Optimal Denominations

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Optimal Denominations"

Transcription

1 Optimal Denominations Manjong Lee, Neil Wallace, and Tao Zhu February 16, 2004 Abstract Previous work on the denomination structure of currency treats as exogenous the distribution of transactions and the denominations held by people. Here, by way of a matching model, both are endogenous. In the model, trades in pairwise meetings alternate in time with the opportunity to freely choose a portfolio of denominations and people trade off the benefits of small-denomination money for transacting against the costliness of carrying a large quantity of smalldenomination money. For a given denomination structure, a monetary steady state is shown to exist. Powers-of-two and powers-of-three denomination structures are compared numerically for an example. JEL classification #: E40. Key words: currency, denominations, matching-model. 1 Introduction The small literature on the optimal denomination structure of a currency treats as exogenous both the distribution of transactions and the portfolios of denominations held by transactors. Telser [6] starts from a problem in number theory. The problem of Bâchet seeks the smallest number of weights capable of weighing any unknown integer.... The version pertinent Department of Economics, The Pennsylvania State University Department of Economics, The Pennsylvania State University Department of Economics, Cornell University 1

2 to this paper allows the unknown weights to be placed in either pan....the solution is weights that are powers of three, namely, 1, 3, 9, 27 and so on... [For the currency version,] the unknown amount to be weighed corresponds to a... transaction....allowing weights to go in either pan corresponds to making change. Finally, that the weights must be capable of weighing any quantity between one and [some] upper bound corresponds to the assumption that a transaction is equally likely to be anywhere between one and some finite upper bound (Telser [6] pages, ). Bâchet s problem is a one-person problem and the application of the solution to multiple transactors, at least a buyer and a seller, is far from straightforward; in particular, who owns which denominations? Van Hove and Heyndels [8] also assume a uniform distribution of transactions. They assume that the buyer and the seller each hold at least one unit of each denomination and judge denomination structures by the number of monetary objects needed to be exchanged to accomplish the transactions. They show that a powersof-two structure, 1, 2, 4,.., can result in a lower average number of monetary objects used in transactions. The main limitation of all of this work is that too much is taken to be exogenous. Here, we formulate a model in which the distribution of transactions and the portfolios of denominations held are endogenous. We use a matching model of money a model in which trades occur in pairwise meetings, between a buyer and seller. Those meetings alternate in time with the opportunity to freely choose a portfolio of denominations subject, of course, to a wealth constraint. The two-person trade is natural for the study of denomination structure because it brings to the fore the limitations imposed on a buyer and seller if neither has small change. Our model focuses on the trade-off between the benefits for trade of small-denomination money and the costliness for people of carrying a large quantity of small-denomination money a trade-off which is in the spirit of the objectives used in the previous literature. For a given a denomination structure, we show that there exists a nice monetary steady state, nice in that the implied value function for (monetary) wealth is strictly increasing and concave. 1 Then we report on numerical 1 We often apply the term concave to functions defined on discrete subsets of R n. Suppose X I n, where I is an interval. We say that f : X R is (strictly) concave if 2

3 work in which we compare expected utility across steady states with different denomination structures expected utility where the expectation is taken with respect to the steady-state distribution of wealth. Although we could, in principle, search numerically for an optimal denomination structure, we limit ourselves to comparing two alternatives addressed in the previous literature: one is the powers-of-three structure; the other is the powers-of-two structure. The latter is the solution to a version of Bâchet s problem in which the object to be weighed is in one pan and weights are placed only in the other pan, a no-change version. Although the making of change is permitted in our model, in our example the powers-of-two structure is better than the powers-of-three structure. 2 The Model The background environment is borrowed from Shi [4] and Trejos and Wright [7]. Time is discrete. There is a [0, 1] continuum of each of N 3 types of infinitely lived agents and there are N distinct produced and perishable types of divisible goods at each date. A type n agent, n {1, 2,...,N}, produces type n good and consumes only type n+1 goods (modulo N). Each person maximizes expected discounted utility with discount factor β (0, 1). Trading histories are private so that any kind of borrowing and lending in pairwise meetings is impossible. The rest of the model is best described in terms of the sequence of actions. Very briefly, the sequence is as follows. Each person starts a period with a portfolio consisting of integer quantities of various denominations for example, 3 ones and 7 fives. Then the person is allowed to freely adjust denominations for example, exchange 2 fives for 10 ones. Then the person meets one other person at random. They trade, as described below, and then go on to the next period. To facilitate a more detailed description, it is helpful to introduce some notation. Let s = (s 1,s 2,...,s K ) be a given denominational structure of the currency. Here s k is the size of the k-th smallest denomination. We assume that 1/s 1 is a positive integer, that s k /s 1 is an integer, and that s k > s k 1. (For example, in the powers-of-three structure, s k = 3s k 1.) The generic symbol for a person s portfolio at the start of a date is y = (y 1,y 2,...,y K ), where y k 0 is the integer quantity of size-s k money held. there exists g : I n R such that f is the restriction of g to X and g is (strictly) concave. 3

4 The wealth implied by y is the inner product of s and y, which we denote sy. Because individuals can freely choose portfolios, the state of an individual with portfolio y at the start of a date is simply sy. The state of the economy at that time is the distribution of wealth. We assume that each specialization type has the same distribution. To achieve compactness, we assume that an individual s wealth z {0,s 1, 2s 1,...,Z} Z, where Z is an integer. We let π denote a probability measure on Z, where π(z) is the fraction of each specialization type with wealth z. As a normalization, we impose zπ(z) = 1. With this normalization, 1/s 1 is the ratio of mean wealth to the size of the smallest unit of money and Z is the ratio of the bound on wealth to mean wealth. We let Y = {y = (y 1,y 2,...,y K ) Z K + : sy Z} be the set of feasible individual portfolios. (Here, Z + denotes the set of non negative integers.) And we let θ denote a probability measure on Y, where θ(y) is the fraction of each specialization type with portfolio y. A person with wealth z chooses y Y with which to enter trade subject to sy z. For a type n person with portfolio y just prior to pairwise meetings, realized utility in a period is u(q n+1 ) q n γ k y k where q n+1 R + is consumption of good n + 1 and q n R + is production of good n, and γ > 0 is the utility cost of carrying money per piece of money. (The linear carrying-of-money cost function could be replaced by a more general class of convex functions of k y k.) The utility function u : R + R is strictly concave, strictly increasing, continuously differentiable and satisfies u(0) = 0 and u ( ) = 0. In addition, u (0) is sufficiently large, but need not be infinite. After the portfolio is chosen, a person meets another person at random. We assume that trading partners see each other s portfolios and types. There are no-coincidence meetings during which nothing happens. In singlecoincidence meetings, we assume that the buyer makes a take-it-or-leave-it offer. We formally define and prove existence for a version in which people can choose lotteries both at the portfolio choice stage and in meetings. The definition is similar and the existence result holds for a version without lotteries (by allowing randomization over multiple deterministic optima for the individual problems). To save space, they are not presented. However, both versions are studied in our numerical work. 4

