ON THE LOGIC OF CLOSURE ALGEBRA

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "ON THE LOGIC OF CLOSURE ALGEBRA"

Transcription

1 Bulletin of the Section of Logic Volume 40:3/4 (2011), pp Ahmet Hamal ON THE LOGIC OF CLOSURE ALGEBRA Abstract An open problem in modal logic is to know if the fusion S4 S4 is the complete modal logic for the product of any two metric separable dense-in-themselves spaces. This would be settled, positively, if one could prove the following conjecture: When S4 is the complete logic for two complete atomic closure algebras, B and C, then the fusion S4 S4 is the complete modal logic for their product B C. This essay is an effort to give new garments to old results, in the hope that it would lead to a proof of this conjecture. Keywords: Modal logic, Dissectable closure algebra, Completeness, Fusion of modal logics. 1. Introduction The correspondence between elementary topology and the modal logic S4 was first established by McKinsey. In [6], he introduced the topological interpretation of S4, where the necessitation operator box,, is interpreted as the topological interior, and showed that S4 is complete for the class of all topological spaces. Later more mathematically interesting results such as S4 is complete for any dense-in-itself separable metric space where obtained by McKinsey and Tarski [7]. The original algebraic proof given in [7] was very complex, the later more topologic version presented in [10] is not much more accessible. Recently, several attempts were made to simplify the proof in [7] among which we mention Mint s completeness proof of S4 AMS subject classification : 03B45, 06E25, 54A05

2 148 Ahmet Hamal for the Cantor set [8] and two slightly different proofs of the completeness of S4 for the real segment (0, 1) given by Mints and Zhang [9], and Aiello, van Benthem and Bezhanishvili [1]. In this paper, we also made an attempt, in a modern way, to clarify the most important results in [7] whose proofs, mostly implicit and difficult to grasp, are improved by the use of a simple and precise language. 2. Definitions and notations Given a Boolean algebra, we shall use the following notions: (1) x y for the order relation. (2) x y and x y, for the upper and lower bounds respectively. (3) 0 and 1, for the lowest and highest elements respectively. (4) x c, for the complement of x. A closure operation on a Boolean algebra B is a map x x from B to B with the following properties: (1) 0 = 0, (2) (x y) = x y, (3) x x, (4) x = x Closure algebras A Closure algebra is a Boolean algebra with a closure operation. Associated with the closure operation is the interior operation x x = x c c which, therefore, has the following properties: (1) 1 = 1, (2) (x y) = x y, (3) x x, (4) x = x. An element x is said to be closed whenever x = x, open whenever x = x. Clearly then, x is open if and only if x c is closed. A special property. Given a topological space E, the Boolean algebra P(E) of all the subsets of E with its closure operator is, of course a closure algebra. It has the following known ( and quite useful) property: If A is an

3 On the Logic of Closure Algebra 149 open subset, then A B (A B). This is also true in every closure algebra: Let x be open in a closure algebra. We then have x y (x y) for every y. Proof. For more details, see [5]. From this it follows that, if x is open, then x (x y) = x y for each y Relativization The notion of subspace of a topological space generalizes to closure algebras. Given a closure algebra K and one of its elements a, set K a = {x : a x K}. Then K a has a naturel structure of closure algebra induced by the structure on K. In K a, the operations and are unchanged, while the original operations x x c and x x become x a x c and x a x respectively. Moreover, when a is open in K, the original operation x x stays as x x for any x K a. For more details, see [5] Extending a closure operation Let K be a complete Boolean algebra [ i.e., a Boolean algebra in which every subset has a lowest upper bound (l.u.b.) and, therefore, also a greatest lower bound(g.l.b.)]. Let H K be given with an operation from H into H, x x such that (1) 0 H and 0 = 0, (2) if x, y H, then x y H and (x y) = x y, (3) if x H, then x x = x. This looks very much as if it were a closure operation on H, except that H is not really a Boolean algebra because it misses a complement operation. Set g(x) = {z : z H and x z = z }. Then g is a closure operation on K which extends the operation on H; in fact it is the only such closure operation on K. The proof is quite straightforward.

4 150 Ahmet Hamal 2.4. Representation theorems There are two important representation theorems for Boolean algebras and closure algebras. The first is due to M. H. Stone. The second is proved in the paper by McKinsey and Tarski: It can be viewed as a generalization of Stone s Theorem from the discrete case to the general topological case. We first state both theorems. Theorem 2.1 (M. H. Stone). Every Boolean algebra is isomorphic to a subalgebra of the Boolean algebra P(X) of all the subsets of an adequate set X. Theorem 2.2 (Mckinsey-Tarski). Every closure algebra is isomorphic to a subalgebra of the closure algebra of an adequate topological space. For a better understanding of those results, we present the classical notions of filters and ultrafilters for Boolean algebras ( which are not included in [7]). Filters and ultrafilters. Let B be a Boolean algebra. A Boolean filter on B is a nonempty subset F B with the following properties: (i) 0 F, (ii) if x F and x y, then y F, (iii) if x F and y F, then x y F. This is the exact generalization of the notion of filter on a set: A filter on a set X is, precisely, a filter on the Boolean algebra P(X) of all the subsets of X. A Boolean ultrafilter U on B is a nonempty subset U B such that U B and with the following properties: (i) x U and y U iff x y U (ii) x U or y U iff x y U We give here a sketchy of Stone theorem; see [2],[3], for details. Sketch of the proof of Stone Teorem. Let X = Υ(B) be the set of all Boolean ultrafilters on a Boolean algebra B. For each x B, set f(x) = {U : x U Υ(B)}. Using the definition of Boolean ultrafilters,

5 On the Logic of Closure Algebra 151 it is easily seen that the function f : B P(X) is an isomorphism of the Boolean algebra B onto a subalgebra of P(X). The proof of McKinsey-Tarski theorem. Let K be a closure algebra. Using Stone s theorem, we can suppose that K is a subalgebra of P(X) for an adequate set X. Using the extension of closures discussed above, it is immediately seen that the closure operation on K is extended into a closure operation on P(X) which, of course, turns X into a topological space Three classes of closure algebras We will encounter three classes of closure algebras corresponding to three well-known classes of topological spaces. Here are the definitions. Consider the two properties (C) and (W ) for a closure algebra: (C) if x and y are nonempty closed and x y = 1, then x y 0. (W) if x and y are nonempty closed, then x y 0. Closure algebra K is called connected whenever it has property (C), otherwise it is called disconnected. It is called well-connected whenever it has property (W) and 0 1. Similarly, an element a K is called connected whenever the closure algebra K a is connected, otherwise a is called disconnected. The closure algebra K is called totaly disconnected whenever each nonempty open element in K is disconnected. Some peculiarities. Every well-connected closure algebra is connected. The smallest closure algebra, the null algebra {0}, is connected but not well-connected. Moreover, it is also totally disconnected. The second smallest, {0, 1}, is both connected and well-connected. We can reformulate property (W) as: (W1) The lower bound of any finite family of nonempty closed elements is nonempty. Of course (W1)implies (W) but there is a slight difference between the two: Think of the empty family in a closure algebra K; all its elements are nonempty closed and its lower bound is 1. If K satisfies (W1), then 1 must be 0 1. So, the well-connected closure algebras are those that have property (W1), without any proviso!.

