sing I d rather drive a truck. Ricky Nelson

10. Finite Lattices and their Congruence Lattices. If memories are all I sing I d rather drive a truck. Ricky Nelson 10. Finite Lattices and their Congruence Lattices If memories are all I sing I d rather drive a truck. Ricky Nelson In this chapter we want to study the structure of finite lattices, and how it is reflected

More information

NOTES ON PLANAR SEMIMODULAR LATTICES. IV. THE SIZE OF A MINIMAL CONGRUENCE LATTICE REPRESENTATION WITH RECTANGULAR LATTICES

NOTES ON PLANAR SEMIMODULAR LATTICES. IV. THE SIZE OF A MINIMAL CONGRUENCE LATTICE REPRESENTATION WITH RECTANGULAR LATTICES NOTES ON PLANAR SEMIMODULAR LATTICES. IV. THE SIZE OF A MINIMAL CONGRUENCE LATTICE REPRESENTATION WITH RECTANGULAR LATTICES G. GRÄTZER AND E. KNAPP Abstract. Let D be a finite distributive lattice with

More information

GENERALIZED DIFFERENCE POSETS AND ORTHOALGEBRAS. 0. Introduction

GENERALIZED DIFFERENCE POSETS AND ORTHOALGEBRAS. 0. Introduction Acta Math. Univ. Comenianae Vol. LXV, 2(1996), pp. 247 279 247 GENERALIZED DIFFERENCE POSETS AND ORTHOALGEBRAS J. HEDLÍKOVÁ and S. PULMANNOVÁ Abstract. A difference on a poset (P, ) is a partial binary

More information

NOTES ON PLANAR SEMIMODULAR LATTICES. IV. THE SIZE OF A MINIMAL CONGRUENCE LATTICE REPRESENTATION WITH RECTANGULAR LATTICES

NOTES ON PLANAR SEMIMODULAR LATTICES. IV. THE SIZE OF A MINIMAL CONGRUENCE LATTICE REPRESENTATION WITH RECTANGULAR LATTICES NOTES ON PLANAR SEMIMODULAR LATTICES. IV. THE SIZE OF A MINIMAL CONGRUENCE LATTICE REPRESENTATION WITH RECTANGULAR LATTICES G. GRÄTZER AND E. KNAPP Abstract. Let D be a finite distributive lattice with

More information

Sets and Motivation for Boolean algebra

Sets and Motivation for Boolean algebra SET THEORY Basic concepts Notations Subset Algebra of sets The power set Ordered pairs and Cartesian product Relations on sets Types of relations and their properties Relational matrix and the graph of

More information

Section Summary. Relations and Functions Properties of Relations. Combining Relations

Section Summary. Relations and Functions Properties of Relations. Combining Relations Chapter 9 Chapter Summary Relations and Their Properties n-ary Relations and Their Applications (not currently included in overheads) Representing Relations Closures of Relations (not currently included

More information

On the Structure of Rough Approximations

On the Structure of Rough Approximations On the Structure of Rough Approximations (Extended Abstract) Jouni Järvinen Turku Centre for Computer Science (TUCS) Lemminkäisenkatu 14 A, FIN-20520 Turku, Finland jjarvine@cs.utu.fi Abstract. We study

More information

Embedding theorems for normal divisible residuated lattices

Embedding theorems for normal divisible residuated lattices Embedding theorems for normal divisible residuated lattices Chapman University Department of Mathematics and Computer Science Orange, California University of Siena Department of Mathematics and Computer

More information

Finite pseudocomplemented lattices: The spectra and the Glivenko congruence

Finite pseudocomplemented lattices: The spectra and the Glivenko congruence Finite pseudocomplemented lattices: The spectra and the Glivenko congruence T. Katriňák and J. Guričan Abstract. Recently, Grätzer, Gunderson and Quackenbush have characterized the spectra of finite pseudocomplemented

More information

DISTRIBUTIVE, STANDARD AND NEUTRAL ELEMENTS IN TRELLISES. 1. Introduction

DISTRIBUTIVE, STANDARD AND NEUTRAL ELEMENTS IN TRELLISES. 1. Introduction Acta Math. Univ. Comenianae Vol. LXXVII, 2 (2008), pp. 167 174 167 DISTRIBUTIVE, STANDARD AND NEUTRAL ELEMENTS IN TRELLISES SHASHIREKHA B. RAI Abstract. In this paper, the concepts of distributive, standard

