Fusing o-minimal structures

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Fusing o-minimal structures"

Transcription

1 Fusing o-minimal structures A.J. Wilkie Mathematical Institute University of Oxford St Giles Oxford OX1 3LB UK May 3, 2004 Abstract In this note I construct a proper o-minimal expansion of the ordered additive group of rationals. 1 Introduction Following work by van den Dries on expansions of the real field (see [1]) Pillay and Steinhorn layed the foundations for the general theory of o-minimality in [11]. At that time, and very much in the spirit of model theory of the period, Steinhorn asked whether the most atomic of all (interesting) o-minimal structures, namely the ordered, additive group of rationals, could have a proper o-minimal expansion. Although, as we shall show here, the answer to this question is disappointingly positive, much research into o-minimal expansions of ordered, divisible groups was activated by Steinhorn s question (see [12], [2], [6], [7], [8], [5], [14], [10]). The most recent is reported in [9] where many of the natural questions in the case of structures related to R an are settled, but where it is also pointed out that fundamental issues remain unresolved in general. The purpose of this paper is to show that the o-minimal condition places almost no restriction on partial (abelian) group structures that can exist on 1

2 bounded parts of archimedean structures related to R an. The following result gives the flavour of our main theorem. Here, and throughout the paper, we use the convention that if 0 E R and F : E n E, then for r, s E with r < s, F [r,s] : E n E is the function sending x to F ( x) if x E n [r, s] n, and to 0 if x E n \ [r, s] n. Theorem 1. There exists an expansion B; of the ordered ring B := B; 0, 1, <, +, of real algebraic numbers such that the reduct B; 0, 1, <, is isomorphic to the ordered, additive group of rational numbers (with 1 distinguished) and such that both the structures and are o-minimal. B; [r,s] r,s B,r<s B; 0, 1, <, + [r,s], [r,s], r,s B,r<s I should remark that by a result of [6], the domain of an o-minimal structure can support at most two definable ordered groups (up to definable isomorphism) and it follows fairly easily from this that the structure B; itself cannot be o-minimal. However, the second displayed structure in Theorem 1 may be viewed as an expansion of the ordered additive group of rationals, and is certainly a proper expansion (e.g. because its definable closure operator is non-modular), so we do have an answer to Steinhorn s question. In fact, the rationals may be replaced by any countable, archimedean ordered, divisible abelian group and the real algebraics by any countable, archimedean ordered, real closed field. Notice also that Theorem 1 implies that the additive (circle) groups of rationals (mod 1) and real algebraics (mod 1) can coexist o-minimally on the same set. 2 Preliminaries and statements of results A function f : R n R is called restricted analytic if it is of the form F [0,1] : R n R, where F : R n R is analytic at least on some open set U R n with [0, 1] n U. With this notation, if α N n is a multi-index and G : R n R is any function agreeing with the α th derivative F (α) of F on U, then we write f (α) for the restricted analytic function G [0,1]. 2