6 152 Ahmet Hamal 2.6. Dissectable closure algebras Let K be a closure algebra. In order to make the definitions and statements as simple as possible, we introduce the following terminology. Given a couple of integers r 0 and s 0, an (r, s)-dissection of an element a K is defined to be a set of mutually exclusive nonempty elements a 1, a 2,..., a r and b 1, b 2,..., b s of K such that: (i) a = a 1 a2... ar b1 b2... bs, (ii) the elements a 1, a 2,..., a r all open, (iii) the closures b 1, b 2,..., b s are all equal to a closed element c, (iv) a a c c a i for each i r. The closure algebra K is said to be dissectable whenever each nonempty open x has an (r, s)-dissection for each couple of integers r 0 and s 0. The important fact about dissectable closure algebras is: The closure algebra of a separable metric space without isolated points is dissectable. For more details, see [10] Universal algebras A closure algebra K is called universal for a given class of algebras A whenever each algebra in the class A is isomorphic to a subalgebra of K. The algebra K is called generalized universal for A whenever each algebra in the class A is isomorphic to a subalgebra of the relativized algebra K a for some open a in K. This is taken from [7]. We further introduce the following definitions(implict in [7]). Given two closure algebras H and K together with an element a K, an immersion of H in K relative to a is an isomorphism h of H onto a subalgebra L of the relativized algebra K a such that, for every nonempty element x L, one has a a c x. Any isomorphism of H onto a subalgebra of K is, of course, an immersion (1 1 c = 0). We call the algebra K special universal for the class A whenever, for each algebra H A and each nonempty open a K, there is an immersion of H in K relative to a. Clearly, if K is special universal for the class A, then it is universal for that class. If K is universal for A, then it is generalized universal for A.

7 On the Logic of Closure Algebra Canonical decomposition and main universality results In this section, we define a composition closure algebra and decomposition of a finite closure algebra in order to prove main universality results. Then, we will give main universality results Companion of a closure algebra Let K be a closure algebra. Set K = K {0, 1}. The elements of K are couples (x, e) with x K and e = 0 or 1. In a quite natural way, K is a Boolean algebra, thus (x, e) (y, f) = (x y, e f), (x, e) (y, f) = (x y, e f), (x, e) c = (x c, e c ). Setting (0, 0) = (0, 0) and, otherwise, (x, e) = (x, 1), we obtain a closure operator on K which turns it into a companion closure algebra to K. The main features of the companion algebra K follow: The closed elements are (0, 0) and those of the form (x, 1) with x closed in K. The open elements are (1, 1) and those of the form (x, 0) with x open in K. So (0, 1) is closed and (1, 0) is open. The closure algebra K is well-connected since the closed (0, 1) is included in each (x, 1). Set H = K(1,0). The map x (x, 0) is easily seen to be an isomorphism of the closure algebra K onto the closure algebra H. Since the nonempty open elements of K are the elements (x, 0) with x nonempty open in K, one can easily see that K is dissectable whenever K is dissectable Canonical decomposition in a finite closure algebra Two cases are presented separately: Well-connected algebras and not wellconnected algebras The well-connected case Given a well-connected finite algebra, there is a canonical decomposition

8 154 Ahmet Hamal 1 = c e 1 e2... er with c nonempty closed, (e i ) 1 i r a family of nonempty open elements in H, disjoint from c, and r 0. The construction of this decomposition is by steps. (1) Let A be the set of atoms in H and C = {a : a A}. Since H is well-connected, there is a least element c in C, and we have x c for each nonempty closed x in H. (2) For a A, we have a c iff a = c dir. Indeed, if a c, then a c = c, and a c (because a is nonempty closed) so a = c. The converse is clear. (3) Let B = {a : a A, a c} = {a : a A, a = c}. Then, of course, c = B. (4) Let D = C \ {c}. If D =, let M =, if not, let M be the set of minimal elements in D. In both cases, set M = r so that r 0. In case r > 0, enumerate the elements in M as m 1, m 2,..., m r. (5) For 1 i r, set A i = {a : a A, a m i } and e i = A i. (6) Notice that A is the set-union of B and all the A i s. So c e 1 e2... er = 1. (7) The e i s are open in H, but not necessarily mutually exclusive [see the counter example]. Indeed, Let f i = (A\A i ), then e i = fi c and f i = {a : a A\A i }. We only have to show that f i ei = 0. Suppose, otherwise, that there exists a A\A i such that a e i 0. This means there is an atom d a such that d A i and, therefore m i d a and a A i, a contradiction. Set A = p, A i = p i, M = r, B = s and notice that p i < p, r 0 and s > 0. For simplicity, we shall set e 0 = c and write H i for the relativized subalgebras H ei, 1 i r. Notice that each H i is again a well-connected finite closure algebra: H 0, c is the unique nonempty closed element, and m i ei is a least nonempty closed element in H i for 1 i r. For each x H, define the constituents x i = x e i H i, 1 i r. Then clearly x = x 0 x1 x2... xr.

9 On the Logic of Closure Algebra 155 The counterexample. Let E = {0, 1, 2, 3} be the topological space in which the closure operation is defined by 0 = {0}, 1 = {0, 1}, 2 = {0, 2}, 3 = E. In the closure algebra K of the topologic space E, let the atoms (corresponding to the points) be simply denoted 0, 1, 2, 3. Clearly, K is well-connected and 0 is its least closed nonempty element. We have A 1 = {1, 3} and A 2 = {2, 3}. So 3 belongs to both A 1 and A 2. The not well-connected case Given a not well-connected closure algebra, there is a canonical decomposition 1 = e 1 e2... er with r > 1 and (e i ) 1 i r a family of nonempty open elements in H. [Notice that r > 1 because, otherwise, 1 = e 1 and H would be well-connected.] For simplicity, we shall write H i for the relativized subalgebras H ei, 1 i r. Notice again that each H i is a well-connected finite closure algebra. The construction of this decomposition is a quite similar to that in well-connected case. It can be carried out, mutatis mutandis, with the sole difference that B = Preparation Lemma The well-connected case Let H be well-connected finite closure algebra with its canonical decomposition 1 = c e 1 e2... er We use the notations in 3.2. Let A = p, B = s. Let K be a closure algebra together with a nonempty element a K and an (r, s)- dissection of a in r + s mutually exclusive elements a 1, a 2,..., a r, b 1, b 2,..., b s. We set a 0 = b 1 b2... bs and write, to simple again, K i for the relativized subalgebra K ai, 1 i r. Let c 1, c 2,..., c s be the s atoms in B and set h 0 (c j ) = b j. There is a unique extension of h 0 to an isomorphism h 0 from H 0 onto a subalgebra L 0 of K 0. Notice that we have h 0 (e 0 ) = a 0 and, for each nonempty element

