To Infinity and Back: Logical Limit Laws and Almost Sure Theories

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "To Infinity and Back: Logical Limit Laws and Almost Sure Theories"

Transcription

1 U.U.D.M. Report 2014:4 To Infinity and Back: Logical Limit Laws and Almost Sure Theories Ove Ahlman Filosofie licentiatavhandling i matematik som framläggs för offentlig granskning den 19 maj 2014, kl 13.15, sal 2005, Ångströmlaboratoriet, Uppsala Department of Mathematics Uppsala University

2

3 TO INFINITY AND BACK: LOGICAL LIMIT LAWS AND ALMOST SURE THEORIES OVE AHLMAN This thesis consists of the following papers referred to by their Roman numerals: I O. Ahlman, V. Koponen, Random l-colourable structures with a pregeometry II O. Ahlman, V. Koponen, Limit laws and automorphism groups of random non-rigid structures III O. Ahlman, Countably categorical almost sure theories Introduction History and preliminaries. A cornerstone of mathematical logic is the abstract vocabulary of mathematics. A vocabulary V consists of constant, function and relation symbols where each relation symbol and function symbol has an associated positive integer to it, called its arity. From a vocabulary we may create formulas by adding variables, connectives (e.g. and ) and quantiers (e.g. and ) together with the symbols from the vocabulary. If we want to evaluate some kind of truth of a formula it needs to be a sentence i.e. have no free variables. A quick example from graph theory is the sentence x y(e(x, y) E(y, x)) which states that the edge relation E (part of the vocabulary in graph theory) is symmetric. Dierent parts of mathematical logic do dierent things with languages. The eld of proof theory studies what and how deductions from formulas are possible using certain proof rules. Recursion theory describes what and how fast we may compute functions in models of Peano arithmetic (and things similar to Peano arithmetic). In this thesis we will focus on something in between those elds called model theory, where we discover which sentences are true or false in structures of some (often general) vocabulary and how these structures relate to each other. We will consider vocabularies which only contain relation symbols (called relational vocabularies) making the structures a bit easier to study and avoids certain complications, especially we have the property that any subset of the universe of a structure induces a substructure. A structure with vocabulary V consists of a universe set and, for each ρ N, interpretations of each relation symbol of arity ρ as a set of ordered ρ tuples of elements in the universe. We will denote the structures with calligraphic letters M, N, A, B,... and their universes with the corresponding non-calligraphic letter M, N, A, B,... In order to relate structures 1

4 2 OVE AHLMAN to each other we use embeddings and isomorphisms. An embedding (of relational structures) between V structures A, B is an injective function f : A B such that for each relation symbol R and a 1,..., a r A we have that R is true for the ordered tuple (a 1,..., a r ), noted A = R(a 1,..., a r ), i B = R(f(a 1 ),..., f(a r )). That a function is an embedding between structures will be written f : A B. If f is also a bijection then we say that f is an isomorphism and then A is isomorphic to B, written A = B. For each n N let K n be some set of nite (nite universe) structures over a vocabulary V and let µ n : K n [0, 1] R be a probability measure on K n. The most natural example is to let K n be all V structures with universe {1,..., n} and let µ n be the uniform measure i.e. µ n (N ) = 1 K n for each N K n. In order to study the properties of the structures, we will extend the probability measure µ n so that for a property P (often a sentence in the language) we have that µ n (P) = µ n ({N K n : N satises P}). We may study what happens to the 'really big' structures by regarding lim n µ n (P). This probability does not, for a general K n, even converge. However if a property P is such that lim n µ n (P) = 1 we say that it is an almost sure property. If each sentence ϕ in the language is almost sure or lim n µ n (ϕ) = 0 then we say that K = n=1 K n has a 0 1 law (under the measure µ n ). That a set K has a 0 1 law is hence a proof that it is very well behaved. The study of 0 1 laws for dierent sets K and measures µ n started with Glebskii, Kogan, Liogonkii and Talanov [7] and Fagin [5] who independently proved that for each relational vocabulary V, if K n is the set of all V structures with universe {1,..., n} then K has a 0 1 law under the uniform measure (each structure has the same probability in K n ). It has since then been discovered that many dierent sets have 0 1 laws, spanning from Comptons [3] result about K n being partial orders under the uniform measure to Koponen [11] who proved that an l coloured structure with a pregeometry has a 0 1 law under the dimension conditional measure. In these articles, the method Fagin used, when proving the rst 0 1 law, is adapted to the context and since this method is vital for all three papers we shall take a brief look at Fagins proof. Further examples of 0 1 laws may be found in [1, 2, 4, 8, 9, 10, 13, 14, 15, 16, 17, 18]. The rst thing which is done by Fagin [5] is to nd certain sentences from the language called extension axioms. Each extension axiom speaks about two structures A B such that A + 1 = B and the extension axiom says that for each instance of A we may extend this into the structure B. The proof then continues by proving that these extension axioms are almost surely true in K, which consist of all nite structures of the specied relational vocabulary. A theory (collection of sentences) T is then created by collecting all extension axioms and this theory is shown to be ℵ 0 categorical.

5 TO INFINITY AND BACK: LOGICAL LIMIT LAWS AND ALMOST SURE THEORIES 3 The categoricity follows from a back and forth building of isomorphisms, using that any model of T satises the extension axioms. An ℵ 0 categorical theory, without nite models, is complete and hence any formula is either implied by the theory (thus must have probability 1) or its negation is (thus the formula has probability 0). This theory T, which hence consist of all formulas with probability 1, is called the almost sure theory. For more information about nite model theory the reader is suggested to look at [4]. A pregeometry G = (G, cl) consists of a set G and a closure operator cl : P(G) P(G) acting as a function on the power set of G. The closure operator should satisfy the following axioms for each X, Y G: Reexivity: X cl(x). Monotonicity: X cl(y ) cl(x) cl(y ). Finite character: cl(x) = {cl(x 0 ) : X 0 X and X 0 < ℵ 0 }. Exchange: For a, b G if a cl(x {b}) cl(x) then b cl(x {a}). The most trivial example, called the trivial pregeometry, is the pregeometry where for each X G we have that cl(x) = X. Pregeometries may be viewed as generalizations of vector spaces and we get a direct example by letting G be the vectors and cl be the span operator. In the spirit of vector spaces we say that a set X G is independent if for each a X we have a / cl(x {a}). The dimension of a set X is the size of the largest independent subset Y X. We will however not consider structures with an explicit closure operator, but we may be able to dene it. For a structure M and X M we say that the pregeometry G = (M, cl) is X denable in M if there are formulas θ 0 (x 0 ),..., θ n (x 0,..., x n ),... (possibly with parameters from X) such that for b, a 1,..., a n M we have b cl(a 1,..., a n ) M = θ n (b, a 1,..., a n ). If the pregeometry is denable we may say that M is a pregeometry. About paper I. An old famous problem in mathematics is the study of the colouring of a map or, in mathematical terms, a planar graph. The basic concept is that if we have two vertices adjacent to each other then they need to have dierent colours. For K n being l coloured graphs with universe {1,..., n} Kolaitis et al[10] showed that there is a 0 1 law under the uniform measure. However the concept of colouring is not trivially generalized to vocabularies with higher arities. The key problem is that if we have a relation R(a 1,..., a m ), in some structure, then should all a 1,..., a m have different colours or should only at least two of them have dierent colours? In [11] Koponen discussed a set K n consisting of structures all of which have the same denable pregeometry with dimension n. But in order to give a more general take on l coloured structures, for some xed number l Z +, Koponen studies coloured structures where the underlying pregeometry affects how the colouring is done in the following way: (1) Each element, except those in cl( ), has one of the l colours.

6 4 OVE AHLMAN (2) Any two elements in the same 1 dimensional closure have the same colour. (3) For each relation R(a 1,..., a n ) there are elements b, c cl(a 1,..., a n ) cl( ) such that b and c have dierent colours. Notice that if the underlying pregeometry is the trivial pregeometry then (3) gives us exactly the colouring condition noted above i.e. that at least two elements in a relation needs to have dierent colours. Following this we also want to speak about strongly coloured structures who satisfy the following condition (in addition to (1)-(3)): (4) For each relation R(a 1,..., a n ) and any independent elements b, c cl(a 1,..., a n ) we have dierent colours of b and c. Notice that one important part of being a coloured structure is that there are unary relations P 1,..., P l which represent the colours in the language. Koponen showed that for l coloured structures K n with pregeometries (as described above) and random relations (not involved in the pregeometry) K has a 0 1 law. This generalized the result of Kolaitis et al, which becomes especially clear when the pregeometries are trivial. However, the study of coloured structures becomes much harder when removing the colours from the vocabulary, and just looking at colourable structures. An (strongly) l colourable structure is a structure where we may add l unary relation symbols such that this new structure becomes (strongly) l coloured. Koponen [11] studied the case of K n being just l colourable structures, however she only presented a 0 1 law in the case where the underlying pregeometry is trivial. The big problem when not having a trivial pregeometry is that we have no obvious knowledge about the possible colour of an element, and hence even realizing if a structure is l colourable or not becomes a bit tricky. In paper I we extend the 0 1 law of l colourable structures, to those structures who have a vector space pregeometry (and some closely related variants). This is done by proving that there exists a binary formula ξ(x, y), denable without having explicit colours in the vocabulary, such that almost surely in K, if some structure M = ξ(a, b) then a and b must be assigned the same colour, when colouring the structure M. We then use the formula ξ(x, y) to create extension axioms which suit the class K n and then prove the 0 1 law in the spirit of Fagin's [5] proof. Most of paper I is spent actually creating the formula ξ which is done in surprisingly dierent ways, depending on if we assume the colouring to be strong or not. In the strong case, this is proven through a method inspired by Koponen [12] where we dene the formula by brute force. ξ(x, y) then states that there are so many elements in relation to x and y such that any two elements satisfying ξ(x, y) has to be of the same colour, since we know that (independent) elements in relation to each other have dierent colour, and only l colours exists. The opposite direction, that any two elements with the same colour satisfy ξ, is proven by using the extension properties developed for coloured structures