3 The proof of our main theorem relies heavily on the following result, due to Gabrielov, in which I use R to denote the real ordered field R; 0, 1, <, +,. Proposition 1. Let F be a collection of restricted analytic functions closed under differentiation. Then the structure R; F has a model complete theory and is o-minimal. If we take F to be the collection of all restricted analytic functions, then the corresponding structure R; F is usually denoted R an and was first shown to be model complete by Gabrielov in 1969 (see [3]). The above refinement was established much later in the paper [4]. We can now state our main theorem. Theorem 2. Let F be a countable collection of restricted analytic functions closed under differentiation and set A := R; F. Let B be a countable elementary substructure of A. Then for any countable elementary substructure G of R; 0, 1, <, +, there exists an expansion B, of B such that B; 0, 1, <, = G (where B = dom(b)) and such that the structure B, [r,s] r,s B,r<s is o-minimal. Proof of Theorem 1 assuming Theorem 2. We take F =, B the ordered ring of algebraic numbers and G the ordered additive group of rationals (with 1, as well as 0, distinguished) in Theorem 2. Then all but the very last assertion of Theorem 1 follow immediately. To obtain this as well, we need the following facts and I am grateful to Philip Scowcroft for pointing them out to me (private communication: the crucial result is Theorem 1.1 of [10]): Let D be any expansion of the ordered additive group of rationals (with 0, 1 distinguished) by bounded relations, and let ψ(x) be any formula of L(D). Then (a) there exists q Q such that either p Q with p q, D ψ[p] or p Q with p q, D ψ[p], and (b) for any r, s Q with r < s, there exists a formula θ(x) of L(D), all of whose quantifiers are bounded by closed terms, such that D x[r x s (ψ(x) θ(x))]. Thus, thanks to these results, the o-minimality of the structure B; 0, 1, <, + [r,s], [r,s], r,s B,r<s follows readily from that of B; 0, 1, <, + [r,s], [r,s], [r,s] r,s B,r<s (which, of course, follows immediately from that of B, [r,s] r,s B,r<s ). 3 Towards the proof of the main theorem Let F, A, B, B, G be as in the hypothesis of Theorem 2. Say G = dom(g) so that G is the underlying set of a divisible additive subgroup of R, 0, + 3

4 containing 1. We shall fuse G onto B via the restriction to B of a certain function φ : R R satisfying several properties, the first few of which are as follows:- 3.1 φ is analytic and bijective; 3.2 φ(0) = 0, φ(1) = 1; 3.3 x R φ (1) (x) > 0 (so that φ 1 is also analytic and both φ and φ 1 are monotonically increasing); 3.4 φ maps B bijectively onto G. Now define the function : R 2 R by x y := φ 1 (φ(x) + φ(y)) (for x, y R). Then is analytic and, by 3.4, maps B 2 to B.Also, by , the map φ B is an isomorphism from the structure B; 0, 1, <, to G. In order to establish the o-minimality of the structure B; [r,s] r,s B,r<s consider the expansion A := A;, φ (i) i 1 of A. If 3.5 for all i 1, the i th derivative φ (i) of φ maps B to B, then B; has a (unique) expansion, B say, to a substructure of A. We shall construct φ so that, in addition to , the following holds:- 3.6 B is existentially closed in A. Now before proceeding we need the following Lemma 1. For all multi-indices l, m N 2 with l + m 1, the l, m th derivative x (l,m) y of x y is expressible as a rational function, with integer coefficients, in the quantities φ (i) (x), φ (j) (y) and φ (k) (x y) for 1 i, j, k l + m. A similar result holds for the functions µ N (for N N) defined by N {}}{ µ N (x) := x x x (= φ 1 (N φ(x))) (for x R). Further, the denominators of these expressions are,respectively, powers of φ (1) (x y) and φ (1) (µ N (x)),so by 3.3 they are nowhere vanishing. Proof. Differentiation of the identity φ(x y) = φ(x) + φ(y) yields x (1,0) y = φ(1) (x) φ (1) (x y) and x (0,1) y = 4 φ(1) (y) φ (1) (x y).