10 156 Ahmet Hamal x H 0, h 0 (x) = k = a 0. Thus, h 0 is an immersion of H 0 into K relative to a 0. Now, for 1 i r, let h i : H i K i be an immersion of H i in K relative to a i. We sew the h i s into a patchwork: For each x H set h(x) = h 0 (x 0 ) h 1 (x 1 )... h r (x r ) to define h : H K. Then h is an immersion of H in K relative to a. Proof. We have to prove that h is an injective Boolean homomorphism such that h(x ) = a h(x) and a a c h(x) for each nonempty x H. (1) If h(x) = h(y) then x = y because the a i s are mutually exclusive, and all the h i s are injective. (2) That h(1) = a and h is an Boolean isomorphism onto L = h(h) is clear enough. (3) For x H, we have have to show that h(x ) = a h(x), the closure h(x) being taken in the algebra K. That is h 0 (x e 0 ) h 1 (x e 1 )... h r (x e r ) = a (h 0 (x 0 ) h 1 (x 1 )... h r (x r ) ), the closures h i (x i ) being taken in the algebra K. We also have to prove, when x is nonempty, that a a c h(x). Of course, all we have to do is to prove the equality and the inclusion for atoms! Here are some details for the proof. If x B, then x = c = e 0, x 0 = x, x e 0 = e 0, and, since h 0 is an isomorphism, a h 0 (x 0 ) = h 0 (x e 0 ). Moreover, for i 0, we have x i = 0 and x e i = 0. If x A i for some i 0, we have x m i, x 0 = 0, x e 0 = e 0, x i = x, x e i = m i ei, and, since h i is an isomorphism, a h i (x i ) = h i (x e i ). While, if x A j for some j 0, then x j = 0 and x e j = 0.

11 On the Logic of Closure Algebra 157 The equality easily follows, just by looking at the formula for h(x ) and h(x). As to the inclusion a a c h(x), it is simply a consequence of the definition of immersions. Indeed, h i is supposed to be an immersion of of H i in K relative to a i. The not well-connected case Let H be a not well-connected finite closure algebra with its canonical decomposition 1 = e 1 e2... er We use the notations in 3.2. Let A = p, B = 0. Let K closure algebra together with a nonempty element a K and r mutually exclusive elements a 1, a 2,..., a r, such that a = a 1 a2... ar. For 1 i r, let h i : H i K i be an isomorphism of H i with a subalgebra of K i. We sew again the h i s into a patchwork: For each x H set h(x) = h 1 (x 1 )... h r (x r ) to define h : H K. Then h is an immersion of H on a subalgebra of K a. The proof is quite similar to the previous one Main universality results We are ready for the main universality results. Theorem 3.1. Every (non null) dissectable closure algebra is special universal (therefore also universal) for the class of well-connected finite closure algebras. Proof. Given a dissectable closure algebra K {0} together with a nonempty open element a K and a well-connected finite closure algebra H, we prove, by induction on the number of atoms in H, the existence of an immersion of H in K relative to a.

12 158 Ahmet Hamal If H has only one atom, the result is clear enough. Given an integer p > 1, suppose the result holds whenever the number of atoms is < p. Let H with its canonical decomposition 1 = c e 1 e2... er have p atoms. All we have to do is to use the Preparation Lemma with an (r, s)- dissection of a where B = s. Indeed, the number of atoms in each H i, for i 0, is < p! so the immersion h i of H i in K relative to a i, and the patchwork produces an immersion h of H in K relative to a. Theorem 3.2. Every (non null) dissectable closure algebra is generalized universal for the class of finite closure algebras. Proof. Given a dissectable closure algebra K {0} and a finite closure algebra H, we have to show that there is an open element a K such that H is isomorphic to subalgebra of the relativized algebra K a. This is easily done using the companion algebra H which is well-connected. By Theorem 3.1, there exist a subalgebra L of K itself together with an isomorphism h : H L. Now, H is isomorphic to the subalgebra H(1,0) of H. Since (1, 0) open in H, the element a = h(1, 0) is open in L and also in K. So that all is said. Theorem 3.3. Every (non null) totaly disconnected dissectable closure algebra is universal for the class of finite closure algebras. Proof. Given a totally disconnected dissectable closure algebra K and a finite closure algebra H, we show that H is isomorphic to subalgebra of K. If H is well-connected, the result follows from Theorem 3.1. If not, consider the canonical decomposition of H and the corresponding relativized algebras H i, each of which is well-connected, for 1 i r. Since K is totally disconnected, there is a set of r mutually exclusive nonempty open elements a 1, a 2,..., a r such that 1 = a 1 a2... ar. The corresponding relativized subalgebras K i are dissectable because each a i is open. Therefore, for each i, there exists a subalgebra L i of K i together with an isomorphism h i : K i L i. We only have to sew those isomorphisms to get an isomorphism h of H onto a subalgebra of K.

13 On the Logic of Closure Algebra 159 This proof is not exactly the one given in [7]. It is an improvement. Indeed, this proof shows a little bit more than is stated : We do not need the algebra K to be totally disconnected. All that is needed is that: (*) For every integer r > 1, a decomposition 1 = a 1 a2... ar exists with r mutually exclusive nonempty open elements. So we have the following stronger result. Theorem 3.4. Every (non null) dissectable closure algebra is universal for the class of finite closure algebras if it has property (*). Remarks. There exist closure algebras that satisfy property (*) without being totally disconnected: The closure algebra K of the topological space E = R\ Z is dissectable but not totally disconnected. Yet E is the union of the mutually exclusive nonempty subsets (n, n + 1) for n Z so that K satisfies condition (*), therefore K is an universal algebra for finite closure algebras. This also leads to the following observation. Can Theorem 3.1 be strengthened to assert that every dissactable closure algebra is universal for all connected finite algebras. The answer is no. Both the question and the answer are given in [7]. Concluding this section, we give two important theorems: Theorem 3.5. S4 is the logic of finite well-connected topological spaces. Proof. See [1]. Theorem 3.6. S4 is the logic of any metric separable dense-in- itself space. Proof. Since the closure algebra of a separable metric space without isolated points is dissectable, proof follows from Theorem 3.1 and Theorem 3.5.

14 160 Ahmet Hamal 4. Products For Closure Algebras 4.1. The Boolean Algebra P(X Y ) Clearly enough, given two sets X and Y, the Boolean algebra of the subsets of their Cartesian product, P(X Y ), is not the product of the Boolean algebras P(X) and P(Y ). Still less : If X and Y are topological spaces, the corresponding closure algebra of the product space X Y cannot be identified with the product of their closure algebras. So what is to be done? Here is tentative answer A special product Let B and C be two complete atomic Boolean algebras whose sets of atoms are H and V respectively. Take B C to be the product B C = v V B v, where B v is a copy of the Boolean algebra B. This, of course, is again a complete Boolean algebra. It is the set of all indexed families x = (x v ) v V with x v B for each v V, partially ordered according to the product relation = v. v V The definition is clearly not symmetric in B and C. Nonetheless, there is a natural isomorphism f between the two Boolean algebras B C and C B. Indeed, given any element x = (x v ) v V in B C, simply define f(x) = (y h ) h H C B by y h = {v V : h x v }. Then, f : B C C B is an isomorphism. Proof. First, show that f is a bijection. Let x x where x = (x v ) v V B C and x = (x v) v V B C. Then there is V V such that x vi x v i for every v i V. Now from B is atomic Boolean algebra we see that x vi = {h H vi : H vi H} and x v i = {h H v i : H v i H} imply H vi H v i. Hence there is an h 0 H such that h 0 H vi and h 0 H v i or h 0 H vi and h 0 H v i. By definition, we have y h0 y h 0, and so (y h ) h H (y h ) h H.