7 TO INFINITY AND BACK: LOGICAL LIMIT LAWS AND ALMOST SURE THEORIES 5 by Koponen [11] which can induce the structure which ξ(x, y) claims to exist. The normal (non-strong) l colourings on the other hand are proven using a Ramsey theoretic theorem which says that if we have a large enough coloured vector space, then we need to have a large mono-coloured subspace. Using this we create a structure which has as many relations as possible, and yet is still l colourable, in order to x the colouring of the structure. The formula ξ(x, y) then says that x and y are part of the same mono-coloured subspace of this structure, and hence must have the same colour. To show that any elements with the same colour must satisfy ξ(x, y) we again use the extension axioms for coloured structures to nd this large mono-coloured structure in the right place. About paper II. An automorphism on a structure M is an isomorphism from M to M. It is an easy result to show that the set of all automorphisms on M, Aut(M), form a group under compositions. This group acts with a group action on M where one of the more important concepts are the support of an automorphism, which are the elements which are not mapped to themselves. For K n being all V structures with universe {1,..., n} under the uniform measure, Fagin [6] proved that the automorphism group is almost surely the trivial group for structures in K. This has as a consequence that the set K consisting of only nite structures with a trivial automorphism group, has a 0 1 law. One natural follow up to this is to discover what happens if K consists only of structures without trivial automorphism group. These kinds of sets are what we discuss in paper II, where we do a general investigation in the area, discussing what happens when we x the automorphism group or size of the support. In the case of K consisting of all structures we see that the support is almost surely empty, since the automorphism group is almost surely trivial. This does in some way give a hint that the support is almost surely 'small'. In paper II we prove that when comparing the sets of structures K and C where all structures in C has 'a bit larger' support on some automorphism, than the support of any automorphism in K, then Cn K n 0. This is the basis of the paper since it means that whenever we look at structures with large support, or large automorphism group, we may restrict the amount of elements moved by the automorphism. After further work we deduce that we may actually reduce this to having a bounded amount of elements which are actually moved by some automorphism. Using these results we now have a quite a clear picture of how these structures without trivial automorphism group look, one bounded part where the automorphisms can move elements around, and one place which is xed under any automorphisms. This knowledge leads to an estimate of the amount of structures having a certain structure of the elements in the support. Having an estimate of the supports it then becomes easier to compare sets K and C with dierent automorphism group with each other and receive yet another estimate of which of them are more common.

8 6 OVE AHLMAN This paper leads up to a 0 1 law. However it is only possible to deduce it for a very restricted set of structures having a xed structure on the support and the automorphism group being somewhat xed. In the case where we only restrict the support of structures in K or the automorphism groups then we just get a convergence law i.e. the asymptotic probability lim n µ n (ϕ) converges, but not necessarily to 0 or 1. About paper III. In paper III we work in a very general setting using any set of V structures K n under any kind of probability measure µ n, with the only restriction being that the structures in K n grow in size (almost surely) as n grow. Using this general K we study how the almost sure theory of K aects K in the case where K has a 0 1 law under the measure µ n. Especially important for this study are the equivalence relations denable (using formulas from the vocabulary) in the models of the almost sure theories, which we show induce a restriction of which sizes the structures in K may attain. Especially this induces a restriction on the sizes of structures which dene a pregeometry since being independent is an equivalence relation. As mentioned in the preliminaries, Fagin's [5] method for proving a 0 1 law for K consisting of all nite V structure, involves proving that the almost sure theory is ℵ 0 categorical and hence complete. In paper III we do a generalization of this concept and study how an almost sure theory which is ℵ 0 categorical induces properties on the set of structures from which it came from. The result is that the set of structures almost surely satises some kind of extension axioms (not necessarily as easily described as those in [5]), if and only if the almost sure theory is ℵ 0 categorical. So Fagin's method works to prove the 0 1 law of any set K which has an ℵ 0 categorical almost sure theory (and a 0 1 law). Furthermore the sets K with ℵ 0 categorical almost sure theories may be extended in the same way as M eq, getting elements representing equivalence classes. The nice thing about this extension is that the set of extended structures has a 0 1 law if and only if the original set had one, giving us a new way to transform sets of structures in order to nd out if they have a 0 1 law or not. A theory T is strongly minimal if for each model M of T, tuple ā M and formula ϕ(x, ȳ) either ϕ(x, ā) or ϕ(x, ā) is only satised by a nite amount of elements. Paper III ends with a classication of sets K with a 0 1 law whose almost sure theory is both ℵ 0 categorical and strongly minimal. These kinds of theories have quite many nice properties which help in producing the result. The classication comes down to that the sets K who induce these almost sure theories need to have structures where the automorphism group permutes almost all elements. This condition is equivalent with having an ω categorical strongly minimal almost sure theory. Acknowledgments I would like to thank my advisor Vera Koponen, who has put down a lot of work discussing things I have written and who is always positive to my

9 TO INFINITY AND BACK: LOGICAL LIMIT LAWS AND ALMOST SURE THEORIES 7 ideas. My graduate student colleagues at the Department of Mathematics also deserve gratitude, for listening and being part of multiple conversations inside and outside of the area of mathematics. Finally I dedicate this thesis to the shade of my heart, my ancée Karin, for always being encouraging towards me, even when I am not. References [1] S.N. Burris, Number theoretic density and logical limit laws, Mathematical surveys and monographs, Volume 86, American mathematical society (2001). [2] K.J. Compton, A logical approach to asymptotic combinatorics. I. First order properties, advances in mathematics, Volume 65 (1987) [3] K.J. Compton, The computational complexity of asymptotic problems I: partial orders, Inform. and comput. 78 (1988), [4] H-D. Ebbinghaus, J. Flum, Finite model theory, Springer verlag (2000). [5] R. Fagin, Probabilities on nite models, J. Symbolic Logic 41(1976), no. 1, [6] R. Fagin, The number of nite relational structures, Discrete mathematics, Vol. 19 (1977) [7] Y.V. Glebskii, D.I. Kogan, M.I. Liogonkii, V.A. Talanov, Volume and fraction of satis- ability of formulas over the lower predicate calculus, Kibernetyka Vol. 2 (1969) [8] S. Haber, M. Krivelevich, The logic of random regular graphs, Journal of combinatorics, Volume 1 (2010) [9] H.J. Keisler, W.B. Lotfallah, Almost everywhere elimination of probability quantiers, The journal of symbolic logic, Volume 74 (2009) [10] P.G. Kolaitis, H.J. Prömel, B.L. Rothschild, K l+1 -free graphs: asymptotic structure and a 0-1 law, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 303 (1987) [11] V. Koponen, Asymptotic probabilities of extension properties and random l-colourable structures, Annals of pure and applied logic, Vol 163 (2012) [12] V. Koponen, A limitlaw of almost l-partite graphs, The journal of symbolic logic, Volume 78 (2013) [13] V. Koponen, Random graphs with bounded maximum degree: asymptotic structure and a logical limit law, Discrete mathematics and theoretical computer science, Volume 14 (2012) [14] J.F. Lynch, Convergence law for random graphs with specied degree sequence, ACM Transactions on computational logic, Volume 6 (2005) [15] J. Spencer, The strange logic of random graphs, Springer (2000). [16] J. Spencer, S. Shelah, Zero-one laws for sparse random graphs, Journal of the american mathematical society, Volume 1 (1988) [17] J. Tyszkiewicz, Probabilities in rst-order logic of a unary function and a binary relation, Random structures & algorithms, Volume 6 (1995) [18] P. Winkler, Random structures and zero-one laws, in N.W. Sauer et al (editors) Finite and innite combinatorics in sets and logic, NATO advanced science institute series, Kluver (1993)

10 Random l-colourable structures with a pregeometry Ove Ahlman and Vera Koponen July 20, 2012 Abstract We study nite l-colourable structures with an underlying pregeometry. The probability measure that is used corresponds to a process of generating such structures (with a given underlying pregeometry) by which colours are rst randomly assigned to all 1-dimensional subspaces and then relationships are assigned in such a way that the colouring conditions are satised but apart from this in a random way. We can then ask what the probability is that the resulting structure, where we now forget the specic colouring of the generating process, has a given property. With this measure we get the following results: 1. A zero-one law. 2. The set of sentences with asymptotic probability 1 has an explicit axiomatisation which is presented. 3. There is a formula ξ(x, y) (not directly speaking about colours) such that, with asymptotic probability 1, the relation there is an l-colouring which assigns the same colour to x and y is dened by ξ(x, y). 4. With asymptotic probability 1, an l-colourable structure has a unique l-colouring (up to permutation of the colours). Keywords: model theory, nite structure, zero-one law, colouring, pregeometry. 1 Introduction We begin with some background. Let l 2 be an integer. Random l-colourable (undirected) graphs were studied by Kolaitis, Prömel and Rothschild in [7] as part of proving a zero-one law for (l + 1)-clique-free graphs. They proved that random l-colorable graphs satises a (labelled) zero-one law, when the uniform probability measure is used. In other words, if C n denotes the set of undirected l-colourable graphs with vertices 1,..., n, then, for every sentence ϕ in a language with only a binary relation symbol (besides the identity symbol), the proportion of graphs in C n which satisfy ϕ approaches either 0 or 1. They also showed that the proportion of graphs in C n which have a unique l-colouring (up to permuting the colours) approaches 1 as n. In [7] its authors also proved the other statements labelled 14 in this paper's abstract, when using the uniform probability measure on C n, although in case of 3 it is not made explicit. This work was preceeded, and probably stimulated, by an article of Erdös, Kleitman and Rothschild [4] in which it was proved that proportion of triangle-free graphs with vertices 1,..., n which are bipartite (2-colourable) approaches 1 as n. One can generalise l-colourings from structures with only binary relations to structures with relations of any arity r 2 by saying that a structure M is l-coloured if the elements of M can be assigned colours from the set of colours {1,..., l} in such that if M = R(a 1,..., a r ) for some relation symbol R, then {a 1,..., a r } contains at least two 1

