Social Interactions under Incomplete Information with Heterogeneous Expectations

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Social Interactions under Incomplete Information with Heterogeneous Expectations"

Transcription

1 Social Interactions under Incomplete Information with Heterogeneous Expectations Chao Yang and Lung-fei Lee Ohio State University February 15, 2014 A Very Preliminary Version Abstract We build a framework to analyze social interactions under various types of information structures when exogenous characteristics may or may not be observed to all agents in a group. We consider two types of heterogeneity in conditional expectations about group members behaviors. First, due to variation in individual features, expectations on behaviors of two different agents may differ. Second, because of asymmetry in private information, two agents expectations on the behavior of a third person may not be the same. We relate our model to a simultaneous move game with incomplete information and adopt the solution concept of Bayesian Nash Equilibrium. This extends current literature, where due to the rational expectation assumption, the second type of heterogeneity is missing. Hence, our model is capable of investigating social interactions with a variety of assumptions about asymmetric private information. Additionally, it can be used to inspect influences of information structures on intensity of social interactions. There is a one-to-one correspondence between a Bayesian Nash Equilibrium and the conditional expectation of group members behaviors. As the latter is a vector-valued function of privately known group members characteristics, we use functional contraction mapping to derive a sufficient condition for equilibrium existence and uniqueness. We show how to solve equilibrium under some special information structures. Moreover, we find that, by Monte Carlo experiments, nested fixed point maximum likelihood estimation performs well for linear model, binary choice model and Tobit model. Extensions to some more complicated cases of incomplete information, such as unobserved group random effects and private information about social relations, are also discussed. 1 Introduction We develop a framework which analyzes social interactions under incomplete information. By allowing asymmetry of both personal exogenous characteristics and individual private information sets, we extend current literature by allowing the expectation of an agent on 1

2 behavior of socially related agents to be heterogeneous in two aspects: the agent whose behavior expectation is taken about and the set of private information on which prediction is based. The framework can incorporate many frequently used models, such as linear model, binary choice model, and Tobit model. Additionally, our analysis applies to general form of incomplete information. Therefore, our model makes it possible to investigate interactions of various types of behaviors for socially related agents under different information structures. It is natural to believe that in a social group, like a class, some information on group members is shared by everybody but some information is known only to a subgroup of members. An agent may not know the features of all the other agents in her group. For example, when analyzing the interactions of college students academic performances, individual IQ and /or SAT scores are often used as exogenous covariates. As we know, it is not likely that a student knows the IQ and/or SAT score of all the other students in her class. She might only know that information about her close friends. Moreover, since different students make different friends, one student s knowledge about students IQ s in her class differs from that of another student in general. As a result, their predictions on math score of a third student will not necessarily be equal. With different expectations on other classmates performances in math class, those two students may make different study plans, even when all of their other personal traits are the same. Therefore, heterogeneity in private information can influence social effects. Different information structures can result in different intensities of social interactions. However, this type of heterogeneity has not been analyzed in existing literature. In previous models, after rational expectation assumption is imposed, an individual forms that same expectation over other agents behaviors as econometricians do. Therefore, two agents form the same expectation on a third individual in the group. The rational expectation assumption largely simplifies calculation of equilibrium. Additionally, it is suitable for the case when all group and personal characteristics are public information or when individuals make the same type of decisions repeatedly so that a stable status is formed. However, when there is asymmetric private information about some variables, such as individual s IQ, or when some decisions are made just once, it is not realistic to impose that assumption any more. So we try to investigate social interactions with information asymmetry without making that assumption. To achieve our goal, we build a behavioral model. We assume that an agent s decision on a certain economic action is related to her expectation of the behaviors of other agents she is associated with, conditional on her own information about publicly known group and individual characteristics, social relationships between group members, and personal traits of a subset of agents in her group. That framework is related to a simultaneous move game with incomplete information. In such a game, agents in a group make decisions at the same time. The potential payoff of an agent is affected by actions of agents with whom she is associated. Then she will make a prediction on their actions conditional on her private information and choose her best response in order to maximize her expected 2

3 payoff. Moreover, when taking expectations, a rational agent will take into account that her rival will make decisions in the same way. Therefore, an agent s strategy is to take the best response given others strategy. That is, a Bayesian Nash Equilibrium (BNE) will be derived when rational agents play the game. In our model, when we view agents behaviors as best responses, observed outcome is a realization of a BNE. One advantage of adopting BNE as a solution concept, instead of rational expectation, is that BNE allows the information on which expectation is based to be different, which makes it possible to bring in information heterogeneity. We show that we can solve equilibrium via conditional expectation on group members behaviors. First, it is shown that for an arbitrarily chosen individual, conditional expectation on her behavior is a function of possible vectors composed of privately known personal characteristics of some group members. Equilibrium conditional expectations, as a result, is a vector-valued function. Second, we prove that there is a one-to-one correspondence between a BNE and a conditional expectation function satisfying the consistency condition. Therefore, we can analyze existence and uniqueness of BNE by functional analysis. Embedding conditional expectation in a complete normed function space, we find that a conditional expectation function satisfies consistency condition if it is a fixed point of an operator. Utilizing Banach fixed point theorem, we derive that that operator is a contraction mapping when intensity of social interactions is within a reasonable range. Owing to contraction mapping, we get not only a sufficient condition for existence and uniqueness of an equilibrium, but also a possible method to solve equilibrium, namely, contraction mapping iterations. Moreover, it is possible to solve equilibrium analytically in some special cases. We illustrate solution of equilibrium by some concrete examples of information structures. If privately known personal features are discrete, we can represent an equilibrium conditional expectation as a finite-dimension vector. Coordinates of that vector correspond to function values on points in the finite support. Then we can employ contraction mapping to solve it. If privately known personal features are continuously distributed, we can either discretize the sample space and use the previous method, or use the projection method, introduced by Juud (1998)[11]. The key idea in this method is to approximate conditional expectation function as a linear combination of a finite number of basis functions. We choose the coefficients such that consistency condition is satisfied. Our framework is general. It can incorporate a variety of models frequently used in empirical studies, such as linear model, binary choice model, and Tobit model with social interactions. It also allows general information structures, including the case when all information is public, some features are self-known and some characteristics are shared by friends. However, there are still some restrictions about information structure in the basic framework. First, it is assumed that all social relations are public information to group members. Second, idiosyncratic shocks are not used to make predictions. Additionally, all exogenous characteristics used to make predictions can be observed by econometricians. Those assumptions are later relaxed. First of all, we show that owing to independence between idiosyncratic shocks and exogenous variables as well as independence of idiosyncratic 3

4 shocks between agents, including idiosyncratic shocks in the private information used by agents to make predictions does not change conditional expectation. So there is not a loss of generality in our basic framework where we assume that idiosyncratic shocks do not play a role in individual prediction. We then extend our model to include group characteristics that are observed by group members and not by econometricians. We treat them as group random effects. Equilibrium can be solved in the same way. However, when estimating the model, we need to simulate the unobserved group random effects. A more challenging extension case is that social relationships is privately known. That is, the complete social relationship in a group is not necessarily known to everyone in the group. In that case, when an agent is predicting the behavior of one agent she is associated with, it is necessary of her to consider not only possible realizations of private personal features in that agent s information set but also the subset of social relations that agent knows. We show that theoretically we can analyze the model in a way similar to that is used in the basic framework. But computational burden will be largely increased. However, in some cases, computation is tractable. Model parameters can be estimated by nesting solution of conditional expectation in an inner loop of maximum likelihood estimation. Since the conditional expectation function is a fixed point of a function operator, the method can be called nested fixed point (NFXP) MLE. That method is frequently used to estimate discrete choices in dynamic models, such as Rust[16]. Moreover, when there is unobserved group random effects, we need to simulate group random effects. In that case, the model is estimated by nesting fixed point maximum simulated likelihood estimation (NFXPMSL). Monte Carlo experiment results are present to illustrate computational aspects and finite sample properties of proposed estimators. We focus on three popular models, linear model, binary choice model and Tobit model; and two information structures, one with publicly known characteristics and another with self-known characteristics. We see that generally those estimation methods perform well. One interesting thing about our experiment is that we estimate each model under two distinct information structures, one consistent with data generating process and one not. We compare estimation bias, standard deviation, as well as maximized sample likelihood. It is found that when data is generated in the situation that all characteristics are known to every group member, estimation under the assumption that personal characteristics are self-known does not bring in additional bias (but has a smaller value of maximized sample log likelihood on average). In contrast, when data is generated in the case that personal characteristics are self-known, but all of them were regarded to be publicly known by an empirical researcher for estimation, there can be additional bias, which can not be reduced even if sample size is increased. Note that after imposing rational expectation assumption, for any arbitrarily chosen agent, conditional expectation about her behavior will be constant. As a result, in terms of model estimation, to assume public information is equivalent to assume rational expectation. Therefore, as it is shown by our Monte Carlo experiments, we need to be cautious when following previous literature and assuming rational expectation. Information structures do influence our estimation of social effects. 4