15 On the Logic of Closure Algebra 161 Let y C B with y = (y h ) h H. Then by C is atomic Boolean algebra, we write for all h H. In this case, we set y h = {v V h : V h V }. x v := {h H : v y h } and x := (x v ) v V. Then by definition we have that, f(x) = y and x B C. It is easy to verify that the function f preserves Boolean operations. As an example, Let s show it for the operation. Consider x, x B C. since B is atomic Boolean algebra gives us x v = {h H v : H v H} and x v = {h H v : H v H} for all v V, then we get x v x v = {h : h H v H v}. Thus by definition, we will obtain f(x v x v) = {v V : h x v x v}. Therefore, we deduce easily the required result from {v V : h xv x v} = ( {v V : h x v }) ( {v V : x v}). One way to put it, also, is as follows: h x v v y h ( ) So, B C and C B can be identified, elementwise, thus obtaining one and the same object, a complete atomic Boolean algebra, to be denoted B C, whose set of atoms can be identified with H V. Clearly, if B = P(X) and C = P(Y ), then B C is identified with P(X Y ). Any given subset of the product X Y is an element of the Boolean algebra B C and has two presentations: A vertical presentation as x = (x v ) v V, and a horizontal presentation as y = (y h ) h H, linked together by the relation ( ) above Biclosure product algebra Moreover, if X and Y are topological space, so that B and C are closure algebras, then B C is endowed with a natural structure of biclosure algebra: The two closure operations correspond, respectively, to the horizontal and vertical topologies on X Y. This is quite easily seen, using the two presentations mentioned above. More precisely, let x = (x v ) v V and y = (y h ) h H be the two presentations of the same element a B C. Then, the two closures of a are simply defined as follows: a V = (x v ) v V, a H = (y h ) h H.

16 162 Ahmet Hamal Notice that this algebra is dissectable with respect to the vertical closure operation a V whenever the topological space Y is dissectable. Similarly, this algebra is dissectable with respect to the horizontal closure operation a H whenever the topological space X is dissectable. Let L 1 2 be a bimodal language with modal operators 1 and 2. We recall that the fusion of S4 with itself, denoted by S4 S4, is the least set of formulas containing S4- axioms both 1 and 2, and closed under modus ponens, substitution, ϕ ψ 1 ϕ 1 ψ, and ϕ ψ 2 ϕ 2 ψ. For more details, see [4] Conjecture If S4 is the complete logic for B and for C, two complete atomic closure algebras, then the fusion S4 S4 is the complete modal logic for their product B C. From this would immediately follow that the fusion S4 S4 is the complete modal logic for the product of any two metric separable densein-themselves spaces. Acknowledgement: I m grateful to Professor Labib HADDAD and Professor Mehmet TERZILER for their invaluable contribution and guiding ideas for the manuscript to be complete. References [1] M. Aiello, J. van Benthem, and G. Bezhanishvili, Reasoning about space: the modal way, J. Logic Comput. 13(2003), no. 6, pp [2] P. Blackburn, M. de Rijke and Y. Venema, Modal Logic, Cambridge tracts in theoretical computer science, Vol. 53. CUP, Cambridge, (2001). [3] A. Chagrov and M. Zakharyaschev, Modal Logic, Oxford University Press, volume 35 of Oxford Logic Guides, (1997). [4] D. M. Gabbay, A. Kurucz, F. Wolter and M. Zakharyaschev, Many Dimensional Modal Logics: Theory and Applications. Studies in Logic and the Foundations on Mathematics, Elsevier, Volume 148, (2003). [5] A. Hamal, Spatial Modal Logics, Ph.D. Thesis, Ege University, (2007).

17 On the Logic of Closure Algebra 163 [6] J. C. C. McKinsey, A solution of the decision problem for the Lewis systems S2 and S4, with an application to topology, The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 6 (4)(1941), pp [7] J. C. C. McKinsey and A. Tarski, The algebra of topology, Annals of Mathematics, 45 (1945), pp [8] G. Mints, A completeness proof for propositional S4 in Cantor space, in: E. Orlowska (Ed.), Logic at Work: Essays Dedicated to the Memory of Helena Rasiowa,1999, Physica-Verlag, Heidelberg, pp [9] G. Mints and T. Zhang A proof of topological completeness for S4 in (0, 1), Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, 133(2005), no. 1-3, pp [10] H. Rasiowa and R. Sikorski, The Mathematics of Metamathematics, Panstwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe, (1963). Department of Mathematics, Ege University, Bornova, Izmir, Turkey ahmet.hamal@ege.edu.tr

Logics above S4 and the Lebesgue measure algebra

Logics above S4 and the Lebesgue measure algebra Logics above S4 and the Lebesgue measure algebra Tamar Lando Abstract We study the measure semantics for propositional modal logics, in which formulas are interpreted in the Lebesgue measure algebra M,

More information

A NEW PROOF OF THE MCKINSEY-TARSKI THEOREM

A NEW PROOF OF THE MCKINSEY-TARSKI THEOREM A NEW PROOF OF THE MCKINSEY-TARSKI THEOREM G. BEZHANISHVILI, N. BEZHANISHVILI, J. LUCERO-BRYAN, J. VAN MILL Abstract. It is a landmark theorem of McKinsey and Tarski that if we interpret modal diamond

More information

A proof of topological completeness for S4 in (0,1)

A proof of topological completeness for S4 in (0,1) A proof of topological completeness for S4 in (,) Grigori Mints and Ting Zhang 2 Philosophy Department, Stanford University mints@csli.stanford.edu 2 Computer Science Department, Stanford University tingz@cs.stanford.edu

More information

cse371/mat371 LOGIC Professor Anita Wasilewska Fall 2018

cse371/mat371 LOGIC Professor Anita Wasilewska Fall 2018 cse371/mat371 LOGIC Professor Anita Wasilewska Fall 2018 Chapter 7 Introduction to Intuitionistic and Modal Logics CHAPTER 7 SLIDES Slides Set 1 Chapter 7 Introduction to Intuitionistic and Modal Logics

More information

ALL NORMAL EXTENSIONS OF S5-SQUARED ARE FINITELY AXIOMATIZABLE

ALL NORMAL EXTENSIONS OF S5-SQUARED ARE FINITELY AXIOMATIZABLE ALL NORMAL EXTENSIONS OF S5-SQUARED ARE FINITELY AXIOMATIZABLE Nick Bezhanishvili and Ian Hodkinson Abstract We prove that every normal extension of the bi-modal system S5 2 is finitely axiomatizable and

More information

On minimal models of the Region Connection Calculus

On minimal models of the Region Connection Calculus Fundamenta Informaticae 69 (2006) 1 20 1 IOS Press On minimal models of the Region Connection Calculus Lirong Xia State Key Laboratory of Intelligent Technology and Systems Department of Computer Science

More information

Modal Logic of Forcing Classes

Modal Logic of Forcing Classes Outline CUNY Graduate Center Department of Mathematics March 11, 2016 Outline Outline 1 Outline 1 Modal Logic Background Modal Axioms K (ϕ ψ) ( ϕ ψ) T ϕ ϕ 4 ϕ ϕ.2 ϕ ϕ.3 ( ϕ ψ) [(ϕ ψ) (ψ ϕ)] 5 ϕ ϕ Modal

More information

De Jongh s characterization of intuitionistic propositional calculus

De Jongh s characterization of intuitionistic propositional calculus De Jongh s characterization of intuitionistic propositional calculus Nick Bezhanishvili Abstract In his PhD thesis [10] Dick de Jongh proved a syntactic characterization of intuitionistic propositional

More information

Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem

Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem Hongtaek Jung December 27, 2017 Abstract This is a part of a supplementary note for a Logic and Set Theory course. The main goal is to

More information

S4.3 AND HEREDITARILY EXTREMALLY DISCONNECTED SPACES. On the occasion of the one hundredth anniversary of the birth of George Chogoshvili.

