Centre de Referència en Economia Analítica

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Centre de Referència en Economia Analítica"

Transcription

1 Centre de Reerència en Economia Analítica Barcelona Economics Working Paper Series Working Paper nº 166 A Theorem on Preerence Aggregation Salvador Barberà July, 2003

2 A THEOREM ON PREFERENCE AGGREGATION Salvador Barberà * Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona Barcelona Economics WP nº 166 This Drat: July, 2003 Abstract I present a general theorem on preerence aggregation. This theorem implies, as corollaries, Arrow s Impossibility Theorem, Wilson s extension o Arrow s to non-paretian aggregation rules, the Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem and Sen s result on the Impossibility o a Paretian Liberal. The theorem shows that these classical results are not only similar, but actually share a common root. The theorem expresses a simple but deep act that transcends each o its particular applications: it expresses the tension between decentralizing the choice o aggregate into partial choices based on preerences over pairs o alternatives, and the need or some coordination in these decisions, so as to avoid contradictory recommendations. * This paper is based on the second part o my invited lecture at the 5th meeting o the Social Choice and Welare Society (Alicante, June 29 - July 2, 2000). I am grateul to Michael Florig, Jean Fraysse, Matthew Jackson, Cristina Rata, Peter Vida and especially to Carmen Beviá or their comments and help. I thank the editor o Social Choice and Welare and one anonymous reeree or their careul comments, and Bernard Monjardet or extensive historical remarks, rom which I have drawn reely. Financial support rom the Spanish Ministry o Education and Culture through grant PB , rom the Spanish Ministry o Science and Technology through 1

3 1. Introduction I present a general theorem on preerence aggregation. The substance o the theorem is to exhibit the tension between two general principles. One principle would consider the possibility o decomposing the choice o a social aggregate into a set o partial decisions, each one based on pairwise comparisons o alternatives. The other principle would require that no agent plays a dominant role in the aggregation process. I show that, in the presence o some other requirements, decomposable rules can only avoid contradictory recommendations in the presence o the strongest coordination device: a single agent being determinant at all times on all aspects o the global decision. The theorem implies, as corollaries, Arrow's Impossibility Theorem, Wilson's extension o Arrow's theorem to non-paretian aggregation rules, the Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem and Sen's result on the Impossibility o a Paretian Liberal. Hence, one contribution o the paper is to provide a common ramework that includes as particular cases all the dierent classes o aggregation rules that these classic theorems reer to. This allows us to understand the many connections that had already been noted among the substance and also among the proos o these dierent results. In particular, it clariies that the connections between Arrow's and Gibbard's results go deeper than any parallelism in their proos; both come rom a common root. It also allows us to note the intimate connection between other results, like Arrow's and Sen's, which had passed less noticed (with some signiicant exceptions that I reer to later). Arrow s and Wilson s theorems consider social welare unctions. The Gibbard- Satterthwaite theorem applies to social choice unctions, and Sen s result is expressed or social decision unctions. All o these unctions have a common domain: the proiles o individual preerences on some set o alternatives. All o them map these proiles into some type o related object, which we call an aggregate. Aggregates are dierent objects in each o these ormulations. In Arrow s and Wilson s ramework, an aggregate is a preerence order satisying the same properties that are required rom individual preerences. In Sen s ormulation, an aggregate is an acyclic binary relation (thus not necessarily transitive when social indierences are allowed). In the context where the Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem applies, aggregates are simply alternatives. My theorem reers to preerence aggregation rules. These are unctions which map proiles o preerences on alternatives into some set o unspeciied objects, to be called aggregates. They include all o the above as special cases. Speciically, the theorem concentrates on the class o preerence aggregation rules that I call local. All o the classical results I have mentioned reer to special cases o local aggregation. It is thus important to clariy the concept immediately. Local aggregation rules are based on the idea that dierent parts o the inormation contained in preerence proiles can be used in making partial choices among aggregates, and that these partial choices eventually determine the one aggregate which corresponds to each grant BEC , and rom the Generalitat o Catalonia through grant SGR is grateully acknowledged. 2

4 proile. Not all preerence aggregation rules admit a description in these terms, but many do. Formal deinitions come in Section 2, but we should discuss immediately the meaning o local aggregation. When given an aggregation rule, it may be hard to ind out what is the algorithm, the procedure or the set o considerations which lead to associate a certain aggregate to a given preerence proile. But here is one possible way to do it, which characterizes local aggregation: (1) First, identiy some pieces o inormation that will be considered relevant. In our ormulation o local rules, we'll consider that the set o comparisons made by the agents between each pair o alternatives are the pieces o relevant inormation. (2) Second, associate a set o aggregates to each piece o relevant inormation. We can consider this set as the collection o aggregates that are admissible, given the inormation at hand. For example, i aggregators are binary relations, (like those we obtain rom majority rule), we can associate to each set o individual comparisons between x and y the set o all binary relations which rank x as preerred to y, or the set o all those which rank y over x. As another example, consider social choice unctions, which aggregate preerences and choose one alternative to be the aggregate. In that case, a local rule could associate a set o alternatives to each piece o relevant inormation, and interpret that the elements in each o these sets are the potential aggregates whose choice is not precluded by the inormation available. (3) Third, describe the social aggregate as the result o combining the use o all the relevant pieces o inormation. Speciically, the chosen aggregate should be the one (and only one, in our ormulation), which belongs to all the sets o non-excluded aggregates obtained rom using all the available pieces o relevant inormation. They can be a binary relation, obtained as the intersection o sets o binary relations, or an alternative, resulting rom intersecting sets o alternatives, or any other abstract object which belongs to the intersection o sets o objects in the relevant class o aggregates. Limiting attention to local rules is somewhat restrictive. Many aggregation rules one can think o, like the Borda counts and other point voting rules, do not adjust to the structure required by this condition. But we shall see that a theorem on local rules is able to cover substantial ground. More speciically, the theorem is about local and restricted aggregation rules. As already pointed out, the aggregates obtained rom a local rule can be described as combinations o objects that satisy some eatures, but not all combinations o eatures are necessarily acceptable to orm an aggregate. For example, the eature o ranking x over y is acceptable or aggregates which are orders. So is ranking y over z. And so is ranking z over x. These three eatures would be compatible i the binary relation which results rom aggregation was not restricted any urther, as with majority rule. But the three eatures together cannot be met by an aggregate binary relation, i we urther require this relation to satisy transitivity, as Arrow or Wilson do, or acyclicity, as in Sen. Similarly, admissible eatures o an aggregate in the Gibbard-Satterthwaite setting are that the aggregate is not x, that it is not y, and so on, or any possible alternative. But the union o all these eatures cannot be met by any aggregate, because only the empty set, which is not an acceptable aggregate, can meet them all. Again in Section 2, I provide a ormal deinition or a local rule to be restricted, which is enough to capture all the limitations in the choice o an aggregate that is imposed by our classical reerence theorems, in each o the cases. 3

5 As pointed out by Bernard Monjardet in private correspondence, this view o an aggregation process is not only natural but has a long tradition. I quote rom Monjardet s generous comments: "In his Memoire Recherches sur la loi de croissance de I'homme published in 1832 the statistician and social scientist Quetelet proposed to deine the "mean man" o a population o men described by several measurable characteristics by taking the means on each characteristics. This conception was severely criticized by people like the mathematician Cournot which remarked (In Exposition de la théorie des chances, Paris 1843) that this mean man could be nothing else that an impossible man. Indeed one meets a similar "paradox" by considering the triangle obtained by taking the 3 means o the lengths o the corresponding sides o a set o rectangular triangles; this triangle is not necessary rectangular. More generally Cournot writes: "Lorsqu'on applique la détermination des moyennes aux diverses parties d'un système compliqué, il aut bien prendre garde que ces valeurs moyennes peuvent ne pas se convertir: en sorte que l'état du système dans lequel tous les elements prendraint à la ois le valeurs moyennes déterminées séparément pour chacun d'eux serait un état impossible" 1. For Cournot, a 19 th century mathematician, a mean is any mathematical mean deined on numerical values. But more generally any p-ary operation deined on a set and satisying some properties (like idempotence) can be called a mean and the Cournot text can be applied to any aggregation procedure which is "local" in the sense that it is obtained by 1) Decomposing the set o complex objects (to aggregate) into sets o simple objects. 2) Applying mean operation to each o the sets. 3) Recomposing a complex object rom obtained simple objects. The "eet Condorcet" (or paradox o voting) is another amous example o the diiculty met by such a procedure and the relation between these various aggregation paradoxes and the Arrow's theorem has been developed in the (unortunately not suiciently read) 1952 paper by Guilbaud. Let me just add that in the present ormulation I have been completely agnostic about the nature o the object to be called an aggregate. This radical decision makes it hard to give explicit meaning to attractive notions like that o a mean, or that o closeness. Otherwise, I eel very comortable and happy to work within a model with such an old and distinguished tradition. Within the realm o local and restricted aggregators, the theorem expresses a tension between two eatures which are essential in the description o a rule: these are its lexibility, and the way in which it distributes among agents the power to inluence its result. We say that a rule is lexible i two conditions hold: one, that or each pair o alternatives, the rule's outcome is sometimes sensitive to changes in the relative positions o these two alternatives alone; and two, that this sensitivity should not be conditional on the position o any third 1 Compare with my previous remark that "since not all combinations o characteristics or an aggregate are jointly compatible, the ully decentralized choices o characteristics or aggregators across dierent pairs o alternatives may be contradictory". 4