5 The linear model is related to the linear-in-means model of social interactions by Manski (1993)[14]. In that model, he assumes that agents in a group make predictions on group average behaviors conditional on publicly known group features. Hence, in his model, expectation on others behavior is a scalar. In their micro-based model, Brock and Durlauf (2007)[5], model an individual makes predictions on other agents outcomes. However, after imposing symmetry and rational expectation, expectation reduces to a scalar. Relaxing symmetry in exogenous characteristics, Lee, Li and Lin (2013)[13] allow expectation on one agent s behavior to be different from expectation on another agent s behavior. That is, there is one type of heterogeneity in their model, the heterogeneity due to difference in personal features. But by imposing rational expectation assumption, any two agents will have the same expectation on actions of a third agent. So the second type of heterogeneity is missing there. The paper proceeds as follows. In Section 2, we introduce the model framework, as well as the relationship between the model and a simultaneous move game with incomplete information. In Section 3, we first show the one-to-one correspondence between a BNE and a conditional expectation function and then discuss existence and uniqueness of equilibrium. Equilibrium solution and model estimation are respectively discussed in Section 4 and Section 5. After three possible extensions in Section 6, some Monte Carlo experiment results are present in Section 7. Section 8 concludes. Some interesting qualitative analysis of equilibrium conditional expectations is put in the AppendixA. 2 Models 2.1 A Model Framework Consider a group of socially related agents 1 The size of the group is n. We use i to index an individual in that group. The n n matrix, W, is used to represent their (exogenous) social relations. For example, it can be used to represent friendship relations or competitor relations. In that case, for any i j, W i,j = 1 if i is associated with j; and W i,j = 0 otherwise. For any i, W i,i = 0. More generally, W i,j can depend on geographic, economic or social distance between i and j. We only require that elements of W are non-negative, W i,j 0 for any i, j; and W i,i = 0 for any i. So it can show not only whether i and j are associated but also the strength of relations. Note that W may be asymmetric or symmetric. To incorporate possible discrete choices in additional to continuous outcomes, the model is presented with a latent variable and a relationship between observed outcomes and latent variables. The observed outcome, or observed agent s behavior, y i, depends on the latent 1 In empirical studies, we may encounter many independent groups. In that case, interactions within each group can be analyzed in the same way. So theoretically, we can analyze social interactions in a single group. As a result, in Section 2 and Section 3, we just look at one group. When we need to discuss different groups, we will use subscript, g, to denote variables for group g. 5

6 variable, y i. y i = h i (y i ), (2.1) where h i ( ) : R R is a real-valued function, which can be linear, piecewisely linear, or nonlinear. From (2.1), for generality, we may allow the function form to vary across different agents. the latent variable for i is interacted with her expectations about other agents outcomes in her group. y i = u(x i ) + λ j i W i,j E[y j X p J i, Z] ɛ i. (2.2) From Equation (2.2), we can see that yi is determined by three parts of factors. The first part, u(x i ), represents the direct effect of exogenous covariates. X i = (X g, Xi c, Xp i ) is composed of three types of exogenous characteristics, the group features, X g ; some commonly known individual characteristics, Xi c, as well as some privately known information, X p i. The third part, ɛ i, is the idiosyncratic shock. It is assumed that ɛ i s are i.i.d. and independent of all the exogenous characteristics and social relations. Its distribution is characterized by a pdf function, f ɛ ( ), with its CDF function, F ɛ ( ). Assume that ɛ i is observed by individual i herself, but not other agents, or econometricians. Innovations of our model reside in the second part. It shows two features of social interactions. First, i s latent variable is related to that of agent j only if i is associated with j, i.e., W i,j 0. Second, instead of assuming that latent variables are directly socially interacted, in this model, j influences i indirectly through i s expectation on the true outcome of j s behavior. This assumption is quite intuitive in the situation where agents in the same group make decisions simultaneously when there are some privately known personal traits. In that case, when an individual, i, is making a decision, she does not know either the true realizations of other agents payoffs or the actions they will take. But it is the actions actually taken by other agents that influence her payoff. As a result, she makes predictions about her payoff on the basis of her expectations of other agents actions (or behaviors). For example, when counties in a state are setting a tax rate, they will make a trade off between increasing average tax they gained from each person and a loss of tax base, for residents or business may move to neighboring counties who choose lower tax rates. As a result, a county in tax competition will make plans based on its expectation on tax rates set by its neighbors. Later, we will see that this assumption is consistent with Bayesian Nash Equilibrium in a simultaneous move non-cooperative game under incomplete information. Moreover, in this model, expectation is based on i s information about exogenous characteristics, social relations as well as information structure in the group. Since group common features, X g, and some individual characteristics, Xj c s, are publicly known in a group, they are known to i. We assume that all social relations are known to each group member. So W is also known to i 2. However, information about another part of personal 2 Here, W represents the vector formed by all its elements, (W 1,1,, W 1,n,, W n,1,, W n,n), which 6

7 features, X p j s, is not public. Therefore, except for Xp i, i may only know part of the rest characteristics. We can see that, in fact, the information structure in a group can be fully described by specifying for every agent the subset of agents whose X p s are known to her. Therefore, for each i, we define a n 1 vector, J i, in the following way: J i (j) = 1, if i knows X p j ; (2.3) and J i (j) = 0, otherwise, for each 1 j n. Hence, information structure in a group can be represented by an n 2 1 vector, J = (J 1,, J n). (2.4) For every i, we define by X p J i, the vector formed by the random variables, X p j s, which are known to i. X p J i = (X p j : J i (j) = 1). (2.5) Suppose that X p j is of dimension k p. Then the dimension of X p J i is M i = ( n j=1 J i(j))k p. For instance, if 1 only knows X p 1, Xp 2 and Xp 3, J 1(j) = 1 for j = 1, 2, 3 and J 1 (j) = 0 for j > 3. We also have that X p J 1 = (X p 1, Xp 2, Xp 3 ). We assume that information structure is common knowledge. So i knows J. This assumption can be interpreted in this way. Under our assumption, which type of information is known to i is publicly known. But the realization of those random variables are private information. For example, it is publicly known that agent 1 knows her own feature and that of agents 2 and 3. But the realizations of X p 1, Xp 2 and Xp 3 are unknown to agent 4. To simplify notation, we summarize all the publicly known variables in one vector, Z = (X g, X c 1,, X c n, W 1,1,, W 1,n,, W n,1,, W n,n, J 1,, J n). (2.6) Agent i is private information is represented by X p J i. Therefore, i s expectations about other agents behaviors are based on two vectors, one about private information, X p J i ; and another about public information, Z. Variables in those two vectors are random variables. When a random variable is included in X p J i or Z, i knows its realization. If the same random variables are included in X p J i and X p J j, i.e., J i = J j, their realizations must be the same. In that case, those two agents have the same private information. Although it is natural to assume that an agent s prediction is also based on the realization of her idiosyncratic shocks, there is no loss of generality if we exclude them from private information X p J i. We will show in Section 6 that due to independence between idiosyncratic shocks, {ɛ i } s, and exogenous characteristics, X i s, as well as independence among idiosyncratic shocks, an agent s conditional expectations do not change if ɛ i is also used to make predictions. In Section 6, we also consider the case that there is private shows all social relations in the group. 7

8 information about W. In that case, W is not included in Z. Instead, some of its elements may be private information. It is shown that we can use similar method to analyze the model in that case. But there will be additional computational burden. We allow X p J i to vary across agents. As a result, there are two types of heterogeneity in expected outcomes, E[y j,g X p J i, Z] s. On one hand, since agent j and j may be different in terms of personal characteristics, i.e., X j X j, their expected outcome may differ in i s eyes. That is, in general, E[y j X p J i, Z] E[y j X p J i, Z], for i j, i j, and j j. On the other, because two agents may have different private information, their expectation on the behavior of the same third person might differ. Namely, E[y j X p J i, Z] E[y j X p J k, Z] when J i J k in general. Those two types of heterogeneity distinguishes the current model from previous research. For instance, in the classical model about social interactions by Manski (1993)[14], expectations are taken on the average behavior of the whole group based on commonly known group features. So in that model, everyone has the same expectation on group mean. There is no heterogeneity in expected outcomes in a group. In the discrete choice model by Brock and Durlauf [5], agents make predictions on others choices. However, due to symmetry among agents, after imposing rational expectation assumption, every agent has the same expectation on any other agent s choice in her group. Their work is extended by Lee, Li and Lin [13], who introduce asymmetry in personal characteristics and allow expectation on choices of different agents to differ. However, with rational expectation, any two agents have the same expectation on the choice of a third agent. That is, there is the first type of heterogeneity in expectation, but not the second type. Therefore, our model extends existing research in social interactions with incomplete information by incorporating two types of heterogeneity in conditional expectations about group members behaviors. In the discussion below, we will see this extension largely changes solution of equilibrium. Moreover, it makes it possible to analyze social interactions under various information structures. We suppose that all the exogenous characteristics, X g, Xi c s, Xp i s, W and J are observed by econometricians. Therefore, any variables, except idiosyncratic risks, used by agents to make predictions are known to econometricians. That assumption is reasonable in many cases. That is because econometricians are capable of gathering much information about members of the whole group by survey. Of course, there can be some variables known to agents in a group but are not reflected by data set. One case in point is quality of services, which is hard to measure objectively. So we relax that assumption in Section 6, where unobserved group random effects are added to the model. The intensity of social interaction effects is denoted by the parameter, λ. It is assumed to be homogeneous across all the agents. If λ > 0, the social interaction effect is positive. If λ < 0, outcomes are negatively related. The case of λ = 0 represents absence of social interactions. 8

9 2.2 Models and Information Structures Simple as it is, the model, (2.1) and (2.2), provides with a framework broad enough to incorporate many interesting cases. First, by specifying the dependence of observed outcomes on latent variable, we consider several specific models important in empirical studies. 1. (Linear Model) h i (z) = h(z) = z for any z R. That is, the latent variable can be perfectly observed. y i = y i. (2.7) 2. (Binary Choice) h i ( ) = h( ) for any i. h( ) can take only two values, 0 and 1. Namely, observed outcome is a binary variable, whose value depends on sign of the latent variable. y i = I(y i > 0). (2.8) 3. (Ordered Multinomial Choice) More generally, observed outcome can take a finite number of integer values. Suppose that h i ( ) = h( ) for any i, which is a step function. Let S be a finite integer, y i {0, 1,, S}. S+1 y i = I(c s 1 < yi c s )(s 1), (2.9) s=1 where c s for s = 1,, S are S cutoff points and c 0 =, c S+1 = (Tobit Model) The latent variable is right-censored. The cutoff value of the censoring rule is homogeneous and normalized to be equal to 0. That is, yi is observed if and only if yi > 0. In this case, h i( ) = h( ) and h( ) is piecewisely linear with a kink of 0. y i = I(yi > 0)yi. (2.10) 5. (Two-sided Censored Data) The latent variable is double-sided censored. The two cutoff points of the censoring rule are the same for all the agents. y i = I(y i < c 1 )c 1 + I(c 1 y i < c 2 )y i + I(y i c 2 )c 2. (2.11) Specifications on X p J i s reflect information structures. Some examples are cited below. They will be elaborated later. 1. (Publicly Known Characteristics) All exogenous group and individual characteristics, social relations and information structure is publicly known. In that case, X p J i include all X p j s. X p J i = (X p 1,, Xp n ). (2.12) 9