S4.3 AND HEREDITARILY EXTREMALLY DISCONNECTED SPACES. On the occasion of the one hundredth anniversary of the birth of George Chogoshvili. S43 AND HEREDITARILY EXTREMALLY DISCONNECTED SPACES G BEZHANISHVILI, N BEZHANISHVILI, J LUCERO-BRYAN, J VAN MILL On the occasion of the one hundredth anniversary of the birth of George Chogoshvili 1 Abstract

More information

Lattice Theory Lecture 5. Completions

Lattice Theory Lecture 5. Completions Lattice Theory Lecture 5 Completions John Harding New Mexico State University www.math.nmsu.edu/ JohnHarding.html jharding@nmsu.edu Toulouse, July 2017 Completions Definition A completion of a poset P

More information

A proof of topological completeness for S4 in (0,1)

A proof of topological completeness for S4 in (0,1) A proof of topological completeness for S4 in (0,1) G. Mints, T. Zhang Stanford University ASL Winter Meeting Philadelphia December 2002 ASL Winter Meeting 1 Topological interpretation of S4 A topological

More information

Modal and temporal logic

Modal and temporal logic Modal and temporal logic N. Bezhanishvili I. Hodkinson C. Kupke Imperial College London 1 / 83 Overview Part II 1 Soundness and completeness. Canonical models. 3 lectures. 2 Finite model property. Filtrations.

More information

Absolute Completeness of S4 u for Its Measure-Theoretic Semantics

Absolute Completeness of S4 u for Its Measure-Theoretic Semantics Absolute Completeness of S4 u for Its Measure-Theoretic Semantics David Fernández-Duque Group for Logic, Language and Information Universidad de Sevilla dfduque@us.es Abstract Given a measure space X,

More information

ANNIHILATOR IDEALS IN ALMOST SEMILATTICE

ANNIHILATOR IDEALS IN ALMOST SEMILATTICE BULLETIN OF THE INTERNATIONAL MATHEMATICAL VIRTUAL INSTITUTE ISSN (p) 2303-4874, ISSN (o) 2303-4955 www.imvibl.org /JOURNALS / BULLETIN Vol. 7(2017), 339-352 DOI: 10.7251/BIMVI1702339R Former BULLETIN

More information

Chapter 1 The Real Numbers

Chapter 1 The Real Numbers Chapter 1 The Real Numbers In a beginning course in calculus, the emphasis is on introducing the techniques of the subject;i.e., differentiation and integration and their applications. An advanced calculus

More information

Meta-logic derivation rules

Meta-logic derivation rules Meta-logic derivation rules Hans Halvorson February 19, 2013 Recall that the goal of this course is to learn how to prove things about (as opposed to by means of ) classical first-order logic. So, we will

More information

On the Structure of Rough Approximations

On the Structure of Rough Approximations On the Structure of Rough Approximations (Extended Abstract) Jouni Järvinen Turku Centre for Computer Science (TUCS) Lemminkäisenkatu 14 A, FIN-20520 Turku, Finland jjarvine@cs.utu.fi Abstract. We study

More information

Propositional Logic of Continuous Transformations in Cantor Space

Propositional Logic of Continuous Transformations in Cantor Space Propositional Logic of Continuous Transformations in Cantor Space Grigori Mints Philosophy Department, Stanford University Ting Zhang Computer Science Department, Stanford University 1 Introduction A well-known

More information

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year Part II Year 2018 2017 2016 2015 2014 2013 2012 2011 2010 2009 2008 2007 2006 2005 2018 60 Paper 4, Section II 16G State and prove the ǫ-recursion Theorem. [You may assume the Principle of ǫ- Induction.]

More information

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA  address: Topology Xiaolong Han Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA E-mail address: Xiaolong.Han@csun.edu Remark. You are entitled to a reward of 1 point toward a homework

More information

Universal Algebra for Logics

Universal Algebra for Logics Universal Algebra for Logics Joanna GRYGIEL University of Czestochowa Poland j.grygiel@ajd.czest.pl 2005 These notes form Lecture Notes of a short course which I will give at 1st School on Universal Logic

More information

Course 212: Academic Year Section 1: Metric Spaces

Course 212: Academic Year Section 1: Metric Spaces Course 212: Academic Year 1991-2 Section 1: Metric Spaces D. R. Wilkins Contents 1 Metric Spaces 3 1.1 Distance Functions and Metric Spaces............. 3 1.2 Convergence and Continuity in Metric Spaces.........

More information

Basic Algebraic Logic

Basic Algebraic Logic ELTE 2013. September Today Past 1 Universal Algebra 1 Algebra 2 Transforming Algebras... Past 1 Homomorphism 2 Subalgebras 3 Direct products 3 Varieties 1 Algebraic Model Theory 1 Term Algebras 2 Meanings

More information

Topics in Subset Space Logic

Topics in Subset Space Logic Topics in Subset Space Logic MSc Thesis (Afstudeerscriptie) written by Can BAŞKENT (born July 18 th, 1981 in Istanbul, Turkey) under the supervision of Eric Pacuit, and submitted to the Board of Examiners

More information

Representable Cylindric Algebras and Many-Dimensional Modal Logics

Representable Cylindric Algebras and Many-Dimensional Modal Logics Representable Cylindric Algebras and Many-Dimensional Modal Logics Agi Kurucz Department of Informatics King s College London agi.kurucz@kcl.ac.uk The equationally expressible properties of the cylindrifications

More information

INVERSE LIMITS AND PROFINITE GROUPS

INVERSE LIMITS AND PROFINITE GROUPS INVERSE LIMITS AND PROFINITE GROUPS BRIAN OSSERMAN We discuss the inverse limit construction, and consider the special case of inverse limits of finite groups, which should best be considered as topological

More information

Notes on Ordered Sets

Notes on Ordered Sets Notes on Ordered Sets Mariusz Wodzicki September 10, 2013 1 Vocabulary 1.1 Definitions Definition 1.1 A binary relation on a set S is said to be a partial order if it is reflexive, x x, weakly antisymmetric,

More information

3. FORCING NOTION AND GENERIC FILTERS

3. FORCING NOTION AND GENERIC FILTERS 3. FORCING NOTION AND GENERIC FILTERS January 19, 2010 BOHUSLAV BALCAR, balcar@math.cas.cz 1 TOMÁŠ PAZÁK, pazak@math.cas.cz 1 JONATHAN VERNER, jonathan.verner@matfyz.cz 2 We now come to the important definition.