11 elements with dierent colour. Another way of generalising the notion of l-colouring for graphs, giving the notion of strong l-colouring, is to require that if M = R(a 1,..., a r ) then i j implies that a i and a j have dierent colours. (If the language has only binary relation symbols then there is no dierence between the two notions of l-colouring.) In [8], Koponen proved that, for every nite relational langauge, if C n is the set of l-colourable structures with universe {1,..., n}, then the statements 14 from the abstract hold, for the dimension conditional probability measure, as well as for the uniform probability measure, on C n. The same results hold if we instead consider strongly l- colourable structures. Moreover, the results still hold, for both types of colourings and both probability measures, if we insist that some of the relation symbols are always interpreted as irreexive and symmetric relations. A consequence of the zero-one law for (strongly) l-colourable structures is that if, for some nite relational vocabulary and for each positive n N, K n is a set of structures with universe {1,..., n} containing every l-colourable structure with that universe, and the probability, using either the dimension conditional measure or the uniform measure, that a random member of K n is (strongly) l-colourable approaches 1 as n, then K n has a zero-one law for the corresponding measure; i.e. for every sentence ϕ, the probability that ϕ is true in a random M K n approaches either 0 or 1 as n. In [11], Person and Schacht proved that if F denotes the Fano plane as a 3-hypergraph (so F has seven elements and seven 3-hyperedges such that every pair of distinct elements are contained in a unique 3-hyperedge) and K n is the set of F-free 3-hypergraphs with universe (vertex set) {1,..., n}, then the proportion of hypergraphs in K n which are 2-colourable approaches 1 as n. Since every 2-colourable 3-hypergraph is F-free, it follows the F-free 3-hypergraphs satisfy a zero-one law if we use the uniform probability measure. As another example, Balogh and Mubayi [1] have proved that if H denotes the hypergraph with vertices 1, 2, 3, 4, 5 and 3-hyperedges {1, 2, 3}, {1, 2, 4} and {3, 4, 5} and if K n denotes the set of H-free 3- hypergraphs with universe {1,..., n}, then the proportion of hypergraphs in K n which are strongly 3-colourable approaches 1 as n. Since every strongly 3-colourable 3-hypergraph is H-free it follows that H-free 3-hypergraphs satisfy a zero-one law. In the present article we generalise the work in [8] to the context of (strongly) l- colourable structures with an underlying (combinatorial) pregeometry, also called matroid. Roughly speaking, a structure M with a pregeometry will be called l-colourable if its 1-dimensional subspaces (i.e. closed subsets of M) can be assigned colours from l given colours in such a way that if R is a relation symbol and M = R(a 1,..., a r ), then there are i and j such that the subspaces spanned by a i and by a j, respectively, have dierent colours. A structure M will be called strongly l-colourable if its 1-dimensional subspaces can be assigned colours from l given colours in such a way that if M = R(a 1,..., a r ), then any two distinct 1-dimensional subspaces that are included in the closure of {a 1,..., a r } have dierent colours. The main motivation for this generalisation is to understand how the combinatorics of colourings work out if the elements of a structure are related to each other in a geometrical way, where in particular, the role of cardinality is taken over by dimension. The main examples of pregeometries for which the results of this article apply are vector spaces, projective spaces and ane spaces over some xed nite eld. Another motivation is the fact that pregeometries have played an important role in the study of innite models and one may ask to what extent the notion of pregeometry can be combined with the study of asymptotic properties of nite structures. In [8] a framework for studying asymptotic properties of nite structures with an underlying pregeometry was presented. Here we work within that framework, but since we only consider (strongly) l-colourable structures some notions from [8] become simpler here. 2

12 We now give rough explanations of the notions that will be involved and the main results. Precise denitions are given in Section 2. We x an integer l 2. L pre denotes a rst-order language and for every n N, G n is an L pre -structure such that (G n, cl Gn ) is a pregeometry (Denition 2.1) where the closure operator cl Gn is denable by L pre -formulas (in a sense given by Denition 2.3 and Assumption 2.12). We will consider the property `polynomial k-saturation' (Denition 2.10) of the enumerated set G = {G n : n N}. From Assumption 2.12 it follows that the dimension of G n approaches innity as n tends to innity. The language L rel (from Assumption 2.12) includes L pre and has, in addition, nitely many new relation symbols, all of arity at least 2. By C n we denote the set of all L rel -structures M such that M L pre = G n and M is l-colourable (Denition 2.14). By S n we denote the set of all L rel -structures M such that M L pre = G n and M is strongly l-colourable (Denition 2.14). For every n, δn C denotes the probability measure given by Denition 2.17, which means, roughly speaking, that if X C n, then δn C (X) is the probability that M C n belongs to X if M generated by the following procedure: rst randomly assign l colours to the 1-dimensional subspaces of M, then, for every relation symbol R that belongs to the vocabulary of L rel but not to the vocabulary of L pre, choose an interpretation of R randomly from all possibilities of interpretations R M such that the previous assignment of colours is an l-colouring of the resulting structure, and nally forget the colour assignment, leaving us with an L rel -structure. The probability measure δn S on S n is dened similarly (Denition 2.17). If ϕ is an L rel -sentence then δn C (ϕ) = δn C ( {M Cn : M = ϕ} ) and similarly for δn(ϕ). S Theorem 1.1. Suppose that Assumption 2.12 holds and that G = {G n : n N} is polynomially k-saturated for every k N. Then, for every L rel -sentence ϕ, δ C n (ϕ) approaches either 0 or 1, and δ S n(ϕ) approaches either 0 or 1, as n. If F is a eld and G is the set of vectors of a vector space or of an ane space over F, or if G is the set of lines of a projective space over F, then (G, cl) where cl is the linear closure operator, ane closure operator, or projective closure operator, respectively, forms a pregeometry (see for example [10] or [9]). Theorem 1.2. Suppose that the conditions of Assumption 2.12 hold and that for some nite eld F one of the following three cases holds for every n N: G n is an (a) n-dimensional vector space, or (b) n-dimensional ane space, or (c) n-dimensional projective space, over F, and cl Gn is the linear, ane or projective closure operator on G n, respectively. Moreover, assume that L pre is the generic language L gen from Example 2.4, with the intepretations of symbols given in that example. (i) There is an L rel -formula ξ(x, y) such that the δ C n -probability that the following holds for M C n approaches 1 as n : For all a, b M cl M ( ), M = ξ(a, b) if and only if every l-colouring of M gives a and b the same colour. (ii) lim n δn C ( {M Cn : M has a unique l-colouring} ) = 1. (iii) lim n δn C ( {M Cn : M is not l -colourable if l < l} ) = 1. (iv) The set {ϕ L rel : lim n δn C (ϕ) = 1} forms a countably categorical theory which can be explicitly axiomatised (as in Section 5) by L rel -sentences of the form x ȳψ( x, ȳ) where ψ is quantier-free, mainly in terms of what we call l-colour compatible extension axioms, which involve the formula ξ(x, y) from part (i). (v) The statements (i)(iv) hold if we assume that, for each n N, G n is an n- dimensional vector space over F, cl Gn is the linear closure operator on G n and that 3

13 L pre is the language L F from Example 2.6, with the interpretation of symbols from that example. The assumptions of Theorem 1.2 imply the assumptions of Theorem 1.3, which is explained in Example That is, when dealing with strongly l-colourable structures, the assumptions on the underlying pregeometries can be weaker. By a subspace of a pregeometry we mean a closed set with respect to the given closure operator (Denition 2.3). Theorem 1.3. Suppose that the conditions of Assumption 2.12 hold and that G is polynomially k-saturated for every k N. Also assume that for every n N, every 2- dimensional subspace of G n has at most l dierent 1-dimensional subspaces. (i) There is an L rel -formula ξ(x, y) such that the δ S n-probability that the following holds for M S n approaches 1 as n : For all a, b M cl M ( ), M = ξ(a, b) if and only if every l-colouring of M gives a and b the same colour. (ii) lim n δ S n( {M Sn : M has a unique strong l-colouring} ) = 1. (iii) lim n δ S n( {M Sn : M is not strongly l -colourable if l < l} ) = 1. (iv) Suppose, moreover, that the formulas of L pre which, according to Assumption 2.12, dene the pregeometry G = {G n : n N} are quantier-free. Then the set {ϕ L rel : lim n δ S n(ϕ) = 1} forms a countably categorical theory which can be explicitly axiomatised (as in Section 5) by L rel -sentences of the form x ȳψ( x, ȳ) where ψ is quantierfree, mainly in terms of what we call l-colour compatible extension axioms, which involve the formula ξ(x, y) from part (i). It turns out that Theorem 1.1 follows rather straightforwardly from Theorem 7.32 in [8] when we have proved Lemma 2.21 below. However, Theorem 1.1 in itself does not give information about which sentences have asymptotic probability 1 (or 0), or about properties of the theory consisting of those sentences which have asymptotic probability 1. Neither does it tell us anything about typical properties of large (strongly) l-colourable structures. In order to prove part (i) of Theorems 1.2 and 1.3, which give information of this kind, we treat l-colourable structures and strongly l-colourable structures separately and need to add some assumption(s). The case of strong l-colourings is the easier one and is treated in Section 3; that is, most of the argument leading to part (i) of Theorem 1.3 is carried out in Section 3. The main part of the proof of (i) of Theorem 1.2, dealing with (not necessarily strong) l-colourings, is carried out in Section 4 where we use a theorem from structural Ramsey theory by Graham, Leeb and Rothschild [5]. Once we have established part (i) of Theorems 1.2 and 1.3, which, as said above, is done separately, parts (ii)(iv) (and (v) of Theorem 1.2) can be proved in a uniform way, that is, it is no longer necessary to distinguish between l-colourable structures and strongly l-colourable structures. This is done in Section 5. It is possible to read Section 5 directly after Section 2 and then consider the details of denability of colorings in Sections 3 and 4, which are independent of each other. The theorems above generalise the results of Section 9 of [8] to the situation when a nontrivial pregeometry (subject to certain conditions) is present. In other words, if the closure of a set A is always A (so every set is closed) and we let L pre be the language whose vocabulary contains only the identity symbol `=', and, for every n N, G n is the unique (under these assumtions) L pre -structure with universe {1,..., n+1}, then (i)(iv) of Theorems 1.2 and 1.3 hold by results in Section 9 of [8]. Theorem 1.1 includes this case, without reformulation. 4