10 2. (Self-Known Characteristics) X p i is observed by i but not by any other group members. That is, X p J i = X p i. (2.13) 3. (Socially-Known Characteristics) i knows X p j if i is associated with j, i.e., W i,j Game Theoretical Explanation X p J i = (X p j ) j:1 j n,j=i, or W i,j 0. (2.14) It can be shown that the model, (2.1) and (2.2), can be related to a simultaneous move game with incomplete information. There are n agents in a group. The association among agents in the group is represented by the matrix, W, as before. Agents in the same group are making decisions at the same time. As a result, when i is making her decision, she does not know which actions other group members will take. Hence, she will make predictions on them. Assume that there is incomplete information and different agents may have different private information. Suppose that i makes predictions on the basis of public information Z and private information X p J i. Let s focus on two important cases, continuous choice and binary choice. 1. (Continuous Choice) Denote the action taken by i as y i. Let X p J i be any feasible action in i s set of actions. The payoff i gets when other agents take actions, y i is as follows: r(x p J i, y i ) = s(x i ) + (u(x i ) ɛ i )a i + λ j i W i,j y j a i 1 2 a2 i. Therefore, her expected payoff is E[r(X p J i, y i ) X p J i, Z] = s(x i ) + (u(x i ) ɛ i )a i + λ j i W i,j E[y j X p J i, Z]a i 1 2 a2 i. This is a quadratic function of X p J i. It is easy to derive the optimal strategy, y i = u(x i ) + λ j i W i,j E[y j X p J i, Z] ɛ i. Observed outcomes are realizations of optimal strategies. y i = yi. Therefore, we derive the following relationships of optimal strategies(also for observed outcomes): y i = u(x i ) + λ j i W i,j E[y j X p J i, Z] ɛ i. (2.15) for all i. When agents are rational, they will perceive that their rivals choose optimal strategies in the same way. Hence, Equation (2.15) defines a Bayesian Nash Equilibrium. 10

11 2. (Binary Choice) Consider the case that agent i s action, y i can only take two values, 0 and 1. The payoff associated with action 0 is normalized to be equal to 0. The payoff associated with y i = 1 is t i = u(x i ) + λ j i W i,j y j ɛ i. Thus, her expected payoff when taking action 1 is y i = u(x i ) + λ j i W i,j E[y j X p J i, Z] ɛ i. Therefore, i s optimal strategy is y i = 1 if and only if u(x i ) + λ j i W i,j E[y j X p J i, Z] > ɛ i ; and y i = 0 otherwise. Therefore, the following equation system, y i = I(u(X i ) + λ j i W i,j E[y j X p J i, Z] ɛ i > 0), (2.16) defines a BNE of the model when rational agents expect their rivals to choose strategies in the above way and take best response accordingly. From the above two examples, we can see that our model, (2.1) and (2.2), is consistent with a simultaneous move game under incomplete information where a (reduced-form) BNE {y i,g } is characterized by the following equation system: y i = h i (u(x i ) + λ j i W i,j E[y j X p J i, Z] ɛ i ). (2.17) Observed outcomes are just realizations of an equilibrium, y i. 3 3 Equilibrium Analysis 3.1 Equilibrium and Expectations Given that observed outcomes are realizations of an equilibrium satisfying Equation { (2.17), } we need to solve equilibrium strategies via solving the expectation terms, E[y j X p J i, Z]. Pick any i and k such that i k. By consistency, we get that E[y i X p J k, Z] = E[h i (u(x i ) + λ j i W i,j E[y j X p J i, Z] ɛ i ) X p J k, Z]. (3.1) 3 A strategy is a decision rule. It is a function of exogenous variables and idiosyncratic shocks. So it is a random variable. Observed action (or, outcome) is its realization, hence, a scalar. To simplify notation, however, I use y i to denote both a strategy and its realization. 11

12 As we defined in last section, Z is a vector representing public information, representing publicly known group and individual features, social relations, and information structures. X p J i is a vector representing private information, composed of a part of privately known personal characteristics observed by i. According to our assumption, k only knows which type of information is in X p J i. She does not know the realizations of those random variables. From her eye, X p J i, which contains privately known characteristics, is a random vector; and E[y j X p J i, Z] is a random variable. As a result, she has to integrate over all possible realizations of X p J i conditioning on realizations of her own information, X p J k, Z. Conditional on public information in the group, Z, her expectation about i s behavior might change when she knows X p s of a different subgroup of agents, i.e., the random variables in X p J k differ. Therefore, given public information, Z, conditional expectation, E[y i X p J k, Z], is a function of random vector, X p J i. Conditional expectations for behaviors of all group members, (E[y 1, Z],, E[y n, Z]), is a vector of such types of functions. That distinguishes our model from previous research by Manski [14], Brock and Durlauf [5], and Lee, Li and Lin [13]. Manski [14] and Brock and Durlauf [5] solve just one expectation, expected group average behaviors or expected behavior of symmetric group members, as a scalar. Lee, Li and Lin [13] assume rational expectation. So expectation formed by an individual agent is the same as expectation formed by econometricians. For each j, they only need to solve E[y j ] as a scalar, given all observable characteristics of members in the group and group features. When j runs over all group members, they solve expected behaviors in a group as a vector. Nonetheless, adopting BNE, with heterogeneity in private information, we have to know how expectation of y j vary with private information used to make predictions. Since an agent only predicts the behaviors of agents with whom she is associated, for each i, we only need to define conditional expectation on random vectors known to associated agents. Conditional on Z = z, let (Ω, F, P ) denote the probability space on which the random variables, X p j s are defined. For each i, for any j such that W j,i 0, by (2.3), the type of private information of k is described by J j. X p J j is a random vector composed of some X p k s. Therefore, when the dimension of each Xp k is k p, X p J j is a measurable function from (Ω, F) to (R M j, B M j R ), where M j = ( n j=1 J k(j))k p is the dimension of the vector X p J j, B M j R is the Borel set. Then for each J j, we define a measurable function, ψi,j e j, from (R M j, B M j R ) to (R, B R) such that ψ e i,j j (x) = E[y i X p J j = x, z], (3.2) for any x R M k. Then the composite, ψ e i,j j (X p J j ) : (Ω, F, P ) (R, B R, m R ) is a random variable with ψ e i,j j (X p J j ) = E[y i X p J j, z]. (3.3) Therefore, given J j, the random vector used to make predictions is fixed. Then the function ψ i,jj shows how conditional expectation on y i varies with realization of that vector. So 12

13 we can characterize how conditional expectation changes with the random vector on which expectation is based by defining a function on random vector. Let s begin with the domain. { } A i = X p J j : W j,i 0. (3.4) for any 1 i n. For A i A i, there is j, such that W j,i 0 and A i = X p J j. Denote the set of all random variables on (Ω, F, P ) by C, define ψ e : n i=1 A i C n, such that for any A = (A 1,, A n ) n i=1 A i, ψ e (A) i = ψ e i (A i ) = ψ e i,j j (X p J j ) = E[y i X p J j, Z = z], (3.5) where A i = X p J j for some j = 1,, n. For simplicity, we will write E[y i X p J j, z] instead of E[y i X p J j, Z = z] in the discussions below. We now investigate the relationship between a BNE and expectation functions. Proposition 3.1 Conditional on public information Z = z, if a profile of strategies, n y = (y 1,, y n ) : A i R n, is a BNE in the model, i.e., they satisfy (2.17), the vector function, ψ e : n i=1 A i C n, defined by (3.5), for any i = 1, 2,, n, and A = (A 1,, A n ) n i=1 A i, satisfies the consistency condition: ψ e (A) i = ψ e i (A i ) i=1 = E[h i (u(x i ) + λ j i W i,j ψ e j (X p J i ) ɛ i ) A i ], (3.6) for any i. On the reverse, if ψ e : n i=1 A i C n satisfies ψ e (A) i = ψ e i (A i ), (3.7) for any i = 1, 2,, n, and A = (A 1,, A n ) n i=1 A i, and condition (3.6), (3.5) holds. Moreover, the strategy profile, (y 1,, y n ), defined by y i = h i (u(x i ) + λ j i W i,j ψ e j (X p J i ) ɛ i ) (3.8) is a BNE, i.e., it satisfied (2.17). Proof. The first part follows straightforwardly from the definition of ψ e and consistency condition of expectations in equilibrium, (3.1). For the second part, from (3.8), we have that E[y i A i, z] =E[h i (u(x i ) + λ j i W i,j ψ e j (X p J i ) ɛ i ) A i, z] =ψ(a) i, 13