5 3 Existence of a Steady State We begin by defining a steady state. For a given denomination structure, s, a steady state is a collection of functions (w s,π s,θ s ) that satisfies the conditions described below. The functions w s and π s pertain to the start of a period, prior to the choice of portfolios: w s : Z R, where w s (z) is the expected discounted value of having wealth z, and π s : Z [0, 1], where π s (z) is the fraction of each specialization type with wealth z. The function θ s : Y [0, 1] is a measure where θ s (y) is the fraction of each specialization type with portfolio y. We suppress the dependence of a steady state on the denomination structure s whenever the context is clear. We begin with the choice of a portfolio. We let a person with wealth z choose any lottery over portfolios in Y whose value does not exceed z. That is, we let Γ 1 (z), a subset of probability measures defined on Y, be defined by Γ 1 (z) = {σ : σ(y) = 0 if sy > z}. (1) We let h : Y R denote expected discounted utility after the portfolio is chosen and before pairwise meetings. In terms of h, the portfolio-choice problem is g(z,h) = max σ(y)h(y). (2) σ Γ 1 (z) We denote the set of maximizers in (2) by 1 (z,h). That is, 1 (z,h) is a subset of probability measures on Y, where δ 1 (z,h) is an optimal lottery and δ(y) is the implied probability of holding portfolio y. We now turn to trade in meetings. Let S(y) = {v Z K + : v k y k }. (3) That is, S(y) is the set portfolios that a person with y could surrender. Now, consider a meeting between a buyer with y and a seller with y. We let X(y,y ) = {x [0,Z sy ] : x = s(v v ),v S(y),v S(y )}. (4) That is, X(y,y ) is the set of feasible wealth transfers from the buyer to the seller taking into account the denominations held and the possibility of making change. Let W be an upper bound on w that is defined in the existence proof. We define Γ 2 (y,y,w), a set of probability measures on [0,W] X(y,y ), by 5

6 Γ 2 (y,y,w) = {σ : E σ [ q + βw(x + sy )] βw(sy )}, (5) where E σ denotes the expectation with respect to σ and where the arguments of σ are (q,x). Then we let f(y,y,w) = max E σ [u(q) + βw(sy x)]. (6) σ Γ 2 (y,y ;w) This description implies the payoffs from trade. That is, the buyer s payoff is f(y,y,w) and, because the inequality in (5) will be binding, the seller s is βw(sy ). We denote the set of maximizers in (6) by 2 (y,y,w). Because it can be shown that each maximizer is degenerate in q, in what follows, for a maximizer, we denote the maximizing q by ˆq. To describe the law of motion, it is convenient to define z 1 (y,y ) = {x : sy x = z} for z Z, the set of asset trades that leave the buyer with wealth z. Then we define 2 (y,y,w), a subset of probability measures on Z, by 2 (y,y,w) = {δ : δ(z) = δ(ˆq,x), for δ 2 (y,y,w)}. (7) z 1 (y,y ) That is, for δ 2 (y,y,w), δ(z) is the probability that the buyer with y leaves with wealth z after meeting a seller with y. Now we can complete the conditions for a steady state. The value function w must satisfy w(z) = g(z,h), (8) where the function h is defined by h(y) = γ y k + N 1 N βw(sy) + 1 θ(y )f(y,y,w). (9) N And the measures π and θ must satisfy where π T π (w,θ) and θ T θ (w,π,θ), (10) T π (w,θ) = {ω : ω(z) = (y,y ) θ(y )θ(y )[δ(z) + δ(sy z + sy )], for δ 2 (y,y,w)}, (11) 6

7 and T θ (w,π,θ) = {ω : ω(y) = z π(z)δ(y) for δ 1(z,h)}. (12) (Notice that T π (w,θ) is a set of probability measures on Z and T θ (w,π,θ) is a set of probability measures on Y. Also, notice that the dependence of T θ (w,π,θ) on (w,θ) is through the dependence of h on (w,θ). Finally, in (11), as a convention, δ(x) = 0 if x / Z.) Definition 1 Given a denomination structure s, a steady state is (w,π,θ) that satisfies (1)-(12). Now we prove that if u (0), 1/s 1, and Z are large enough and if γ is small enough, then there exists a nice steady state. Here nice, as above, means a steady state with a strictly increasing and concave value function. We summarize the result formally as follows. Proposition 1 Given a denomination structure s, if u (0), 1/s 1, and Z are sufficiently large and if γ is sufficiently small, then there exists a steady state (w,π,θ) with w strictly increasing and strictly concave. Proof. See Appendix 1. As is well known, the challenge in models like the one above is to show that there is a reasonable monetary steady state. The monetary challenge is met by the conclusion that w is strictly increasing; the reasonableness challenge is met by the concavity of w. The proof shows that there is a neighborhood of γ = 0 with such a steady state. Given earlier results in [10] and [11], the proof is very simple. The proof establishes properties of the mapping used to define a steady state. First, it uses the fact previously established in [11], which, in turn, rests on the results in [10] that for γ = 0 the mapping has fixed-point index 1. The result in [11] can be applied because if γ = 0, then portfolios that consist entirely of the smallest denomination money are equilibrium portfolios. But given such portfolios, the model is the same as the money-only case of the model in [11]. (For such portfolios, the non lottery version is the model in [10].) Second, the mapping is shown to be upper hemicontinuous in γ at γ = 0. Those two facts give the result. Notice, by the way, that the mapping is not continuous in γ at γ = 0; that is, a portfolio that is an equilibrium portfolio when γ = 0 is not, in 7

8 general, close to those that are equilibrium portfolios when γ > 0 and small. That is why the model can have rich implications for portfolios even if γ is small. In accord with such discontinuity, there is a general conclusion about portfolios that is related to Telser s conclusions about optimal denomination structure; namely, portfolios do not have surplus divisibility. Lemma 1 If σ solves the problem in (2) and y is in the support of σ, then ỹ satisfying (i) sỹ = sy, (ii) S(y) S(ỹ), and (iii) k ỹk < k y k. Proof. Suppose, by contradiction, that ỹ exists. It suffices to show that h(ỹ) > h(y). By (9) and properties (i) and (iii), h(ỹ) > h(y) if f(ỹ,y,w) f(y,y,w). To establish the latter, suppose x X(y,y ) (see (4)). Then there exists v and v with x = sv sv with v S(y). But by condition (ii), there exists ṽ with ṽ S(ỹ) with sṽ = sv. Therefore x X(ỹ,y ), which implies that any offer that is feasible when the buyer has y is also feasible when the buyer has ỹ. This and (i) imply f(ỹ,y,w) f(y,y,w). To see that this lemma rules out some portfolios, suppose s is the powersof-two structure and consider y = (3, 0,..., 0) and ỹ = (1, 1, 0,...0). If σ solves the problem in (2), then y cannot be in the support of σ because ỹ satisfies the three conditions in the lemma. And, using strict concavity of w, we can say a bit more about offers in meetings. The following lemma shows how to use the best trade when the buyer s portfolio consists entirely of the smallest denomination to construct the best trade for all portfolios with the same wealth. The best trade is described in terms of a lottery, possibly degenerate, over the amount of wealth transferred. The corresponding implied (deterministic) output is that which satisfies the producer s participation constraint in (5) with equality. Lemma 2 Consider a buyer with y and a seller with y. (i) If the buyer s portfolio is (sy/s 1, 0, 0,..., 0), then the solution for the wealth transfer from the buyer is a lottery over {m,m + s 1 } for some m Z. (ii) Let m be as described in part (i). In general, the solution for the wealth transfer from the buyer is a lottery over {m,m + } = {max x m X(y,y ), min x m+s 1 X(y,y )}, (13) where X(y,y ) is defined in (4) and where the lottery is degenerate on m if m + does not exist. 8

9 Proof. Both (i) and (ii) are obvious consequences of strict concavity of w. Lemma 2 helps simplify the computation of a steady state. 4 Comparing Powers of Two and Three We compare welfare under different denomination structures in terms of πw expected utility prior to the assignment of wealth holdings, where the assignment is made in accord with the steady-state distribution. Here, we compare two denomination structures: powers-of-two and powers-of-three. We make this comparison for two versions, one with and one without lotteries. We assume that both denomination structures have the same s 1, the same smallest denomination. The standard computational procedure involves iterating on the mapping studied to prove existence, the usual mapping studied in heterogeneous-agent models. Even conceptually, this is not straightforward. First, as in many other models, there are no theorems that guarantee that the iterates of such a mapping converge. Second, there are no uniqueness results pertaining to nice steady states. Nevertheless, experience with related one-denomination models (see Molico [2]) suggests that neither of these issues arises in computations. As noted above, we report results for the version with lotteries and the version without lotteries. Lotteries and randomization are identical at the portfolio choice stage. The two differ with regard to what happens in meetings and that difference, of course, produces different steady states. Even in the non lottery version, we always find unique outcomes for both choice problems. 2 For outcomes for which there is a unique portfolio associated with each wealth level, it is well-known that πw satisfies (1 β)πw = πc + 1 N πgπ. (14) 2 This may seem surprising for the portfolio choice. We suspect that it happens because the wealth distribution is smooth and has full support. If the wealth distribution were degenerate, then any steady state would seem to have mixing. After all, if everyone else has the smallest denomination, then why should I? 9