14 Remark 1.4. One may want to consider only L rel -structures in which certain relation symbols from the vocabulary of L rel are always interpreted as irreexive and symmetric relations (see beginning of Section 2). Theorems 1.1 and 1.2 hold with exactly the same proofs also in this situation. This claim uses that all results of [8] (see Remark 2.1 of that article) hold whether or not one assumes that certain relation symbols are always interpreted as irreexive and symmetric relations. If a technical assumption is added, explained in Remark 3.7, then Theorem 1.3 also holds in the context when some relation symbols are always interpreted as irreexive and symmetric relations. Remark 1.5. In [8], results corresponding to Theorems , in the case of trivial pregeometries (i.e. when every set is closed), where proved also for the uniform probability measure. The proof used the fact, proved in Section 10 of [8], that, when the pregeometries considered are trivial, then the probability, with the uniform probability measure, that a random (strongly) l-colourable structure with n elements has an l-colouring with relatively even distribution of colours, approaches 1 as n. We believe that the same is true in the context of Theorems 1.2 and 1.3 above, by proofs analogous to those in Section 10 of [8]. But when the underlying pregeometries are no longer assumed to be trivial, then this condition alone seems to be insucient for proving analogoues of Theorems if δn C is replaced by the uniform probability measure on C n and δn S is replaced by the uniform probability measure on S n. In other words, it appears to be a more dicult task to transfer the results of this article to the uniform probability measure (if possible at all) than was the case in [8]. This article ends with a small errata to [8], which makes explicit some assumptions, used implicity in Section 8 of [8], but not stated explicitly in the places in Sections 78 of [8] where they are relevant. 2 Pregeometries and (strongly) l-colourable structures The notation used here is more or less standard; see [3, 9] for example. The formal languages considered are always rst-order and denoted L, often with a subscript. Such L denotes the set of rst-order formulas over some vocabulary, also called signature, consisting of constant-, function- and/or relation symbols. First-order structures are denoted with calligraphic letters A, B,..., M, N,..., and their universes with the corresponding noncalligraphic letters A, B,..., M, N,.... If the vocabulary of a language L has no constant or function symbols, then we allow an L-structure to have an empty universe. Finite sequences/tuples of objects, usually elements from structures or variables, are denoted with ā, x, etc. By ā A we mean that every element of the sequence ā belongs to the set A, and A denotes the cardinality of A. A function f : M N is called an embedding of M into N if, for every constant symbol c, f(c M ) = c N, for every function symbol g and tuple (a 1,..., a r ) M r where r is the arity of g, g N (f(a 1 ),..., f(a r )) = f(g M (a 1,..., a r )), and for every relation symbol R and tuple (a 1,..., a r ) M r where r is the arity of R, M = R(a 1,..., a r ) N = R(f(a 1 ),..., f(a r )). It follows that an isomorphism from M to N is the same as a surjective embedding from M to N. Suppose that L is a language whose vocabulary is included in the vocabulary of L. For any L-structure M, by M L we denote the reduct of M to L. If M is an L-structure and A M, then M A denotes the substructure of M which is generated by the set A, that is, M A is the unique substructure N of M such that A N M and if N M and A N M, then N N. A third meaning of the symbol ` ' with respect to structures is given by Denition Suppose that A is a set, n 2 and R A n an n-ary relation on A. We 5

15 call R irreexive if (a 1,..., a n ) R implies that a i a j whenever i j. We call R symmetric if (a 1,..., a n ) R implies that (π(a 1 ),..., π(a r )) R for every permutation π of {a 1,..., a n }. For any set A, P(A) denotes the power set of A. A usual, we call a formula existential if it has the form where ϕ is quantier free. y 1,..., y m ϕ(x 1,..., x k, y 1,..., y m ) Denition 2.1. We say that (A, cl), with cl : P(A) P(A) is a pregeometry (also called matroid) if it satises the following for all X, Y A: 1. (Reexivity) X cl(x). 2. (Monotonicity) Y cl(x) cl(y ) cl(x). 3. (Exchange property) If a, b A then a cl(x {b}) cl(x) b cl(x {a}). 4. (Finite Character) cl(x) = {cl(x 0 ) : X 0 X and X 0 is nite}. If X, Y A then we say that X is independent from Y if cl(x) cl(y ) = cl( ). From the exchange property it follows that X is indepependent from Y if and only if Y is independent from X (symmetry of independence). We will often write cl(a 1,..., a n ) instead of cl({a 1,..., a n }) and say `a is independent from b' instead of `{a} is independent from {b} over '. We say that a set X is independent if for, each a X, we have that {a} is independent from X {a}. We say that a set X A is closed (in (A, cl)) if cl(x) = X. For X A, the dimension of X is dened as dim(x) = inf{ Y : Y X and X cl(y )}. For more about pregeometries the reader is refered to [9, 10] for example. We will use the following lemma, which has probably been proved somewhere, but for the sake of completeness we give a proof of it here. Lemma 2.2. Let A = (A, cl) be a pregeometry. If {a, v 1,..., v m, w 1,..., w n } A is an independent set then cl(a, v 1,..., v m ) cl(a, w 1,..., w n ) = cl(a) Proof. Suppose that {a, v 1,..., v m, w 1,..., w n } A is an independent set. By reexivity a cl(a, v 1,..., v m ) cl(a, w 1,..., w n ) and so by monotonicity cl(a) cl(a, v 1,..., v m ) cl(a, w 1,..., w n ). For the opposite direction we assume that x cl(a, v 1,..., v m ) cl(a, w 1,..., w n ) and use induction over n to prove that x cl(a). Base case: If n = 0 then cl(a, w 1,..., w n ) = cl(a) so, as x cl(a), we are done. Induction step: Suppose that x cl(a, v 1,..., v m ) cl(a, w 1,..., w n+1 ), so we have two cases to consider: either x ( cl(a, v 1,..., v m ) cl(a, w 1,..., w n+1 ) ) ( cl(a, v 1,..., v m ) cl(a, w 1,..., w n ) ), or x cl(a, v 1,..., v m ) cl(a, w 1,..., w n ). In the rst case we get the consequence that x cl(a, w 1,..., w n+1 ) cl(a, w 1,..., w n ) and hence by the exchange property we get that w n+1 cl(a, w 1,..., w n, x). We already know that x cl(a, v 1,..., v m ) and by also using the assumption that {a, v 1,..., v m, w 1,..., w n } is independent we get that 1 + m + n = dim(a, v 1,..., v m, w 1,..., w n ) = dim(a, v 1,..., v m, w 1,..., w n, x) = 6

16 dim(a, v 1,..., v m, w 1,..., w n, w n+1, x) = dim(a, v 1,..., v m, w 1,..., w n+1 ) = 1 + m + n + 1, so 1 + m + n = 1 + m + n + 1, a contradiction. Hence, x cl(a, v 1,..., v m ) cl(a, w 1,..., w n ), so by the induction hypothesis we get that x cl(a). By induction we conclude that cl(a, v 1,..., v m ) cl(a, w 1,..., w n ) cl(a) holds for all n, which nishes the proof. We will consider rst-order structures M for which there is a closure operator cl on M such that (M, cl) is a pregeometry and, for each n, the relation x n+1 cl(x 1,..., x n ) is denable by a rst-order formula without parameters. More precisely, we have the following denition. Denition 2.3. (i) We say that an L-structure A is a pregeometry if there are L- formulas θ n (x 1,..., x n+1 ), for all n N, such that if the operator cl A : P(A) P(A) is dened by (a) and (b) below, then (A, cl A ) is a pregeometry: (a) For every n N, every sequence b 1,..., b n A and every a A, a cl A (b 1,..., b n ) A = θ n (b 1,..., b n, a). (b) For every B A and every a A, a cl A (B) if and only if a cl A (b 1,..., b n ) for some b 1,..., b n B. (ii) Suppose that A is a pregeometry in the sense of the above denition. Then, for every B A, dim A (B) denotes the dimension of B with respect to the closure operator cl A. In other words, dim A (B) = min{ B : B B and cl A (B ) B}. We sometimes abbreviate dim B (B) with dim(b). A closed subset of A is also called a subspace of A. A substructure B A is called closed if its universe B is closed in (A, cl A ). (iii) Suppose that G is a set of L-structures. We say that G is a pregeometry if there are L-formulas θ n (x 1,..., x n+1 ), for all n N, such that for each A G, (A, cl A ) is a pregeometry if cl A is dened by (a) and (b). It may happen that for an L-structure A there are L-formulas θ n and θ n, for n N, such that the sequence θ n, n N, denes a dierent pregeometry on A (according to Denition 2.3 (i)) than does the sequence θ n, n N. When we use these notions it will, however, be clear that we x a sequence of formulas θ n, n N, and the pregeometry that they dene on each structure from a given set, which will be denoted G. Example 2.4. (Generic example) Every pregeometry (A, cl) can be viewed as a rstorder structure A in the following way. For every n N, let P n be an (n+1)-ary relation symbol and let the vocabulary of L gen be {P n : n N}. For every n N and every (a 1,..., a n+1 ) A n+1, let (a 1,..., a n+1 ) (P n ) A if and only if a n+1 cl(a 1,..., a n ). Then A is a pregeometry in the sense of Denition 2.3 (i) and cl = cl A. It follows that every set of pregeometries G, viewed as L gen -structures is a pregeometry in the sense of Denition 2.3 (iii). Example 2.5. (Trivial pregeometries) If A is a set and cl(b) = B for every B A, then (A, cl) is a pregeometry, called a trivial preometry. Let L be the language with vocabulary, so L can only express whether elements are identical or not. If, for n > 0, θ n (x 1,..., x n+1 ) denotes a formula which expresses that x n+1 is identical to one of x 1,..., x n, and θ 0 (x 1 ) is some formula which can never be satised, then every L -structure is a pregeometry in the sense of Denition 2.3 (i). Moreover, every set G of L -structures is a pregeometry in the sense of Denition 2.3 (iii). 7