More information

8. Distributive Lattices. Every dog must have his day.

8. Distributive Lattices. Every dog must have his day. 8. Distributive Lattices Every dog must have his day. In this chapter and the next we will look at the two most important lattice varieties: distributive and modular lattices. Let us set the context for

More information

Three Classes of Orthomodular Lattices 3

Three Classes of Orthomodular Lattices 3 International Journal of Theoretical Physics, Vol. 45, No. 2, February 2006 ( C 2006) DOI: 10.1007/s10773-005-9022-y Three Classes of Orthomodular Lattices 3 Richard J. Greechie 1 and Bruce J. Legan 2

More information

Boolean Algebra CHAPTER 15

Boolean Algebra CHAPTER 15 CHAPTER 15 Boolean Algebra 15.1 INTRODUCTION Both sets and propositions satisfy similar laws, which are listed in Tables 1-1 and 4-1 (in Chapters 1 and 4, respectively). These laws are used to define an

More information

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved. Topology Proceedings Web: http://topology.auburn.edu/tp/ Mail: Topology Proceedings Department of Mathematics & Statistics Auburn University, Alabama 36849, USA E-mail: topolog@auburn.edu ISSN: 0146-4124

More information

Lattice Theory Lecture 4. Non-distributive lattices

Lattice Theory Lecture 4. Non-distributive lattices Lattice Theory Lecture 4 Non-distributive lattices John Harding New Mexico State University www.math.nmsu.edu/ JohnHarding.html jharding@nmsu.edu Toulouse, July 2017 Introduction Here we mostly consider

More information

Free and Finitely Presented Lattices

Free and Finitely Presented Lattices C h a p t e r 2 Free and Finitely Presented Lattices by R. Freese and J. B. Nation This is an extended version of our chapter in the book LatticeTheory: Special Topics and Applications, vol 2, edited by

More information

STRICTLY ORDER PRIMAL ALGEBRAS

STRICTLY ORDER PRIMAL ALGEBRAS Acta Math. Univ. Comenianae Vol. LXIII, 2(1994), pp. 275 284 275 STRICTLY ORDER PRIMAL ALGEBRAS O. LÜDERS and D. SCHWEIGERT Partial orders and the clones of functions preserving them have been thoroughly

More information

Congruence Coherent Symmetric Extended de Morgan Algebras

Congruence Coherent Symmetric Extended de Morgan Algebras T.S. Blyth Jie Fang Congruence Coherent Symmetric Extended de Morgan Algebras Abstract. An algebra A is said to be congruence coherent if every subalgebra of A that contains a class of some congruence

More information

A note on congruence lattices of slim semimodular

A note on congruence lattices of slim semimodular A note on congruence lattices of slim semimodular lattices Gábor Czédli Abstract. Recently, G. Grätzer has raised an interesting problem: Which distributive lattices are congruence lattices of slim semimodular

More information

Posets, homomorphisms and homogeneity

Posets, homomorphisms and homogeneity Posets, homomorphisms and homogeneity Peter J. Cameron and D. Lockett School of Mathematical Sciences Queen Mary, University of London Mile End Road London E1 4NS, U.K. Abstract Jarik Nešetřil suggested

More information

On the size of Heyting Semi-Lattices and Equationally Linear Heyting Algebras

On the size of Heyting Semi-Lattices and Equationally Linear Heyting Algebras On the size of Heyting Semi-Lattices and Equationally Linear Heyting Algebras Peter Freyd pjf@upenn.edu July 17, 2017 The theory of Heyting Semi-Lattices, hsls for short, is obtained by adding to the theory

More information

Duality and Automata Theory

Duality and Automata Theory Duality and Automata Theory Mai Gehrke Université Paris VII and CNRS Joint work with Serge Grigorieff and Jean-Éric Pin Elements of automata theory A finite automaton a 1 2 b b a 3 a, b The states are