10 Here the z th component of the vector c is the carrying cost implied by the portfolio associated with wealth level z, and the element in row z and column z of the matrix G is G zz = u[q(z,z )] q(z,z ), (15) where q(z,z ) is output when the buyer has wealth z and the seller has wealth z. If q maximizes u(q) q, then u(q ) q is an (unattainable) upper bound on N(1 β)πw. This upper bound would be attained if q was produced and consumed in every single-coincidence meeting and no money was held. 4.1 Parameters We need to specify u,n,β,z,s 1, and γ. We let u(q) = q 1/2 /(1/2). This satisfies all our assumptions and has the virtue of implying a linear firstorder condition for the choice of lotteries in meetings. It implies q = 1 and u(q ) q = 1. We let N = 3, the smallest magnitude consistent with our assumption. We let β =.9 (1/12), which corresponds to one meeting per month and an annual discount factor of.9. We choose Z = 4, which is large enough so that almost no one is at the bound in a steady state. We set s 1 = 1. 8 Recalling that 1/s 1 is the ratio of the mean amount of (monetary) wealth to the size of the smallest unit, this choice of s 1 is a large smallest unit. However, it is consistent with France in the 17-th century if the smallest denomination is taken to be the single coin that was being minted. 3 These choices of Z and s 1 imply that there are 33 elements in the set Z, a conveniently small number for computations. For these choices, s 2 = 1 (1, 2, 4, 8, 16) is the 8 powers-of-two denomination structure and s 3 = 1 (1, 3, 9, 27) is the powersof-three denomination structure. 4 As regards γ, we study γ =.001 which 8 makes the carrying cost per unit a tenth of one percent of the best level of output. 3 See Redish [3] for the size of the coins being minted and see Spooner [5] for estimates of the per capita stock of money. 4 Notice that we have omitted from the powers-of-two structure s 6 = 4. Even omitting this, the powers-of-two structure turns out to be better. In any case, omitting it has no discernible effect on welfare because almost no one has enough wealth to hold such a unit. 10

11 4.2 Computational details The mapping used for the iterative scheme is the mapping studied to prove existence in Appendix 1. The mapping uses an initial condition: (w,π,θ) = x. Given an iteration-i outcome, denoted x i, the initial condition for the i+1 iteration, denoted z i, is formed by a weighted average of the components x i and x i 1, where different weights are used for the different components. The convergence criterion is max (z i+1 z i )/z i 10 5, where the maximization is taken over all elements except that (i) w(0), which is zero, is excluded, and (ii) π and θ are replaced by their corresponding cumulative distributions to avoid dividing by numbers near 0. 5 To get initial conditions and as a check on our computations, we did two preliminary computations. Both are for one-denomination structures, ones that are equivalent to forcing people to hold only the smallest denomination money. We do this for γ = 0 and for the assumed γ. We use the former as one initial condition. The other initial condition we use is the latter, but with θ given by the portfolio that minimizes carrying costs. In each case, the resulting sequence converged to the same limit. 4.3 Results The results for welfare and some other summary statistics are in table 1. The first row describes the steady state we find if γ = 0 (and if we impose the restriction, innocuous in that case, that only the smallest denomination is held). The second row describes the steady state if we impose that only the smallest denomination is held. The outcomes for welfare for those cases bracket those for the powers-of-two and three structures. Both for the lottery and non lottery version, the powers of-two structure has higher welfare than the powers-of-three structure, although the differences are small, no matter how they are measured. In the table, Eq is expected output over singlecoincidence meetings. Underlying these welfare results are outcomes for π and w that do not vary much between the two denomination structures. Figure 1 shows w and π for the powers-of-two structure. (In these figures and those below, the domain is 8 times wealth, so that mean wealth corresponds to 8.) Those for the powers-of-three structure could not be distinguished visually. (See table 2 in Appendix 2 for the underlying data for both structures.) Although the 5 A copy of the computer code is available upon request. 11

12 Table 1: Comparison between powers-of-two and three Non Lottery Lottery Eq E k y k πw Eq E k y k πw γ = s 1 only Powers-of Powers-of wealth distributions have full support, almost no one has as much as 3 times average wealth. Not surprisingly, the lottery version has both a higher value function and a more concentrated wealth distribution. Figure 1: Powers-of-two: w and π Lottery 60 Lottery Non Lottery Non Lottery The higher ex ante welfare of the lottery version has several sources, including more meetings where money holdings of the buyer and the seller are consistent with output near unity. This is confirmed in figure 2 where we show the distribution of output over single-coincidence meetings for the powers-of-two structure. The distribution for the lottery version is much closer to the best output level, unity for our example, than is that for the non lottery version. 12

13 Figure 2: Powers-of-two: frequency distribution of output over singlecoincidence meetings Lottery Non Lottery As suggested by the results for the average number of monetary units held in table 1, the portfolios differ quite a bit across the two denomination structures. The portfolios in the lottery version are very simple: for each wealth level, there is a unique best portfolio and it is the deterministic portfolio that minimizes the number of units of money held. For example, in the powers-of-three structure, someone with wealth 27/8, approximately three times average wealth, holds a single unit of money, despite the fact that this portfolio and the implied trades produce a risk of losing almost all of it in meetings with sufficiently poor producers. The expected wealth transfers E σ x in (5) and (6) are shown in figure 4 in Appendix 2. The portfolios in the non lottery version do not minimize carrying costs (see table 3 in Appendix 2). In the powers-of-three structure steady state, every person holds at least one unit of the smallest denomination. And with one exception, offers of money are either 0, which happens when the seller is sufficiently wealthy relative to the buyer, or 1 unit of the smallest denomination. The one exception is that a buyer with upper bound wealth offers two units of the smallest denomination to a seller with zero. In the powers-of-two structure, those who are sufficiently wealthy do not hold the smallest denomination. For example, a person with wealth 28/8 holds the 13

14 portfolio (0, 2, 0, 1, 1). And a buyer with that portfolio offers 1/4 to a seller with 0, even though a buyer with wealth 29/8, who necessarily holds a unit of the smallest denomination, offers only 1/8 to such a producer (see figure 3 in appendix 2). Such non monotonicity of offers in the wealth of the buyer cannot happen in a one-denomination structure. Again, however, most offers are either 0 or 1 unit of the smallest denomination. The predominance of offers equal to 0 or 1 unit of the smallest denomination in the non lottery version is, of course, a consequence of the indivisibility implied by s 1 = 1/8. Moreover, that indivisibility almost certainly plays a role in our finding that the powers of-two structure is better than the powersof-three structure. 5 Concluding Remarks We have set out a very simple model suitable for studying the effects of different denomination structures. However, there are many effects of the denomination structure that are not in our model. For example, because we have assumed that money never wears out, replacement costs play no role. And we have not considered illegal activity and the impact of the denomination structure on the ease of carrying out illegal transactions. Even aside from those omissions, it is easy to come up with plausible variations of our model. For example, additional heterogeneity could be introduced by replacing our return function by u(q n+1 ) ηq n γ k y k, where η is an idiosyncratic taste (productivity) shock. Indeed, such heterogeneity would seem to bring the model closer to generating the kind of distribution of transactions assumed in the previous literature. And the assumption that the opportunity to choose a portfolio alternates over time with pairwise meetings could be generalized in many ways. Thus, as hardly needs to be mentioned, our numerical finding is, at best, in the nature of a counter-example to the idea that powers-of-three are best. Does that make our model and ones like it irrelevant? We think not. The model highlights the kinds of features that are needed in order to study the interaction between the denomination structure, on the one hand, and the portfolios held and the distribution of transactions, on the other. At a minimum, having before us a model in which those interactions are modeled and in which the optimum problem is posed in terms of welfare helps us see the limitations of models in which the distribution of transactions is 14