14 for any i = 1, 2,, n, and A i A i. Therefore, we have that y i = h i (u(x i ) + λ j i W i,j E[y j X p J i, z] ɛ i ). The second part is proved. Hence, there is a one-to-one correspondence between a Bayesian Nash Equilibrium and expectation function satisfying (3.6). We can analyze equilibrium via analyzing the functional equation, (3.6). 3.2 Existence and Uniqueness From above discussion, we can see that there is a BNE in our model if and only if there is a expectation function, ψg e : n g i=1 B i,g C n, satisfying (3.7) and (3.6). We investigate possible existence and uniqueness of such a function by functional analysis. First, impose the following assumptions on model primitives. Assumption 3.1 f ɛ (ɛ) > 0 for all < ɛ <. That is, the support for all the ɛ i s is R. Assumption 3.2 Both h i ( ) for each i = 1,, n and u( ) are continuous. Assumption 3.3 For any real number x, E[ h i (x ɛ) ] <. Furthermore, H i (x) = E[h i (x ɛ)] is differentiable with respect to x. Assumption 3.4 The derivative of H i ( ) is uniformly bounded. That is, max 1 i n dh i(x) dx <. Let Ψ be a set of functions, fixing Z = z, any ψ Ψ is a function mapping a profile of sets A = (A 1,, A n ) n i=1 A i to a random vector in C n, such that (3.7) holds for any i and A. For each i and A i A i, there is a j such that W j,i 0 and A i = X p J j. Suppose that conditional on Z = z, the joint distribution of X p = (X p 1,, Xp n) is F p ( Z = z) 4, which is denoted as F p for simplicity. Functions of Ψ satisfy the following integrability condition: max max ψ i (X p J j ) df p (X p ) <, (3.9) 1 i n {j:w j,i 0} where X p J i is a random vector composed of X p j s. That is, ψ is integrable with respect to the distribution of private personal characteristics, conditional on public information in the group, Z = z. From discussions above, we can see that conditional expectation in 4 We allow correlation between publicly information, Z, and privately known characteristics, (X p 1,, Xp n). When they are independent, conditional distribution will be the same as unconditional distribution. 14

15 equilibrium, ψ e, is a mapping from n i=1 A i to C n and satisfies (3.7). We assume that it meets the requirement, 3.9. So ψ e Ψ. 5 Define sum and scalar product operation of functions in Ψ in the conventional way. That is, for any ψ, ψ Ψ, α R 1, and (A 1,, A n ) n i=1 A i, (ψ + ψ )(A 1,, A n ) = ψ(a 1,, A n ) + ψ (A 1,, A n ); (αψ)(a 1,, A n ) = αψ(a 1,, A n ). Zero is a function which is equal to 0 almost everywhere with respect to F p ( ). It is easy to see that under the above definition, Ψ is a linear space. In addition, define ψ = max max (ψ) i (X p J j ) df p (X p ), (3.10) 1 i n {j:w j,i 0} which is shown to be a norm is the following lemma. Lemma 3.1 is a well-defined norm on Ψ. Proof. By the definition of Ψ, for any ψ Ψ, ψ is non-negative. Moreover, ψ = 0 if and only if ψ i (A i ) = 0 a.e. for any i and A i A i, i.e., ψ = 0. For any real number α, αψ = max max (αψ) i (A i ) df p (X p ) 1 i n {j:w j,i 0} = α max max ψ i (A i ) df p (X p ) 1 i n {j:w j,i 0} = α ψ. Additionally, for any ψ, ψ Ψ, ψ + ψ = max max (ψ + ψ ) i (A i ) df p (X p ) 1 i n {j:w j,i 0} max max ψ i (A i ) df p (X p ) + max 1 i n {j:w j,i 0} = ψ + ψ. max 1 i n {j:w j,i 0} psi i(a i ) df p (X p ) By Lemma 3.1, (Ψ, ) is a linear normed space. In addition, it is complete as the following lemma shows. 5 We use ψ e to represent exclusively equilibrium conditional expectation. ψ is used to denote any arbitrarily chosen point in the function space Ψ. 15

16 Lemma 3.2 The linear normed space (Ψ, ) is complete. Hence, it is a Banach space. Proof. Suppose {ψ m } is a Cauchy sequence in Ψ. m 1 m 2, such that (ψ mk+1 ) i (A i ) (ψ mk ) i (A i ) df p (X p ) ψmk+1 ψ mk < 1 2 k, for any i and A i A i. For every k, define φ k such that and function φ such that (φ k ) i (A i ) = (ψ m1 ) i (A i ) + (φ) i (A i ) = (ψ m1 ) i (A i ) + k (ψ ml+1 ) i (A i ) (ψ ml ) i (A i ). l=1 (ψ ml+1 ) i (A i ) (ψ ml ) i (A i ). l=1 It is easy to see that {j:w j,i 0} φ k ψ m Because φ k φ, by monotonicity convergence, max max (φ) i (X p i J j ) df p (X p ) = max max lim i {j:w j,i 0} k ψ m (φ k ) i (X p J j ) df p (X p ) Therefore, φ < a.e.. So the series ψ m1 + k=1 (ψ m k+1 ψ mk ) converges a.e.. ψ = lim k ψ mk is well-defined and ψ φ. Therefore, ψ Ψ. By Fatou s Lemma, max max (ψ m ) i (X p i J {j:w j,i 0} j ) (ψ) i (X p J j ) df p (X p ) max max lim inf (ψ m ) i (X p i {j:w j,i 0} k J j ) (ψ mk ) i (X p J j ) df p (X p ) lim inf max max (ψ m ) i (X p k i J j ) (ψ mk ) i (X p J j ) df p (X p ). {j:w j,i 0} By definition of the Cauchy sequence, lim n ψ m ψ = 0. Define an operator, T, on Ψ, such that (T (ψ)) i (A 1,, A n ) =(T (ψ)) i (A i ) =E[H i (u(x i ) + λ j i W i,j ψ j (X p J i )) A i, z]. (3.11) 16

17 where H i (x) = h i (x ɛ)f ɛ (ɛ)dɛ. (3.12) We can see that if H i (u(x i ) + λ j i W i,jψ j (X p J i )) is integrable with respect to F p ( ), T (ψ) Ψ for any ψ Ψ. If ψ e Ψ, it is a fixed point of T. Additionally, if function ψ Ψ is a fixed point of T, it satisfies consistency condition. So it is an equilibrium conditional expectation function. That is to say, if we focus on functions in (Ψ, ), there is a one-to-one correspondence between equilibrium conditional expectation functions and fixed points of operator T. The proposition that follows shows that T can be a contraction mapping. Proposition 3.2 Under the condition that λ W D < 1, (3.13) where D = max i sup x dh i(x) dx is well-defined under assumption 3.4, T : (Ψ, ) (Ψ, ) is a contraction mapping. Therefore, by the Banach fixed point theorem, T has one and only one fixed point. Thus, there is one and only one BNE in the model. Proof. Pick any two functions, ψ, ψ (Ψ, ), T (ψ) T (ψ ) = max max E[(H i (u(x i ) + λ W i,j ψ j (X p J i )) j i 1 i n {k:w k,i 0} H i (u(x i ) + λ j i W i,j ψ j(x p J i ))) X p J k, Z = z] df p (X p ) max max 1 i n {k:w k,i 0} = max max 1 i n {k:w k,i 0} λ D W i,j j i = max max 1 i n {k:w k,i 0} λ D W i,j j i λ W D ψ ψ. E[D λ j i W i,j ψ j (X p J i ) ψ j(x p J i ) X p J k, z]df p (X p ) E[ ψ j (X p J i ) ψ j(x p J i ) X p J k, z]df p (X p ) ψ j (X p J i ) ψ j(x p J i ) df p (X p ) It is conventional to row-normalize W such that W = 1. As a result, how stringent the condition (3.13) will be depends on the upper bound of dh i(x) dx. We take some popular models as examples below, linear model, binary choice model and Tobit model. 17

18 1. (Linear Model) For the case of (2.7), H i (x) = (x ɛ)f ɛ (ɛ)dɛ = x E[ɛ]. Thus, sup x dh i(x) dx = (Binary Choice) For the case of (2.8), H i (x) = F ɛ (x). Thus, sup x dh i(x) dx = sup x f ɛ (x). In this case, the uniform boundedness of dh i(x) dx is due to boundedness of ɛ s density. In statistics, many density functions are bounded. Cases in point are the standard normal distribution where sup x f ɛ (x) 1 2π, and the logistic distribution where sup x f ɛ (x) (Tobit model) For the case, (2.10), H i (x) = xf ɛ (x) Thus, dh i (x) dx ɛ<x = F ɛ (x). ɛf ɛ (ɛ)dɛ. As a result, max i sup x dh i(x) dx = sup x F ɛ (x) 1. That is, the absolute value of the derivative of H i (x) is uniformly bounded by 1. 4 Equilibrium Solution and Calculation Proposition 3.2 is the key result for discussion of general model framework. It not only provides with a sufficient condition for equilibrium existence and uniqueness, but also suggests a numerical method to solve equilibrium. That is because the fixed point of a contraction mapping can be derived by recursive iteration beginning with an arbitrary initial guess. In this section, we choose three different information structures and illustrate how equilibrium can be solved in each case. We show that in some special cases, it is possible to solve equilibrium conditional expectations analytically. For all the analysis that follows, we assume that condition (3.13) is satisfied. So there is one and only one BNE. 18