More information

Computability of Heyting algebras and. Distributive Lattices

Computability of Heyting algebras and. Distributive Lattices Computability of Heyting algebras and Distributive Lattices Amy Turlington, Ph.D. University of Connecticut, 2010 Distributive lattices are studied from the viewpoint of effective algebra. In particular,

More information

int cl int cl A = int cl A.

int cl int cl A = int cl A. BAIRE CATEGORY CHRISTIAN ROSENDAL 1. THE BAIRE CATEGORY THEOREM Theorem 1 (The Baire category theorem. Let (D n n N be a countable family of dense open subsets of a Polish space X. Then n N D n is dense

More information

CHAPTER 11. Introduction to Intuitionistic Logic

CHAPTER 11. Introduction to Intuitionistic Logic CHAPTER 11 Introduction to Intuitionistic Logic Intuitionistic logic has developed as a result of certain philosophical views on the foundation of mathematics, known as intuitionism. Intuitionism was originated

More information

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy The Mathematics of Boolean Algebra First published Fri Jul 5, 2002; substantive revision Mon Jul 14, 2014 Boolean algebra is the algebra of two-valued logic with only

More information

Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics.

Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics. MAT 200, Logic, Language and Proof, Fall 2015 Summary Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics. Definition. A proposition is a sentence which is either true or false. Truth table for the connective or :

More information

Logic via Algebra. Sam Chong Tay. A Senior Exercise in Mathematics Kenyon College November 29, 2012

Logic via Algebra. Sam Chong Tay. A Senior Exercise in Mathematics Kenyon College November 29, 2012 Logic via Algebra Sam Chong Tay A Senior Exercise in Mathematics Kenyon College November 29, 2012 Abstract The purpose of this paper is to gain insight to mathematical logic through an algebraic perspective.

More information

Contents. Index... 15

Contents. Index... 15 Contents Filter Bases and Nets................................................................................ 5 Filter Bases and Ultrafilters: A Brief Overview.........................................................

More information

Equational Logic. Chapter Syntax Terms and Term Algebras

Equational Logic. Chapter Syntax Terms and Term Algebras Chapter 2 Equational Logic 2.1 Syntax 2.1.1 Terms and Term Algebras The natural logic of algebra is equational logic, whose propositions are universally quantified identities between terms built up from

More information

This chapter contains a very bare summary of some basic facts from topology.

This chapter contains a very bare summary of some basic facts from topology. Chapter 2 Topological Spaces This chapter contains a very bare summary of some basic facts from topology. 2.1 Definition of Topology A topology O on a set X is a collection of subsets of X satisfying the

More information

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory Part V 7 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets Lebesgue Integration Theory Definition 7. (Preliminary). A measure on a set is a function :2 [ ] such that. () = 2. If { } = is a finite

More information

CW complexes. Soren Hansen. This note is meant to give a short introduction to CW complexes.

CW complexes. Soren Hansen. This note is meant to give a short introduction to CW complexes. CW complexes Soren Hansen This note is meant to give a short introduction to CW complexes. 1. Notation and conventions In the following a space is a topological space and a map f : X Y between topological

More information

The Fundamental Group and Covering Spaces

The Fundamental Group and Covering Spaces Chapter 8 The Fundamental Group and Covering Spaces In the first seven chapters we have dealt with point-set topology. This chapter provides an introduction to algebraic topology. Algebraic topology may

More information

A generalization of modal definability

A generalization of modal definability A generalization of modal definability Tin Perkov Polytechnic of Zagreb Abstract. Known results on global definability in basic modal logic are generalized in the following sense. A class of Kripke models

More information

Krivine s Intuitionistic Proof of Classical Completeness (for countable languages)

Krivine s Intuitionistic Proof of Classical Completeness (for countable languages) Krivine s Intuitionistic Proof of Classical Completeness (for countable languages) Berardi Stefano Valentini Silvio Dip. Informatica Dip. Mat. Pura ed Applicata Univ. Torino Univ. Padova c.so Svizzera

More information

Infinite-Dimensional Triangularization

Infinite-Dimensional Triangularization Infinite-Dimensional Triangularization Zachary Mesyan March 11, 2018 Abstract The goal of this paper is to generalize the theory of triangularizing matrices to linear transformations of an arbitrary vector

More information

POL502: Foundations. Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University. October 10, 2005

POL502: Foundations. Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University. October 10, 2005 POL502: Foundations Kosuke Imai Department of Politics, Princeton University October 10, 2005 Our first task is to develop the foundations that are necessary for the materials covered in this course. 1

More information

Extension of continuous functions in digital spaces with the Khalimsky topology

Extension of continuous functions in digital spaces with the Khalimsky topology Extension of continuous functions in digital spaces with the Khalimsky topology Erik Melin Uppsala University, Department of Mathematics Box 480, SE-751 06 Uppsala, Sweden melin@math.uu.se http://www.math.uu.se/~melin

More information

The integers. Chapter 3

The integers. Chapter 3 Chapter 3 The integers Recall that an abelian group is a set A with a special element 0, and operation + such that x +0=x x + y = y + x x +y + z) =x + y)+z every element x has an inverse x + y =0 We also

More information

STRONGLY CONNECTED SPACES

STRONGLY CONNECTED SPACES Undergraduate Research Opportunity Programme in Science STRONGLY CONNECTED SPACES Submitted by Dai Bo Supervised by Dr. Wong Yan-loi Department of Mathematics National University of Singapore Academic

More information

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces

Part III. 10 Topological Space Basics. Topological Spaces Part III 10 Topological Space Basics Topological Spaces Using the metric space results above as motivation we will axiomatize the notion of being an open set to more general settings. Definition 10.1.

More information

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes These notes form a brief summary of what has been covered during the lectures. All the definitions must be memorized and understood. Statements

More information

Filters in Analysis and Topology

Filters in Analysis and Topology Filters in Analysis and Topology David MacIver July 1, 2004 Abstract The study of filters is a very natural way to talk about convergence in an arbitrary topological space, and carries over nicely into

More information

z -FILTERS AND RELATED IDEALS IN C(X) Communicated by B. Davvaz

z -FILTERS AND RELATED IDEALS IN C(X) Communicated by B. Davvaz Algebraic Structures and Their Applications Vol. 2 No. 2 ( 2015 ), pp 57-66. z -FILTERS AND RELATED IDEALS IN C(X) R. MOHAMADIAN Communicated by B. Davvaz Abstract. In this article we introduce the concept

More information

Section 2: Classes of Sets

Section 2: Classes of Sets Section 2: Classes of Sets Notation: If A, B are subsets of X, then A \ B denotes the set difference, A \ B = {x A : x B}. A B denotes the symmetric difference. A B = (A \ B) (B \ A) = (A B) \ (A B). Remarks

More information

Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G. Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21

Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G. Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21 Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21 Introduction These notes were originally prepared in July 1972 as a handout for a class in modern algebra taught at the Carnegie-Mellon

More information

1 The Local-to-Global Lemma

1 The Local-to-Global Lemma Point-Set Topology Connectedness: Lecture 2 1 The Local-to-Global Lemma In the world of advanced mathematics, we are often interested in comparing the local properties of a space to its global properties.