6 alternative. We say that one agent concentrates all power under a rule i only the preerences o this agent (when they are strict) determine the social aggregate. I prove that i a preerence aggregation rule is local and restricted, then either it is not lexible or else it gives all decision power to a single individual. From this theorem we can derive as corollaries all the above mentioned classical results. Providing a common ramework or such disparate theorems is interesting per se. In some cases (Arrow and Wilson), the close connection was obvious rom the start. Yet, the present ormulation allows or a better understanding o the role played by the Pareto condition in Arrow, and in particular reinorces Wilson s message that this role is quite limited. In the case o Arrow and Gibbard-Satterthwaite, the existence o a close connection has been very well understood or years, but claiming that both results are a corollary o a unique theorem is a stronger and novel statement. The connection established here between Sen s result and the rest may be more problematic because Sen's model and its interpretation are themselves subject to debate (Salles, 2000). At any rate, Saari (1998) had emphasized the relationship between Sen s and Arrow s result, by using a dierent line o argument. We discuss all these connections later, in Section 3. I do not want to leave the reader with the impression that all I do here is to orce old results into a common rame or the sake o it. I already pointed out that the theorem has content and meaning o its own: the tensions between locality, restriction and lexibility can only be solved by an extreme distribution o decision power. Moreover, this content is clearly relected in the structure o its proo, which ollows the essential line o two proos o Arrow s and Gibbard-Satterthwaite s theorem that I provided some twenty years ago (Barberà, 1980, 1983a, 1983b). These separate proos are now blended into a single one, which reveals the essence o the diiculty at hand. Local aggregation requires the decomposition o our choice o aggregate into partial choices, each o which must be exclusively dependent on the relative positions o some pair o alternatives. Although possibly centralized among agents, decisions are decentralized in terms o the inluence exerted by dierent pairs o alternatives in determining which aggregates are ruled out as possible candidates. Since not all combinations o characteristics or an aggregate are jointly compatible, the ully decentralized choices o characteristics or aggregators across dierent pairs o alternatives may be contradictory. Some connections must be ensured between the choices made or some pairs and the choices made by some others. It turns out that, or any given preerence proile, and as long as rules are lexible, this restricts the ability to inluence the choice o aggregate to a single agent. Moreover, this local concentration o power extends to become global: only a single agent can make a dierence, at any preerence proile (as long as this agent holds strict preerences). The need or coordinated action becomes extreme: only one agent can make any dierence at all! Beore I inish this Introduction, let me comment on some related papers. The connections between Arrow's theorem and the issue o manipulability had been remarked (see Vickrey, 1960) even beore Gibbard's ormulation o his celebrated theorem. Gibbard's proo relies on Arrow's, and establishes a connection that was later stressed by Satterthwaite (1975), Mueller and Satterthwaite (1977) and many other authors. One should point out that the possibility o deining a nondictatorial Arrowian Social Welare Function on a given domain 5

7 o preerences, or that o deining a nondictatorial strategy-proo social choice unction on the same domain are logically independent questions: there are domains where one o the two objectives can be achieved and not the other. But the connection is tight or universal domains, the ones considered here, and also or the domains o single-peaked preerences (Barberà, Gul and Stacchetti, 1993). For universal domains, the present theorem oers a convincing explanation o why so many parallels have been observed between the two classics: there is a general statement that covers both! Regarding proos, Arrow's own (Arrow 1963), which has been reined by many other authors (see Sen, 1970, or a very nice version), relies on a careul analysis o the global decision power o coalitions: it is irst observed that, under Arrow's conditions, i a coalition is decisive or a pair it must be decisive or all pairs; it is then proven that i a coalition is decisive and can be broken into subcoalitions, one o these subcoalitions must also be decisive; inally, observing that the grand coalition is decisive allows to prove the theorem. In the preceding argument, decisiveness is the ability to determine the outcome o aggregation at all preerence proiles: a coalition is either decisive or not. As already mentioned, Gibbard's (1973) early proo, and many that ollowed, used a construct that allowed to prove that result by indirectly appealing to Arrow's theorem. There exist many proos o the Gibbard- Satterthwaite theorem, using dierent approaches. Those by Schmeidler and Sonnenschein (1978), Batteau, Blin and Monjardet (1981) or Barberà and Peleg (1990) did constitute real innovations by the time they appeared. Recent interest on the subject is obvious: three simple proos o the theorem have been published recently (Benoit, 2000; Sen, 2001; and Reny, 2001). One o them (Reny, 2001) highlights the parallelism between the proos o Arrow and (one o the) proos o Gibbard-Satterthwaite. A very recent paper by Eliaz (2001) makes the point that both theorems are corollaries o a larger result. In that sense, the paper by Eliaz emphasizes, as my paper does, the act that there is a deeper connection between these results than just a parallelism. Other than that, however, the paper by Eliaz and the present paper proceed quite dierently, both in the ormal model and in the type o proo. My strategy o proo here ollows the line o my already mentioned papers in the early eighties (Barberà 1980, 1983a, 1983b), which were the irst to exploit the role o pivotal voters. The proo starts by considering the ability o agents to change the outcomes o the aggregation process at a given preerence proile: it concentrates on a local property. Then I proceed to show that, under the conditions o the paper, i one agent can aect the outcome o the aggregation process at some proile, it must be able to aect it at any proile. The paper is organized as ollows. First, I present notation, ormal deinitions and a statement o the theorem in a simpliied ramework (Section 2). Then I discuss the relationship between the general theorem and the classical results (Section 3). Section 4 concludes, with a discussion o the possibility or a more general version o the theorem and its proo. 6

8 2. A simple version o the Theorem Let N = { 1,2,..., n} be a inite set o agents ( n 2). Let X = { x, y,... } be a inite set o alternatives ( X 3). Let A = { a 1 a,... } be a set o aggregates., 2 A 2 stands or the power set o A. A is the set o singletons in 2. D stands or the set o distinct pairs o alternatives. Let P be the set o linear orders 2 (complete, antisymmetric, transitive binary relations) on X. Elements o P are called preerences. n Elements o P are preerence proiles. Preerence proiles are denoted by P, P ', etc. Given a preerence proile P, and any set S o alternatives, denote by P(S) the proile o preerences on S such that, or all i N, P i (S) is the restriction o i s preerence P i to the set S. In particular, we denote by P() the preerence proile on the pair x, y induced by the proile P on X. A Alternatives x and y are contiguous in Pi i or all z X, z { x, y}, zpi x zpi y. Alternatives x and y are contiguous in P i they are contiguous in Pi, or all i N. Proiles P where two alternatives are contiguous play an important role in my setup, because they can be changed to other proiles P ' where P( ) P'( ) while keeping P ( zw) = P' ( zw) or all other pairs z, w other than x, y. Proiles P and P ' are -equivalent i P ( ) = P'( ). Otherwise, say that P and P ' ' dier on x, y. Proiles P and P only dier on x,y i they dier on x, y, and they are zw - equivalent or any pair z, w other than x, y. Clearly, i P and P ' only dier on x, y it must be that x and y are contiguous in the preerences o all agents, both in P and P '. or all Proiles P and ' P ' dier on i i P. They only dier on i i P and i P i ' i P i j i. They only dier on x,y or i, i they only dier on i and they only dier on ' P j = P j x, y. Contiguity o a pair o alternatives is a special case o what I will call connectedness o a set o alternatives with respect to a preerence. Formally, B X is connected in Pi i only i or all x, y B, z A \ B, zpix zpi y. B is connected in P i it is connected or all Pi 's. 2 Notice that I assume preerences to be strict (no indierences are allowed among dierent alternatives, by antisymmetry). This simpliies the exposition. 7

9 n An aggregation rule (on the universal domain P ) is a unction : P n A assigning a single aggregate to each preerence proile 3. P n and An aggregation rule is local i or each pair { 2 A \, such that ( P) = Ι g ( P) (1) or each x, y X, P, P ', x, y D, ' ' [ P( ) = P ( )] [ g ( P) g ( P )], x, y } D, there exist unctions = g : that is, g is a unction o x and y 's relative position in a proile, or any proile. (2) the range r o consists o two distinct sets o aggregates T, T, or all x, y X g 4. g 2 1 A Locality is a demanding requirement on aggregation rules. Locality requires that the global decision on which aggregator to attach to any given preerence proile should be decomposable into partial decisions, one or each pair o alternatives, depending only on the ranking o this pair o alternatives in the proile 5. Each partial decision attached to one pair o alternatives is a set o aggregators, and the global decision is the unique aggregator belonging to all o the sets selected, or each pair o alternatives, given the preerence proile. Locality 3 Notice that I model the unction as choosing a singleton set in A, rather than an alternative in A. This is to keep as ormal as possible. 4 This second requirement could be relaxed to cover several additional interesting cases. In particular, I could allow or the image o some s to consist o a single value. This would leave room to include the constant g unctions (and others) among the local we could also allow or more than two sets in the range. This would extend the reach o the theorem s applications to cover, among others, the case o Arrowian aggregation when social preerences can express indierence between pairs o alternatives. And it would require a careul modiication o the way to deine restricted aggregators (see my concluding remarks). I have chosen to keep this somewhat restrictive requirement (2) or expositional clarity. 5 O course, this is extremely close to the idea that the aggregation rule satisies Arrow's Independence o Irrelevant Alternatives. But I preer to reer to it by another term because (1) it applies to a larger context, and (2) it implies the description o aggregation as the intersection o sets, which is neither necessary nor implied by Arrow's ormulation. 8