19 4.1 Publicly Known Characteristics When all personal characteristics are publicly known, X p J i = (X p 1,, Xp n). An agent has the same expectation as that of econometricians, for any i and j, E[y i X p J j, z] = E[y i X p 1,, Xp n, z]. We can see that the equilibrium conditional expectation is a vector, ψ = (E[y 1 X p 1,, Xp n, z],, E[y n X p 1,, Xp n, z]). Hence, consistency condition for equilibrium expectation, (3.6), reduces to ψ e i = E[h i (u(x i ) + λ j i W i,j ψ e j ɛ i ) X p 1,, Xp n, z], (4.1) for any i. It can be solved by contraction mapping iteration. This is the case in Lee, Li and Lin [13]. In general, for the linear model, h i (x) = h(x) = x for any i 6, given that E[ɛ i ] = 0 for any i, we have that ψ e i = u(x i ) + λ j i W i,j ψ e i, (4.2) which corresponds to the spatial autoregressive model (SAR) in spatial econometrics. For linear model, with W row-normalized (i.e., sum of each row of W is 1), condition (3.13) reduces to λ < 1. We have the equilibrium: ψ e = ψ e 1. ψ e n 4.2 Self-known Characteristics u(x 1 ) = (I λw ) 1. u(x n ) In this case, X p i is known only to i. We have that X p J i = X p i and A i = { } X p j : W j,i 0.. (4.3) Since X p i,g s are the same type of characteristics of agents in the same group, it is natural to assume that they have the same support. Furthermore, we simplify discussion by imposing an exchangeable property on their joint distribution conditional on group public information, Z = z. Assumption 4.1 Conditional on public information, Z = z, X p i s have the same support, S p. Moreover, their conditional joint distribution, f p (X p 1,, Xp n; Z = z), is exchangeable 6 Note that in this part, we only require that h i( ) is the identity function. We do not impose linearity on u( ) here. 19

20 with respect to the identities of the agents. That is, for any permutation, s : {1,, n} {1,, n}, f p (X p 1,, Xp n, Z = z) = f p (X p s(1),, Xp s(n), Z = z). (4.4) Under Assumption 4.1, f(x p i Xp k = x, Z = z) = f(xp i Xp k and k i. When realizations X p k = Xp k = x, = x, Z = z), for any k i ψ e i,j k (x) =E[y i X p k = x, z] = H i (u(x g, Xi c, y) + λ W i,j ψj e (y))f p (y Xk P j i = = x, Z = z)dy H i (u(x g, Xi c, y) + λ W i,j ψj e (y))f p (y X P = x, Z = z)dy k j i (4.5) =E[y i X p k = x, z] =ψ e i,j k (x). where H i (x) = h(x ɛ)f ɛ (ɛ)dɛ. Thus, with Assumption 4.1, the identity of private characteristics used to make predictions does not matter. It is its realization that influences conditional expectation. Previously, we define conditional expectations in two steps. We first describe how conditional expectation varies with the random vector used to make predictions. We then characterize how conditional expectation changes with realization of a given random vector. Owing to the fact that conditional expectation is neutral to the identity of the random private characteristics, now we can directly define ψi e as a mapping from R kp (k p is the dimension of X p j s) to R1. To be specific, for any i, pick a k i, define ψ e i (x) = ψ e i,j k (x) = E[y i X p k = x, z] (4.6) By (4.5), ψ e i is well-defined. Then define ψe : R nkp R n by ψ e (x 1,, x n ) i = ψ e i (x i ), (4.7) similar to what we did in previous sections. Because this is a special case of the basic framework, our previous analysis about equilibrium existence and uniqueness applies here. In this case, consistency condition (3.6) reduces to ψi e (x) = H i (u(x g, Xi c, y) + λ W i,j ψj e (y))f p (y x)dy, (4.8) j i where f p (y x) is a simplified notation for the density of X p i conditional on X p j = x and Z = z. By exchangeability, f p (X p j = y Xp i = x, z) = f p(x p k = y Xp i = x, z), 20

21 for any j i and j i. So this simplification is reasonable. We investigate condition (4.8) in three different cases that follow Independent Characteristics Given Z = z, if the characteristics X p j s are independent of each other, conditional distribution f p (y x) = f p (X p k = y Xp i = x, z) is the same as f p (y) = f p (X p k = y z). So we have that ψi e (x) = H i (u(x g, Xi c, y) + λ W i,j ψj e (y))f p (y)dy. j i So ψi e(x) is a constant function of x, whose value can be denoted as ψe i. Specifically, it satisfies the following equations: ψi e = H i (u(x g, Xi c, y) + λ W i,j ψj e )f p (y)dy. (4.9) j i for i = 1,, n. The vector, ψ e = (ψ1 e,, ψe n) can be solved by contraction mapping iteration as in Lee, Li and Lin[13]. For the linear model, (4.9) is a linear equation system and we can derive an analytical solution: ψ e 1 E[u(X g, X1 c ψ e =. = (I λw ) 1, y)].. (4.10) E[u(X g, Xn, c y)] ψ e n Compared with (4.3), instead of true realizations, expectation is used in (4.10). This is because X p i is not observed by any agent other than i in the group Correlated Discrete Characteristics In general, X p i s may be correlated with each other among group members7. In this subsection, we focus on the case that X p i has a finite support. As a result, any expectation, ψi e ( ), is a function defined on a finite set. To solve it is to obtain its value at every point in that finite set. Thus, for each i, we can view ψi e ( ) as a vector. Suppose that the support of X p i is { x l : 1 l m }, where x l is a vector with specific values and m is the number of support points of X p i for all i = 1,, n. Under exchangeability, conditional distribution is fully captured by the matrix, p 11 p 12 p 1m P =......, p m1 p m2 p mm 7 This is possible, for example, even conditional on observed group variables, there might still be unobserved group variables which may influence members in a group equally (so exchangeable), and those unobserved group variables are random across different groups. The notion of exchangeability has been characterized in this way by De Finetti (1975). 21

22 where p ll = prob(x p i = x l X p k = xl ), for k i, which is invariant with respect to k by xchangeability. Using P, we have that ψ e i (x l ) = m l =1 p ll H i (u(x g, X c i, x l ) + λ j i W ij,g ψ e j (x l )). (4.11) Stacking all possible values of those conditional expectations in a vector as ψ e = (ψ e 1(x 1 ),, ψ e n(x 1 ),, ψ e 1(x m ),, ψ e n(x m )), we may solve it by contraction mapping iteration. In particular, for the linear model, the equilibrium conditional expectation, ψ e, which is an nm 1 vector, is characterized by ψ e i (x l ) = m l =1 p ll (u(x g, X c i, x l ) + λ j i and can be solved analytically. To be specific, define W i,j ψ e j (x l )), (4.12) u = (u(x g, X c 1, x 1 ),, u(x g, X c n, x 1 ),, u(x g, X c 1, x m ),, u(x g, X c n, x m )). Then equilibrium condition can be written as ψ e = (P I n )u + λ(p W )ψ, where I n is the n n-dimension identity matrix. As P W P W = W, under (3.13), λ(p W ) < 1. So I λ(p W ) is invertible. Thus, we have that Correlated Continuous Characteristics ψ e = (I λ(p W )) 1 (P I n )u. (4.13) Now we consider the case where X p i s have a continuous pdf conditional on Z = z. Since the support is no longer finite, solution of model equilibrium is more complicated. However, there is still a analytical solution for linear model when conditional on X p j and Z, expectation of X p i is linear in X p j. To be specific, we impose the following assumptions. Assumption 4.2 h i (x) = x for any z and i. Namely, the model is linear. Assumption 4.3 E[ɛ i ] = 0 for any i. 22

Econometric Analysis of Games 1

Econometric Analysis of Games 1 Econometric Analysis of Games 1 HT 2017 Recap Aim: provide an introduction to incomplete models and partial identification in the context of discrete games 1. Coherence & Completeness 2. Basic Framework

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago December 2015 Abstract Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970) represent random

More information

SEQUENTIAL ESTIMATION OF DYNAMIC DISCRETE GAMES. Victor Aguirregabiria (Boston University) and. Pedro Mira (CEMFI) Applied Micro Workshop at Minnesota

SEQUENTIAL ESTIMATION OF DYNAMIC DISCRETE GAMES. Victor Aguirregabiria (Boston University) and. Pedro Mira (CEMFI) Applied Micro Workshop at Minnesota SEQUENTIAL ESTIMATION OF DYNAMIC DISCRETE GAMES Victor Aguirregabiria (Boston University) and Pedro Mira (CEMFI) Applied Micro Workshop at Minnesota February 16, 2006 CONTEXT AND MOTIVATION Many interesting

More information

Preliminary Results on Social Learning with Partial Observations

Preliminary Results on Social Learning with Partial Observations Preliminary Results on Social Learning with Partial Observations Ilan Lobel, Daron Acemoglu, Munther Dahleh and Asuman Ozdaglar ABSTRACT We study a model of social learning with partial observations from

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago January 2016 Consider a situation where one person, call him Sender,

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago September 2015 Abstract Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970) introduce a

More information

d(x n, x) d(x n, x nk ) + d(x nk, x) where we chose any fixed k > N

d(x n, x) d(x n, x nk ) + d(x nk, x) where we chose any fixed k > N Problem 1. Let f : A R R have the property that for every x A, there exists ɛ > 0 such that f(t) > ɛ if t (x ɛ, x + ɛ) A. If the set A is compact, prove there exists c > 0 such that f(x) > c for all x

More information

ECONOMETRICS II (ECO 2401S) University of Toronto. Department of Economics. Winter 2014 Instructor: Victor Aguirregabiria

ECONOMETRICS II (ECO 2401S) University of Toronto. Department of Economics. Winter 2014 Instructor: Victor Aguirregabiria ECONOMETRICS II (ECO 2401S) University of Toronto. Department of Economics. Winter 2014 Instructor: Victor guirregabiria SOLUTION TO FINL EXM Monday, pril 14, 2014. From 9:00am-12:00pm (3 hours) INSTRUCTIONS:

More information

Hypothesis Registration: Structural Predictions for the 2013 World Schools Debating Championships

Hypothesis Registration: Structural Predictions for the 2013 World Schools Debating Championships Hypothesis Registration: Structural Predictions for the 2013 World Schools Debating Championships Tom Gole * and Simon Quinn January 26, 2013 Abstract This document registers testable predictions about

More information

Bayesian Learning in Social Networks

Bayesian Learning in Social Networks Bayesian Learning in Social Networks Asu Ozdaglar Joint work with Daron Acemoglu, Munther Dahleh, Ilan Lobel Department of Electrical Engineering and Computer Science, Department of Economics, Operations