More information

Generalized Pigeonhole Properties of Graphs and Oriented Graphs

Generalized Pigeonhole Properties of Graphs and Oriented Graphs Europ. J. Combinatorics (2002) 23, 257 274 doi:10.1006/eujc.2002.0574 Available online at http://www.idealibrary.com on Generalized Pigeonhole Properties of Graphs and Oriented Graphs ANTHONY BONATO, PETER

More information

Faithful embedding on finite orders classes

Faithful embedding on finite orders classes Faithful embedding on finite orders classes Alain Guillet Jimmy Leblet Jean-Xavier Rampon Abstract We investigate, in the particular case of finite orders classes, the notion of faithful embedding among

More information

EQUATIONS OF TOURNAMENTS ARE NOT FINITELY BASED

EQUATIONS OF TOURNAMENTS ARE NOT FINITELY BASED EQUATIONS OF TOURNAMENTS ARE NOT FINITELY BASED J. Ježek, P. Marković, M. Maróti and R. McKenzie Abstract. The aim of this paper is to prove that there is no finite basis for the equations satisfied by

More information

Boolean Algebras. Chapter 2

Boolean Algebras. Chapter 2 Chapter 2 Boolean Algebras Let X be an arbitrary set and let P(X) be the class of all subsets of X (the power set of X). Three natural set-theoretic operations on P(X) are the binary operations of union

More information

SIMPLICIAL COMPLEXES WITH LATTICE STRUCTURES GEORGE M. BERGMAN

SIMPLICIAL COMPLEXES WITH LATTICE STRUCTURES GEORGE M. BERGMAN This is the final preprint version of a paper which appeared at Algebraic & Geometric Topology 17 (2017) 439-486. The published version is accessible to subscribers at http://dx.doi.org/10.2140/agt.2017.17.439

More information

Partial cubes: structures, characterizations, and constructions

Partial cubes: structures, characterizations, and constructions Partial cubes: structures, characterizations, and constructions Sergei Ovchinnikov San Francisco State University, Mathematics Department, 1600 Holloway Ave., San Francisco, CA 94132 Abstract Partial cubes

More information

Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem

Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem Hongtaek Jung December 27, 2017 Abstract This is a part of a supplementary note for a Logic and Set Theory course. The main goal is to

More information

LATTICE PROPERTIES OF T 1 -L TOPOLOGIES

LATTICE PROPERTIES OF T 1 -L TOPOLOGIES RAJI GEORGE AND T. P. JOHNSON Abstract. We study the lattice structure of the set Ω(X) of all T 1 -L topologies on a given set X. It is proved that Ω(X) has dual atoms (anti atoms) if and only if membership

More information

The lattice of varieties generated by residuated lattices of size up to 5

The lattice of varieties generated by residuated lattices of size up to 5 The lattice of varieties generated by residuated lattices of size up to 5 Peter Jipsen Chapman University Dedicated to Hiroakira Ono on the occasion of his 7th birthday Introduction Residuated lattices

More information

REGULAR IDENTITIES IN LATTICES

REGULAR IDENTITIES IN LATTICES TRANSACTIONS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 158, Number 1, July 1971 REGULAR IDENTITIES IN LATTICES BY R. PADMANABHANC) Abstract. An algebraic system 3i = is called a quasilattice

More information

TIGHT RESIDUATED MAPPINGS. by Erik A. Schreiner. 1. Introduction In this note we examine the connection

TIGHT RESIDUATED MAPPINGS. by Erik A. Schreiner. 1. Introduction In this note we examine the connection Proc. Univ. of Houston Lattice Theory Conf..Houston 1973 TIGHT RESIDUATED MAPPINGS by Erik A. Schreiner 1. Introduction In this note we examine the connection between certain residuated mappings on a complete

More information

Notes on Ordered Sets

Notes on Ordered Sets Notes on Ordered Sets Mariusz Wodzicki September 10, 2013 1 Vocabulary 1.1 Definitions Definition 1.1 A binary relation on a set S is said to be a partial order if it is reflexive, x x, weakly antisymmetric,

More information

Chapter 1. Sets and Mappings

Chapter 1. Sets and Mappings Chapter 1. Sets and Mappings 1. Sets A set is considered to be a collection of objects (elements). If A is a set and x is an element of the set A, we say x is a member of A or x belongs to A, and we write

More information

Given a lattice L we will note the set of atoms of L by At (L), and with CoAt (L) the set of co-atoms of L.