10 also requires that the set o aggregators g (P) associated to each -pair at proile P should only depend on the relative ranking o x and y in the preerences o the agents, at that proile. Finally, the range o the partial decision unctions is restricted to a limited number o values. In the present ormulation, the ranges o these unctions are restricted to be dichotomic. The rules g associated to a local aggregation rule are called 's partial selection rules. For any range o g P, (P) is either T or T. I denote by g 1 g which is not chosen at P. 2 [ g ] comp P) ( the element in the Beore we proceed, let us see how this ormulation applies to the rameworks o other classical results. Consider the simple version o Arrow s theorem where the preerences o agents, as well as the preerences or society (the aggregates) are required to be linear orders. First notice that under the assumption o Independence o Irrelevant Alternatives, the social order between any two alternatives x, y, at any preerence proile P, will be determined only by the ranking o x and y in the preerences o individuals at P. Hence, given a preerence proile and two alternatives, x, y, one o the two possibilities x preerred to y or y preerred to x will be excluded. The set o all orders o alternatives ranking x and y in the nonexcluded position will be the image o the unction g (P) or each P. Indeed, the image (P) will be the order respecting the nonexcluded positions or all pairs. Hence, it is clear that any IIA social welare unction can be written as a local aggregation unction, where the aggregate is the intersection o sets o nonexcluded orders; a similar reasoning applies in the ramework considered by Wilson. The analysis o strategy proo rules as local aggregators builds on two essential remarks already made by Gibbard (1973). One is that, when all agents agree that all alternatives in a set S are preerred by all agents to all alternatives in X \ S, then a strategyproo social choice unction must choose rom S. (I assume here that the set o alternatives equals the range o a strategy-proo social choice unction. I not, drop the alternatives not in the range and start again, with no loss o generality). This implies, in particular, unanimity: an alternative must be chosen i it is unanimously considered to be the best by all agents. The second remark is that, i an alternative x is chosen when x and y are the best two alternatives or all agents, then y cannot be chosen at any preerence proile where the order o these two alternatives is preserved. Building on these two remarks, notice that the outcome at each proile can be written in the orm demanded by a local aggregate. For each given proile P, and each pair x, y, determine which one o the two alternatives is deinitely a noncandidate to be the aggregate at this proile. For this, check which one o the two alternatives would not be elected at the proile P() obtained rom P and where, ceteris paribus, x and y become the top two alternatives rom all agents. 9

11 Now, any strategy-proo social choice unction can be written as a local aggregation unction, where or each pair o alternatives x, y, either the set X \ x or the set X \ y are retained (the one not containing the alternative which is eliminated by pairwise comparisons). The aggregate corresponding to each proile must clearly be expressed as the intersection o all the sets o non-excluded alternatives, or each pairwise comparison. Having illustrated the basic eatures o local aggregation rules, let us now go back to study some urther requirements. Given a local aggregation rule, and a set o pairs D D deine Ι x, y D G( P, D) = g ( P). We can interpret G( P, D) as the set o aggregates which are not excluded on the basis o the comparisons o pairs in D. Clearly, with this notation, G(P, D ) = (P), or all P. We say that is -sensitive at P i comp ( P) = G (P, D) G( P, D \ { x, y} ) g ( P). Thus, is -sensitive at P i a change in the value o the -partial selection would change the value o the global selection o aggregate. The notion o sensitivity is introduced because it is not always the case that the change in one o the partial decisions associated to one pair o alternatives can change the global outcome. This depends on the type o aggregate we consider. Since we want to cover dierent types o aggregates, and provide a result that is independent o the type o aggregate under consideration, we cannot be more speciic on the connections between changes in the partial decisions and eventual changes in the aggregate. In Arrow's ramework, where each partial decision determines the ranking o a pair o alternatives within the overall ranking o alternatives, any change in one partial decision is translated into a change in the aggregate. Yet, in Gibbard's ramework, the same is not true. Starting rom some preerence proile, you may change the partial recommendation on a pair x, y, and yet see a third alternative z be elected beore and ater the change: the aggregation rule would not then be -sensitive at that proile. We say that is restricted i, or all x, y, z X, and all proiles P where is - sensitive and yz-sensitive, there exist sets and in the range o and g or which G( P, D \ { y} T r x,, { z} yz T s y, ) T yz r T A. s g yz 10

12 To better understand this assumption, let us again go back to examples. In Arrow's ramework, or each unction, the range consists o two possible outcomes, each o which g is a set o orders: the orders with x over y, on the one hand, and the orders with y over x, on the other. The act that aggregates must be orders implies that our aggregation unction must be restricted: indeed, take any proile and any triple x, y, z. I at the initial proile P we have x over y, then the set o orders with x over y appears in the intersection o values deining the aggregate at P. Then, the set o orders with y over z, and the set o orders with yz g xz g z over x, both in the ranges o and, respectively, will have an empty intersection with the rest o sets o orders deining the value o at P. Likewise, i at P we had that y stood over x, then the choices o sets o orders with x over z and z over y would have led to the empty intersection required by restriction. Thus, the condition called restriction in our general theorem corresponds in Arrow s theorem to the requirement o transitivity o the social aggregate. The social choice unctions in Gibbard-Satterthwaite are also restricted local aggregators: indeed, or each pair o alternatives, the ranges o the unctions consist o two well-deined sets: all alternatives except x and all alternatives except y. Notice that, or any triple x, y, z o alternatives, and any proile P where is -sensitive and also yz - sensitive, the intersection o all the partial selections at P, other than those or and yz, must contain x, y and z. But then, the choice o X \ y rom the range o, coupled with the choice o X \ y, as well, rom the range o g, would leave us with both x and z in the overall intersection. Since only singletons, not two-element sets o aggregates, can be in the range o, we have identiied a restriction to be satisied by the social choice unctions considered in the Gibbard-Satterthwaite setup. Hence, a rule is restricted i not all partial choices or dierent pairs are compatible with an acceptable global choice, when these partial choices do make a dierence. A restricted local aggregation rule is thus one or which the choices o the dierent sets o aggregates associated to each pair o alternatives is not completely ree: some combinations o potential choices would not be able to produce any aggregate at all. Hence, some coordination among partial outcomes will be necessary in order to obtain one and only one aggregator or each particular proile. We say that is lexible i or some triple o alternatives x, y, z X, there is some proile P at which z} (1) The set { x, y, is connected in the preerences o all agents at P, (2) is -sensitive and also yz -sensitive at P, xz comp (3) G( P,D\{ x, y},{ x, z}) ( g ( P)) ( g ( P)) G( P,D\{ x, y},{ x, z} ) ( g yz g g ( P)) comp ( g xz ( P)) comp, 11

13 P and y, z,{ x, z} yz xz comp g ( P)) ( g ( P)) G(,D\{ } ) ( P G(,D\{ x, y},{ z} x, ) ( g yz ( P)) comp ( g xz ( P)) comp, In words, condition 3 requires that 's -sensitivity and yz-sensitivity at P would be xz preserved by changes in the value o g. Flexibility encompasses two requirements. One is that, or each pair o alternatives, their relative position alone can sometime make a dierence. The other, complementary requirement, is that i the relative positions o two pairs make a dierence at the same proile, then the relative position o any third alternative does not aect the rule s sensitivity with regard to any o these two pairs. In Arrow's ramework, lexibility is an implication o the Pareto axiom and IIA. In Gibbard's and Satterthwaite's, the connection requires more care and it is discussed below, in section 3.4. Agent i concentrates all power under rule i, or all preerence proiles P, P ' and all pairs x, y, be written as ' [ P ( ) P ( ) ] g ( P) g ( P' ) =. i i = Notice that, then, we can write each partial unction as g P ), and that then can P ), or all P. ( i ( i Also notice that a dictator (with strict preerences) concentrates all power, but that an anti-dictator also does, and so do any agents whose preerences are the only relevant inputs to determine the outcome o an aggregation rule. Theorem I an aggregation rule is local, lexible and restricted, then there is a single agent i who concentrates all the power under. Proo Let be local, lexible and restricted. We irst provide some useul deinitions. We say that agent i is -pivotal at preerence proile P i P ' such that P and P ' only dier in or agent i and such that ( P) ( P' ). (Clearly, i agent i is -pivotal at P, he is also -pivotal at P '.) 12

14 Remark (and Remark that i P and P ' only dier in or agent i, and is -sensitive at P P ' ), then i is -pivotal at P (and P ' ). Lemma 1 The proo is organized through a sequence o simple Lemmas. I i is -pivotal at proile P, P ' only diers rom P in j 's ranking o x, } and ( P ) = ( P' ), then i is still -pivotal at P '. { z, w} { y Proo Just notice that, since ( P) = ( P' ) and i is -pivotal, it must be that (P, D \ x, y ) = G( P' D \ { x, y}). G { }, Lemma 2 and There cannot be any proile P at which two dierent agents i and j are -pivotal yz -pivotal, respectively, with x and y contiguous in P and y and z contiguous in P. i j Proo P i Suppose there was, and that i, j were the preerences (with x and y contiguous in P, and y and z contiguous in ) such that ( P, P ) ( P), ( P, P ) ( P). Then, P j we can write the images (P), (P, ), ( P P ), ( P ij P ) as r i P i P G( P, D \ { y} i x,, { y, z} i j, j,, P i j g r yz s ) T T, or all possible choices o T in the range o and T in the range o ( use Lemma 1). Hence, one o these our possible outcomes cannot be an aggregate, because is restricted. Lemma 3 There is an agent who concentrates all power under rule. yz s j j yz g 13