More information

Contracts under Asymmetric Information

Contracts under Asymmetric Information Contracts under Asymmetric Information 1 I Aristotle, economy (oiko and nemo) and the idea of exchange values, subsequently adapted by Ricardo and Marx. Classical economists. An economy consists of a set

More information

Robust Predictions in Games with Incomplete Information

Robust Predictions in Games with Incomplete Information Robust Predictions in Games with Incomplete Information joint with Stephen Morris (Princeton University) November 2010 Payoff Environment in games with incomplete information, the agents are uncertain

More information

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer Social learning and bargaining (axiomatic approach)

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer Social learning and bargaining (axiomatic approach) UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2015 Social learning and bargaining (axiomatic approach) Block 4 Jul 31 and Aug 1, 2015 Auction results Herd behavior and

More information

Lecture 11. Probability Theory: an Overveiw

Lecture 11. Probability Theory: an Overveiw Math 408 - Mathematical Statistics Lecture 11. Probability Theory: an Overveiw February 11, 2013 Konstantin Zuev (USC) Math 408, Lecture 11 February 11, 2013 1 / 24 The starting point in developing the

More information

Estimating Dynamic Programming Models

Estimating Dynamic Programming Models Estimating Dynamic Programming Models Katsumi Shimotsu 1 Ken Yamada 2 1 Department of Economics Hitotsubashi University 2 School of Economics Singapore Management University Katsumi Shimotsu, Ken Yamada

More information

Monotonic ɛ-equilibria in strongly symmetric games

Monotonic ɛ-equilibria in strongly symmetric games Monotonic ɛ-equilibria in strongly symmetric games Shiran Rachmilevitch April 22, 2016 Abstract ɛ-equilibrium allows for worse actions to be played with higher probability than better actions. I introduce

More information

ECE353: Probability and Random Processes. Lecture 7 -Continuous Random Variable

ECE353: Probability and Random Processes. Lecture 7 -Continuous Random Variable ECE353: Probability and Random Processes Lecture 7 -Continuous Random Variable Xiao Fu School of Electrical Engineering and Computer Science Oregon State University E-mail: xiao.fu@oregonstate.edu Continuous

More information

Syllabus. By Joan Llull. Microeconometrics. IDEA PhD Program. Fall Chapter 1: Introduction and a Brief Review of Relevant Tools

Syllabus. By Joan Llull. Microeconometrics. IDEA PhD Program. Fall Chapter 1: Introduction and a Brief Review of Relevant Tools Syllabus By Joan Llull Microeconometrics. IDEA PhD Program. Fall 2017 Chapter 1: Introduction and a Brief Review of Relevant Tools I. Overview II. Maximum Likelihood A. The Likelihood Principle B. The

More information

On the iterated estimation of dynamic discrete choice games

On the iterated estimation of dynamic discrete choice games On the iterated estimation of dynamic discrete choice games Federico A. Bugni Jackson Bunting The Institute for Fiscal Studies Department of Economics, UCL cemmap working paper CWP13/18 On the iterated

More information

Estimating Single-Agent Dynamic Models

Estimating Single-Agent Dynamic Models Estimating Single-Agent Dynamic Models Paul T. Scott New York University Empirical IO Course Fall 2016 1 / 34 Introduction Why dynamic estimation? External validity Famous example: Hendel and Nevo s (2006)

More information

0.1 Uniform integrability

0.1 Uniform integrability Copyright c 2009 by Karl Sigman 0.1 Uniform integrability Given a sequence of rvs {X n } for which it is known apriori that X n X, n, wp1. for some r.v. X, it is of great importance in many applications

More information

Gibbs Sampling in Latent Variable Models #1

Gibbs Sampling in Latent Variable Models #1 Gibbs Sampling in Latent Variable Models #1 Econ 690 Purdue University Outline 1 Data augmentation 2 Probit Model Probit Application A Panel Probit Panel Probit 3 The Tobit Model Example: Female Labor

More information

Estimation of Large Network Formation Games

Estimation of Large Network Formation Games Estimation of Large Network Formation Games Geert Ridder Shuyang Sheng Preliminary and Incomplete Abstract This paper provides estimation methods for network formation models using observed data of a single

More information

Estimation of Large Network Formation Games

Estimation of Large Network Formation Games Estimation of Large Network Formation Games Geert Ridder Shuyang Sheng February 8, 207 Preliminary Abstract This paper develops estimation methods for network formation using observed data from a single

More information

Voluntary Leadership in Teams and the Leadership Paradox

Voluntary Leadership in Teams and the Leadership Paradox Voluntary Leadership in Teams and the Leadership Paradox Susanne Mayer 1 and Christian Hilbe 2 1 Institute for Social Policy, Department Socioeconomics, Vienna University of Economics and Business, Nordbergstraße

More information

Lecture notes: Rust (1987) Economics : M. Shum 1

Lecture notes: Rust (1987) Economics : M. Shum 1 Economics 180.672: M. Shum 1 Estimate the parameters of a dynamic optimization problem: when to replace engine of a bus? This is a another practical example of an optimal stopping problem, which is easily

More information

Estimating Semi-parametric Panel Multinomial Choice Models

Estimating Semi-parametric Panel Multinomial Choice Models Estimating Semi-parametric Panel Multinomial Choice Models Xiaoxia Shi, Matthew Shum, Wei Song UW-Madison, Caltech, UW-Madison September 15, 2016 1 / 31 Introduction We consider the panel multinomial choice

More information

Notes on Random Vectors and Multivariate Normal

Notes on Random Vectors and Multivariate Normal MATH 590 Spring 06 Notes on Random Vectors and Multivariate Normal Properties of Random Vectors If X,, X n are random variables, then X = X,, X n ) is a random vector, with the cumulative distribution

More information

Functional Analysis, Math 7320 Lecture Notes from August taken by Yaofeng Su

Functional Analysis, Math 7320 Lecture Notes from August taken by Yaofeng Su Functional Analysis, Math 7320 Lecture Notes from August 30 2016 taken by Yaofeng Su 1 Essentials of Topology 1.1 Continuity Next we recall a stronger notion of continuity: 1.1.1 Definition. Let (X, d

More information

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Ozan Candogan, Asuman Ozdaglar and Pablo A. Parrilo September 6, 2011 Abstract Potential games are a special class of games for which many adaptive user dynamics

More information

MLE for a logit model

MLE for a logit model IGIDR, Bombay September 4, 2008 Goals The link between workforce participation and education Analysing a two-variable data-set: bivariate distributions Conditional probability Expected mean from conditional

More information

Online Appendices for Large Matching Markets: Risk, Unraveling, and Conflation

Online Appendices for Large Matching Markets: Risk, Unraveling, and Conflation Online Appendices for Large Matching Markets: Risk, Unraveling, and Conflation Aaron L. Bodoh-Creed - Cornell University A Online Appendix: Strategic Convergence In section 4 we described the matching

More information

An empirical model of firm entry with endogenous product-type choices

An empirical model of firm entry with endogenous product-type choices and An empirical model of firm entry with endogenous product-type choices, RAND Journal of Economics 31 Jan 2013 Introduction and Before : entry model, identical products In this paper : entry with simultaneous

More information

Weak Stochastic Increasingness, Rank Exchangeability, and Partial Identification of The Distribution of Treatment Effects

Weak Stochastic Increasingness, Rank Exchangeability, and Partial Identification of The Distribution of Treatment Effects Weak Stochastic Increasingness, Rank Exchangeability, and Partial Identification of The Distribution of Treatment Effects Brigham R. Frandsen Lars J. Lefgren December 16, 2015 Abstract This article develops

More information

Recap from previous lecture

Recap from previous lecture Recap from previous lecture Learning is using past experience to improve future performance. Different types of learning: supervised unsupervised reinforcement active online... For a machine, experience

More information

Area I: Contract Theory Question (Econ 206)

Area I: Contract Theory Question (Econ 206) Theory Field Exam Summer 2011 Instructions You must complete two of the four areas (the areas being (I) contract theory, (II) game theory A, (III) game theory B, and (IV) psychology & economics). Be sure

More information

Lecture Notes 1 Probability and Random Variables. Conditional Probability and Independence. Functions of a Random Variable

Lecture Notes 1 Probability and Random Variables. Conditional Probability and Independence. Functions of a Random Variable Lecture Notes 1 Probability and Random Variables Probability Spaces Conditional Probability and Independence Random Variables Functions of a Random Variable Generation of a Random Variable Jointly Distributed

More information

Payoff Continuity in Incomplete Information Games

Payoff Continuity in Incomplete Information Games journal of economic theory 82, 267276 (1998) article no. ET982418 Payoff Continuity in Incomplete Information Games Atsushi Kajii* Institute of Policy and Planning Sciences, University of Tsukuba, 1-1-1

More information

1 Probability theory. 2 Random variables and probability theory.

1 Probability theory. 2 Random variables and probability theory. Probability theory Here we summarize some of the probability theory we need. If this is totally unfamiliar to you, you should look at one of the sources given in the readings. In essence, for the major

More information

Stability of optimization problems with stochastic dominance constraints

Stability of optimization problems with stochastic dominance constraints Stability of optimization problems with stochastic dominance constraints D. Dentcheva and W. Römisch Stevens Institute of Technology, Hoboken Humboldt-University Berlin www.math.hu-berlin.de/~romisch SIAM

More information

GMM Estimation of the Spatial Autoregressive Model in a System of Interrelated Networks

GMM Estimation of the Spatial Autoregressive Model in a System of Interrelated Networks GMM Estimation of the Spatial Autoregressive Model in a System of Interrelated etworks Yan Bao May, 2010 1 Introduction In this paper, I extend the generalized method of moments framework based on linear