Given a lattice L we will note the set of atoms of L by At (L), and with CoAt (L) the set of co-atoms of L. ACTAS DEL VIII CONGRESO DR. ANTONIO A. R. MONTEIRO (2005), Páginas 25 32 SOME REMARKS ON OCKHAM CONGRUENCES LEONARDO CABRER AND SERGIO CELANI ABSTRACT. In this work we shall describe the lattice of congruences

More information

On poset Boolean algebras

On poset Boolean algebras 1 On poset Boolean algebras Uri Abraham Department of Mathematics, Ben Gurion University, Beer-Sheva, Israel Robert Bonnet Laboratoire de Mathématiques, Université de Savoie, Le Bourget-du-Lac, France

More information

Christopher J. TAYLOR

Christopher J. TAYLOR REPORTS ON MATHEMATICAL LOGIC 51 (2016), 3 14 doi:10.4467/20842589rm.16.001.5278 Christopher J. TAYLOR DISCRIMINATOR VARIETIES OF DOUBLE-HEYTING ALGEBRAS A b s t r a c t. We prove that a variety of double-heyting

More information

Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G. Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21

Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G. Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21 Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21 Introduction These notes were originally prepared in July 1972 as a handout for a class in modern algebra taught at the Carnegie-Mellon

More information

A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries

A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries Johannes Marti and Riccardo Pinosio Draft from April 5, 2018 Abstract In this paper we present a duality between nonmonotonic

More information

Tree sets. Reinhard Diestel

Tree sets. Reinhard Diestel 1 Tree sets Reinhard Diestel Abstract We study an abstract notion of tree structure which generalizes treedecompositions of graphs and matroids. Unlike tree-decompositions, which are too closely linked

More information

Varieties of Heyting algebras and superintuitionistic logics

Varieties of Heyting algebras and superintuitionistic logics Varieties of Heyting algebras and superintuitionistic logics Nick Bezhanishvili Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam http://www.phil.uu.nl/~bezhanishvili email: N.Bezhanishvili@uva.nl

More information

Notes on CD-independent subsets

Notes on CD-independent subsets Acta Sci. Math. (Szeged) 78 (2012), 3 24 Notes on CD-independent subsets Eszter K. Horváth and Sándor Radeleczki Communicated by G. Czédli Abstract. It is proved in [8] that any two CD-bases in a finite

More information

TEST GROUPS FOR WHITEHEAD GROUPS

TEST GROUPS FOR WHITEHEAD GROUPS TEST GROUPS FOR WHITEHEAD GROUPS PAUL C. EKLOF, LÁSZLÓ FUCHS, AND SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. We consider the question of when the dual of a Whitehead group is a test group for Whitehead groups. This turns

More information

UNIVERSALITY OF THE LATTICE OF TRANSFORMATION MONOIDS

UNIVERSALITY OF THE LATTICE OF TRANSFORMATION MONOIDS UNIVERSALITY OF THE LATTICE OF TRANSFORMATION MONOIDS MICHAEL PINSKER AND SAHARON SHELAH Abstract. The set of all transformation monoids on a fixed set of infinite cardinality λ, equipped with the order

More information

Knowledge spaces from a topological point of view

Knowledge spaces from a topological point of view Knowledge spaces from a topological point of view V.I.Danilov Central Economics and Mathematics Institute of RAS Abstract In this paper we consider the operations of restriction, extension and gluing of

More information

Homogeneous Structures and Ramsey Classes

Homogeneous Structures and Ramsey Classes Homogeneous Structures and Ramsey Classes Julia Böttcher April 27, 2005 In this project report we discuss the relation between Ramsey classes and homogeneous structures and give various examples for both

More information

Congruence Boolean Lifting Property

Congruence Boolean Lifting Property Congruence Boolean Lifting Property George GEORGESCU and Claudia MUREŞAN University of Bucharest Faculty of Mathematics and Computer Science Academiei 14, RO 010014, Bucharest, Romania Emails: georgescu.capreni@yahoo.com;

More information

Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics.

Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics. MAT 200, Logic, Language and Proof, Fall 2015 Summary Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics. Definition. A proposition is a sentence which is either true or false. Truth table for the connective or :

More information

RELATION ALGEBRAS. Roger D. MADDUX. Department of Mathematics Iowa State University Ames, Iowa USA ELSEVIER

RELATION ALGEBRAS. Roger D. MADDUX. Department of Mathematics Iowa State University Ames, Iowa USA ELSEVIER RELATION ALGEBRAS Roger D. MADDUX Department of Mathematics Iowa State University Ames, Iowa 50011 USA ELSEVIER AMSTERDAM. BOSTON HEIDELBERG LONDON NEW YORK. OXFORD PARIS SAN DIEGO. SAN FRANCISCO. SINGAPORE.

More information

A CLASS OF INFINITE CONVEX GEOMETRIES

A CLASS OF INFINITE CONVEX GEOMETRIES A CLASS OF INFINITE CONVEX GEOMETRIES KIRA ADARICHEVA AND J. B. NATION Abstract. Various characterizations of finite convex geometries are well known. This note provides similar characterizations for possibly

More information

Semantics of intuitionistic propositional logic

Semantics of intuitionistic propositional logic Semantics of intuitionistic propositional logic Erik Palmgren Department of Mathematics, Uppsala University Lecture Notes for Applied Logic, Fall 2009 1 Introduction Intuitionistic logic is a weakening

More information

Unless otherwise specified, V denotes an arbitrary finite-dimensional vector space.

Unless otherwise specified, V denotes an arbitrary finite-dimensional vector space. MAT 90 // 0 points Exam Solutions Unless otherwise specified, V denotes an arbitrary finite-dimensional vector space..(0) Prove: a central arrangement A in V is essential if and only if the dual projective

More information

ON GENERATING DISTRIBUTIVE SUBLATTICES OF ORTHOMODULAR LATTICES

ON GENERATING DISTRIBUTIVE SUBLATTICES OF ORTHOMODULAR LATTICES PKOCkLDINGS OF Tlik AM1 KlCAN MATIiL'MATlCAL SOCIETY Vulume 67. Numher 1. November 1977 ON GENERATING DISTRIBUTIVE SUBLATTICES OF ORTHOMODULAR LATTICES RICHARD J. GREECHIE ABSTRACT.A Foulis-Holland set

More information

ON VARIETIES OF LEFT DISTRIBUTIVE LEFT IDEMPOTENT GROUPOIDS

ON VARIETIES OF LEFT DISTRIBUTIVE LEFT IDEMPOTENT GROUPOIDS ON VARIETIES OF LEFT DISTRIBUTIVE LEFT IDEMPOTENT GROUPOIDS DAVID STANOVSKÝ Abstract. We describe a part of the lattice of subvarieties of left distributive left idempotent groupoids (i.e. those satisfying

More information

Introduction to generalized topological spaces

Introduction to generalized topological spaces @ Applied General Topology c Universidad Politécnica de Valencia Volume 12, no. 1, 2011 pp. 49-66 Introduction to generalized topological spaces Irina Zvina Abstract We introduce the notion of generalized

More information

D-bounded Distance-Regular Graphs

D-bounded Distance-Regular Graphs D-bounded Distance-Regular Graphs CHIH-WEN WENG 53706 Abstract Let Γ = (X, R) denote a distance-regular graph with diameter D 3 and distance function δ. A (vertex) subgraph X is said to be weak-geodetically

More information

Universal Algebra for Logics

Universal Algebra for Logics Universal Algebra for Logics Joanna GRYGIEL University of Czestochowa Poland j.grygiel@ajd.czest.pl 2005 These notes form Lecture Notes of a short course which I will give at 1st School on Universal Logic

More information

Closure operators on sets and algebraic lattices

Closure operators on sets and algebraic lattices Closure operators on sets and algebraic lattices Sergiu Rudeanu University of Bucharest Romania Closure operators are abundant in mathematics; here are a few examples. Given an algebraic structure, such