17 Example 2.6. (Vector spaces over a nite eld) Let F be a eld. Let L F be the language with vocabulary {0, +} {f : f F }, where 0 is a constant symbol, + a binary function symbol and each f F represents a unary function symbol. Every vector space over F can be viewed as an L F -structure by interpreting 0 as the zero vector, + as vector addition and each f F as scalar multiplication by f. Now add the assumption that F is nite. If, for every n N, θ n (x 1,..., x n+1 ) is an L F -formula that expresses that x n+1 belongs to the linear span of x 1,..., x n, then every F -vector space V, viewed as an L F -structure, is a pregeometry accordning to Denition 2.3 (i). In particular, every set G of vector spaces over a nite eld F, viewed as L F -structures, is a pregeometry according to Denition 2.3 (iii). Denition 2.7. We say that the pregeometry G = {G n : n N} is uniformly bounded if there is a function f : N N such that for every n N and every X G n, clgn (X) ( f dimgn (X) ). Example 2.8. (Vector space pregeometries) Let G = {G n : n N} is a pregeometry. Suppose that, for every n N, (G n, cl G ) is isomorphic (as a pregeometry) with (V n, cl Vn ) where each V n is a vector space of dimension n over a (xed) nite eld F and cl Vn is linear span in V n. Then G = {G n : n N} is uniformly bounded. We get the same conclusion if, instead, each V n is a projective space over F with dimension n, or if each V n is an ane space over F with dimension n. Example 2.9. (Sub-pregeometries of R n ) Let cl n denote the linear closure operator in R n. It is straightforward to verify that whenever X n R n and cl n is dened by cl n(a) = cl n (A) X n for every A X n, then (X n, cl n) is a pregeometry. For every positive integer n choose nite X n R n and, for all n N, let G n = (X n+1, cl n+1). Let L gen be the language from Example 2.4. Then each G n can be viewed as a rst-order structure in the way explained in that example. It follows that G = {G n : n N} is a pregeometry in the sense of Denition 2.3 (iii). Suppose that, in addition, the choice of each X n is made in such a way that for every k > 0 there is m k such that if n > 0 and a 1,..., a k X n, then cl(a 1,..., a k ) X n m k. Then G is uniformly bounded. Denition Let k N. We say that the pregeometry G = {G n : n N} is polynomially k-saturated if there are a sequence of natural numbers (λ n : n N) with lim n λ n = and a polynomial P (x) such that for every n N: (1) λ n G n P (λ n ), and (2) whenever A is a closed substructure of G n and there are G and B A such that A and B are closed substructures of G, G is isomorphic with some member of G and dim G (A) + 1 = dim G (B) k, then there are closed substructures B i M, for i = 1,..., λ n, such that B i B j = A if i j, and each B i is isomorphic with B via an isomorphism that xes A pointwise. Example (i) Let L be the empty language from Example 2.5. It is straightforward to verify that if for every n N, G n is the unique L -structure with universe {1,..., n + 1}, then G is polynomially k-saturated for every k N. (ii) Let F be a nite eld and let L = L gen as in Example 2.4 or L = L F as in Example 2.6. For n N let V n be a vector space over F of dimension n. Each V n gives rise to a pregeometry (V n, cl n ) where cl n is linear span, and each V n can be viewed as an L-structure, call it G n, as in any one of the mentioned examples (depending on whether we take L = L gen or L = L F ). Then the pregeometry G = {G n : n N} is polynomially 8

18 k-saturated for every k N. This is explained in some more detail in [8] and the proofs in Section 3.2 of [2] translate to the present context. (iii) Let F be a nite eld. If G n, for n N, is instead the pregeometry obtained from a projective space over F with dimension n, viewed as an L gen -structure as in Example 2.4, then G = {G n : n N} is polynomially k-saturated for every k N. The same holds if `projective space' is replaced with `ane space'. These facts are proved are proved in a slightly dierent context Section 3.2 of [2], but the proofs there translate straightforwardly to the present context. Assumption We now x some notation and assumptions for the rest of the paper. (1) Let l 2 be an integer, P 1,..., P l unary relation symbols and let V col = {P 1,..., P l }. The symbols P i represent colours. Let V rel be a nite nonempty set of relation symbols all of which have arity at least 2. Let ρ be the maximal arity among the relation symbols in V rel. (2) Let L pre be a language with vocabulary V pre, which is disjoint from both V col and V rel. Suppose that G = {G n : n N} is a set of nite L pre -structures where G n is the universe of G n and G is a pregeometry in the sense of Denition 2.3 (iii). Also, assume that the L pre -formulas θ n (x 1,..., x n+1 ), n N, dene the pregeometry according to Denition 2.3. (3) Let L col be the language with vocabulary V pre V col, let L rel be the language with vocuabulary V pre V rel and let L be the language with vocabulary V pre V col V rel. (4) G is uniformly bounded and, for every n N, if A G n is closed (with respect to cl Gn ) then A is the universe of a substructure of G n (or equivalently, A contains all interpretations of constant symbols and is closed under interpretations of function symbols, if such occur in the language). (5) For every n N, if A is a closed substructure of G n and a 1,..., a n+1 A, then a n+1 cl Gn (a 1,..., a n ) A = θ n (a 1,..., a n+1 ). In other words, the restriction of cl Gn to A is denable in A by the same formulas θ n. (6) For every n N, if A is a closed substructure of G n, then there is m such that A = G m. Also assume that lim n dim(g n ) = and, for every n N, G n cl Gn ( ) = G 0. (7) For every n N, there is a characteristic quantier-free L pre -formula χ Gn (x 1,..., x mn ) of G n, where m n = G n, such that if A is an L pre -structure in which the formulas θ n dene a pregeometry (according to Denition 2.3) and A = χ Gn (a 1,..., a s ) for some enumeration a 1,..., a s of A, then A = G n. Remark (i) If θ n is quantier free for every n N, then (5) holds. Note that in all examples above, it is possible to let θ n be quantier free for every n N, either by using using the generic language L gen from Example 2.4, or by using some of the other languages mentioned in the examples. (ii) Observe that by (5), if A is a closed substructure of G n then the formulas θ n dene a pregeometry (A, cl A ), according to Denition 2.3, and for all X A, cl A (X) = cl Gn (X). By (5)(6), for every k N, there are only nitely many L pre -structures A, up to isomorphism, such that for some n, A G n and dim Gn (A) k. (iii) Condition (7) obviously holds if the vocabulary V pre is nite. But we want to be 9

The nite submodel property and ω-categorical expansions of pregeometries

The nite submodel property and ω-categorical expansions of pregeometries The nite submodel property and ω-categorical expansions of pregeometries Marko Djordjevi bstract We prove, by a probabilistic argument, that a class of ω-categorical structures, on which algebraic closure

More information

Simple homogeneous structures

Simple homogeneous structures Department of Mathematics Uppsala University Logic Colloquium, 3-8 August 2015, Helsinki Introduction Homogeneous structures have interesting properties from a model theoretic point of view. They also

More information

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010)

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010) http://math.sun.ac.za/amsc/sam Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics 2009-2010 Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010) Contents 2009 Semester I: Elements 5 1. Cartesian product

More information

VAUGHT S THEOREM: THE FINITE SPECTRUM OF COMPLETE THEORIES IN ℵ 0. Contents

VAUGHT S THEOREM: THE FINITE SPECTRUM OF COMPLETE THEORIES IN ℵ 0. Contents VAUGHT S THEOREM: THE FINITE SPECTRUM OF COMPLETE THEORIES IN ℵ 0 BENJAMIN LEDEAUX Abstract. This expository paper introduces model theory with a focus on countable models of complete theories. Vaught

More information

March 3, The large and small in model theory: What are the amalgamation spectra of. infinitary classes? John T. Baldwin

March 3, The large and small in model theory: What are the amalgamation spectra of. infinitary classes? John T. Baldwin large and large and March 3, 2015 Characterizing cardinals by L ω1,ω large and L ω1,ω satisfies downward Lowenheim Skolem to ℵ 0 for sentences. It does not satisfy upward Lowenheim Skolem. Definition sentence

More information

Introduction to Model Theory

Introduction to Model Theory Introduction to Model Theory Charles Steinhorn, Vassar College Katrin Tent, University of Münster CIRM, January 8, 2018 The three lectures Introduction to basic model theory Focus on Definability More

More information

A MODEL-THEORETIC PROOF OF HILBERT S NULLSTELLENSATZ

A MODEL-THEORETIC PROOF OF HILBERT S NULLSTELLENSATZ A MODEL-THEORETIC PROOF OF HILBERT S NULLSTELLENSATZ NICOLAS FORD Abstract. The goal of this paper is to present a proof of the Nullstellensatz using tools from a branch of logic called model theory. In

More information

Zero-one laws for multigraphs

Zero-one laws for multigraphs Zero-one laws for multigraphs Caroline Terry University of Illinois at Chicago AMS Central Fall Sectional Meeting 2015 Caroline Terry (University of Illinois at Chicago) Zero-one laws for multigraphs October

More information

INDEPENDENCE OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS

INDEPENDENCE OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS INDEPENDENCE OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS CAPSTONE MATT LUTHER 1 INDEPENDENCE OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS 2 1. Introduction This paper will summarize many of the ideas from logic and set theory that are

More information

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes These notes form a brief summary of what has been covered during the lectures. All the definitions must be memorized and understood. Statements

More information

Lecture 2: Syntax. January 24, 2018

Lecture 2: Syntax. January 24, 2018 Lecture 2: Syntax January 24, 2018 We now review the basic definitions of first-order logic in more detail. Recall that a language consists of a collection of symbols {P i }, each of which has some specified

More information

Mathematics 114L Spring 2018 D.A. Martin. Mathematical Logic

Mathematics 114L Spring 2018 D.A. Martin. Mathematical Logic Mathematics 114L Spring 2018 D.A. Martin Mathematical Logic 1 First-Order Languages. Symbols. All first-order languages we consider will have the following symbols: (i) variables v 1, v 2, v 3,... ; (ii)