15 Proo Since is lexible, P and x, y, z X such that (1) the set { x, y, z} is connected in the preerences o all agents at P, and (2) is -sensitive and also yz -sensitive at P. '' Notice that, since is -sensitive at P there must exist P ', P such that they only dier on { x, y} in i and g ( P' ) g ( P" ). Similarly, there must exist P ~, Pˆ and j such that yz ~ they only dier on { y, in j, and g yz (Pˆ) g (P). z} Since x, y and z are connected, it is possible to ind a proile P where x, y and y} are still connected, where { x, are contiguous in i y, z are contiguous in P j, and i is -pivotal, while j is yz -pivotal. We use here condition 3 in the deinition o lexibility, since in such proile the relative position o xz or zy may be dierent that at the original P. Only one o these two needs to be changed in order to meet the requirements. To see that, notice that i an agent is -pivot when x and y are contiguous, the agent is still pivot when its preerences over x and y are switched. P, { } But now we have the conditions o Lemma 1. Hence, only one agent can be pivotal at this proile, and it is pivotal or two dierent pairs. From this point on, we can start switching the preerences o any agent or dierent pairs o contiguous alternatives including any one o the three alternatives x, y or z in question. No such change alter the outcome i it happens or any agent other than i, since that would lead us to the situation o Lemma 2. Hence, at some proile we shall eventually get a pivot or the pair, and this pivot will necessarily be i again. That general argument can be applied repeatedly to conclude that the same agent i must be pivot at some proile or all pairs o alternatives and hence concentrate all the power under. z 3. Some applications and corollaries In what ollows, I present a sketchy discussion o why the new theorem does indeed cover the setups or which dierent results were initially ormulated, and how the particular conditions under which the classical theorems hold are particular versions o those imposed here. 14

16 3.1. Arrow's ramework and Theorem We have already discussed why Arrowian Social Welare unctions are local and restricted. Notice now that the Pareto condition imposed by Arrow implies lexibility. Indeed, or proiles where all agents agree that x is preerred to y, x must be preerred to y socially, and the reverse must hold when all agents rank y over x. By changing the preerences one by one, reversing the order o x and y, starting rom a proile where x and y are contiguous and all agents preer x to y, and moving to one where they all preer y to x, it must be that one agent is -pivotal at some o the proiles in this sequence. This can be done or other pairs yz. Moreover, -pivotality and yz -pivotality can be preserved in proiles where the conditions o lexibility do hold. It is thus obvious that an Arrowian social welare unction must be a local, restricted and lexible aggregator: hence, all the decision power must be concentrated in an agent. Moreover, again by Pareto, this agent obtains the ranking x over y whenever he preers x to y : this is the dictator Wilson s theorem The initial ramework is the same as Arrow s: IIA implies locality and transitivity implies that the aggregation unction is restricted. Unlike in Arrow s ormulation, lexibility does not come rom Pareto, but rom the range condition requiring that x should be ranked above y or some proile, and below y or some other. The same construction as beore, but having as extremes two such proiles with x and y contiguous, shows the existence o -pivots or all pairs. Hence, one agent always concentrates all decision power: but this agent may be getting always the same order among pairs o alternatives that he expresses, or the reverse. Because Pareto does not necessarily apply, the individual who concentrates the power may be a dictator or an anti-dictator. Other combinations, where the agent might be a dictator over some pairs, and an anti-dictator over other pairs are excluded by restriction. For example, i some pairs were ordered according to the preerences o one agent and others in the opposite direction than the preerences o the same agent, this could easily lead to cycles. On the other hand, we may consider the constant unction as an example o an aggregation rule which satisies all o our conditions except or lexibility and locality 6. This is the other type o aggregator obtained by Wilson, again violating the Pareto condition. 6 I we had chosen to use a more general deinition o locality as discussed in Aizerman and Aleskerov (1995), then the constant unction could be accommodated among the local ones, while still violating lexibility. 15

17 3.3. Sen s impossibility o a Paretian liberal The essential remark regarding Sen s result is that, it postulates explicitly as desiderata the two conditions which are stated by our theorem to be incompatible under local and restricted rules. One o them is the Pareto condition: we have already seen that this condition, or a universal domain o preerences, implies that the aggregation unction must be lexible. The other condition imposed by Sen is that at least two agents must be able to determine the strict ranking o two alternatives each (these two alternatives describe social states which are identical except or some eatures over which the agent in question is entitled to have ull control. This is the condition o (minimal) liberalism, a condition which is in open contradiction with the possibility o one agent holding all the decision power under an aggregation rule. The interpretation o this ability to determine the ranking o some alternatives is subject to debate, because Sen is reerring to rights, and their connection to choices is not an obvious one. In the present paper I limit mysel to comments about the ormal structure in Sen's ormulation, not about its meaning(s). Since Sen requires two conditions which are incompatible or any local and restricted rule, it is enough or us to argue that he is considering, in his theorem, rules that can be written as members o this class. No explicit argument is provided by Sen regarding the general structure o the unctions he considers: hence, some characteristics o these unctions or some special proiles might escape the description (and hence the ull orce) o our theorem. But remember that the theorem contains two statements: one is about the impossibility o allocating pivotal rights to more than one individual at the same proile (the local aspect, step one o the proo), and the other is the extension o this local argument to a global one. We only need the local result to understand Sen s impossibility. When it applies, the Pareto principle allows us to ascertain that the aggregate must be among the class o binary relations respecting the agents unanimous ranking o a pair. Likewise, the rankings o pairs associated to the private domain o an agent depend only (by the assumption o minimal liberalism) on the interested agent s ranking o these pairs. Hence, the aggregate or proiles where Pareto applies and agents have strict preerences over the pairs o their exclusive concern must be in the intersection o those sets o aggregates respecting the above conditions, as in a local aggregation rule. Now, the aggregate is required by Sen to be an acyclic rule, and this imposes a restriction on the choice o aggregates, which cannot be respected at proiles where Pareto applies and both agents with rights can exert them The Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem I have already discussed why a strategy-proo social choice unction is a local and restricted aggregator. Moreover, strategy-prooness guarantees that, whenever the range o the rule contains at least three alternatives, then there must be proiles where some agent is pivotal or more than one pair. My 1983 proo o the Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem establishes (step g) the ollowing consequence o strategy-prooness: i no individual is ever pivotal under or more than two alternatives, then the range o consists o at most two alternatives. Moreover, the construction in Gibbard s proo that determines whether each alternative is 16

18 excluded or is not at a proile can only depend on the positions o pairs o alternatives, when is strategy-proo. This gives us the second part o lexibility. We can now reer to the general theorem to obtain dictatorship. 4. Final Remarks I have proven the theorem or the case where the range o each partial selection rule consists o two sets only. The proo is suicient to cover the Gibbard-Satterthwaite theorem. It is also suicient to cover the versions o the rest o the theorems we mention (Arrow, Wilson, Sen) where society's preerences are required to be strict. But since these theorems also hold when societies (as well as individuals) are allowed to express indierences, it would be interesting to discuss how our theorem should be extended to cover the case o three-valued (or many-valued) ranges. The same basic ideas apply, but urther deinitions and some delicate distinctions must be made. I leave this extension or another paper. REFERENCES Aizerman, M. and F. Aleskerov (1995): "Theory o Choice", North Holland, Elsevier Science, Amsterdam. Arrow, K. (1963): "Social Choice and Individual Values", 2nd edition, Wiley: New York. Barberà, S. (1980): "Pivotal Voters: A New Proo o Arrow's Theorem", Economics Letters 6, Barberà, S. (1983a): "Strategy-Prooness and Pivotal Voters: A Direct Proo o the Gibbard- Satterthwaite Theorem", International Economic Review 24, 2, Barberà, S. (1983b): "Pivotal Voters: A Simple Proo o Arrow's Theorem", in P.K. Pattanaik and M. Salles (Eds.), Social Choice and Welare, North Holland. Barberà, S., Gul, F. and E. Stacchetti (1993): "Generalized Median Voter Schemes and Committees", Journal o Economic Theory 61, Barberà, S. and Peleg, B. (1990): "Strategy-proo Voting Schemes with Continuous Preerences", Social Choice and Welare 7, Batteau, P., Blin, J-M. and B. Monjardet (1981): "Stability o Aggregation Procedures, Ultrailters and Simple Games", Econometrica 40, Benoit, J-P. (2000): "The Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem: A Simple Proo", Economics Letters 69,