More information

II - REAL ANALYSIS. This property gives us a way to extend the notion of content to finite unions of rectangles: we define

II - REAL ANALYSIS. This property gives us a way to extend the notion of content to finite unions of rectangles: we define 1 Measures 1.1 Jordan content in R N II - REAL ANALYSIS Let I be an interval in R. Then its 1-content is defined as c 1 (I) := b a if I is bounded with endpoints a, b. If I is unbounded, we define c 1

More information

The Axiom of Choice and Zorn s Lemma

The Axiom of Choice and Zorn s Lemma The Axiom of Choice and Zorn s Lemma Any indexed family of sets A ={Ai: i I} may be conceived as a variable set, to wit, as a set varying over the index set I. Each Ai is then the value of the variable

More information

Chapter 2 Metric Spaces

Chapter 2 Metric Spaces Chapter 2 Metric Spaces The purpose of this chapter is to present a summary of some basic properties of metric and topological spaces that play an important role in the main body of the book. 2.1 Metrics

More information

Department of Computer Science University at Albany, State University of New York Solutions to Sample Discrete Mathematics Examination II (Fall 2007)

Department of Computer Science University at Albany, State University of New York Solutions to Sample Discrete Mathematics Examination II (Fall 2007) Department of Computer Science University at Albany, State University of New York Solutions to Sample Discrete Mathematics Examination II (Fall 2007) Problem 1: Specify two different predicates P (x) and

More information

The Banach-Tarski paradox

The Banach-Tarski paradox The Banach-Tarski paradox 1 Non-measurable sets In these notes I want to present a proof of the Banach-Tarski paradox, a consequence of the axiom of choice that shows us that a naive understanding of the

More information

8. Distributive Lattices. Every dog must have his day.

8. Distributive Lattices. Every dog must have his day. 8. Distributive Lattices Every dog must have his day. In this chapter and the next we will look at the two most important lattice varieties: distributive and modular lattices. Let us set the context for

More information

On Modal Logics of Partial Recursive Functions

On Modal Logics of Partial Recursive Functions arxiv:cs/0407031v1 [cs.lo] 12 Jul 2004 On Modal Logics of Partial Recursive Functions Pavel Naumov Computer Science Pennsylvania State University Middletown, PA 17057 naumov@psu.edu June 14, 2018 Abstract

More information

Chapter Summary. Sets The Language of Sets Set Operations Set Identities Functions Types of Functions Operations on Functions Computability

Chapter Summary. Sets The Language of Sets Set Operations Set Identities Functions Types of Functions Operations on Functions Computability Chapter 2 1 Chapter Summary Sets The Language of Sets Set Operations Set Identities Functions Types of Functions Operations on Functions Computability Sequences and Summations Types of Sequences Summation

More information

DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET

DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET 1. THE AXIOM OF FOUNDATION Early on in the book (page 6) it is indicated that throughout the formal development set is going to mean pure set, or set whose elements,

More information

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers Chapter The Real Numbers.. Some Preliminaries Discussion: The Irrationality of 2. We begin with the natural numbers N = {, 2, 3, }. In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend

More information

Axioms of separation

Axioms of separation Axioms of separation These notes discuss the same topic as Sections 31, 32, 33, 34, 35, and also 7, 10 of Munkres book. Some notions (hereditarily normal, perfectly normal, collectionwise normal, monotonically

More information

2.23 Theorem. Let A and B be sets in a metric space. If A B, then L(A) L(B).

2.23 Theorem. Let A and B be sets in a metric space. If A B, then L(A) L(B). 2.23 Theorem. Let A and B be sets in a metric space. If A B, then L(A) L(B). 2.24 Theorem. Let A and B be sets in a metric space. Then L(A B) = L(A) L(B). It is worth noting that you can t replace union

More information

Continuity of partially ordered soft sets via soft Scott topology and soft sobrification A. F. Sayed

Continuity of partially ordered soft sets via soft Scott topology and soft sobrification A. F. Sayed Bulletin of Mathematical Sciences and Applications Online: 2014-08-04 ISSN: 2278-9634, Vol. 9, pp 79-88 doi:10.18052/www.scipress.com/bmsa.9.79 2014 SciPress Ltd., Switzerland Continuity of partially ordered

More information

{x : P (x)} P (x) = x is a cat

{x : P (x)} P (x) = x is a cat 1. Sets, relations and functions. 1.1. Set theory. We assume the reader is familiar with elementary set theory as it is used in mathematics today. Nonetheless, we shall now give a careful treatment of

More information

Extensions Of S-spaces

Extensions Of S-spaces University of Central Florida Electronic Theses and Dissertations Doctoral Dissertation (Open Access) Extensions Of S-spaces 2013 Bernd Losert University of Central Florida Find similar works at: http://stars.library.ucf.edu/etd

More information

AN ALGEBRAIC APPROACH TO GENERALIZED MEASURES OF INFORMATION

AN ALGEBRAIC APPROACH TO GENERALIZED MEASURES OF INFORMATION AN ALGEBRAIC APPROACH TO GENERALIZED MEASURES OF INFORMATION Daniel Halpern-Leistner 6/20/08 Abstract. I propose an algebraic framework in which to study measures of information. One immediate consequence

More information

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting 5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting Let N denote the positive integers, N 0 := N {0} be the non-negative integers and Z = N 0 ( N) the positive and negative integers including 0, Q the rational numbers,

More information

On the strong cell decomposition property for weakly o-minimal structures

On the strong cell decomposition property for weakly o-minimal structures On the strong cell decomposition property for weakly o-minimal structures Roman Wencel 1 Instytut Matematyczny Uniwersytetu Wroc lawskiego ABSTRACT We consider a class of weakly o-minimal structures admitting

More information

Sets, Models and Proofs. I. Moerdijk and J. van Oosten Department of Mathematics Utrecht University

Sets, Models and Proofs. I. Moerdijk and J. van Oosten Department of Mathematics Utrecht University Sets, Models and Proofs I. Moerdijk and J. van Oosten Department of Mathematics Utrecht University 2000; revised, 2006 Contents 1 Sets 1 1.1 Cardinal Numbers........................ 2 1.1.1 The Continuum

More information

Notes on ordinals and cardinals

Notes on ordinals and cardinals Notes on ordinals and cardinals Reed Solomon 1 Background Terminology We will use the following notation for the common number systems: N = {0, 1, 2,...} = the natural numbers Z = {..., 2, 1, 0, 1, 2,...}

More information

Measures. Chapter Some prerequisites. 1.2 Introduction

Measures. Chapter Some prerequisites. 1.2 Introduction Lecture notes Course Analysis for PhD students Uppsala University, Spring 2018 Rostyslav Kozhan Chapter 1 Measures 1.1 Some prerequisites I will follow closely the textbook Real analysis: Modern Techniques

More information

Group construction in geometric C-minimal non-trivial structures.