15 exogenous even if, in the end, we decide to use such a model. Of course, we have to concede that models of the sort we have described may have very limited use in the future. The computing power that permits us to study some of the properties of models like ours is also responsible for the widespread use of plastic in the form of credit, debit, and stored-value cards. If plastic were to completely replace currency, then divisibility would become essentially free and there would be no need to choose a denomination structure. 6 Appendix 1 As a prelude to the proof, we begin with some notation and assumptions. Let γ [0, 1]. Let R [N (N 1)β] 1 < 1. Also, let D be the unique solution to u (D) = [2/(Rβ)] 2. Notice that D > 0 provided that u (0) > [2/(Rβ)] 2, one of our assumptions. Let W be the unique solution of N(1 β)w = u(βw). We assume that 1/s 1 βw/d and that Z 4. Let W be the set of non-decreasing and concave functions w : Z [0,W] with w(4) D/β. Let K W be the set of non-decreasing functions from Z to [0,W]. Notice that the interior of W (relative to K) is non-empty and that an element of the interior is strictly increasing, strictly concave, and satisfies w(4) > D/β. Let Π be the set of probability measures π defined on Z satisfying π(z)z = 1. Let Θ be the set of probability measures θ on Y satisfying θ(y)sy = 1. Now we can formally define the mapping to be studied. Let the mapping T w : W Θ [0, 1] K be defined by T w (w,θ,γ)(z) = g(z,h), (16) where g(z,h) is given in (2) and h is given by (9). (Here, the dependence of T w (w,θ,γ) on (w,θ,γ) is through the dependence of h on (w,θ,γ) which is given by (9) with f given by (6).) We let T : W Π Θ [0, 1] K Π Θ be defined by T(w,π,θ,γ) = (T w (w,θ,γ),t π (w,θ),t θ (w,π,θ)), (17) where T w (w,θ,γ) is given by (16), T π (w,θ) is given by (11), and T θ (w,π,θ) is given by (12). Lemma 3 A fixed point of T is a steady state. 15

16 Proof. Obvious. Our proof of proposition 1 uses a fixed-point index theorem. Definition 2 Let Λ Π Θ and let W denote the boundary of W (with respect to K). Let G denote the set of upper-hemicontinuous (u.h.c.), compact valued, and convex valued mappings g : W Λ K Λ satisfying (w,λ) / g(w,λ) for all (w,λ) W Λ. Two mappings g 0,g 1 G are said to be homotopic on W Λ if there exists a u.h.c., compact valued, and convex valued mapping G : W Λ [0, 1] K Λ such that (i) (w,λ,α) / G(w,λ,α) for all (w,λ,α) W Λ [0, 1] and (ii) G(w,λ,α) = g α (w,λ) for all (w,λ,α) W Λ {0, 1}. The version of the fixed point index theorem we need is the following (see [1, Theorem 36.1, p. 218] and [9, 13.6a, p. 604]). There exists a fixed-point index defined on G, denoted ind, satisfying: (A1) If g is constant on W Λ with the value (w 0,λ 0 ) where w 0 W W, then ind(g) = 1. (A2) If ind(g) 0, then there exist some (w,λ) W W Λ with (w,λ) g(w,λ). (A3) If g 0,g 1 G are homotopic on W Λ, then ind(g 0 ) = ind(g 1 ). The next three lemmas constitute a proof of proposition 1 by appealing the above theorem. Lemma 4 T is u.h.c., compact valued, and convex valued. Proof. This follows from the Theorem of Maximum and convexification by lotteries. (For the non lottery version, we would allow all possible randomizations over the elements of the sets corresponding to 1 and 2.) In what follows, we write T(.,γ) as T γ (.). Lemma 5 ind(t 0 ) = 1. Proof. Notice that T 0 is identical to the mapping Φ studied in ([10]) and it is also identical to the mapping Φ 1 studied in ([11]). Then, by the exact logic to show ind(φ 1 ) = 1 in ([11, Lemma 2]), we have ind(t 0 ) = 1. Lemma 6 There exists γ 0 > 0 such that if γ γ 0, then T γ has a fixed point. Proof. This follows from Lemma 5, Lemma 4, and the fixed point theorem. 16

17 7 Appendix 2 Table 2: Value Functions and Distributions w π Non Lottery Lottery Non Lottery Lottery 8z powers-2 Powers-3 powers-2 Powers-3 powers-2 Powers-3 powers-2 Powers

18 Table 3: Optimal Portfolios: Non Lottery Powers-of-2 Powers-of-3 8z

19 Figure 3: Wealth Transfer: Non Lottery Figure 4: Wealth Transfer: Lottery 19

20 References [1] Krasnoel skiĭ, M.A., and P.P. Zabreĭko, Geometrical Methods of Nonlinear Analysis, Springer-Verlag, New York, [2] Molico, M., The Distribution of Money and Prices in Search Equilibrium, Ph.D Thesis, University of Pennsylvania, Philadelphia, [3] Redish, A., Bimetallism: An Economic and Historical Analysis, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, [4] Shi, S., Money and prices: a model of search and bargaining, J. of Econ. Theory 67 (1995) [5] Spooner, F., The International Economy and Monetary Movements in France, , Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, [6] Telser, L., Optimal denominations for coins and currency, Economics Letters 49 (1995) [7] Trejos, A., and R. Wright, Search, bargaining, money and prices, J. of Political Economy 103 (1995) [8] Van Hove and Heyndels, On the optimal spacing of currency denominations, European J. of Operational Research 90 (1996) [9] Zeidler, E., Nonlinear Functional Analysis and its Applications I: Fixed- Point Theorems, Springer-Verlag, New York, [10] Zhu, T., Existence of monetary steady states in a matching model: indivisible money, J. Econ. Theory 112 (2003), [11] Zhu, T., and N. Wallace, Cash-in-advance with a twist, manuscript, The Pennsylvania State University,

Heterogeneity and Lotteries in Monetary Search Models

Heterogeneity and Lotteries in Monetary Search Models SÉBASTIEN LOTZ ANDREI SHEVCHENKO CHRISTOPHER WALLER Heterogeneity and Lotteries in Monetary Search Models We introduce ex ante heterogeneity into the Berentsen, Molico, and Wright monetary search model

More information

Lecture 19 Search Theoretic Models of Money. Noah Williams

Lecture 19 Search Theoretic Models of Money. Noah Williams Lecture 19 Search Theoretic Models of Money Noah Williams University of Wisconsin - Madison Economics 712 Williams Economics 712 Essential Models of Money Hahn (1965): money is essential. if it allows

More information

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers September 6, 016 ONLINE APPENDIX In this Appendix we present in full additional results and extensions which are only mentioned in the paper. In the exposition

More information

A Unified Framework for Monetary Theory and Policy Analysis

A Unified Framework for Monetary Theory and Policy Analysis A Unified Framework for Monetary Theory and Policy Analysis Ricardo Lagos NYU Randall Wright Penn 1 Introduction 2 We develop a framework that unifies micro and macro models of monetary exchange Why? Existing