More information

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007)

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω 0. Introduction David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) In its simplest form the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem for L ω1 ω states that if σ L ω1

More information

1 CHAPTER 1 INTRODUCTION 1.1 Background One branch of the study of descriptive complexity aims at characterizing complexity classes according to the l

1 CHAPTER 1 INTRODUCTION 1.1 Background One branch of the study of descriptive complexity aims at characterizing complexity classes according to the l viii CONTENTS ABSTRACT IN ENGLISH ABSTRACT IN TAMIL LIST OF TABLES LIST OF FIGURES iii v ix x 1 INTRODUCTION 1 1.1 Background : : : : : : : : : : : : : : : : : : : : : : : : : : : : 1 1.2 Preliminaries

More information

On some Metatheorems about FOL

On some Metatheorems about FOL On some Metatheorems about FOL February 25, 2014 Here I sketch a number of results and their proofs as a kind of abstract of the same items that are scattered in chapters 5 and 6 in the textbook. You notice

More information

2.2 Lowenheim-Skolem-Tarski theorems

2.2 Lowenheim-Skolem-Tarski theorems Logic SEP: Day 1 July 15, 2013 1 Some references Syllabus: http://www.math.wisc.edu/graduate/guide-qe Previous years qualifying exams: http://www.math.wisc.edu/ miller/old/qual/index.html Miller s Moore

More information

Computability of 0-1 Laws

Computability of 0-1 Laws Computability of 0-1 Laws Nate Ackerman University of California, Berkeley Stanford Logic Seminar December 7, 2010 0-1 Law For First Order Logic Lets begin by reviewing what the 0-1 law for first order

More information

Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory

Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory Department of Mathematics Bachelor Thesis (7.5 ECTS) Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory Author: Dionijs van Tuijl Supervisor: Dr. Jaap van Oosten June 15, 2016 Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Preliminaries

More information

A GEOMETRIC ZERO-ONE LAW

A GEOMETRIC ZERO-ONE LAW A GEOMETRIC ZERO-ONE LAW ROBERT H. GILMAN, YURI GUREVICH, AND ALEXEI MIASNIKOV Abstract. Each relational structure X has an associated Gaifman graph, which endows X with the properties of a graph. If x

More information

Disjoint n-amalgamation

Disjoint n-amalgamation October 13, 2015 Varieties of background theme: the role of infinitary logic Goals 1 study n- toward 1 existence/ of atomic models in uncountable cardinals. 2 0-1-laws 2 History, aec, and Neo-stability

More information

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory Part V 7 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets Lebesgue Integration Theory Definition 7. (Preliminary). A measure on a set is a function :2 [ ] such that. () = 2. If { } = is a finite

More information

3. Only sequences that were formed by using finitely many applications of rules 1 and 2, are propositional formulas.

3. Only sequences that were formed by using finitely many applications of rules 1 and 2, are propositional formulas. 1 Chapter 1 Propositional Logic Mathematical logic studies correct thinking, correct deductions of statements from other statements. Let us make it more precise. A fundamental property of a statement is

More information

AN INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY THEORY

AN INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY THEORY AN INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY THEORY SALMAN SIDDIQI Abstract. In this paper, we will introduce some of the most basic concepts in geometric stability theory, and attempt to state a dichotomy theorem

More information

Classifying classes of structures in model theory

Classifying classes of structures in model theory Classifying classes of structures in model theory Saharon Shelah The Hebrew University of Jerusalem, Israel, and Rutgers University, NJ, USA ECM 2012 Saharon Shelah (HUJI and Rutgers) Classifying classes

More information

CHAPTER 3: THE INTEGERS Z

CHAPTER 3: THE INTEGERS Z CHAPTER 3: THE INTEGERS Z MATH 378, CSUSM. SPRING 2009. AITKEN 1. Introduction The natural numbers are designed for measuring the size of finite sets, but what if you want to compare the sizes of two sets?

More information

Morley s Proof. Winnipeg June 3, 2007

Morley s Proof. Winnipeg June 3, 2007 Modern Model Theory Begins Theorem (Morley 1965) If a countable first order theory is categorical in one uncountable cardinal it is categorical in all uncountable cardinals. Outline 1 2 3 SELF-CONSCIOUS

More information

FIRST ORDER SENTENCES ON G(n, p), ZERO-ONE LAWS, ALMOST SURE AND COMPLETE THEORIES ON SPARSE RANDOM GRAPHS

FIRST ORDER SENTENCES ON G(n, p), ZERO-ONE LAWS, ALMOST SURE AND COMPLETE THEORIES ON SPARSE RANDOM GRAPHS FIRST ORDER SENTENCES ON G(n, p), ZERO-ONE LAWS, ALMOST SURE AND COMPLETE THEORIES ON SPARSE RANDOM GRAPHS MOUMANTI PODDER 1. First order theory on G(n, p) We start with a very simple property of G(n,

More information

AMS regional meeting Bloomington, IN April 1, 2017

AMS regional meeting Bloomington, IN April 1, 2017 Joint work with: W. Boney, S. Friedman, C. Laskowski, M. Koerwien, S. Shelah, I. Souldatos University of Illinois at Chicago AMS regional meeting Bloomington, IN April 1, 2017 Cantor s Middle Attic Uncountable

More information

Model Theory on Finite Structures

Model Theory on Finite Structures Model Theory on Finite Structures Anuj Dawar Department of Computer Science University of Wales Swansea Swansea, SA2 8PP, U.K. e-mail: a.dawar@swansea.ac.uk 1 Introduction In mathematical logic, the notions

More information

LINDSTRÖM S THEOREM SALMAN SIDDIQI

LINDSTRÖM S THEOREM SALMAN SIDDIQI LINDSTRÖM S THEOREM SALMAN SIDDIQI Abstract. This paper attempts to serve as an introduction to abstract model theory. We introduce the notion of abstract logics, explore first-order logic as an instance

More information

Preliminaries. Introduction to EF-games. Inexpressivity results for first-order logic. Normal forms for first-order logic

Preliminaries. Introduction to EF-games. Inexpressivity results for first-order logic. Normal forms for first-order logic Introduction to EF-games Inexpressivity results for first-order logic Normal forms for first-order logic Algorithms and complexity for specific classes of structures General complexity bounds Preliminaries

More information

Fragments of existential second-order logic. without 0-1 laws. Jean-Marie Le Bars. Informatique, GREYC/Universite de Caen.

Fragments of existential second-order logic. without 0-1 laws. Jean-Marie Le Bars. Informatique, GREYC/Universite de Caen. Fragments of existential second-order logic without 0- laws. Jean-Marie Le Bars Informatique, GREYC/Universite de Caen Esplanade de la paix/403 CAEN cedex/france E-mail lebars@info.unicaen.fr Abstract

More information

HOW DO ULTRAFILTERS ACT ON THEORIES? THE CUT SPECTRUM AND TREETOPS

HOW DO ULTRAFILTERS ACT ON THEORIES? THE CUT SPECTRUM AND TREETOPS HOW DO ULTRAFILTERS ACT ON THEORIES? THE CUT SPECTRUM AND TREETOPS DIEGO ANDRES BEJARANO RAYO Abstract. We expand on and further explain the work by Malliaris and Shelah on the cofinality spectrum by doing

More information

Countability. 1 Motivation. 2 Counting

Countability. 1 Motivation. 2 Counting Countability 1 Motivation In topology as well as other areas of mathematics, we deal with a lot of infinite sets. However, as we will gradually discover, some infinite sets are bigger than others. Countably

More information

2. The Concept of Convergence: Ultrafilters and Nets

2. The Concept of Convergence: Ultrafilters and Nets 2. The Concept of Convergence: Ultrafilters and Nets NOTE: AS OF 2008, SOME OF THIS STUFF IS A BIT OUT- DATED AND HAS A FEW TYPOS. I WILL REVISE THIS MATE- RIAL SOMETIME. In this lecture we discuss two

More information

Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005

Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005 Instructions: Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005 If you signed up for Computability Theory, do two E and two C problems. If you signed up for Model Theory, do two E and two M problems. If you signed up

More information

arxiv: v3 [math.lo] 1 Oct 2014

arxiv: v3 [math.lo] 1 Oct 2014 ON SETS WITH RANK ONE IN SIMPLE HOMOGENEOUS STRUCTURES OVE AHLMAN AND VERA KOPONEN arxiv:1403.3079v3 [math.lo] 1 Oct 2014 Abstract. We study definable sets D of SU-rank 1 in M eq, where M is a countable

More information

A version of for which ZFC can not predict a single bit Robert M. Solovay May 16, Introduction In [2], Chaitin introd

A version of for which ZFC can not predict a single bit Robert M. Solovay May 16, Introduction In [2], Chaitin introd CDMTCS Research Report Series A Version of for which ZFC can not Predict a Single Bit Robert M. Solovay University of California at Berkeley CDMTCS-104 May 1999 Centre for Discrete Mathematics and Theoretical

More information

0-1 LAWS IN LOGIC: AN OVERVIEW

0-1 LAWS IN LOGIC: AN OVERVIEW 0-1 LAWS IN LOGIC: AN OVERVIEW ANAND ABRAHAM Abstract. I give an overview of 0-1 laws in logic. I give a proof of the 0-1 law for first-order logic, and then guide the reader through a series of extensions

More information

An Application of First-Order Logic to a Problem in Combinatorics 1

An Application of First-Order Logic to a Problem in Combinatorics 1 An Application of First-Order Logic to a Problem in Combinatorics 1 I. The Combinatorial Background. A. Families of objects. In combinatorics, one frequently encounters a set of objects in which a), each

More information

Szemerédi s regularity lemma revisited. Lewis Memorial Lecture March 14, Terence Tao (UCLA)

Szemerédi s regularity lemma revisited. Lewis Memorial Lecture March 14, Terence Tao (UCLA) Szemerédi s regularity lemma revisited Lewis Memorial Lecture March 14, 2008 Terence Tao (UCLA) 1 Finding models of large dense graphs Suppose we are given a large dense graph G = (V, E), where V is a

More information

Chapter One. The Real Number System

Chapter One. The Real Number System Chapter One. The Real Number System We shall give a quick introduction to the real number system. It is imperative that we know how the set of real numbers behaves in the way that its completeness and

More information

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year Part II Year 2018 2017 2016 2015 2014 2013 2012 2011 2010 2009 2008 2007 2006 2005 2018 60 Paper 4, Section II 16G State and prove the ǫ-recursion Theorem. [You may assume the Principle of ǫ- Induction.]