19 Eliaz, K. (2001): "Arrow's Theorem and the Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem Are Special Cases o a Single Theorem", mimeo, Tel-Aviv University. Gibbard, A. (1973): "Manipulation o Voting Schemes: A General Result", Econometrica 41, Guilbaud, G. Th. (1952): Les Théories de l Intérêt Général et le Problème Logique de l Aggrégation, Economie Appliquée 5, English translation in P.F Lazarseld and N.W. Henry (Eds.) Readings in Mathematical Social Sciences (Science Research association Inc.-Chicago, 1965) pp Mueller, E. and A. Satterthwaite (1977): "The Equivalence o Strong Positive Association and Strategy-Prooness", Journal o Economic Theory 14, Reny, P.J. (2001): "Arrow's Theorem and the Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem: A Uniied Approach", Economics Letters 70, Saari, D. (1998): Connecting and Resolving Sen s and Arrow s Theorems, Social Choice and Welare 15, Salles, M. (2001): "Amartya Sen: Droits et Choix Social", Revue Economique 81-3, Satterthwaite, M. (1975): "Strategy-Prooness and Arrow's Conditions: Existence and Correspondence Theorems or Voting Procedures and Social Welare Functions", Journal o Economic Theory 10, Schmeidler, D. and H. Sonnenschein (1978): "Two Proos o the Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem on the Possibility o Strategy-Proo Social Choice Functions", in H.W. Gottinger and W. Leinellner (eds.), Decision Theory and Social Ethics, Issues in Social Choice, , D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland. Sen, A.K. (1970): "The Impossibility o a Paretian Liberal", Journal o Political Economy 78, Sen, A. (2001): "Another Direct Proo o the Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem", Economics Letters 70, (2001). Vickrey, W.S. (1969): "Utility, Strategy and Social Decision Rules", Quarterly Journal o Economics 74, Wilson, R. (1972): "Social Choice without the Pareto Principle", Journal o Economic Theory 5,

Coalitionally strategyproof functions depend only on the most-preferred alternatives.

Coalitionally strategyproof functions depend only on the most-preferred alternatives. Coalitionally strategyproof functions depend only on the most-preferred alternatives. H. Reiju Mihara reiju@ec.kagawa-u.ac.jp Economics, Kagawa University, Takamatsu, 760-8523, Japan April, 1999 [Social

More information

Published in the American Economic Review Volume 102, Issue 1, February 2012, pages doi: /aer

Published in the American Economic Review Volume 102, Issue 1, February 2012, pages doi: /aer Published in the American Economic Review Volume 102, Issue 1, February 2012, pages 594-601. doi:10.1257/aer.102.1.594 CONTRACTS VS. SALARIES IN MATCHING FEDERICO ECHENIQUE Abstract. Firms and workers

More information

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups 6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar MIT December 9, 2009 1 Introduction Outline Group and collective choices Arrow s Impossibility Theorem Gibbard-Satterthwaite

More information

Arrow s Paradox. Prerna Nadathur. January 1, 2010

Arrow s Paradox. Prerna Nadathur. January 1, 2010 Arrow s Paradox Prerna Nadathur January 1, 2010 Abstract In this paper, we examine the problem of a ranked voting system and introduce Kenneth Arrow s impossibility theorem (1951). We provide a proof sketch

More information

The Axiomatic Method in Social Choice Theory:

The Axiomatic Method in Social Choice Theory: The Axiomatic Method in Social Choice Theory: Preference Aggregation, Judgment Aggregation, Graph Aggregation Ulle Endriss Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam Ulle Endriss

More information

Ordered Value Restriction

Ordered Value Restriction Ordered Value Restriction Salvador Barberà Bernardo Moreno Univ. Autònoma de Barcelona and Univ. de Málaga and centra March 1, 2006 Abstract In this paper, we restrict the pro les of preferences to be

More information

ON STRATEGY-PROOF SOCIAL CHOICE BETWEEN TWO ALTERNATIVES

ON STRATEGY-PROOF SOCIAL CHOICE BETWEEN TWO ALTERNATIVES Discussion Paper No. 1013 ON STRATEGY-PROOF SOCIAL CHOICE BETWEEN TWO ALTERNATIVES Ahinaa Lahiri Anup Pramanik Octoer 2017 The Institute o Social and Economic Research Osaka University 6-1 Mihogaoka, Iaraki,

More information

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send  to: COPYRIGHT NOTICE: Ariel Rubinstein: Lecture Notes in Microeconomic Theory is published by Princeton University Press and copyrighted, c 2006, by Princeton University Press. All rights reserved. No part

More information

13 Social choice B = 2 X X. is the collection of all binary relations on X. R = { X X : is complete and transitive}

13 Social choice B = 2 X X. is the collection of all binary relations on X. R = { X X : is complete and transitive} 13 Social choice So far, all of our models involved a single decision maker. An important, perhaps the important, question for economics is whether the desires and wants of various agents can be rationally

More information

Comparing impossibility theorems

Comparing impossibility theorems Comparing impossibility theorems Randy Calvert, for Pol Sci 507 Spr 2017 All references to A-S & B are to Austen-Smith and Banks (1999). Basic notation X set of alternatives X set of all nonempty subsets

More information

On the Correspondence of Contracts to Salaries in (Many-to-Many) Matching

On the Correspondence of Contracts to Salaries in (Many-to-Many) Matching On the Correspondence o Contracts to Salaries in (Many-to-Many) Matching Scott Duke Kominers 1, Becker Friedman Institute or Research in Economics, University o Chicago Abstract In this note, I extend

More information

Antonio Quesada Universidad de Murcia. Abstract

Antonio Quesada Universidad de Murcia. Abstract From social choice functions to dictatorial social welfare functions Antonio Quesada Universidad de Murcia Abstract A procedure to construct a social welfare function from a social choice function is suggested

More information

(C) The rationals and the reals as linearly ordered sets. Contents. 1 The characterizing results

(C) The rationals and the reals as linearly ordered sets. Contents. 1 The characterizing results (C) The rationals and the reals as linearly ordered sets We know that both Q and R are something special. When we think about about either o these we usually view it as a ield, or at least some kind o

More information

MAXIMAL POSSIBILITY AND MINIMAL DICTATORIAL COVERS OF DOMAINS

MAXIMAL POSSIBILITY AND MINIMAL DICTATORIAL COVERS OF DOMAINS MAXIMAL POSSIBILITY AND MINIMAL DICTATORIAL COVERS OF DOMAINS Gopakumar Achuthankutty 1 and Souvik Roy 1 1 Economic Research Unit, Indian Statistical Institute, Kolkata Abstract In line with the works

More information

A General Impossibility Result on Strategy-Proof Social Choice Hyperfunctions

A General Impossibility Result on Strategy-Proof Social Choice Hyperfunctions A General Impossibility Result on Strategy-Proof Social Choice Hyperfunctions Selçuk Özyurt and M. Remzi Sanver May 22, 2008 Abstract A social choice hyperfunction picks a non-empty set of alternatives

More information

THREE BRIEF PROOFS OF ARROW S IMPOSSIBILITY THEOREM JOHN GEANAKOPLOS COWLES FOUNDATION PAPER NO. 1116

THREE BRIEF PROOFS OF ARROW S IMPOSSIBILITY THEOREM JOHN GEANAKOPLOS COWLES FOUNDATION PAPER NO. 1116 THREE BRIEF PROOFS OF ARROW S IMPOSSIBILITY THEOREM BY JOHN GEANAKOPLOS COWLES FOUNDATION PAPER NO. 1116 COWLES FOUNDATION FOR RESEARCH IN ECONOMICS YALE UNIVERSITY Box 208281 New Haven, Connecticut 06520-8281

More information

Non-Manipulable Domains for the Borda Count

Non-Manipulable Domains for the Borda Count Non-Manipulable Domains for the Borda Count Martin Barbie, Clemens Puppe * Department of Economics, University of Karlsruhe D 76128 Karlsruhe, Germany and Attila Tasnádi ** Department of Mathematics, Budapest

More information

Social Choice. Jan-Michael van Linthoudt

Social Choice. Jan-Michael van Linthoudt Social Choice Jan-Michael van Linthoudt Summer term 2017 Version: March 15, 2018 CONTENTS Remarks 1 0 Introduction 2 1 The Case of 2 Alternatives 3 1.1 Examples for social choice rules............................