More information

UNIVERSITY OF VIENNA

UNIVERSITY OF VIENNA WORKING PAPERS Cycles and chaos in the one-sector growth model with elastic labor supply Gerhard Sorger May 2015 Working Paper No: 1505 DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS UNIVERSITY OF VIENNA All our working papers

More information

1. Money in the utility function (start)

1. Money in the utility function (start) Monetary Economics: Macro Aspects, 1/3 2012 Henrik Jensen Department of Economics University of Copenhagen 1. Money in the utility function (start) a. The basic money-in-the-utility function model b. Optimal

More information

Second Welfare Theorem

Second Welfare Theorem Second Welfare Theorem Econ 2100 Fall 2015 Lecture 18, November 2 Outline 1 Second Welfare Theorem From Last Class We want to state a prove a theorem that says that any Pareto optimal allocation is (part

More information

The Phillips curve in a matching model

The Phillips curve in a matching model The Phillips curve in a matching model Tai-Wei Hu and Neil Wallace August 1, 016 Abstract Following ideas in Hume, monetary shocks are embedded in the Lagos-Wright (005) model in a new way: there are only

More information

Area I: Contract Theory Question (Econ 206)

Area I: Contract Theory Question (Econ 206) Theory Field Exam Summer 2011 Instructions You must complete two of the four areas (the areas being (I) contract theory, (II) game theory A, (III) game theory B, and (IV) psychology & economics). Be sure

More information

1 Bewley Economies with Aggregate Uncertainty

1 Bewley Economies with Aggregate Uncertainty 1 Bewley Economies with Aggregate Uncertainty Sofarwehaveassumedawayaggregatefluctuations (i.e., business cycles) in our description of the incomplete-markets economies with uninsurable idiosyncratic risk

More information

Monetary Policy, Price Dynamics, and Welfare

Monetary Policy, Price Dynamics, and Welfare Monetary Policy, Price Dynamics, and Welfare Jonathan Chiu Bank of Canada jchiu@bankofcanada.ca Miguel Molico Bank of Canada mmolico@bankofcanada.ca January 2008 DRAFT - Very Preliminary and Incomplete

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago December 2015 Abstract Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970) represent random

More information

Notes on Recursive Utility. Consider the setting of consumption in infinite time under uncertainty as in

Notes on Recursive Utility. Consider the setting of consumption in infinite time under uncertainty as in Notes on Recursive Utility Consider the setting of consumption in infinite time under uncertainty as in Section 1 (or Chapter 29, LeRoy & Werner, 2nd Ed.) Let u st be the continuation utility at s t. That

More information

Preliminary Results on Social Learning with Partial Observations

Preliminary Results on Social Learning with Partial Observations Preliminary Results on Social Learning with Partial Observations Ilan Lobel, Daron Acemoglu, Munther Dahleh and Asuman Ozdaglar ABSTRACT We study a model of social learning with partial observations from

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago September 2015 Abstract Rothschild and Stiglitz (1970) introduce a

More information

"0". Doing the stuff on SVARs from the February 28 slides

0. Doing the stuff on SVARs from the February 28 slides Monetary Policy, 7/3 2018 Henrik Jensen Department of Economics University of Copenhagen "0". Doing the stuff on SVARs from the February 28 slides 1. Money in the utility function (start) a. The basic

More information

Differentiable Welfare Theorems Existence of a Competitive Equilibrium: Preliminaries

Differentiable Welfare Theorems Existence of a Competitive Equilibrium: Preliminaries Differentiable Welfare Theorems Existence of a Competitive Equilibrium: Preliminaries Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 19, November 7 Outline 1 Welfare Theorems in the differentiable case. 2 Aggregate excess

More information

Microeconomics II Lecture 4: Incomplete Information Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics November 2016

Microeconomics II Lecture 4: Incomplete Information Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics November 2016 Microeconomics II Lecture 4: Incomplete Information Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics November 2016 1 Modelling incomplete information So far, we have studied games in which information was complete,

More information

Online Appendix for Investment Hangover and the Great Recession

Online Appendix for Investment Hangover and the Great Recession ONLINE APPENDIX INVESTMENT HANGOVER A1 Online Appendix for Investment Hangover and the Great Recession By MATTHEW ROGNLIE, ANDREI SHLEIFER, AND ALP SIMSEK APPENDIX A: CALIBRATION This appendix describes

More information

Introduction. 1 University of Pennsylvania, Wharton Finance Department, Steinberg Hall-Dietrich Hall, 3620

Introduction. 1 University of Pennsylvania, Wharton Finance Department, Steinberg Hall-Dietrich Hall, 3620 May 16, 2006 Philip Bond 1 Are cheap talk and hard evidence both needed in the courtroom? Abstract: In a recent paper, Bull and Watson (2004) present a formal model of verifiability in which cheap messages

More information

where u is the decision-maker s payoff function over her actions and S is the set of her feasible actions.

where u is the decision-maker s payoff function over her actions and S is the set of her feasible actions. Seminars on Mathematics for Economics and Finance Topic 3: Optimization - interior optima 1 Session: 11-12 Aug 2015 (Thu/Fri) 10:00am 1:00pm I. Optimization: introduction Decision-makers (e.g. consumers,

More information

Introduction to General Equilibrium: Framework.

Introduction to General Equilibrium: Framework. Introduction to General Equilibrium: Framework. Economy: I consumers, i = 1,...I. J firms, j = 1,...J. L goods, l = 1,...L Initial Endowment of good l in the economy: ω l 0, l = 1,...L. Consumer i : preferences

More information

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix

Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Bayesian Persuasion Online Appendix Emir Kamenica and Matthew Gentzkow University of Chicago June 2010 1 Persuasion mechanisms In this paper we study a particular game where Sender chooses a signal π whose

More information

Elimination of Arbitrage States in Asymmetric Information Models

Elimination of Arbitrage States in Asymmetric Information Models Elimination of Arbitrage States in Asymmetric Information Models Bernard CORNET, Lionel DE BOISDEFFRE Abstract In a financial economy with asymmetric information and incomplete markets, we study how agents,

More information

Supplementary appendix to the paper Hierarchical cheap talk Not for publication

Supplementary appendix to the paper Hierarchical cheap talk Not for publication Supplementary appendix to the paper Hierarchical cheap talk Not for publication Attila Ambrus, Eduardo M. Azevedo, and Yuichiro Kamada December 3, 011 1 Monotonicity of the set of pure-strategy equilibria

More information

Government Transaction Policy, the Media of Exchange and Prices

Government Transaction Policy, the Media of Exchange and Prices Government Transaction Policy, the Media of Exchange and Prices Li and Wright (1998 JET) April 2018 Introduction Karl Menger (1892) Money has not been generated by law. In its origin it is a social, and

More information

Boundary Behavior of Excess Demand Functions without the Strong Monotonicity Assumption

Boundary Behavior of Excess Demand Functions without the Strong Monotonicity Assumption Boundary Behavior of Excess Demand Functions without the Strong Monotonicity Assumption Chiaki Hara April 5, 2004 Abstract We give a theorem on the existence of an equilibrium price vector for an excess

More information

Intro to Economic analysis

Intro to Economic analysis Intro to Economic analysis Alberto Bisin - NYU 1 Rational Choice The central gure of economics theory is the individual decision-maker (DM). The typical example of a DM is the consumer. We shall assume

More information

Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities. By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1

Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities. By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1 Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1 Abstract: This note determines the precise connection between an agent s attitude towards income

More information

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance

Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance Comment on The Veil of Public Ignorance Geoffroy de Clippel February 2010 Nehring (2004) proposes an interesting methodology to extend the utilitarian criterion defined under complete information to an

More information

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion

A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion A Rothschild-Stiglitz approach to Bayesian persuasion Matthew Gentzkow and Emir Kamenica Stanford University and University of Chicago January 2016 Consider a situation where one person, call him Sender,

More information

On the Pareto Efficiency of a Socially Optimal Mechanism for Monopoly Regulation

On the Pareto Efficiency of a Socially Optimal Mechanism for Monopoly Regulation MPRA Munich Personal RePEc Archive On the Pareto Efficiency of a Socially Optimal Mechanism for Monopoly Regulation Ismail Saglam Ipek University 4 May 2016 Online at https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/71090/

More information

Unlinked Allocations in an Exchange Economy with One Good and One Bad

Unlinked Allocations in an Exchange Economy with One Good and One Bad Unlinked llocations in an Exchange Economy with One Good and One ad Chiaki Hara Faculty of Economics and Politics, University of Cambridge Institute of Economic Research, Hitotsubashi University pril 16,

More information

Problem Set 6 Solution. k i = βx i + (1 β)y. π x φ = πx + β 2 π y. k i = E[A x i, y] = (1 α)e[θ x i, y] + αe[k = [(1 α) + αβ]e[θ.