5 The result for (both parts) now follows easily by induction on l + m using the chain rule. Similarly µ (1) N (x) = N φ(1) (x) φ (1) (µ N (x)) and so, again by induction, we obtain that µ (1) N (x) is expressible as a rational function, with integer coefficients, in the quantities φ (i) (x), φ (j) (µ N (x)) for 1 i, j l with denominator a power of φ (1) (µ N (x)). Remark: The crucial point in the above expressions is that they do not involve the function φ itself, only its derivatives. Now consider the set { } {µ N : N N} of analytic functions and let H denote its closure under differentiation. Let H res denote the corresponding set {h [0,1] : h H} of restricted analytic functions and let A denote the expansion A; H res of A. Then by Proposition 1, A is o-minimal and has a model complete theory. But by Lemma 1 each function in H res (and H) is certainly existentially definable in A and hence, by 3.6, the structure B has a (unique) expansion to a substructure, B say, of A and, further, B is existentially closed in A. But the theory of A, being model complete, is 2 -axiomatizable so it follows that B is elementarily equivalent to A and hence, by a fundamental result of [11], B is also o-minimal. This obviously implies the o-minimality of its reduct B := B; [0,1], µ N [0,1] N N. However, the presence here of the functions µ N [0,1] clearly implies that all the restricted functions [r,s] (for r, s B, r < s) are definable (with parameters) in B, and hence the structure B; [r,s] r,s B,r<s is o-minimal. Theorem 2 is thus established. So, it remains to construct a function φ : R R satisfying The countably many conditions imposed by 3.5 and 3.6 will be satisfied one by one, and a suitable limit of the inductively defined approximations will then be taken. An appropriate space in which to take such a limit is described in the next section. 4 The Approximation Space I denote by B the set of all entire functions f : C C for which e R M(f; R) is bounded (for R 0) where, as is usual, M(f; R) denotes sup z R f(z), 5

6 and set f := sup e R M(f; R) R 0 for such f. Then B, is easily seen to be a normed linear space. In fact, it is a Banach space. For if f n : n N is any Cauchy sequence in B, then certainly K n N, f n K, so n N, R 0, M(f n ; R) e R K. It follows from Montel s theorem (see [13] page 149 for the exact version that we need here, and see also the subsequent discussion in [13] for why we are working in a complex space even though we are only interested in limits of real functions) that some subsequence f ni : i N of f n : n N converges uniformly on compact subsets of C to an entire function, f say. Let ɛ > 0, and choose N = N(ɛ) large enough so that n, m N f n f m < ɛ/2. Now, for each R > 0 i 0 = i 0 (R) such that M((f f ni0 ), R) < ɛ/2, and we may take i 0 so that n i0 N. It follows that for any n N, M((f f n ), R) M((f f ni0 ), R) + M((f n f ni0 ), R)) < ɛ/2 + e R f n f ni0 < (1 + e R )ɛ/2 and hence f f n < (e R + 1)ɛ/2 < ɛ. Thus the sequence f n : n N converges to f in the space B, as required. Remark: The choice of the dampening factor e R in the definition of is not crucial. We merely require that it dominates every polynomial in R for large R. However, this particular choice does make some later calculations less cumbersome because of the following result. Lemma 2. The map sending f to f (1) is a bounded linear operator on B (with norm e). Proof. Let f B and R > 0. Then for any z C with z R we have, by Cauchy s formula, f (1) (z) = 1 f(w) 2πi C (w z) dw, 2 where C is the circle centred at z and having radius 1. Hence, since w R+1 for w on C, f (1) (z) M(f; R+1) e R+1 f. Thus f (1) e f, as required. We can now state and prove the interpolation property we require of our space B. It is, in fact, a version of the standard Lagrange Interpolation Theorem suitably adapted for present needs. 6

7 Lemma 3. Let n, N be positive integers and K a non-negative integer. Then there exists a positive real number C = C(K, n, N) 1 with the following property: Suppose we are given (i) a 1,..., a n C with a i N and a i a j N 1 for 1 i, j n and i j; (ii) ɛ R with 0 < ɛ < 1; (iii) F B; (iv) non-negative integers K 1,..., K n with K K n = K; (v) b i,j C (for i = 1,..., n, j < K i ) satisfying F (j) (a i ) b i,j < ɛ. Then there exists G B with F G < C ɛ such that G (j) (a i ) = b i,j for each i = 1... n and j < K i. Further, if the a i s and b i,j s are real and if F [R] R, then we may choose G so that G[R] R. Proof. By induction on K. For K = 0 we take C(0, n, N) = 1 and there is nothing to prove. Suppose K > 0 and that C(K 1, n, N) 1 has been found. Set C(K, n, N) := C(K 1, n, N) (2 N 2K (2K 2 + 1) K e N+K + 1). To see that this works, suppose we are given the data as in (i)-(v). Then at least one K i is positive (as K > 0), say K n > 0. By the inductive hypothesis we may choose G 0 B with F G 0 < C(K 1, n, N) ɛ, and such that G (j) 0 (a i ) = b i,j for each i = 1,..., n and j < K i apart from, possibly, the pair i = n and j = K n 1. Now define the functions H, G : C C by and H(z) = n 1 i=1 (z a i) K i n 1 i=1 (a n a i ) K i (z a n) Kn 1, (K n 1)! G(z) = G 0 (z) + H(z) (b n,kn 1 G (Kn 1) 0 (a n )). Since B contains all polynomials (cf, the remark immediately before the statement of Lemma 2) we have that H B and hence G B. Further, for R > 0, e R M(H; R) e R (R+N)K (by (i) and (iv)). But the upper N K 7