More information

Coalitional Structure of the Muller-Satterthwaite Theorem

Coalitional Structure of the Muller-Satterthwaite Theorem Coalitional Structure of the Muller-Satterthwaite Theorem Pingzhong Tang and Tuomas Sandholm Computer Science Department Carnegie Mellon University {kenshin,sandholm}@cscmuedu Abstract The Muller-Satterthwaite

More information

Roberto s Notes on Differential Calculus Chapter 8: Graphical analysis Section 1. Extreme points

Roberto s Notes on Differential Calculus Chapter 8: Graphical analysis Section 1. Extreme points Roberto s Notes on Dierential Calculus Chapter 8: Graphical analysis Section 1 Extreme points What you need to know already: How to solve basic algebraic and trigonometric equations. All basic techniques

More information

2. ETA EVALUATIONS USING WEBER FUNCTIONS. Introduction

2. ETA EVALUATIONS USING WEBER FUNCTIONS. Introduction . ETA EVALUATIONS USING WEBER FUNCTIONS Introduction So ar we have seen some o the methods or providing eta evaluations that appear in the literature and we have seen some o the interesting properties

More information

Finite Dimensional Hilbert Spaces are Complete for Dagger Compact Closed Categories (Extended Abstract)

Finite Dimensional Hilbert Spaces are Complete for Dagger Compact Closed Categories (Extended Abstract) Electronic Notes in Theoretical Computer Science 270 (1) (2011) 113 119 www.elsevier.com/locate/entcs Finite Dimensional Hilbert Spaces are Complete or Dagger Compact Closed Categories (Extended bstract)

More information

Social Choice Theory. Felix Munoz-Garcia School of Economic Sciences Washington State University. EconS Advanced Microeconomics II

Social Choice Theory. Felix Munoz-Garcia School of Economic Sciences Washington State University. EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Social Choice Theory Felix Munoz-Garcia School of Economic Sciences Washington State University EconS 503 - Advanced Microeconomics II Social choice theory MWG, Chapter 21. JR, Chapter 6.2-6.5. Additional

More information

Anonymity-Proof Voting Rules

Anonymity-Proof Voting Rules Anonymity-Proo Voting Rules Vincent Conitzer Department o Computer Science & Department o Economics Duke University Durham, NC 27708, USA conitzer@cs.duke.edu ABSTRACT In open, anonymous environments such

More information

CS 361 Meeting 28 11/14/18

CS 361 Meeting 28 11/14/18 CS 361 Meeting 28 11/14/18 Announcements 1. Homework 9 due Friday Computation Histories 1. Some very interesting proos o undecidability rely on the technique o constructing a language that describes the

More information

Probabilistic Aspects of Voting

Probabilistic Aspects of Voting Probabilistic Aspects of Voting UUGANBAATAR NINJBAT DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS THE NATIONAL UNIVERSITY OF MONGOLIA SAAM 2015 Outline 1. Introduction to voting theory 2. Probability and voting 2.1. Aggregating

More information

Arrow s Theorem as a Corollary

Arrow s Theorem as a Corollary Arrow s Theorem as a Corollary Klaus Nehring University of California, Davis October 2002 Abstract Arrow s Impossibility Theorem is derived from a general theorem on social aggregation in property spaces.

More information

Arrow s General (Im)Possibility Theorem

Arrow s General (Im)Possibility Theorem Division of the Humanities and ocial ciences Arrow s General (Im)Possibility Theorem KC Border Winter 2002 Let X be a nonempty set of social alternatives and let P denote the set of preference relations

More information

Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Ton Storcken. Manipulation under k-approval scoring rules RM/08/056. JEL code: D71, D72

Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Ton Storcken. Manipulation under k-approval scoring rules RM/08/056. JEL code: D71, D72 Hans Peters, Souvik Roy, Ton Storcken Manipulation under k-approval scoring rules RM/08/056 JEL code: D71, D72 Maastricht research school of Economics of TEchnology and ORganizations Universiteit Maastricht

More information

DICTATORIAL DOMAINS. Navin Aswal University of Minnesota, Minneapolis, USA Shurojit Chatterji Indian Statistical Institute, New Delhi, India and

DICTATORIAL DOMAINS. Navin Aswal University of Minnesota, Minneapolis, USA Shurojit Chatterji Indian Statistical Institute, New Delhi, India and DICTATORIAL DOMAINS Navin Aswal University of Minnesota, Minneapolis, USA Shurojit Chatterji Indian Statistical Institute, New Delhi, India and Arunava Sen Indian Statistical Institute, New Delhi, India

More information

APPLIED MECHANISM DESIGN FOR SOCIAL GOOD

APPLIED MECHANISM DESIGN FOR SOCIAL GOOD APPLIED MECHANISM DESIGN FOR SOCIAL GOOD JOHN P DICKERSON Lecture #21 11/8/2016 CMSC828M Tuesdays & Thursdays 12:30pm 1:45pm IMPOSSIBILITY RESULTS IN VOTING THEORY / SOCIAL CHOICE Thanks to: Tuomas Sandholm

More information

Documents de Travail du Centre d Economie de la Sorbonne

Documents de Travail du Centre d Economie de la Sorbonne Documents de Travail du Centre d Economie de la Sorbonne On equilibrium payos in wage bargaining with discount rates varying in time Ahmet OZKARDAS, Agnieszka RUSINOWSKA 2014.11 Maison des Sciences Économiques,

More information

Single-plateaued choice

Single-plateaued choice Single-plateaued choice Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ, University of Montreal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown Montreal QC H3C 3J7, Canada walter.bossert@umontreal.ca and Hans Peters

More information

Quasi-transitive and Suzumura consistent relations

Quasi-transitive and Suzumura consistent relations Quasi-transitive and Suzumura consistent relations Walter Bossert Department of Economics and CIREQ, University of Montréal P.O. Box 6128, Station Downtown, Montréal QC H3C 3J7, Canada FAX: (+1 514) 343

More information

arxiv: v2 [math.co] 14 Apr 2011

arxiv: v2 [math.co] 14 Apr 2011 Complete Characterization of Functions Satisfying the Conditions of Arrow s Theorem Elchanan Mossel and Omer Tamuz arxiv:0910.2465v2 [math.co] 14 Apr 2011 April 15, 2011 Abstract Arrow s theorem implies

More information

A Characterization of Single-Peaked Preferences via Random Social Choice Functions

A Characterization of Single-Peaked Preferences via Random Social Choice Functions A Characterization of Single-Peaked Preferences via Random Social Choice Functions Shurojit Chatterji, Arunava Sen and Huaxia Zeng September 2014 Paper No. 13-2014 ANY OPINIONS EXPRESSED ARE THOSE OF THE

More information

A MAXIMAL DOMAIN FOR STRATEGY-PROOF AND NO-VETOER RULES IN THE MULTI-OBJECT CHOICE MODEL

A MAXIMAL DOMAIN FOR STRATEGY-PROOF AND NO-VETOER RULES IN THE MULTI-OBJECT CHOICE MODEL Discussion Paper No. 809 A MAXIMAL DOMAIN FOR STRATEGY-PROOF AND NO-VETOER RULES IN THE MULTI-OBJECT CHOICE MODEL Kantaro Hatsumi Dolors Berga Shigehiro Serizawa April 2011 The Institute of Social and

More information

SEPARATED AND PROPER MORPHISMS

SEPARATED AND PROPER MORPHISMS SEPARATED AND PROPER MORPHISMS BRIAN OSSERMAN The notions o separatedness and properness are the algebraic geometry analogues o the Hausdor condition and compactness in topology. For varieties over the

More information

Strategy-Proofness on the Condorcet Domain

Strategy-Proofness on the Condorcet Domain College of William and Mary W&M ScholarWorks Undergraduate Honors Theses Theses, Dissertations, & Master Projects 5-2008 Strategy-Proofness on the Condorcet Domain Lauren Nicole Merrill College of William

More information

The Arrow Impossibility Theorem Of Social Choice Theory In An Infinite Society And Limited Principle Of Omniscience

The Arrow Impossibility Theorem Of Social Choice Theory In An Infinite Society And Limited Principle Of Omniscience Applied Mathematics E-Notes, 8(2008), 82-88 c ISSN 1607-2510 Available free at mirror sites of http://www.math.nthu.edu.tw/ amen/ The Arrow Impossibility Theorem Of Social Choice Theory In An Infinite

More information

3.1 Arrow s Theorem. We study now the general case in which the society has to choose among a number of alternatives

3.1 Arrow s Theorem. We study now the general case in which the society has to choose among a number of alternatives 3.- Social Choice and Welfare Economics 3.1 Arrow s Theorem We study now the general case in which the society has to choose among a number of alternatives Let R denote the set of all preference relations

More information

Algorithmic Game Theory Introduction to Mechanism Design

Algorithmic Game Theory Introduction to Mechanism Design Algorithmic Game Theory Introduction to Mechanism Design Makis Arsenis National Technical University of Athens April 216 Makis Arsenis (NTUA) AGT April 216 1 / 41 Outline 1 Social Choice Social Choice

More information

Centre de Referència en Economia Analítica

Centre de Referència en Economia Analítica Centre de Referència en Economia Analítica Barcelona Economics Working Paper Series Working Paper nº 15 Free Triples, Large Indifference Classes and the Majority Rule Salvador Barberà and Lars Ehlers May

More information

INTEGER PROGRAMMING AND ARROVIAN SOCIAL WELFARE FUNCTIONS

INTEGER PROGRAMMING AND ARROVIAN SOCIAL WELFARE FUNCTIONS MATHEMATICS OF OPERATIONS RESEARCH Vol. 28, No. 2, May 2003, pp. 309 326 Printed in U.S.A. INTEGER PROGRAMMING AND ARROVIAN SOCIAL WELFARE FUNCTIONS JAY SETHURAMAN, TEO CHUNG PIAW, and RAKESH V. VOHRA

More information

Dependence and Independence in Social Choice Theory

Dependence and Independence in Social Choice Theory Dependence and Independence in Social Choice Theory Eric Pacuit Department of Philosophy University of Maryland, College Park pacuit.org epacuit@umd.edu March 4, 2014 Eric Pacuit 1 Competing desiderata

More information

Objectives. By the time the student is finished with this section of the workbook, he/she should be able

Objectives. By the time the student is finished with this section of the workbook, he/she should be able FUNCTIONS Quadratic Functions......8 Absolute Value Functions.....48 Translations o Functions..57 Radical Functions...61 Eponential Functions...7 Logarithmic Functions......8 Cubic Functions......91 Piece-Wise