More information

Fixed Point Theorems

Fixed Point Theorems Fixed Point Theorems Definition: Let X be a set and let f : X X be a function that maps X into itself. (Such a function is often called an operator, a transformation, or a transform on X, and the notation

More information

Overfitting, Bias / Variance Analysis

Overfitting, Bias / Variance Analysis Overfitting, Bias / Variance Analysis Professor Ameet Talwalkar Professor Ameet Talwalkar CS260 Machine Learning Algorithms February 8, 207 / 40 Outline Administration 2 Review of last lecture 3 Basic

More information

Computing Equilibria by Incorporating Qualitative Models 1

Computing Equilibria by Incorporating Qualitative Models 1 Computing Equilibria by Incorporating Qualitative Models 1 Sam Ganzfried March 3, 2010 CMU-CS-10-105 Tuomas Sandholm School of Computer Science Carnegie Mellon University Pittsburgh, PA 15213 1 This material

More information

Cross-Asset Speculation in Stock Markets

Cross-Asset Speculation in Stock Markets Cross-Asset Speculation in Stock Markets DA BERHARDT and BART TAUB Abstract In practice, heterogeneously-informed speculators combine private information about multiple stocks with information in prices,

More information

Consistency and Asymptotic Normality for Equilibrium Models with Partially Observed Outcome Variables

Consistency and Asymptotic Normality for Equilibrium Models with Partially Observed Outcome Variables Consistency and Asymptotic Normality for Equilibrium Models with Partially Observed Outcome Variables Nathan H. Miller Georgetown University Matthew Osborne University of Toronto November 25, 2013 Abstract

More information

Ergodicity and Non-Ergodicity in Economics

Ergodicity and Non-Ergodicity in Economics Abstract An stochastic system is called ergodic if it tends in probability to a limiting form that is independent of the initial conditions. Breakdown of ergodicity gives rise to path dependence. We illustrate

More information

Order Statistics and Distributions

Order Statistics and Distributions Order Statistics and Distributions 1 Some Preliminary Comments and Ideas In this section we consider a random sample X 1, X 2,..., X n common continuous distribution function F and probability density

More information

Probability and Measure

Probability and Measure Chapter 4 Probability and Measure 4.1 Introduction In this chapter we will examine probability theory from the measure theoretic perspective. The realisation that measure theory is the foundation of probability

More information

2 (Statistics) Random variables

2 (Statistics) Random variables 2 (Statistics) Random variables References: DeGroot and Schervish, chapters 3, 4 and 5; Stirzaker, chapters 4, 5 and 6 We will now study the main tools use for modeling experiments with unknown outcomes

More information

Rate of Convergence of Learning in Social Networks

Rate of Convergence of Learning in Social Networks Rate of Convergence of Learning in Social Networks Ilan Lobel, Daron Acemoglu, Munther Dahleh and Asuman Ozdaglar Massachusetts Institute of Technology Cambridge, MA Abstract We study the rate of convergence

More information

Lecture Notes 1 Probability and Random Variables. Conditional Probability and Independence. Functions of a Random Variable

Lecture Notes 1 Probability and Random Variables. Conditional Probability and Independence. Functions of a Random Variable Lecture Notes 1 Probability and Random Variables Probability Spaces Conditional Probability and Independence Random Variables Functions of a Random Variable Generation of a Random Variable Jointly Distributed

More information

Mechanism Design: Basic Concepts

Mechanism Design: Basic Concepts Advanced Microeconomic Theory: Economics 521b Spring 2011 Juuso Välimäki Mechanism Design: Basic Concepts The setup is similar to that of a Bayesian game. The ingredients are: 1. Set of players, i {1,

More information

Identi cation of Positive Treatment E ects in. Randomized Experiments with Non-Compliance

Identi cation of Positive Treatment E ects in. Randomized Experiments with Non-Compliance Identi cation of Positive Treatment E ects in Randomized Experiments with Non-Compliance Aleksey Tetenov y February 18, 2012 Abstract I derive sharp nonparametric lower bounds on some parameters of the

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

Probability and Measure

Probability and Measure Part II Year 2018 2017 2016 2015 2014 2013 2012 2011 2010 2009 2008 2007 2006 2005 2018 84 Paper 4, Section II 26J Let (X, A) be a measurable space. Let T : X X be a measurable map, and µ a probability

More information

Microeconomic Theory (501b) Problem Set 10. Auctions and Moral Hazard Suggested Solution: Tibor Heumann

Microeconomic Theory (501b) Problem Set 10. Auctions and Moral Hazard Suggested Solution: Tibor Heumann Dirk Bergemann Department of Economics Yale University Microeconomic Theory (50b) Problem Set 0. Auctions and Moral Hazard Suggested Solution: Tibor Heumann 4/5/4 This problem set is due on Tuesday, 4//4..

More information

Competition relative to Incentive Functions in Common Agency

Competition relative to Incentive Functions in Common Agency Competition relative to Incentive Functions in Common Agency Seungjin Han May 20, 2011 Abstract In common agency problems, competing principals often incentivize a privately-informed agent s action choice

More information

ECE531: Principles of Detection and Estimation Course Introduction

ECE531: Principles of Detection and Estimation Course Introduction ECE531: Principles of Detection and Estimation Course Introduction D. Richard Brown III WPI 22-January-2009 WPI D. Richard Brown III 22-January-2009 1 / 37 Lecture 1 Major Topics 1. Web page. 2. Syllabus

More information

Confronting Theory with Experimental Data and vice versa. Lecture VII Social learning. The Norwegian School of Economics Nov 7-11, 2011

Confronting Theory with Experimental Data and vice versa. Lecture VII Social learning. The Norwegian School of Economics Nov 7-11, 2011 Confronting Theory with Experimental Data and vice versa Lecture VII Social learning The Norwegian School of Economics Nov 7-11, 2011 Quantal response equilibrium (QRE) Players do not choose best response

More information

1 Stochastic Dynamic Programming

1 Stochastic Dynamic Programming 1 Stochastic Dynamic Programming Formally, a stochastic dynamic program has the same components as a deterministic one; the only modification is to the state transition equation. When events in the future

More information

Economics of Networks Social Learning

Economics of Networks Social Learning Economics of Networks Social Learning Evan Sadler Massachusetts Institute of Technology Evan Sadler Social Learning 1/38 Agenda Recap of rational herding Observational learning in a network DeGroot learning

More information

Computational Game Theory Spring Semester, 2005/6. Lecturer: Yishay Mansour Scribe: Ilan Cohen, Natan Rubin, Ophir Bleiberg*

Computational Game Theory Spring Semester, 2005/6. Lecturer: Yishay Mansour Scribe: Ilan Cohen, Natan Rubin, Ophir Bleiberg* Computational Game Theory Spring Semester, 2005/6 Lecture 5: 2-Player Zero Sum Games Lecturer: Yishay Mansour Scribe: Ilan Cohen, Natan Rubin, Ophir Bleiberg* 1 5.1 2-Player Zero Sum Games In this lecture

More information

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics Ozan Candogan, Asuman Ozdaglar and Pablo A. Parrilo January 29, 2012 Abstract Potential games are a special class of games for which many adaptive user dynamics

More information

Mechanism Design: Implementation. Game Theory Course: Jackson, Leyton-Brown & Shoham

Mechanism Design: Implementation. Game Theory Course: Jackson, Leyton-Brown & Shoham Game Theory Course: Jackson, Leyton-Brown & Shoham Bayesian Game Setting Extend the social choice setting to a new setting where agents can t be relied upon to disclose their preferences honestly Start

More information

CSCI-6971 Lecture Notes: Monte Carlo integration

CSCI-6971 Lecture Notes: Monte Carlo integration CSCI-6971 Lecture otes: Monte Carlo integration Kristopher R. Beevers Department of Computer Science Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute beevek@cs.rpi.edu February 21, 2006 1 Overview Consider the following

More information

Lecture 14 More on structural estimation

Lecture 14 More on structural estimation Lecture 14 More on structural estimation Economics 8379 George Washington University Instructor: Prof. Ben Williams traditional MLE and GMM MLE requires a full specification of a model for the distribution

More information

Identification and Estimation of Bidders Risk Aversion in. First-Price Auctions

Identification and Estimation of Bidders Risk Aversion in. First-Price Auctions Identification and Estimation of Bidders Risk Aversion in First-Price Auctions Isabelle Perrigne Pennsylvania State University Department of Economics University Park, PA 16802 Phone: (814) 863-2157, Fax:

More information

Combinatorial Agency of Threshold Functions

Combinatorial Agency of Threshold Functions Combinatorial Agency of Threshold Functions Shaili Jain 1 and David C. Parkes 2 1 Yale University, New Haven, CT shaili.jain@yale.edu 2 Harvard University, Cambridge, MA parkes@eecs.harvard.edu Abstract.