More information

A generalization of modal definability

A generalization of modal definability A generalization of modal definability Tin Perkov Polytechnic of Zagreb Abstract. Known results on global definability in basic modal logic are generalized in the following sense. A class of Kripke models

More information

Lecture 11: Minimal types

Lecture 11: Minimal types MODEL THEORY OF ARITHMETIC Lecture 11: Minimal types Tin Lok Wong 17 December, 2014 Uniform extension operators are used to construct models with nice structural properties Thus, one has a very simple

More information

0-1 Laws for Fragments of SOL

0-1 Laws for Fragments of SOL 0-1 Laws for Fragments of SOL Haggai Eran Iddo Bentov Project in Logical Methods in Combinatorics course Winter 2010 Outline 1 Introduction Introduction Prefix Classes Connection between the 0-1 Law and

More information

Isomorphisms of Non-Standard Fields and Ash s Conjecture

Isomorphisms of Non-Standard Fields and Ash s Conjecture Isomorphisms of Non-Standard Fields and Ash s onjecture Rumen Dimitrov 1, Valentina Harizanov 2, Russell Miller 3, and K.J. Mourad 4 1 Department of Mathematics, Western Illinois University, Macomb, IL

More information

a (b + c) = a b + a c

a (b + c) = a b + a c Chapter 1 Vector spaces In the Linear Algebra I module, we encountered two kinds of vector space, namely real and complex. The real numbers and the complex numbers are both examples of an algebraic structure

More information

VC-DENSITY FOR TREES

VC-DENSITY FOR TREES VC-DENSITY FOR TREES ANTON BOBKOV Abstract. We show that for the theory of infinite trees we have vc(n) = n for all n. VC density was introduced in [1] by Aschenbrenner, Dolich, Haskell, MacPherson, and

More information

Proof Theory and Subsystems of Second-Order Arithmetic

Proof Theory and Subsystems of Second-Order Arithmetic Proof Theory and Subsystems of Second-Order Arithmetic 1. Background and Motivation Why use proof theory to study theories of arithmetic? 2. Conservation Results Showing that if a theory T 1 proves ϕ,

More information

Linear Algebra (part 1) : Vector Spaces (by Evan Dummit, 2017, v. 1.07) 1.1 The Formal Denition of a Vector Space

Linear Algebra (part 1) : Vector Spaces (by Evan Dummit, 2017, v. 1.07) 1.1 The Formal Denition of a Vector Space Linear Algebra (part 1) : Vector Spaces (by Evan Dummit, 2017, v. 1.07) Contents 1 Vector Spaces 1 1.1 The Formal Denition of a Vector Space.................................. 1 1.2 Subspaces...................................................

More information

Properly forking formulas in Urysohn spaces

Properly forking formulas in Urysohn spaces Properly forking formulas in Urysohn spaces Gabriel Conant University of Notre Dame gconant@nd.edu March 4, 2016 Abstract In this informal note, we demonstrate the existence of forking and nondividing

More information

ADVANCED CALCULUS - MTH433 LECTURE 4 - FINITE AND INFINITE SETS

ADVANCED CALCULUS - MTH433 LECTURE 4 - FINITE AND INFINITE SETS ADVANCED CALCULUS - MTH433 LECTURE 4 - FINITE AND INFINITE SETS 1. Cardinal number of a set The cardinal number (or simply cardinal) of a set is a generalization of the concept of the number of elements

More information

There are infinitely many set variables, X 0, X 1,..., each of which is

There are infinitely many set variables, X 0, X 1,..., each of which is 4. Second Order Arithmetic and Reverse Mathematics 4.1. The Language of Second Order Arithmetic. We ve mentioned that Peano arithmetic is sufficient to carry out large portions of ordinary mathematics,

More information

PRESERVATION THEOREMS IN LUKASIEWICZ MODEL THEORY

PRESERVATION THEOREMS IN LUKASIEWICZ MODEL THEORY Iranian Journal of Fuzzy Systems Vol. 10, No. 3, (2013) pp. 103-113 103 PRESERVATION THEOREMS IN LUKASIEWICZ MODEL THEORY S. M. BAGHERI AND M. MONIRI Abstract. We present some model theoretic results for

More information

An exposition of Hrushovski s New Strongly Minimal Set

An exposition of Hrushovski s New Strongly Minimal Set An exposition of Hrushovski s New Strongly Minimal Set Martin Ziegler Barcelona, July 2011 In [5] E. Hrushovski proved the following theorem: Theorem 0.1 (Hrushovski s New Strongly Minimal Set). There

More information

COMPLETENESS OF THE RANDOM GRAPH: TWO PROOFS

COMPLETENESS OF THE RANDOM GRAPH: TWO PROOFS COMPLETENESS OF THE RANDOM GRAPH: TWO PROOFS EUGENIA FUCHS Abstract. We take a countably infinite random graph, state its axioms as a theory in first-order logic, and prove its completeness in two distinct

More information

On The Classification of Geometries of Strongly Minim. Minimal Structures

On The Classification of Geometries of Strongly Minim. Minimal Structures On The Classification of Geometries of Strongly Minimal Structures BPGMT 2013 Definition - Strongly Minimal In this talk, when we say a set is definable in a model M, we mean it is definable in the language

More information

Equational Logic. Chapter Syntax Terms and Term Algebras

Equational Logic. Chapter Syntax Terms and Term Algebras Chapter 2 Equational Logic 2.1 Syntax 2.1.1 Terms and Term Algebras The natural logic of algebra is equational logic, whose propositions are universally quantified identities between terms built up from

More information

A Local Normal Form Theorem for Infinitary Logic with Unary Quantifiers

A Local Normal Form Theorem for Infinitary Logic with Unary Quantifiers mlq header will be provided by the publisher Local Normal Form Theorem for Infinitary Logic with Unary Quantifiers H. Jerome Keisler 1 and Wafik Boulos Lotfallah 2 1 Department of Mathematics University

More information

More Model Theory Notes

More Model Theory Notes More Model Theory Notes Miscellaneous information, loosely organized. 1. Kinds of Models A countable homogeneous model M is one such that, for any partial elementary map f : A M with A M finite, and any

More information

THE METAMATHEMATICS OF RANDOM GRAPHS

THE METAMATHEMATICS OF RANDOM GRAPHS THE METAMATHEMATICS OF RANDOM GRAPHS John T. Baldwin Department of Mathematics, Statistics and Computer Science University of Illinois at Chicago Abstract We explain and summarize the use of logic to provide

More information

Introduction to Metalogic

Introduction to Metalogic Philosophy 135 Spring 2008 Tony Martin Introduction to Metalogic 1 The semantics of sentential logic. The language L of sentential logic. Symbols of L: Remarks: (i) sentence letters p 0, p 1, p 2,... (ii)

More information

Model theory of algebraically closed fields

Model theory of algebraically closed fields U.U.D.M. Project Report 2017:37 Model theory of algebraically closed fields Olle Torstensson Examensarbete i matematik, 15 hp Handledare: Vera Koponen Examinator: Jörgen Östensson Oktober 2017 Department

More information

ClC (X ) : X ω X } C. (11)

ClC (X ) : X ω X } C. (11) With each closed-set system we associate a closure operation. Definition 1.20. Let A, C be a closed-set system. Define Cl C : : P(A) P(A) as follows. For every X A, Cl C (X) = { C C : X C }. Cl C (X) is

More information

Tree sets. Reinhard Diestel

Tree sets. Reinhard Diestel 1 Tree sets Reinhard Diestel Abstract We study an abstract notion of tree structure which generalizes treedecompositions of graphs and matroids. Unlike tree-decompositions, which are too closely linked

More information

Contents. 2.1 Vectors in R n. Linear Algebra (part 2) : Vector Spaces (by Evan Dummit, 2017, v. 2.50) 2 Vector Spaces

Contents. 2.1 Vectors in R n. Linear Algebra (part 2) : Vector Spaces (by Evan Dummit, 2017, v. 2.50) 2 Vector Spaces Linear Algebra (part 2) : Vector Spaces (by Evan Dummit, 2017, v 250) Contents 2 Vector Spaces 1 21 Vectors in R n 1 22 The Formal Denition of a Vector Space 4 23 Subspaces 6 24 Linear Combinations and

More information

JUMPS IN SPEEDS OF HEREDITARY PROPERTIES IN FINITE RELATIONAL LANGUAGES

JUMPS IN SPEEDS OF HEREDITARY PROPERTIES IN FINITE RELATIONAL LANGUAGES JUMPS IN SPEEDS OF HEREDITARY PROPERTIES IN FINITE RELATIONAL LANGUAGES MICHAEL C. LASKOWSKI AND CAROLINE A. TERRY Abstract. Given a finite relational language L, a hereditary L-property is a class of

More information

arxiv: v1 [math.co] 25 Apr 2013

arxiv: v1 [math.co] 25 Apr 2013 GRAHAM S NUMBER IS LESS THAN 2 6 MIKHAIL LAVROV 1, MITCHELL LEE 2, AND JOHN MACKEY 3 arxiv:1304.6910v1 [math.co] 25 Apr 2013 Abstract. In [5], Graham and Rothschild consider a geometric Ramsey problem:

More information

Generic cuts in models of Peano arithmetic

Generic cuts in models of Peano arithmetic Generic cuts in models of Peano arithmetic Tin Lok Wong University of Birmingham, United Kingdom Joint work with Richard Kaye (Birmingham) 5 August, 2009 Preliminary definitions L A is the first-order

More information

18.S097 Introduction to Proofs IAP 2015 Lecture Notes 1 (1/5/2015)