More information

A GUIDE FOR MORTALS TO TAME CONGRUENCE THEORY

A GUIDE FOR MORTALS TO TAME CONGRUENCE THEORY A GUIDE FOR MORTALS TO TAME CONGRUENCE THEORY Tame congruence theory is not an easy subject and it takes a considerable amount of effort to understand it. When I started this project, I believed that this

More information

18.312: Algebraic Combinatorics Lionel Levine. Lecture 11

18.312: Algebraic Combinatorics Lionel Levine. Lecture 11 18.312: Algebraic Combinatorics Lionel Levine Lecture date: March 15, 2011 Lecture 11 Notes by: Ben Bond Today: Mobius Algebras, µ( n ). Test: The average was 17. If you got < 15, you have the option to

More information

Prime Properties of the Smallest Ideal of β N

Prime Properties of the Smallest Ideal of β N This paper was published in Semigroup Forum 52 (1996), 357-364. To the best of my knowledge, this is the final version as it was submitted to the publisher. NH Prime Properties of the Smallest Ideal of

More information

Criteria for existence of semigroup homomorphisms and projective rank functions. George M. Bergman

Criteria for existence of semigroup homomorphisms and projective rank functions. George M. Bergman Criteria for existence of semigroup homomorphisms and projective rank functions George M. Bergman Suppose A, S, and T are semigroups, e: A S and f: A T semigroup homomorphisms, and X a generating set for

More information

On productively Lindelöf spaces

On productively Lindelöf spaces JAMS 1 On productively Lindelöf spaces Michael Barr Department of Mathematics and Statistics McGill University, Montreal, QC, H3A 2K6 John F. Kennison Department of Mathematics and Computer Science Clark

More information

Scott Taylor 1. EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS. Definition 1.1. Let A be a set. An equivalence relation on A is a relation such that:

Scott Taylor 1. EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS. Definition 1.1. Let A be a set. An equivalence relation on A is a relation such that: Equivalence MA Relations 274 and Partitions Scott Taylor 1. EQUIVALENCE RELATIONS Definition 1.1. Let A be a set. An equivalence relation on A is a relation such that: (1) is reflexive. That is, (2) is

More information

Congruence lattices and Compact Intersection Property

Congruence lattices and Compact Intersection Property Congruence lattices and Compact Intersection Property Slovak Academy of Sciences, Košice June 8, 2013 Congruence lattices Problem. For a given class K of algebras describe Con K =all lattices isomorphic

More information

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.gm] 21 Jan 2005

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.gm] 21 Jan 2005 arxiv:math/0501340v1 [math.gm] 21 Jan 2005 SUBLATTICES OF LATTICES OF ORDER-CONVEX SETS, II. POSETS OF FINITE LENGTH MARINA SEMENOVA AND FRIEDRICH WEHRUNG Abstract. For a positive integer n, we denote

More information

The Blok-Ferreirim theorem for normal GBL-algebras and its application

The Blok-Ferreirim theorem for normal GBL-algebras and its application The Blok-Ferreirim theorem for normal GBL-algebras and its application Chapman University Department of Mathematics and Computer Science Orange, California University of Siena Department of Mathematics

More information

Cross Connection of Boolean Lattice

Cross Connection of Boolean Lattice International Journal of Algebra, Vol. 11, 2017, no. 4, 171-179 HIKARI Ltd, www.m-hikari.com https://doi.org/10.12988/ija.2017.7419 Cross Connection of Boolean Lattice P. G. Romeo P. R. Sreejamol Dept.

More information

An Algebraic View of the Relation between Largest Common Subtrees and Smallest Common Supertrees

An Algebraic View of the Relation between Largest Common Subtrees and Smallest Common Supertrees An Algebraic View of the Relation between Largest Common Subtrees and Smallest Common Supertrees Francesc Rosselló 1, Gabriel Valiente 2 1 Department of Mathematics and Computer Science, Research Institute

More information

Mathematics Course 111: Algebra I Part I: Algebraic Structures, Sets and Permutations

Mathematics Course 111: Algebra I Part I: Algebraic Structures, Sets and Permutations Mathematics Course 111: Algebra I Part I: Algebraic Structures, Sets and Permutations D. R. Wilkins Academic Year 1996-7 1 Number Systems and Matrix Algebra Integers The whole numbers 0, ±1, ±2, ±3, ±4,...