More information

Finite Dictatorships and Infinite Democracies

Finite Dictatorships and Infinite Democracies Finite Dictatorships and Infinite Democracies Iian B. Smythe October 20, 2015 Abstract Does there exist a reasonable method of voting that when presented with three or more alternatives avoids the undue

More information

Volume 31, Issue 1. Manipulation of the Borda rule by introduction of a similar candidate. Jérôme Serais CREM UMR 6211 University of Caen

Volume 31, Issue 1. Manipulation of the Borda rule by introduction of a similar candidate. Jérôme Serais CREM UMR 6211 University of Caen Volume 31, Issue 1 Manipulation of the Borda rule by introduction of a similar candidate Jérôme Serais CREM UMR 6211 University of Caen Abstract In an election contest, a losing candidate a can manipulate

More information

Expertise and Complexity in the Social and Engineering Sciences: An Extended Sen s Theorem

Expertise and Complexity in the Social and Engineering Sciences: An Extended Sen s Theorem Expertise and Complexity in the Social and Engineering Sciences: An Extended Sen s Theorem Donald G. Saari Institute for Mathematical Behavioral Sciences University of California Irvine, CA 92617-5100

More information

On High-Rate Cryptographic Compression Functions

On High-Rate Cryptographic Compression Functions On High-Rate Cryptographic Compression Functions Richard Ostertág and Martin Stanek Department o Computer Science Faculty o Mathematics, Physics and Inormatics Comenius University Mlynská dolina, 842 48

More information

The Structure of Strategy-Proof Social Choice:

The Structure of Strategy-Proof Social Choice: The Structure of Strategy-Proof Social Choice: General Characterization and Possibility Results on Median Spaces * Klaus Nehring Department of Economics, UC Davis, Davis, CA 95616, U.S.A. and Institute

More information

Fair Divsion in Theory and Practice

Fair Divsion in Theory and Practice Fair Divsion in Theory and Practice Ron Cytron (Computer Science) Maggie Penn (Political Science) Lecture 6-b: Arrow s Theorem 1 Arrow s Theorem The general question: Given a collection of individuals

More information

The concept of limit

The concept of limit Roberto s Notes on Dierential Calculus Chapter 1: Limits and continuity Section 1 The concept o limit What you need to know already: All basic concepts about unctions. What you can learn here: What limits

More information

Online Appendix: The Continuous-type Model of Competitive Nonlinear Taxation and Constitutional Choice by Massimo Morelli, Huanxing Yang, and Lixin Ye

Online Appendix: The Continuous-type Model of Competitive Nonlinear Taxation and Constitutional Choice by Massimo Morelli, Huanxing Yang, and Lixin Ye Online Appendix: The Continuous-type Model o Competitive Nonlinear Taxation and Constitutional Choice by Massimo Morelli, Huanxing Yang, and Lixin Ye For robustness check, in this section we extend our

More information

The Gibbard random dictatorship theorem: a generalization and a new proof

The Gibbard random dictatorship theorem: a generalization and a new proof SERIEs (2011) 2:515 527 DOI 101007/s13209-011-0041-z ORIGINAL ARTICLE The Gibbard random dictatorship theorem: a generalization and a new proof Arunava Sen Received: 24 November 2010 / Accepted: 10 January

More information

Essential Microeconomics : EQUILIBRIUM AND EFFICIENCY WITH PRODUCTION Key ideas: Walrasian equilibrium, first and second welfare theorems

Essential Microeconomics : EQUILIBRIUM AND EFFICIENCY WITH PRODUCTION Key ideas: Walrasian equilibrium, first and second welfare theorems Essential Microeconomics -- 5.2: EQUILIBRIUM AND EFFICIENCY WITH PRODUCTION Key ideas: Walrasian equilibrium, irst and second welare teorems A general model 2 First welare Teorem 7 Second welare teorem

More information

"Arrow s Theorem and the Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem: A Unified Approach", by Phillip Reny. Economic Letters (70) (2001),

Arrow s Theorem and the Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem: A Unified Approach, by Phillip Reny. Economic Letters (70) (2001), February 25, 2015 "Arrow s Theorem and the Gibbard-Satterthwaite Theorem: A Unified Approach", by Phillip Reny. Economic Letters (70) (2001), 99-105. Also recommended: M. A. Satterthwaite, "Strategy-Proof

More information

Social choice theory, Arrow s impossibility theorem and majority judgment

Social choice theory, Arrow s impossibility theorem and majority judgment Université Paris-Dauphine - PSL Cycle Pluridisciplinaire d Etudes Supérieures Social choice theory, Arrow s impossibility theorem and majority judgment Victor Elie supervised by Miquel Oliu Barton June

More information

JUDGMENT AGGREGATORS AND BOOLEAN ALGEBRA HOMOMORPHISMS

JUDGMENT AGGREGATORS AND BOOLEAN ALGEBRA HOMOMORPHISMS Working Papers Institute of Mathematical Economics 414 February 2009 JUDGMENT AGGREGATORS AND BOOLEAN ALGEBRA HOMOMORPHISMS Frederik Herzberg IMW Bielefeld University Postfach 100131 33501 Bielefeld Germany

More information

SYSU Lectures on the Theory of Aggregation Lecture 2: Binary Aggregation with Integrity Constraints

SYSU Lectures on the Theory of Aggregation Lecture 2: Binary Aggregation with Integrity Constraints SYSU Lectures on the Theory of Aggregation Lecture 2: Binary Aggregation with Integrity Constraints Ulle Endriss Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam [ http://www.illc.uva.nl/~ulle/sysu-2014/

More information

Volume 31, Issue 1. A solution concept for housing market problems with externalities. Alfredo Salgado-Torres Universidad Carlos III de Madrid

Volume 31, Issue 1. A solution concept for housing market problems with externalities. Alfredo Salgado-Torres Universidad Carlos III de Madrid Volume 31, Issue 1 A solution concept for housing market problems with externalities Alfredo Salgado-Torres Universidad Carlos III de Madrid Abstract Since the core of a housing market with externalities

More information

Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory

Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory Chapter 9 Nathan Smooha Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory 9.1 Introduction In this chapter, we briefly discuss some topics in the framework of general equilibrium theory, namely

More information

Locating public facilities by majority: Stability, consistency and group formation

Locating public facilities by majority: Stability, consistency and group formation Games and Economic Behavior 56 (2006) 185 200 www.elsevier.com/locate/geb Note Locating public facilities by majority: Stability, consistency and group formation Salvador Barberà, Carmen Beviá Departament

More information

On the Strategy-proof Social Choice of Fixed-sized Subsets

On the Strategy-proof Social Choice of Fixed-sized Subsets Nationalekonomiska institutionen MASTER S THESIS, 30 ECTS On the Strategy-proof Social Choice of Fixed-sized Subsets AUTHOR: ALEXANDER REFFGEN SUPERVISOR: LARS-GUNNAR SVENSSON SEPTEMBER, 2006 Contents

More information

Constitutional Rights and Pareto Efficiency

Constitutional Rights and Pareto Efficiency Journal of Economic and Social Research, 1 (1) 1999, 109-117 Constitutional Rights and Pareto Efficiency Ahmet Kara 1 Abstract. This paper presents a sufficient condition under which constitutional rights

More information

CATEGORIES. 1.1 Introduction

CATEGORIES. 1.1 Introduction 1 CATEGORIES 1.1 Introduction What is category theory? As a irst approximation, one could say that category theory is the mathematical study o (abstract) algebras o unctions. Just as group theory is the

More information

Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: a generalization of May s theorem to many alternatives

Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: a generalization of May s theorem to many alternatives Positively responsive collective choice rules and majority rule: a generalization of May s theorem to many alternatives Sean Horan, Martin J. Osborne, and M. Remzi Sanver December 24, 2018 Abstract May

More information

SEPARATED AND PROPER MORPHISMS

SEPARATED AND PROPER MORPHISMS SEPARATED AND PROPER MORPHISMS BRIAN OSSERMAN Last quarter, we introduced the closed diagonal condition or a prevariety to be a prevariety, and the universally closed condition or a variety to be complete.