18.S097 Introduction to Proofs IAP 2015 Lecture Notes 1 (1/5/2015) 18.S097 Introduction to Proofs IAP 2015 Lecture Notes 1 (1/5/2015) 1. Introduction The goal for this course is to provide a quick, and hopefully somewhat gentle, introduction to the task of formulating

More information

INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS

INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS TOM CUCHTA 1. Introduction This paper was written as a final project for the 2013 Summer Session of Mathematical Logic 1 at Missouri S&T. We intend to present a short discussion

More information

A DISCUSSION OF KEISLER S ORDER

A DISCUSSION OF KEISLER S ORDER A DISCUSSION OF KEISLER S ORDER ADELE PADGETT Abstract. In model theory, the complex numbers as an algebraically closed field are often given as an example of a simple, well-behaved mathematical structure,

More information

A Pigeonhole Property for Relational Structures

A Pigeonhole Property for Relational Structures ~~~ ~~ ~ ~~~ Math. Log. Quart. 45 (1999) 3, 409-413 Mathematical Logic Quarterly @ WILEY-VCH Verlag Berlin GmbH 1999 A Pigeonhole Property for Relational Structures Anthony Bonatoa and Dejan Deli6 ') a

More information

What are the recursion theoretic properties of a set of axioms? Understanding a paper by William Craig Armando B. Matos

What are the recursion theoretic properties of a set of axioms? Understanding a paper by William Craig Armando B. Matos What are the recursion theoretic properties of a set of axioms? Understanding a paper by William Craig Armando B. Matos armandobcm@yahoo.com February 5, 2014 Abstract This note is for personal use. It

More information

Π 0 1-presentations of algebras

Π 0 1-presentations of algebras Π 0 1-presentations of algebras Bakhadyr Khoussainov Department of Computer Science, the University of Auckland, New Zealand bmk@cs.auckland.ac.nz Theodore Slaman Department of Mathematics, The University

More information

On an algebra related to orbit-counting. Peter J. Cameron. Queen Mary and Westeld College. London E1 4NS U.K. Abstract

On an algebra related to orbit-counting. Peter J. Cameron. Queen Mary and Westeld College. London E1 4NS U.K. Abstract On an algebra related to orbit-counting Peter J. Cameron School of Mathematical Sciences Queen Mary and Westeld College London E1 4NS U.K. Abstract With any permutation group G on an innite set is associated

More information

Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory)

Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory) Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory) VI.1 : Indexed families and set theoretic operations (Halmos, 4, 8 9; Lipschutz, 5.3 5.4) Lipschutz : 5.3 5.6, 5.29 5.32, 9.14 1. Generalize

More information

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ).

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ). Connectedness 1 Motivation Connectedness is the sort of topological property that students love. Its definition is intuitive and easy to understand, and it is a powerful tool in proofs of well-known results.

More information

Characters and triangle generation of the simple Mathieu group M 11

Characters and triangle generation of the simple Mathieu group M 11 SEMESTER PROJECT Characters and triangle generation of the simple Mathieu group M 11 Under the supervision of Prof. Donna Testerman Dr. Claude Marion Student: Mikaël Cavallin September 11, 2010 Contents

More information

Introduction. Itaï Ben-Yaacov C. Ward Henson. September American Institute of Mathematics Workshop. Continuous logic Continuous model theory

Introduction. Itaï Ben-Yaacov C. Ward Henson. September American Institute of Mathematics Workshop. Continuous logic Continuous model theory Itaï Ben-Yaacov C. Ward Henson American Institute of Mathematics Workshop September 2006 Outline Continuous logic 1 Continuous logic 2 The metric on S n (T ) Origins Continuous logic Many classes of (complete)

More information

Solutions to Unique Readability Homework Set 30 August 2011

Solutions to Unique Readability Homework Set 30 August 2011 s to Unique Readability Homework Set 30 August 2011 In the problems below L is a signature and X is a set of variables. Problem 0. Define a function λ from the set of finite nonempty sequences of elements

More information

Graphs, matroids and the Hrushovski constructions

Graphs, matroids and the Hrushovski constructions Graphs, matroids and the Hrushovski constructions David Evans, School of Mathematics, UEA, Norwich, UK Algebra, Combinatorics and Model Theory, Koç University, Istanbul August 2011. ACMT () August 2011

More information

SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS

SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS SYLVIA DURIAN Abstract. This paper develops the ordinal numbers and transfinite induction, then demonstrates some interesting applications of transfinite induction.

More information

INVARIANT MEASURES CONCENTRATED ON COUNTABLE STRUCTURES

INVARIANT MEASURES CONCENTRATED ON COUNTABLE STRUCTURES INVARIANT MEASURES CONCENTRATED ON COUNTABLE STRUCTURES NATHANAEL ACKERMAN, CAMERON FREER, AND REHANA PATEL Abstract. Let L be a countable language. We say that a countable infinite L-structure M admits

More information

A note on fuzzy predicate logic. Petr H jek 1. Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic

A note on fuzzy predicate logic. Petr H jek 1. Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic A note on fuzzy predicate logic Petr H jek 1 Institute of Computer Science, Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic Pod vod renskou v 2, 182 07 Prague. Abstract. Recent development of mathematical fuzzy

More information

2 Exercises 1. The following represent graphs of functions from the real numbers R to R. Decide which are one-to-one, which are onto, which are neithe

2 Exercises 1. The following represent graphs of functions from the real numbers R to R. Decide which are one-to-one, which are onto, which are neithe Infinity and Counting 1 Peter Trapa September 28, 2005 There are 10 kinds of people in the world: those who understand binary, and those who don't. Welcome to the rst installment of the 2005 Utah Math

More information

CS632 Notes on Relational Query Languages I

CS632 Notes on Relational Query Languages I CS632 Notes on Relational Query Languages I A. Demers 6 Feb 2003 1 Introduction Here we define relations, and introduce our notational conventions, which are taken almost directly from [AD93]. We begin

More information

Distinguishing Number of Countable Homogeneous Relational Structures

Distinguishing Number of Countable Homogeneous Relational Structures Distinguishing Number of Countable Homogeneous Relational Structures C. Laflamme University of Calgary Department of Mathematics and Statistics 2500 University Dr. NW. Calgary Alberta Canada T2N1N4 L.

More information

Stable embeddedness and N IP

Stable embeddedness and N IP Stable embeddedness and N IP Anand Pillay University of Leeds January 14, 2010 Abstract We give some sufficient conditions for a predicate P in a complete theory T to be stably embedded. Let P be P with

More information

Lecture 4: Constructing the Integers, Rationals and Reals

Lecture 4: Constructing the Integers, Rationals and Reals Math/CS 20: Intro. to Math Professor: Padraic Bartlett Lecture 4: Constructing the Integers, Rationals and Reals Week 5 UCSB 204 The Integers Normally, using the natural numbers, you can easily define

More information

Forking and Dividing in Random Graphs

Forking and Dividing in Random Graphs Forking and Dividing in Random Graphs Gabriel Conant UIC Graduate Student Conference in Logic University of Notre Dame April 28-29, 2012 Gabriel Conant (UIC) Forking and Dividing in Random Graphs April

More information

On positive local combinatorial dividing-lines in model theory

On positive local combinatorial dividing-lines in model theory On positive local combinatorial dividing-lines in model theory Vincent Guingona and Cameron Donnay Hill February 20, 2017 Abstract We introduce the notion of positive local combinatorial dividing-lines

More information

CHAPTER 0: BACKGROUND (SPRING 2009 DRAFT)

CHAPTER 0: BACKGROUND (SPRING 2009 DRAFT) CHAPTER 0: BACKGROUND (SPRING 2009 DRAFT) MATH 378, CSUSM. SPRING 2009. AITKEN This chapter reviews some of the background concepts needed for Math 378. This chapter is new to the course (added Spring

More information

Erdös-Ko-Rado theorems for chordal and bipartite graphs

Erdös-Ko-Rado theorems for chordal and bipartite graphs Erdös-Ko-Rado theorems for chordal and bipartite graphs arxiv:0903.4203v2 [math.co] 15 Jul 2009 Glenn Hurlbert and Vikram Kamat School of Mathematical and Statistical Sciences Arizona State University,

More information

Peano Arithmetic. CSC 438F/2404F Notes (S. Cook) Fall, Goals Now

Peano Arithmetic. CSC 438F/2404F Notes (S. Cook) Fall, Goals Now CSC 438F/2404F Notes (S. Cook) Fall, 2008 Peano Arithmetic Goals Now 1) We will introduce a standard set of axioms for the language L A. The theory generated by these axioms is denoted PA and called Peano

More information

Discrete Mathematics. Benny George K. September 22, 2011

Discrete Mathematics. Benny George K. September 22, 2011 Discrete Mathematics Benny George K Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology Guwahati ben@iitg.ernet.in September 22, 2011 Set Theory Elementary Concepts Let A and

More information

SKETCHY NOTES FOR WEEKS 7 AND 8

SKETCHY NOTES FOR WEEKS 7 AND 8 SKETCHY NOTES FOR WEEKS 7 AND 8 We are now ready to start work on the proof of the Completeness Theorem for first order logic. Before we start a couple of remarks are in order (1) When we studied propositional

More information

HAMBURGER BEITRÄGE ZUR MATHEMATIK

HAMBURGER BEITRÄGE ZUR MATHEMATIK HAMBURGER BEITRÄGE ZUR MATHEMATIK Heft 8 Degree Sequences and Edge Connectivity Matthias Kriesell November 007 Degree sequences and edge connectivity Matthias Kriesell November 9, 007 Abstract For each

More information

1 Introduction The computational complexity of a problem is the amount of resources, such as time or space, required by a machine that solves the prob

1 Introduction The computational complexity of a problem is the amount of resources, such as time or space, required by a machine that solves the prob Easier Ways to Win Logical Games Ronald Fagin IBM Almaden Research Center 650 Harry Road San Jose, California 95120-6099 email: fagin@almaden.ibm.com URL: http://www.almaden.ibm.com/cs/people/fagin/ Abstract

More information