Group construction in geometric C-minimal non-trivial structures. Group construction in geometric C-minimal non-trivial structures. Françoise Delon, Fares Maalouf January 14, 2013 Abstract We show for some geometric C-minimal structures that they define infinite C-minimal

More information

Propositional Logic, Predicates, and Equivalence

Propositional Logic, Predicates, and Equivalence Chapter 1 Propositional Logic, Predicates, and Equivalence A statement or a proposition is a sentence that is true (T) or false (F) but not both. The symbol denotes not, denotes and, and denotes or. If

More information

Formal Epistemology: Lecture Notes. Horacio Arló-Costa Carnegie Mellon University

Formal Epistemology: Lecture Notes. Horacio Arló-Costa Carnegie Mellon University Formal Epistemology: Lecture Notes Horacio Arló-Costa Carnegie Mellon University hcosta@andrew.cmu.edu Logical preliminaries Let L 0 be a language containing a complete set of Boolean connectives, including

More information

RELATION ALGEBRAS. Roger D. MADDUX. Department of Mathematics Iowa State University Ames, Iowa USA ELSEVIER

RELATION ALGEBRAS. Roger D. MADDUX. Department of Mathematics Iowa State University Ames, Iowa USA ELSEVIER RELATION ALGEBRAS Roger D. MADDUX Department of Mathematics Iowa State University Ames, Iowa 50011 USA ELSEVIER AMSTERDAM. BOSTON HEIDELBERG LONDON NEW YORK. OXFORD PARIS SAN DIEGO. SAN FRANCISCO. SINGAPORE.

More information

The Measure Problem. Louis de Branges Department of Mathematics Purdue University West Lafayette, IN , USA

The Measure Problem. Louis de Branges Department of Mathematics Purdue University West Lafayette, IN , USA The Measure Problem Louis de Branges Department of Mathematics Purdue University West Lafayette, IN 47907-2067, USA A problem of Banach is to determine the structure of a nonnegative (countably additive)

More information

Lecture Notes 1 Basic Concepts of Mathematics MATH 352

Lecture Notes 1 Basic Concepts of Mathematics MATH 352 Lecture Notes 1 Basic Concepts of Mathematics MATH 352 Ivan Avramidi New Mexico Institute of Mining and Technology Socorro, NM 87801 June 3, 2004 Author: Ivan Avramidi; File: absmath.tex; Date: June 11,

More information

Topological properties

Topological properties CHAPTER 4 Topological properties 1. Connectedness Definitions and examples Basic properties Connected components Connected versus path connected, again 2. Compactness Definition and first examples Topological

More information

Seminar I Boolean and Modal Algebras

Seminar I Boolean and Modal Algebras Seminar I Boolean and Modal Algebras Dana S. Scott University Professor Emeritus Carnegie Mellon University Visiting Scholar University of California, Berkeley Visiting Fellow Magdalen College, Oxford

More information

Notas de Aula Grupos Profinitos. Martino Garonzi. Universidade de Brasília. Primeiro semestre 2018

Notas de Aula Grupos Profinitos. Martino Garonzi. Universidade de Brasília. Primeiro semestre 2018 Notas de Aula Grupos Profinitos Martino Garonzi Universidade de Brasília Primeiro semestre 2018 1 Le risposte uccidono le domande. 2 Contents 1 Topology 4 2 Profinite spaces 6 3 Topological groups 10 4

More information

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras Keith A. Kearnes and Greg Oman Abstract. We show that if P is an infinite poset whose proper order ideals have cardinality strictly less than P, and κ is a cardinal

More information

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES ITAY NEEMAN Abstract. We present an approach to forcing with finite sequences of models that uses models of two types. This approach builds on earlier work

More information

Conjunction: p q is true if both p, q are true, and false if at least one of p, q is false. The truth table for conjunction is as follows.

Conjunction: p q is true if both p, q are true, and false if at least one of p, q is false. The truth table for conjunction is as follows. Chapter 1 Logic 1.1 Introduction and Definitions Definitions. A sentence (statement, proposition) is an utterance (that is, a string of characters) which is either true (T) or false (F). A predicate is

More information

Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra

Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra D. R. Wilkins Contents 3 Topics in Commutative Algebra 2 3.1 Rings and Fields......................... 2 3.2 Ideals...............................

More information

Consequence Relations of Modal Logic

Consequence Relations of Modal Logic Consequence Relations of Modal Logic Lauren Coe, Trey Worthington Huntingdon College BLAST 2015 January 6, 2015 Outline 1. Define six standard consequence relations of modal logic (Syntactic, Algebraic,

More information

Isomorphisms between pattern classes

Isomorphisms between pattern classes Journal of Combinatorics olume 0, Number 0, 1 8, 0000 Isomorphisms between pattern classes M. H. Albert, M. D. Atkinson and Anders Claesson Isomorphisms φ : A B between pattern classes are considered.

More information

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007)

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω 0. Introduction David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) In its simplest form the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem for L ω1 ω states that if σ L ω1

More information

MODAL LOGICS OF SPACE

MODAL LOGICS OF SPACE MODAL LOGICS OF SPACE Johan van Benthem, Amsterdam & Stanford, http://staff.science.uva.nl/~johan/ Handbook Launch Spatial Logics, Groningen, 14 November 2007 Pictures: dynamically in real-time on the

More information

Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers

Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers 1. Sets A set is considered to be a collection of objects (elements). If A is a set and x is an element of the set A, we say x is a member of A or x belongs to A, and we write

More information

P-adic Functions - Part 1

P-adic Functions - Part 1 P-adic Functions - Part 1 Nicolae Ciocan 22.11.2011 1 Locally constant functions Motivation: Another big difference between p-adic analysis and real analysis is the existence of nontrivial locally constant

More information

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. The universal modality, the center of a Heyting algebra, and the Blok Esakia theorem

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. The universal modality, the center of a Heyting algebra, and the Blok Esakia theorem Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (2009) 253 267 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Annals of Pure and Applied Logic journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/apal The universal modality, the

More information

Chapter 1. Sets and Mappings

Chapter 1. Sets and Mappings Chapter 1. Sets and Mappings 1. Sets A set is considered to be a collection of objects (elements). If A is a set and x is an element of the set A, we say x is a member of A or x belongs to A, and we write

More information

Contents Ordered Fields... 2 Ordered sets and fields... 2 Construction of the Reals 1: Dedekind Cuts... 2 Metric Spaces... 3

Contents Ordered Fields... 2 Ordered sets and fields... 2 Construction of the Reals 1: Dedekind Cuts... 2 Metric Spaces... 3 Analysis Math Notes Study Guide Real Analysis Contents Ordered Fields 2 Ordered sets and fields 2 Construction of the Reals 1: Dedekind Cuts 2 Metric Spaces 3 Metric Spaces 3 Definitions 4 Separability

More information

cse303 ELEMENTS OF THE THEORY OF COMPUTATION Professor Anita Wasilewska

cse303 ELEMENTS OF THE THEORY OF COMPUTATION Professor Anita Wasilewska cse303 ELEMENTS OF THE THEORY OF COMPUTATION Professor Anita Wasilewska LECTURE 1 Course Web Page www3.cs.stonybrook.edu/ cse303 The webpage contains: lectures notes slides; very detailed solutions to

More information

The McKinsey Lemmon logic is barely canonical

The McKinsey Lemmon logic is barely canonical The McKinsey Lemmon logic is barely canonical Robert Goldblatt and Ian Hodkinson July 18, 2006 Abstract We study a canonical modal logic introduced by Lemmon, and axiomatised by an infinite sequence of

More information