More information

Abstract Measure Theory

Abstract Measure Theory 2 Abstract Measure Theory Lebesgue measure is one of the premier examples of a measure on R d, but it is not the only measure and certainly not the only important measure on R d. Further, R d is not the

More information

A CLOSURE SYSTEM FOR ELEMENTARY SITUATIONS

A CLOSURE SYSTEM FOR ELEMENTARY SITUATIONS Bulletin of the Section of Logic Volume 11:3/4 (1982), pp. 134 138 reedition 2009 [original edition, pp. 134 139] Bogus law Wolniewicz A CLOSURE SYSTEM FOR ELEMENTARY SITUATIONS 1. Preliminaries In [4]

More information

A NEW CHARACTERIZATION OF COMPLETE HEYTING AND CO-HEYTING ALGEBRAS

A NEW CHARACTERIZATION OF COMPLETE HEYTING AND CO-HEYTING ALGEBRAS Logical Methods in Computer Science Vol. 13(3:252017, pp. 1 11 www.lmcs-online.org Submitted Apr. 15, 2015 Published Sep. 14, 2017 A NEW CHARACTERIZATION OF COMPLETE HEYTING AND CO-HEYTING ALGEBRAS FRANCESCO

More information

3. Abstract Boolean Algebras

3. Abstract Boolean Algebras 3. ABSTRACT BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS 123 3. Abstract Boolean Algebras 3.1. Abstract Boolean Algebra. Definition 3.1.1. An abstract Boolean algebra is defined as a set B containing two distinct elements 0 and 1,

More information

Finite homogeneous and lattice ordered effect algebras

Finite homogeneous and lattice ordered effect algebras Finite homogeneous and lattice ordered effect algebras Gejza Jenča Department of Mathematics Faculty of Electrical Engineering and Information Technology Slovak Technical University Ilkovičova 3 812 19

More information

A strongly rigid binary relation

A strongly rigid binary relation A strongly rigid binary relation Anne Fearnley 8 November 1994 Abstract A binary relation ρ on a set U is strongly rigid if every universal algebra on U such that ρ is a subuniverse of its square is trivial.

More information

Prime Rational Functions and Integral Polynomials. Jesse Larone, Bachelor of Science. Mathematics and Statistics

Prime Rational Functions and Integral Polynomials. Jesse Larone, Bachelor of Science. Mathematics and Statistics Prime Rational Functions and Integral Polynomials Jesse Larone, Bachelor of Science Mathematics and Statistics Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Science Faculty

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.co] 16 Feb 2018

arxiv: v1 [math.co] 16 Feb 2018 CHAIN POSETS arxiv:1802.05813v1 [math.co] 16 Feb 2018 IAN T. JOHNSON Abstract. A chain poset, by definition, consists of chains of ordered elements in a poset. We study the chain posets associated to two

More information

Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers

Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers 1. Sets A set is considered to be a collection of objects (elements). If A is a set and x is an element of the set A, we say x is a member of A or x belongs to A, and we write

More information

AN AXIOMATIC FORMATION THAT IS NOT A VARIETY

AN AXIOMATIC FORMATION THAT IS NOT A VARIETY AN AXIOMATIC FORMATION THAT IS NOT A VARIETY KEITH A. KEARNES Abstract. We show that any variety of groups that contains a finite nonsolvable group contains an axiomatic formation that is not a subvariety.

More information

Finite Simple Abelian Algebras are Strictly Simple

Finite Simple Abelian Algebras are Strictly Simple Finite Simple Abelian Algebras are Strictly Simple Matthew A. Valeriote Abstract A finite universal algebra is called strictly simple if it is simple and has no nontrivial subalgebras. An algebra is said

More information

CW complexes. Soren Hansen. This note is meant to give a short introduction to CW complexes.