8 bound here achieves its maximum at some R 2NK 2, so we obtain that H N 2K (2K 2 + 1) K. Now observe that H (Kn 1) (a n ) = 1 and that H (j) (a i ) = 0 for all other pairs i, j with i = 1,..., n and j < K i and hence, in all cases, G (j) (a i ) = b i,j (by the choice of G 0 ). Notice also that if a i R, b i,j R for i = 1,..., n and j < K i, and if our inductive assumption includes the statement that G 0 [R] R, then G[R] R. So it only remains to calculate the required upper bound for F G. For this, we first note that it follows immediately from Lemma 2 that the map sending f to f (Kn 1) is a bounded linear operator on B of norm e Kn 1. Hence F (Kn 1) G (Kn 1) 0 e Kn 1 F G 0 < e K C(K 1, n, N) ɛ. Thus, using also the lemma hypotheses (v) and (i), we obtain b n,kn 1 G (Kn 1) 0 (a n ) b n,kn 1 F (Kn 1) (a n ) + F (Kn 1) (a n ) G (Kn 1) < ɛ + M(F (Kn 1) G (Kn 1) 0 ; N) ɛ + e N F (Kn 1) G (Kn 1) 0 ɛ(1 + e N+K C(K 1, n, N)). However, by the choice of G 0 and the definition of G, F G 0 (a n ) F G 0 + G G 0 < C(K 1, n, N) ɛ + H b n,kn 1 G (Kn 1) 0 (a n ). Hence, by combining the above inequalities (and also using the fact that C(K 1, n, N) 1 ), we finally obtain that F G < C(K 1, n, N) ɛ + N 2K (2K 2 + 1) K ɛ (1 + e N+K C(K 1, n, N)) C(K 1.n, N)(1 + 2N 2K (2K 2 + 1) K e N+K ) ɛ = C(K, n, N) ɛ, as required. We shall also require the following lemma and definition. Lemma 4. Let V := {f B : C > 1 4, x R, f (1) (x) C e x }. Then V is open in B. Proof. Let f V. Choose C > 1 such that x R, f (1) (x) C e x. 4 Let C = 4C+1, so that C > Let ɛ = (C 1) 1, so that ɛ > e I claim that if g B and g f < ɛ, then g V, thus establishing the lemma. Indeed, we have by Lemma 2 that ɛ > g f e 1 g (1) f (1) and so x R, g (1) (x) f (1) (x) e ɛ e x. Hence, x R, g (1) (x) f (1) (x) e ɛ e x C e x e ɛ e x = C e x, which shows that g V as required. Definition 1. With V as in the statement of Lemma 4, we set V := {f V : f(0) = 0, f(1) = 1 and f[r] R}. 8