Problem Set 6 Solution. k i = βx i + (1 β)y. π x φ = πx + β 2 π y. k i = E[A x i, y] = (1 α)e[θ x i, y] + αe[k = [(1 α) + αβ]e[θ. 4.462 Advanced Macroeconomics Spring 24 Problem. The guess implies Problem Set 6 Solution k i x i + ( )y. K θ + ( )y. Combining this with the relationship y K + σ y u yields y θ + σ u u Thus as a signal

More information

First Welfare Theorem

First Welfare Theorem First Welfare Theorem Econ 2100 Fall 2017 Lecture 17, October 31 Outline 1 First Welfare Theorem 2 Preliminaries to Second Welfare Theorem Past Definitions A feasible allocation (ˆx, ŷ) is Pareto optimal

More information

Roles of Convexity in Optimization Theory. Efor, T. E and Nshi C. E

Roles of Convexity in Optimization Theory. Efor, T. E and Nshi C. E IDOSR PUBLICATIONS International Digital Organization for Scientific Research ISSN: 2550-7931 Roles of Convexity in Optimization Theory Efor T E and Nshi C E Department of Mathematics and Computer Science

More information

Introduction to Game Theory

Introduction to Game Theory COMP323 Introduction to Computational Game Theory Introduction to Game Theory Paul G. Spirakis Department of Computer Science University of Liverpool Paul G. Spirakis (U. Liverpool) Introduction to Game

More information

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7).

Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining. Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). Economics 201B Economic Theory (Spring 2017) Bargaining Topics: the axiomatic approach (OR 15) and the strategic approach (OR 7). The axiomatic approach (OR 15) Nash s (1950) work is the starting point

More information

Money, Barter, and Hyperinflation. Kao, Yi-Cheng Department of Business Administration, Chung Yuan Christian University

Money, Barter, and Hyperinflation. Kao, Yi-Cheng Department of Business Administration, Chung Yuan Christian University Money, Barter, and Hyperinflation Kao, Yi-Cheng Department of Business Administration, Chung Yuan Christian University 1 Outline Motivation The Model Discussion Extension Conclusion 2 Motivation 3 Economist

More information

1 General Equilibrium

1 General Equilibrium 1 General Equilibrium 1.1 Pure Exchange Economy goods, consumers agent : preferences < or utility : R + R initial endowments, R + consumption bundle, =( 1 ) R + Definition 1 An allocation, =( 1 ) is feasible

More information

Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College

Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm. Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College Bargaining, Contracts, and Theories of the Firm Dr. Margaret Meyer Nuffield College 2015 Course Overview 1. Bargaining 2. Hidden information and self-selection Optimal contracting with hidden information

More information

Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium

Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium Zeynel Harun Alioğulları Mehmet Barlo February, 2012 Abstract This study argues that Nash equilibria with less variations in players best responses are more appealing.

More information

In the Name of God. Sharif University of Technology. Microeconomics 1. Graduate School of Management and Economics. Dr. S.

In the Name of God. Sharif University of Technology. Microeconomics 1. Graduate School of Management and Economics. Dr. S. In the Name of God Sharif University of Technology Graduate School of Management and Economics Microeconomics 1 44715 (1396-97 1 st term) - Group 1 Dr. S. Farshad Fatemi Chapter 10: Competitive Markets

More information

ADVANCED MACROECONOMICS 2015 FINAL EXAMINATION FOR THE FIRST HALF OF SPRING SEMESTER

ADVANCED MACROECONOMICS 2015 FINAL EXAMINATION FOR THE FIRST HALF OF SPRING SEMESTER ADVANCED MACROECONOMICS 2015 FINAL EXAMINATION FOR THE FIRST HALF OF SPRING SEMESTER Hiroyuki Ozaki Keio University, Faculty of Economics June 2, 2015 Important Remarks: You must write all your answers

More information

ECOM 009 Macroeconomics B. Lecture 2

ECOM 009 Macroeconomics B. Lecture 2 ECOM 009 Macroeconomics B Lecture 2 Giulio Fella c Giulio Fella, 2014 ECOM 009 Macroeconomics B - Lecture 2 40/197 Aim of consumption theory Consumption theory aims at explaining consumption/saving decisions

More information

Appendix (For Online Publication) Community Development by Public Wealth Accumulation

Appendix (For Online Publication) Community Development by Public Wealth Accumulation March 219 Appendix (For Online Publication) to Community Development by Public Wealth Accumulation Levon Barseghyan Department of Economics Cornell University Ithaca NY 14853 lb247@cornell.edu Stephen

More information

The effect of learning on membership and welfare in an International Environmental Agreement

The effect of learning on membership and welfare in an International Environmental Agreement The effect of learning on membership and welfare in an International Environmental Agreement Larry Karp University of California, Berkeley Department of Agricultural and Resource Economics karp@are.berkeley.edu

More information

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups 6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups Daron Acemoglu and Asu Ozdaglar MIT December 9, 2009 1 Introduction Outline Group and collective choices Arrow s Impossibility Theorem Gibbard-Satterthwaite

More information

h Edition Money in Search Equilibrium

h Edition Money in Search Equilibrium In the Name of God Sharif University of Technology Graduate School of Management and Economics Money in Search Equilibrium Diamond (1984) Navid Raeesi Spring 2014 Page 1 Introduction: Markets with Search

More information

Using Markov Chains To Model Human Migration in a Network Equilibrium Framework

Using Markov Chains To Model Human Migration in a Network Equilibrium Framework Using Markov Chains To Model Human Migration in a Network Equilibrium Framework Jie Pan Department of Mathematics and Computer Science Saint Joseph s University Philadelphia, PA 19131 Anna Nagurney School

More information

ECON4510 Finance Theory Lecture 2

ECON4510 Finance Theory Lecture 2 ECON4510 Finance Theory Lecture 2 Diderik Lund Department of Economics University of Oslo 26 August 2013 Diderik Lund, Dept. of Economics, UiO ECON4510 Lecture 2 26 August 2013 1 / 31 Risk aversion and

More information

Dynamic Macroeconomic Theory Notes. David L. Kelly. Department of Economics University of Miami Box Coral Gables, FL

Dynamic Macroeconomic Theory Notes. David L. Kelly. Department of Economics University of Miami Box Coral Gables, FL Dynamic Macroeconomic Theory Notes David L. Kelly Department of Economics University of Miami Box 248126 Coral Gables, FL 33134 dkelly@miami.edu Current Version: Fall 2013/Spring 2013 I Introduction A

More information

The effect of learning on membership and welfare in an International Environmental Agreement

The effect of learning on membership and welfare in an International Environmental Agreement Climatic Change (202) 0:499 505 DOI 0007/s0584-0-034-5 The effect of learning on membership and welfare in an International Environmental Agreement Larry Karp Received: 7 March 200 / Accepted: 20 April