CW complexes. Soren Hansen. This note is meant to give a short introduction to CW complexes. CW complexes Soren Hansen This note is meant to give a short introduction to CW complexes. 1. Notation and conventions In the following a space is a topological space and a map f : X Y between topological

More information

On varieties of modular ortholattices which are generated by their finite-dimensional members

On varieties of modular ortholattices which are generated by their finite-dimensional members On varieties of modular ortholattices which are generated by their finite-dimensional members Christian Herrmann and Micheale S. Roddy Abstract. We prove that the following three conditions on a modular

More information

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals 18 Andreas Gathmann 2. Prime and Maximal Ideals There are two special kinds of ideals that are of particular importance, both algebraically and geometrically: the so-called prime and maximal ideals. Let

More information

Definition: A binary relation R from a set A to a set B is a subset R A B. Example:

Definition: A binary relation R from a set A to a set B is a subset R A B. Example: Chapter 9 1 Binary Relations Definition: A binary relation R from a set A to a set B is a subset R A B. Example: Let A = {0,1,2} and B = {a,b} {(0, a), (0, b), (1,a), (2, b)} is a relation from A to B.

More information

Automata extended to nominal sets

Automata extended to nominal sets Bachelor thesis Computer Science Radboud University Automata extended to nominal sets Author: Joep Veldhoven s4456556 First supervisor/assessor: Jurriaan Rot jrot@cs.ru.nl Second and third supervisor:

More information

COMPACT ORTHOALGEBRAS

COMPACT ORTHOALGEBRAS COMPACT ORTHOALGEBRAS ALEXANDER WILCE Abstract. We initiate a study of topological orthoalgebras (TOAs), concentrating on the compact case. Examples of TOAs include topological orthomodular lattices, and

More information

Remarks on categorical equivalence of finite unary algebras

Remarks on categorical equivalence of finite unary algebras Remarks on categorical equivalence of finite unary algebras 1. Background M. Krasner s original theorems from 1939 say that a finite algebra A (1) is an essentially multiunary algebra in which all operations

More information

MAD 3105 PRACTICE TEST 2 SOLUTIONS

MAD 3105 PRACTICE TEST 2 SOLUTIONS MAD 3105 PRACTICE TEST 2 SOLUTIONS 1. Let R be the relation defined below. Determine which properties, reflexive, irreflexive, symmetric, antisymmetric, transitive, the relation satisfies. Prove each answer.

More information

Thus, X is connected by Problem 4. Case 3: X = (a, b]. This case is analogous to Case 2. Case 4: X = (a, b). Choose ε < b a

Thus, X is connected by Problem 4. Case 3: X = (a, b]. This case is analogous to Case 2. Case 4: X = (a, b). Choose ε < b a Solutions to Homework #6 1. Complete the proof of the backwards direction of Theorem 12.2 from class (which asserts the any interval in R is connected). Solution: Let X R be a closed interval. Case 1:

More information

SEPARATION AXIOMS FOR INTERVAL TOPOLOGIES

SEPARATION AXIOMS FOR INTERVAL TOPOLOGIES PROCEEDINGS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 79, Number 2, June 1980 SEPARATION AXIOMS FOR INTERVAL TOPOLOGIES MARCEL ERNE Abstract. In Theorem 1 of this note, results of Kogan [2], Kolibiar

More information

NOTES ON THE FINITE LATTICE REPRESENTATION PROBLEM

NOTES ON THE FINITE LATTICE REPRESENTATION PROBLEM NOTES ON THE FINITE LATTICE REPRESENTATION PROBLEM WILLIAM J. DEMEO Notation and Terminology. Given a finite lattice L, the expression L = [H, G] means there exist finite groups H < G such that L is isomorphic

More information

Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra

Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra D. R. Wilkins Contents 3 Topics in Commutative Algebra 2 3.1 Rings and Fields......................... 2 3.2 Ideals...............................

More information

Duality in Logic. Duality in Logic. Lecture 2. Mai Gehrke. Université Paris 7 and CNRS. {ε} A ((ab) (ba) ) (ab) + (ba) +

Duality in Logic. Duality in Logic. Lecture 2. Mai Gehrke. Université Paris 7 and CNRS. {ε} A ((ab) (ba) ) (ab) + (ba) + Lecture 2 Mai Gehrke Université Paris 7 and CNRS A {ε} A ((ab) (ba) ) (ab) + (ba) + Further examples - revisited 1. Completeness of modal logic with respect to Kripke semantics was obtained via duality

More information