9 V is not empty. For example φ 0 V where, for z C, φ 0 (z) := (e e 1 ) 1 (e z e z ). Notice also that if f V and g := f R then g : R R is a real analytic function satisfying g(0) = 0, g(1) = 1 and g (1) (x) 1 for all x R. In 4 particular, g is monotonically increasing and bijective. Further, since convergence with respect to our norm on B certainly implies pointwise convergence, and because of lemma 2, it follows that the same is also true of a function g = f R with f only assumed to lie in the closure (in B) of V. 5 Completion of the proof of Theorem 2 Recall the situation: F is a countable collection of restricted analytic functions (closed under differentiation), A denotes the structure R; F and B is a countable elementary substructure of A. We denote the language of B + by L +, ie. L + is the language of the structure A (or B) together with a new constant symbol c b for each element b of B, where B = dom(b). We are also given a countable elementary substructure G of R; 0, 1, <, + with dom(g) = G, say. Let L + 0 denote the language L + {F i : i 1}, where each F i is a unary function symbol, and let L + 1 denote the language L + 0 {π}, where π is a binary function symbol. If φ : R R is any analytic bijection, then A φ denotes the L + 1 -expansion of A in which F i is interpreted as the i th derivative φ (i) of φ (for i 1) and π by the function φ : R 2 R : x, y φ 1 (φ(x) + φ(y)). Our aim, then, is to construct φ so that are satisfied (for A = A φ and B the (unique) expansion of B to an L + 1 -substructure of A ). As we have already indicated, φ will be the (restriction to R of the) limit in the space B of a Cauchy sequence whose terms lie in V. (Here, and henceforth, V and V denote the sets defined in the statement of Lemma 4 and Definition 1 respectively.) Then 3.1,3.2 and 3.3 will be satisfied by the remarks at the end of the previous section. For 3.4 and 3.5 we require the following definition and lemma. Definition 2. Suppose that ψ B, that Q is a positive integer and that B is a finite subset of B containing 0 and 1. Then ψ is called B, Q -correct if ψ V and, for each b B, ψ(b) G and, for i = 1,..., Q 1, ψ (i) (b) B. Lemma 5. With the notation and assumptions of Definition 2, let ψ be B, Q -correct. Let ɛ > 0 be small enough so that θ B, θ ψ < ɛ 9

10 implies θ V (cf. Lemma 4). Then for any Q N, a B and g G, (i) there is ψ 0 B such that ψ 0 is B {a}, Q -correct, and (ii) there is ψ 1 V and b 0 B such that ψ 1 (b 0 ) = g. Further, for k = 0, 1 we have ψ k ψ < ɛ and, for each b B and j < Q, (b) = ψ(j) (b). ψ (j) k Proof. (i) We may assume that Q > Q and a / B. Say B = {a 1,..., a n 1 } (with the a i s distinct) and write a n for a. Choose N N so that a i N and a i a j N 1 for 1 i, j n with i j. Let C = C(nQ, n, N) (cf Lemma 3). For i = 1,..., n 1, j < Q let b i,j := ψ (j) (a i ) and for Q j < Q choose b i,j B so that ψ (j) (a i ) b i,j < ɛ (using the denseness C of B in R ). Similarly, choose b n,0 G and b n,1,..., b n,q 1 B so that ψ (j) (a n ) b n,j < ɛ for j < C Q. The existence of the required ψ 0 B now follows readily from Lemma 3 and our hypothesis on ɛ. (ii) By the argument at the end of section 4, ψ is surjective, so there exists a R with ψ(a) = g. If a B we may take ψ 1 = ψ. Otherwise, choose N N so large that b N and b b N 1, for all b, b B {a} with b b. Now let C = C(nQ, n, 2N), where n = B + 1, and choose b 0 B to satisfy a b 0 < (2N) 1 and g ψ(b 0 ) < ɛ, and proceed as in (i) to obtain C the desired ψ 1 with ψ 1 (b 0 ) = g. We now state and prove the crucial correction lemma which will allow us to cope with the requirement 3.6. Lemma 6. Let Φ(v 1,..., v m ) be a quantifier-free formula of L + 1 and suppose that B is a finite subset of B containing, as well as 0 and 1, all those elements b of B for which the constant symbol c b occurs in Φ. Suppose further that Q 1 is a natural number greater than all those i 1 such that the function symbol F i occurs in Φ. Now let ψ V be a B, Q -correct function such that the formula Φ(v 1,..., v m ) is satisfiable in the structure A ψ and let ɛ be a positive real number. Then there exists ψ 0 V such that (i) ψ ψ 0 < ɛ, (ii) ψ (j) 0 (b) = ψ (j) (b) for all b B and j < Q, and 10