More information

1 Two elementary results on aggregation of technologies and preferences

1 Two elementary results on aggregation of technologies and preferences 1 Two elementary results on aggregation of technologies and preferences In what follows we ll discuss aggregation. What do we mean with this term? We say that an economy admits aggregation if the behavior

More information

Session 4: Money. Jean Imbs. November 2010

Session 4: Money. Jean Imbs. November 2010 Session 4: Jean November 2010 I So far, focused on real economy. Real quantities consumed, produced, invested. No money, no nominal in uences. I Now, introduce nominal dimension in the economy. First and

More information

4 Lecture Applications

4 Lecture Applications 4 Lecture 4 4.1 Applications We now will look at some of the applications of the convex analysis we have learned. First, we shall us a separation theorem to prove the second fundamental theorem of welfare

More information

Econ 2148, spring 2019 Statistical decision theory

Econ 2148, spring 2019 Statistical decision theory Econ 2148, spring 2019 Statistical decision theory Maximilian Kasy Department of Economics, Harvard University 1 / 53 Takeaways for this part of class 1. A general framework to think about what makes a

More information

CONSUMPTION-SAVINGS DECISIONS WITH QUASI-GEOMETRIC DISCOUNTING. By Per Krusell and Anthony A. Smith, Jr introduction

CONSUMPTION-SAVINGS DECISIONS WITH QUASI-GEOMETRIC DISCOUNTING. By Per Krusell and Anthony A. Smith, Jr introduction Econometrica, Vol. 71, No. 1 (January, 2003), 365 375 CONSUMPTION-SAVINGS DECISIONS WITH QUASI-GEOMETRIC DISCOUNTING By Per Krusell and Anthony A. Smith, Jr. 1 1 introduction The purpose of this paper

More information

Markov Perfect Equilibria in the Ramsey Model

Markov Perfect Equilibria in the Ramsey Model Markov Perfect Equilibria in the Ramsey Model Paul Pichler and Gerhard Sorger This Version: February 2006 Abstract We study the Ramsey (1928) model under the assumption that households act strategically.

More information

Decentralized bargaining in matching markets: online appendix

Decentralized bargaining in matching markets: online appendix Decentralized bargaining in matching markets: online appendix Matt Elliott and Francesco Nava March 2018 Abstract The online appendix discusses: MPE multiplicity; the non-generic cases of core-match multiplicity

More information

Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory

Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory Chapter 9 Nathan Smooha Economic Core, Fair Allocations, and Social Choice Theory 9.1 Introduction In this chapter, we briefly discuss some topics in the framework of general equilibrium theory, namely

More information

Lecture 3: Huggett s 1993 model. 1 Solving the savings problem for an individual consumer

Lecture 3: Huggett s 1993 model. 1 Solving the savings problem for an individual consumer UNIVERSITY OF WESTERN ONTARIO LONDON ONTARIO Paul Klein Office: SSC 4044 Extension: 85484 Email: pklein2@uwo.ca URL: http://paulklein.ca/newsite/teaching/619.php Economics 9619 Computational methods in

More information

Uncertainty. Michael Peters December 27, 2013

Uncertainty. Michael Peters December 27, 2013 Uncertainty Michael Peters December 27, 20 Lotteries In many problems in economics, people are forced to make decisions without knowing exactly what the consequences will be. For example, when you buy

More information

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016 Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016 The time limit for this exam is four hours. The exam has four sections. Each section includes two questions.

More information

Bilateral Matching with Latin Squares

Bilateral Matching with Latin Squares Bilateral Matching with Latin Squares C. D. Aliprantis a,, G. Camera a, and D. Puzzello b a Department of Economics, Purdue University, West Lafayette, IN 47907 2056, USA b Departments of Economics and

More information

The Relation Between Implementability and the Core

The Relation Between Implementability and the Core The Relation Between Implementability and the Core Eiichi Miyagawa Department of Economics, Columbia University 420 West 118th Street, New York, NY 10027, U.S.A. em437@columbia.edu June 11, 2002 Abstract

More information

Economic Growth: Lecture 8, Overlapping Generations

Economic Growth: Lecture 8, Overlapping Generations 14.452 Economic Growth: Lecture 8, Overlapping Generations Daron Acemoglu MIT November 20, 2018 Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Economic Growth Lecture 8 November 20, 2018 1 / 46 Growth with Overlapping Generations

More information

Ramsey Cass Koopmans Model (1): Setup of the Model and Competitive Equilibrium Path

Ramsey Cass Koopmans Model (1): Setup of the Model and Competitive Equilibrium Path Ramsey Cass Koopmans Model (1): Setup of the Model and Competitive Equilibrium Path Ryoji Ohdoi Dept. of Industrial Engineering and Economics, Tokyo Tech This lecture note is mainly based on Ch. 8 of Acemoglu

More information

Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1

Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1 Journal of Economic Theory 91, 8690 (2000) doi:10.1006jeth.1999.2590, available online at http:www.idealibrary.com on NOTES, COMMENTS, AND LETTERS TO THE EDITOR Are Probabilities Used in Markets? 1 Larry

More information

Kiyotaki and Wright (1993)

Kiyotaki and Wright (1993) Review May 2017 Kiyotaki and Wright (1993) Π = prob. that a random commodity trader accepts fiat money. π = best response of a representative agent. In steady state, Bellman equations are rv g = β(1 M)x

More information

ONLINE APPENDIX. Upping the Ante: The Equilibrium Effects of Unconditional Grants to Private Schools

ONLINE APPENDIX. Upping the Ante: The Equilibrium Effects of Unconditional Grants to Private Schools ONLINE APPENDIX Upping the Ante: The Equilibrium Effects of Unconditional Grants to Private Schools T. Andrabi, J. Das, A.I. Khwaja, S. Ozyurt, and N. Singh Contents A Theory A.1 Homogeneous Demand.................................

More information

Title: The existence of equilibrium when excess demand obeys the weak axiom

Title: The existence of equilibrium when excess demand obeys the weak axiom Title: The existence of equilibrium when excess demand obeys the weak axiom Abstract: This paper gives a non-fixed point theoretic proof of equilibrium existence when the excess demand function of an exchange

More information

Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1)

Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1) Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1) Tsun-Feng Chiang* *School of Economics, Henan University, Kaifeng, China November 2, 2014 1 / 28 Primitive Notions 1.1 Primitive Notions Consumer

More information

Public Provision of Scarce Resources when Preferences are Non-Linear

Public Provision of Scarce Resources when Preferences are Non-Linear Public Provision of Scarce Resources when Preferences are Non-Linear Katharina Huesmann February 13, 2017 Abstract This paper considers the problem of assigning an indivisible good of limited availability

More information

UNIVERSITY OF KANSAS WORKING PAPERS SERIES IN THEORETICAL AND APPLIED ECONOMICS

UNIVERSITY OF KANSAS WORKING PAPERS SERIES IN THEORETICAL AND APPLIED ECONOMICS UNIVERSITY OF KANSAS WORKING PAPERS SERIES IN THEORETICAL AND APPLIED ECONOMICS Strategy-Proofness versus Efficiency in Exchange Economies: General Domain Properties and Applications Biung-Ghi Ju Paper

More information

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract Pure strategy dominance with quasiconcave utility functions Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam Abstract By a result of Pearce (1984), in a finite strategic form game, the set of a player's serially

More information

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES KIER DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES KYOTO INSTITUTE OF ECONOMIC RESEARCH Discussion Paper No.992 Intertemporal efficiency does not imply a common price forecast: a leading example Shurojit Chatterji, Atsushi

More information

A Simple No-Bubble Theorem for Deterministic Sequential Economies

A Simple No-Bubble Theorem for Deterministic Sequential Economies A Simple No-Bubble Theorem for Deterministic Sequential Economies Takashi Kamihigashi September 28, 2015 Abstract We show a simple no-bubble theorem that applies to a wide range of deterministic sequential