More information

Moral Hazard in Teams

Moral Hazard in Teams Moral Hazard in Teams Ram Singh Department of Economics September 23, 2009 Ram Singh (Delhi School of Economics) Moral Hazard September 23, 2009 1 / 30 Outline 1 Moral Hazard in Teams: Model 2 Unobservable

More information

A remark on discontinuous games with asymmetric information and ambiguity

A remark on discontinuous games with asymmetric information and ambiguity Econ Theory Bull DOI 10.1007/s40505-016-0100-5 RESEARCH ARTICLE A remark on discontinuous games with asymmetric information and ambiguity Wei He 1 Nicholas C. Yannelis 1 Received: 7 February 2016 / Accepted:

More information

Goals. PSCI6000 Maximum Likelihood Estimation Multiple Response Model 1. Multinomial Dependent Variable. Random Utility Model

Goals. PSCI6000 Maximum Likelihood Estimation Multiple Response Model 1. Multinomial Dependent Variable. Random Utility Model Goals PSCI6000 Maximum Likelihood Estimation Multiple Response Model 1 Tetsuya Matsubayashi University of North Texas November 2, 2010 Random utility model Multinomial logit model Conditional logit model

More information

Efficient Sensor Network Planning Method. Using Approximate Potential Game

Efficient Sensor Network Planning Method. Using Approximate Potential Game Efficient Sensor Network Planning Method 1 Using Approximate Potential Game Su-Jin Lee, Young-Jin Park, and Han-Lim Choi, Member, IEEE arxiv:1707.00796v1 [cs.gt] 4 Jul 2017 Abstract This paper addresses

More information

Game Theory. Monika Köppl-Turyna. Winter 2017/2018. Institute for Analytical Economics Vienna University of Economics and Business

Game Theory. Monika Köppl-Turyna. Winter 2017/2018. Institute for Analytical Economics Vienna University of Economics and Business Monika Köppl-Turyna Institute for Analytical Economics Vienna University of Economics and Business Winter 2017/2018 Static Games of Incomplete Information Introduction So far we assumed that payoff functions

More information

Recent Advances in the Field of Trade Theory and Policy Analysis Using Micro-Level Data

Recent Advances in the Field of Trade Theory and Policy Analysis Using Micro-Level Data Recent Advances in the Field of Trade Theory and Policy Analysis Using Micro-Level Data July 2012 Bangkok, Thailand Cosimo Beverelli (World Trade Organization) 1 Content a) Censoring and truncation b)

More information

Econometric Analysis of Cross Section and Panel Data

Econometric Analysis of Cross Section and Panel Data Econometric Analysis of Cross Section and Panel Data Jeffrey M. Wooldridge / The MIT Press Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England Contents Preface Acknowledgments xvii xxiii I INTRODUCTION AND BACKGROUND

More information

Optimality, Duality, Complementarity for Constrained Optimization

Optimality, Duality, Complementarity for Constrained Optimization Optimality, Duality, Complementarity for Constrained Optimization Stephen Wright University of Wisconsin-Madison May 2014 Wright (UW-Madison) Optimality, Duality, Complementarity May 2014 1 / 41 Linear

More information

Lecture 2. We now introduce some fundamental tools in martingale theory, which are useful in controlling the fluctuation of martingales.

Lecture 2. We now introduce some fundamental tools in martingale theory, which are useful in controlling the fluctuation of martingales. Lecture 2 1 Martingales We now introduce some fundamental tools in martingale theory, which are useful in controlling the fluctuation of martingales. 1.1 Doob s inequality We have the following maximal

More information

Metric Spaces and Topology

Metric Spaces and Topology Chapter 2 Metric Spaces and Topology From an engineering perspective, the most important way to construct a topology on a set is to define the topology in terms of a metric on the set. This approach underlies

More information

Homework Assignment #2 for Prob-Stats, Fall 2018 Due date: Monday, October 22, 2018

Homework Assignment #2 for Prob-Stats, Fall 2018 Due date: Monday, October 22, 2018 Homework Assignment #2 for Prob-Stats, Fall 2018 Due date: Monday, October 22, 2018 Topics: consistent estimators; sub-σ-fields and partial observations; Doob s theorem about sub-σ-field measurability;

More information

ECONOMETRIC ANALYSIS OF MODELS WITH SOCIAL INTERACTIONS. 1. Introduction

ECONOMETRIC ANALYSIS OF MODELS WITH SOCIAL INTERACTIONS. 1. Introduction ECONOMETRIC ANALYSIS OF MODELS WITH SOCIAL INTERACTIONS BRENDAN KLINE AND ELIE TAMER 1. Introduction Models with social interactions accommodate the possibility that an individual s outcome may be related

More information

The Geometric Tools of Hilbert Spaces

The Geometric Tools of Hilbert Spaces The Geometric Tools of Hilbert Spaces Erlendur Karlsson February 2009 c 2009 by Erlendur Karlsson All rights reserved No part of this manuscript is to be reproduced without the writen consent of the author

More information

Review of Probability Theory

Review of Probability Theory Review of Probability Theory Arian Maleki and Tom Do Stanford University Probability theory is the study of uncertainty Through this class, we will be relying on concepts from probability theory for deriving

More information

University of Warwick, EC9A0 Maths for Economists Lecture Notes 10: Dynamic Programming

University of Warwick, EC9A0 Maths for Economists Lecture Notes 10: Dynamic Programming University of Warwick, EC9A0 Maths for Economists 1 of 63 University of Warwick, EC9A0 Maths for Economists Lecture Notes 10: Dynamic Programming Peter J. Hammond Autumn 2013, revised 2014 University of

More information

CS281 Section 4: Factor Analysis and PCA

CS281 Section 4: Factor Analysis and PCA CS81 Section 4: Factor Analysis and PCA Scott Linderman At this point we have seen a variety of machine learning models, with a particular emphasis on models for supervised learning. In particular, we

More information

AGEC 661 Note Fourteen

AGEC 661 Note Fourteen AGEC 661 Note Fourteen Ximing Wu 1 Selection bias 1.1 Heckman s two-step model Consider the model in Heckman (1979) Y i = X iβ + ε i, D i = I {Z iγ + η i > 0}. For a random sample from the population,

More information

Conditional Distributions

Conditional Distributions Conditional Distributions The goal is to provide a general definition of the conditional distribution of Y given X, when (X, Y ) are jointly distributed. Let F be a distribution function on R. Let G(,

More information

Players as Serial or Parallel Random Access Machines. Timothy Van Zandt. INSEAD (France)

Players as Serial or Parallel Random Access Machines. Timothy Van Zandt. INSEAD (France) Timothy Van Zandt Players as Serial or Parallel Random Access Machines DIMACS 31 January 2005 1 Players as Serial or Parallel Random Access Machines (EXPLORATORY REMARKS) Timothy Van Zandt tvz@insead.edu

More information

Flexible Estimation of Treatment Effect Parameters

Flexible Estimation of Treatment Effect Parameters Flexible Estimation of Treatment Effect Parameters Thomas MaCurdy a and Xiaohong Chen b and Han Hong c Introduction Many empirical studies of program evaluations are complicated by the presence of both

More information

Inducing Peer Pressure to Promote Cooperation (Supporting Information)

Inducing Peer Pressure to Promote Cooperation (Supporting Information) Inducing Peer Pressure to Promote Cooperation Supporting Information Ankur Mani 1, Iyad Rahwan 1,2, Alex Sandy Pentland 1 1 MIT, 2 Masdar Institute 1 Model of Externalities Consider a set of agents, N,

More information

Markov Chain Monte Carlo (MCMC)

Markov Chain Monte Carlo (MCMC) Markov Chain Monte Carlo (MCMC Dependent Sampling Suppose we wish to sample from a density π, and we can evaluate π as a function but have no means to directly generate a sample. Rejection sampling can

More information

Unobserved Heterogeneity in Matching Games

Unobserved Heterogeneity in Matching Games Unobserved Heterogeneity in Matching Games Jeremy T. Fox University of Michigan and NBER Chenyu Yang University of Michigan April 2011 Abstract Agents in two-sided matching games are heterogeneous in characteristics

More information

Estimation of Treatment Effects under Essential Heterogeneity

Estimation of Treatment Effects under Essential Heterogeneity Estimation of Treatment Effects under Essential Heterogeneity James Heckman University of Chicago and American Bar Foundation Sergio Urzua University of Chicago Edward Vytlacil Columbia University March

More information

6.891 Games, Decision, and Computation February 5, Lecture 2

6.891 Games, Decision, and Computation February 5, Lecture 2 6.891 Games, Decision, and Computation February 5, 2015 Lecture 2 Lecturer: Constantinos Daskalakis Scribe: Constantinos Daskalakis We formally define games and the solution concepts overviewed in Lecture

More information

Statistical Estimation

Statistical Estimation Statistical Estimation Use data and a model. The plug-in estimators are based on the simple principle of applying the defining functional to the ECDF. Other methods of estimation: minimize residuals from

More information

Lecture 8 Inequality Testing and Moment Inequality Models

Lecture 8 Inequality Testing and Moment Inequality Models Lecture 8 Inequality Testing and Moment Inequality Models Inequality Testing In the previous lecture, we discussed how to test the nonlinear hypothesis H 0 : h(θ 0 ) 0 when the sample information comes

More information

Selecting Efficient Correlated Equilibria Through Distributed Learning. Jason R. Marden

Selecting Efficient Correlated Equilibria Through Distributed Learning. Jason R. Marden 1 Selecting Efficient Correlated Equilibria Through Distributed Learning Jason R. Marden Abstract A learning rule is completely uncoupled if each player s behavior is conditioned only on his own realized

More information

Economics 2010c: Lecture 2 Iterative Methods in Dynamic Programming

Economics 2010c: Lecture 2 Iterative Methods in Dynamic Programming Economics 2010c: Lecture 2 Iterative Methods in Dynamic Programming David Laibson 9/04/2014 Outline: 1. Functional operators 2. Iterative solutions for the Bellman Equation 3. Contraction Mapping Theorem

More information

A Bootstrap Test for Conditional Symmetry

A Bootstrap Test for Conditional Symmetry ANNALS OF ECONOMICS AND FINANCE 6, 51 61 005) A Bootstrap Test for Conditional Symmetry Liangjun Su Guanghua School of Management, Peking University E-mail: lsu@gsm.pku.edu.cn and Sainan Jin Guanghua School

More information

Oblivious Equilibrium: A Mean Field Approximation for Large-Scale Dynamic Games

Oblivious Equilibrium: A Mean Field Approximation for Large-Scale Dynamic Games Oblivious Equilibrium: A Mean Field Approximation for Large-Scale Dynamic Games Gabriel Y. Weintraub, Lanier Benkard, and Benjamin Van Roy Stanford University {gweintra,lanierb,bvr}@stanford.edu Abstract

More information