More information

GENERALIZED ABSTRACT NONSENSE: CATEGORY THEORY AND ADJUNCTIONS

GENERALIZED ABSTRACT NONSENSE: CATEGORY THEORY AND ADJUNCTIONS GENERALIZED ABSTRACT NONSENSE: CATEGORY THEORY AND ADJUNCTIONS CHRIS HENDERSON Abstract. This paper will move through the basics o category theory, eventually deining natural transormations and adjunctions

More information

Arrovian Social Choice with Non -Welfare Attributes

Arrovian Social Choice with Non -Welfare Attributes Arrovian Social Choice with Non -Welfare Attributes Ryo-Ichi Nagahisa y Kansai University Koichi Suga z Waseda University November 14, 2017 Abstract A social state is assumed to be chracterized by welfare

More information

Abstract Arrowian Aggregation *

Abstract Arrowian Aggregation * Abstract Arrowian Aggregation * Klaus Nehring Department of Economics, University of California at Davis Davis, CA 95616, U.S.A. kdnehring@ucdavis.edu and Clemens Puppe Department of Economics, University

More information

A Systematic Approach to the Construction of Non-empty Choice Sets

A Systematic Approach to the Construction of Non-empty Choice Sets A Systematic Approach to the Construction of Non-empty Choice Sets John Duggan Department of Political Science and Department of Economics University of Rochester May 17, 2004 Abstract Suppose a strict

More information

Basic properties of limits

Basic properties of limits Roberto s Notes on Dierential Calculus Chapter : Limits and continuity Section Basic properties o its What you need to know already: The basic concepts, notation and terminology related to its. What you

More information

PHIL 308S: Voting Theory and Fair Division

PHIL 308S: Voting Theory and Fair Division PHIL 308S: Voting Theory and Fair Division Lecture 12 Eric Pacuit Department of Philosophy University of Maryland, College Park ai.stanford.edu/ epacuit epacuit@umd.edu October 18, 2012 PHIL 308S: Voting

More information

Competition and Resource Sensitivity in Marriage and Roommate Markets

Competition and Resource Sensitivity in Marriage and Roommate Markets Competition and Resource Sensitivity in Marriage and Roommate Markets Bettina Klaus This Version: April 2010 Previous Versions: November 2007 and December 2008 Abstract We consider one-to-one matching

More information

On the Girth of (3,L) Quasi-Cyclic LDPC Codes based on Complete Protographs

On the Girth of (3,L) Quasi-Cyclic LDPC Codes based on Complete Protographs On the Girth o (3,L) Quasi-Cyclic LDPC Codes based on Complete Protographs Sudarsan V S Ranganathan, Dariush Divsalar and Richard D Wesel Department o Electrical Engineering, University o Caliornia, Los

More information

An axiomatic characterization of the prudent order preference function

An axiomatic characterization of the prudent order preference function An axiomatic characterization of the prudent order preference function Claude Lamboray Abstract In this paper, we are interested in a preference function that associates to a profile of linear orders the

More information

Dynamics of Stable Sets of Constitutions

Dynamics of Stable Sets of Constitutions Dynamics of Stable Sets of Constitutions HOUY Nicolas February 26, 2007 Abstract A Self-Designating social choice correspondence designates itself when it is implemented as a constitution and when the

More information

CHOW S LEMMA. Matthew Emerton

CHOW S LEMMA. Matthew Emerton CHOW LEMMA Matthew Emerton The aim o this note is to prove the ollowing orm o Chow s Lemma: uppose that : is a separated inite type morphism o Noetherian schemes. Then (or some suiciently large n) there

More information

On the Chacteristic Numbers of Voting Games

On the Chacteristic Numbers of Voting Games On the Chacteristic Numbers of Voting Games MATHIEU MARTIN THEMA, Departments of Economics Université de Cergy Pontoise, 33 Boulevard du Port, 95011 Cergy Pontoise cedex, France. e-mail: mathieu.martin@eco.u-cergy.fr

More information

9.3 Graphing Functions by Plotting Points, The Domain and Range of Functions

9.3 Graphing Functions by Plotting Points, The Domain and Range of Functions 9. Graphing Functions by Plotting Points, The Domain and Range o Functions Now that we have a basic idea o what unctions are and how to deal with them, we would like to start talking about the graph o

More information

On preferences over subsets and the lattice structure of stable matchings

On preferences over subsets and the lattice structure of stable matchings On preferences over subsets and the lattice structure of stable matchings Ahmet Alkan Sabanci University, Tuzla 81474 Istanbul, Turkey (e-mail: alkan@sabanciuniv.edu) Abstract. This paper studies the structure

More information

A topological approach to Wilson s impossibility theorem

A topological approach to Wilson s impossibility theorem Journal of Mathematical Economics 43 (2007) 184 191 A topological approach to Wilson s impossibility theorem Yasuhito Tanaka Faculty of Economics, Doshisha University, Kamigyo-ku, Kyoto 602-8580, Japan

More information

CAHIER CANDIDATE STABILITY AND NONBINARY SOCIAL CHOICE. Lars EHLERS and John A. WEYMARK

CAHIER CANDIDATE STABILITY AND NONBINARY SOCIAL CHOICE. Lars EHLERS and John A. WEYMARK CAHIER 26-2001 CANDIDATE STABILITY AND NONBINARY SOCIAL CHOICE Lars EHLERS and John A. WEYMARK CAHIER 26-2001 CANDIDATE STABILITY AND NONBINARY SOCIAL CHOICE Lars EHLERS 1 and John A. WEYMARK 2 1 2 Centre

More information

The basics of frame theory

The basics of frame theory First version released on 30 June 2006 This version released on 30 June 2006 The basics o rame theory Harold Simmons The University o Manchester hsimmons@ manchester.ac.uk This is the irst part o a series

More information

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 29 Mar 2014

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 29 Mar 2014 Testing Top Monotonicity Haris Aziz NICTA and UNSW Australia, Kensington 2033, Australia arxiv:1403.7625v1 [cs.gt] 29 Mar 2014 Abstract Top monotonicity is a relaxation of various well-known domain restrictions

More information

Web Appendix for The Value of Switching Costs

Web Appendix for The Value of Switching Costs Web Appendix or The Value o Switching Costs Gary Biglaiser University o North Carolina, Chapel Hill Jacques Crémer Toulouse School o Economics (GREMAQ, CNRS and IDEI) Gergely Dobos Gazdasági Versenyhivatal

More information

On Domains That Admit Well-behaved Strategy-proof Social Choice Functions

On Domains That Admit Well-behaved Strategy-proof Social Choice Functions On Domains That Admit Well-behaved Strategy-proof Social Choice Functions Shurojit Chatterji, Remzi Sanver and Arunava Sen May 2010 Paper No. 07-2010 ANY OPINIONS EXPRESSED ARE THOSE OF THE AUTHOR(S) AND

More information

Partial lecture notes THE PROBABILITY OF VIOLATING ARROW S CONDITIONS

Partial lecture notes THE PROBABILITY OF VIOLATING ARROW S CONDITIONS Partial lecture notes THE PROBABILITY OF VIOLATING ARROW S CONDITIONS 1 B. Preference Aggregation Rules 3. Anti-Plurality a. Assign zero points to a voter's last preference and one point to all other preferences.

More information

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem: Preference Diversity in a Single-Profile World

Arrow s Impossibility Theorem: Preference Diversity in a Single-Profile World Arrow s Impossibility Theorem: Preference Diversity in a Single-Profile World Brown University Department of Economics Working Paper No. 2007-12 Allan M. Feldman Department of Economics, Brown University

More information

Strategy-proof allocation of indivisible goods

Strategy-proof allocation of indivisible goods Soc Choice Welfare (1999) 16: 557±567 Strategy-proof allocation of indivisible goods Lars-Gunnar Svensson Department of Economics, Lund University, P.O. Box 7082, SE-220 07 of Lund, Sweden (e-mail: lars-gunnar.svensson@nek.lu.se)

More information

CONNECTING PAIRWISE AND POSITIONAL ELECTION OUTCOMES

CONNECTING PAIRWISE AND POSITIONAL ELECTION OUTCOMES CONNECTING PAIRWISE AND POSITIONAL ELECTION OUTCOMES DONALD G SAARI AND TOMAS J MCINTEE INSTITUTE FOR MATHEMATICAL BEHAVIORAL SCIENCE UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, IRVINE, CA 9697-5100 Abstract General conclusions

More information

Efficient Algorithms for Hard Problems on Structured Electorates

Efficient Algorithms for Hard Problems on Structured Electorates Aspects of Computation 2017 Efficient Algorithms for Hard Problems on Structured Electorates Neeldhara Misra The standard Voting Setup and some problems that we will encounter. The standard Voting Setup

More information

A Role of Common Morality in Social Choice

A Role of Common Morality in Social Choice A Role of Common Morality in Social Choice Susumu Cato Graduate School of Economics, The University of Tokyo, Japan Society for the Promotion of Science Research Fellow First Version: January 10, 2007

More information

Approximation Algorithms and Mechanism Design for Minimax Approval Voting

Approximation Algorithms and Mechanism Design for Minimax Approval Voting Approximation Algorithms and Mechanism Design for Minimax Approval Voting Ioannis Caragiannis RACTI & Department of Computer Engineering and Informatics University of Patras, Greece caragian@ceid.upatras.gr

More information

A Note on Object Allocation under Lexicographic Preferences

A Note on Object Allocation under Lexicographic Preferences A Note on Object Allocation under Lexicographic Preferences Daniela Saban and Jay Sethuraman March 7, 2014 Abstract We consider the problem of allocating m objects to n agents. Each agent has unit demand,

More information

Theories of justice. Harsanyi s approach, Rawls approach, Unification

Theories of justice. Harsanyi s approach, Rawls approach, Unification Theories of justice Section 6.4 in JR. The choice of one swf over another is ultimately a choice between alternative sets of ethical values. Two main approaches: Harsanyi s approach, Rawls approach, Unification

More information

Intro to Economic analysis

Intro to Economic analysis Intro to Economic analysis Alberto Bisin - NYU 1 Rational Choice The central gure of economics theory is the individual decision-maker (DM). The typical example of a DM is the consumer. We shall assume

More information

Categories and Natural Transformations

Categories and Natural Transformations Categories and Natural Transormations Ethan Jerzak 17 August 2007 1 Introduction The motivation or studying Category Theory is to ormalise the underlying similarities between a broad range o mathematical

More information

Math 248B. Base change morphisms

Math 248B. Base change morphisms Math 248B. Base change morphisms 1. Motivation A basic operation with shea cohomology is pullback. For a continuous map o topological spaces : X X and an abelian shea F on X with (topological) pullback

More information