More information

Winter Lecture 10. Convexity and Concavity

Winter Lecture 10. Convexity and Concavity Andrew McLennan February 9, 1999 Economics 5113 Introduction to Mathematical Economics Winter 1999 Lecture 10 Convexity and Concavity I. Introduction A. We now consider convexity, concavity, and the general

More information

Repeated bargaining. Shiran Rachmilevitch. February 16, Abstract

Repeated bargaining. Shiran Rachmilevitch. February 16, Abstract Repeated bargaining Shiran Rachmilevitch February 16, 2017 Abstract Two symmetric players bargain over an infinite stream of pies. There is one exogenously given pie in every period, whose size is stochastic,

More information

SIMON FRASER UNIVERSITY. Economics 483 Advanced Topics in Macroeconomics Spring 2014 Assignment 3 with answers

SIMON FRASER UNIVERSITY. Economics 483 Advanced Topics in Macroeconomics Spring 2014 Assignment 3 with answers BURNABY SIMON FRASER UNIVERSITY BRITISH COLUMBIA Paul Klein Office: WMC 3635 Phone: (778) 782-9391 Email: paul klein 2@sfu.ca URL: http://paulklein.ca/newsite/teaching/483.php Economics 483 Advanced Topics

More information

EC476 Contracts and Organizations, Part III: Lecture 2

EC476 Contracts and Organizations, Part III: Lecture 2 EC476 Contracts and Organizations, Part III: Lecture 2 Leonardo Felli 32L.G.06 19 January 2015 Moral Hazard: Consider the contractual relationship between two agents (a principal and an agent) The principal

More information

Economic Growth: Lecture 7, Overlapping Generations

Economic Growth: Lecture 7, Overlapping Generations 14.452 Economic Growth: Lecture 7, Overlapping Generations Daron Acemoglu MIT November 17, 2009. Daron Acemoglu (MIT) Economic Growth Lecture 7 November 17, 2009. 1 / 54 Growth with Overlapping Generations

More information

Counterfeiting as Private Money in Mechanism Design

Counterfeiting as Private Money in Mechanism Design w o r k i n g p a p e r 7 6 Counterfeiting as Private Money in Mechanism Design by Ricardo Cavalcanti and Ed osal FEDERAL RESERVE BAK OF CLEVELAD Working papers of the Federal Reserve Bank of Cleveland

More information

GENERALIZED CONVEXITY AND OPTIMALITY CONDITIONS IN SCALAR AND VECTOR OPTIMIZATION

GENERALIZED CONVEXITY AND OPTIMALITY CONDITIONS IN SCALAR AND VECTOR OPTIMIZATION Chapter 4 GENERALIZED CONVEXITY AND OPTIMALITY CONDITIONS IN SCALAR AND VECTOR OPTIMIZATION Alberto Cambini Department of Statistics and Applied Mathematics University of Pisa, Via Cosmo Ridolfi 10 56124

More information

Informed Principal in Private-Value Environments

Informed Principal in Private-Value Environments Informed Principal in Private-Value Environments Tymofiy Mylovanov Thomas Tröger University of Bonn June 21, 2008 1/28 Motivation 2/28 Motivation In most applications of mechanism design, the proposer

More information

General Examination in Macroeconomic Theory SPRING 2013

General Examination in Macroeconomic Theory SPRING 2013 HARVARD UNIVERSITY DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS General Examination in Macroeconomic Theory SPRING 203 You have FOUR hours. Answer all questions Part A (Prof. Laibson): 48 minutes Part B (Prof. Aghion): 48

More information

Mathematical models in economy. Short descriptions

Mathematical models in economy. Short descriptions Chapter 1 Mathematical models in economy. Short descriptions 1.1 Arrow-Debreu model of an economy via Walras equilibrium problem. Let us consider first the so-called Arrow-Debreu model. The presentation

More information

Two-sided investments and matching with multi-dimensional cost types and attributes

Two-sided investments and matching with multi-dimensional cost types and attributes Two-sided investments and matching with multi-dimensional cost types and attributes Deniz Dizdar 1 1 Department of Economics, University of Montréal September 15, 2014 1/33 Investments and matching 2/33

More information

Problem Set 1 Welfare Economics

Problem Set 1 Welfare Economics Problem Set 1 Welfare Economics Solutions 1. Consider a pure exchange economy with two goods, h = 1,, and two consumers, i =1,, with utility functions u 1 and u respectively, and total endowment, e = (e

More information

36106 Managerial Decision Modeling Linear Decision Models: Part II

36106 Managerial Decision Modeling Linear Decision Models: Part II 1 36106 Managerial Decision Modeling Linear Decision Models: Part II Kipp Martin University of Chicago Booth School of Business January 20, 2014 Reading and Excel Files Reading (Powell and Baker): Sections

More information

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Final Exam Questions and Answers Econ 8712

Department of Economics The Ohio State University Final Exam Questions and Answers Econ 8712 Prof. Peck Fall 20 Department of Economics The Ohio State University Final Exam Questions and Answers Econ 872. (0 points) The following economy has two consumers, two firms, and three goods. Good is leisure/labor.

More information

WHEN ORDER MATTERS FOR ITERATED STRICT DOMINANCE *

WHEN ORDER MATTERS FOR ITERATED STRICT DOMINANCE * WHEN ORDER MATTERS FOR ITERATED STRICT DOMINANCE * Martin Dufwenberg ** & Mark Stegeman *** February 1999 Abstract: We demonstrate that iterated elimination of strictly dominated strategies is an order

More information

Data Abundance and Asset Price Informativeness. On-Line Appendix

Data Abundance and Asset Price Informativeness. On-Line Appendix Data Abundance and Asset Price Informativeness On-Line Appendix Jérôme Dugast Thierry Foucault August 30, 07 This note is the on-line appendix for Data Abundance and Asset Price Informativeness. It contains

More information

Discussion Papers in Economics

Discussion Papers in Economics Discussion Papers in Economics No. 10/11 A General Equilibrium Corporate Finance Theorem for Incomplete Markets: A Special Case By Pascal Stiefenhofer, University of York Department of Economics and Related

More information

Game Theory Fall 2003

Game Theory Fall 2003 Game Theory Fall 2003 Problem Set 1 [1] In this problem (see FT Ex. 1.1) you are asked to play with arbitrary 2 2 games just to get used to the idea of equilibrium computation. Specifically, consider the

More information

Wars of Attrition with Budget Constraints

Wars of Attrition with Budget Constraints Wars of Attrition with Budget Constraints Gagan Ghosh Bingchao Huangfu Heng Liu October 19, 2017 (PRELIMINARY AND INCOMPLETE: COMMENTS WELCOME) Abstract We study wars of attrition between two bidders who

More information

Free and Second-best Entry in Oligopolies with Network

Free and Second-best Entry in Oligopolies with Network Free and Second-best Entry in Oligopolies with Network Effects Adriana Gama Mario Samano September 7, 218 Abstract We establish an important difference between Cournot oligopolies with and without positive

More information

Homework #6 (10/18/2017)

Homework #6 (10/18/2017) Homework #6 (0/8/207). Let G be the set of compound gambles over a finite set of deterministic payoffs {a, a 2,...a n } R +. A decision maker s preference relation over compound gambles can be represented

More information

The Interdisciplinary Center, Herzliya School of Economics Advanced Microeconomics Fall Bargaining The Axiomatic Approach

The Interdisciplinary Center, Herzliya School of Economics Advanced Microeconomics Fall Bargaining The Axiomatic Approach The Interdisciplinary Center, Herzliya School of Economics Advanced Microeconomics Fall 2011 Bargaining The Axiomatic Approach Bargaining problem Nash s (1950) work is the starting point for formal bargaining

More information