11 (iii) there exist b 1,..., b m B such that ψ 0 is B {b 1,..., b m }, Q -correct and A ψ0 Φ[b 1,..., b m ]. Proof. We may suppose, by the usual tricks of introducing variables, that Φ has the form (Φ 1 Φ 2 ) Φ 3, where Φ 1 is a quantifier-free L + -formula, Φ 2 is a conjunction of formulas of the form F j (x) = y for 1 j < Q, and Φ 3 is a conjunction of formulas of the form π(x, y) = z, where x, y, z {v 1,..., v m } {c b : b B }. (We are also using the hypotheses on Q and B here.) Notice that such a form of representation of a formula is stable under identification of variables and under substitution of a constant symbol c b (with b B ) for a variable. Hence we may assume (by a suitable inductive hypothesis on m) that Φ(v 1,..., v m ) is satisfied in the structure A ψ by some α 1,..., α m R m with α i / B for i = 1,..., m and α i α j for 1 i, j m, i j. Having fixed such α 1,..., α m, choose N 1 so that a N and a a N 1 for all a, a B {α 1,..., α m } with a a. We now transform Φ 2 (v 1,..., v m ) into a quantifier-free L + -formula in the variables v i, u i,j (for 1 i m, 1 j < Q), Φ 2(v 1,..., v m, ū) say, as follows. Firstly, replace each occurrence of F j (c b ) (for 1 j < Q, b B ) in Φ 2 by the constant symbol c β, where β = ψ (j) (b). (Notice that β B by the B, Q -correctness of ψ.) Secondly, replace each occurrence of F j (v i ) (for 1 j < Q, 1 i m) by the new variable u i,j. Then clearly we have: (*) for any θ V satisfying θ (j) (b) = ψ (j) (b) for all b B and j = 1,..., Q 1, and any γ 1,..., γ m R, A θ (Φ 1 Φ 2 )[γ 1,..., γ m ] A + (Φ 1 Φ 2)[γ 1,..., γ m, δ] where δ denotes the m(q 1)-tuple with i, j -th entry δ i,j := θ (j) (γ i ) (for 1 i m, 1 j < Q), and A + is the natural expansion of A to an L + - structure. In particular, by applying (*) with θ = ψ, γ i = α i and (hence) δ i,j = ψ (j) (α i ) (for 1 i m and 1 j < Q), it follows that for arbitrarily small boxes R mq containing the point α 1,..., α m, δ and having corners in B mq, we have A + v 1,..., v m, ū (Φ 1 Φ 2)(v 1,..., v m, ū). 11

12 But we may transfer this L + -sentence to B + (since B + A + ) and hence obtain a sequence of points α (p) 1,..., α m (p), δ (p) B mq converging to α 1,..., α m, δ as p and each witnessing (in B +, and so in A + ) the formula (Φ 1 Φ 2). Notice also that for each i = 1,..., m, and j = 1,..., Q 1, ψ (j) (α (p) i ) δ (p) i,j 0 as p. As for the formula Φ 3 (v 1,..., v m ), this may be regarded, as it stands, as a formula of the language of the structure R := R; 0, 1, <, +, g g G and we may interpret the function symbol π by + (ie. the usual addition function on R) and the constant symbols c b (for b B ) as ψ(b). (Notice that ψ(b) G for such b by the B, Q -correctness of ψ.) Then, since x ψ y = z if and only if ψ(x) + ψ(y) = ψ(z) (for any x, y, z R), we have (**) for any θ V satisfying θ(b) = ψ(b) for all b B, and any γ 1,..., γ m R, A θ Φ 3 [γ 1,..., γ m ] R Φ 3 [ψ(γ 1 ),..., ψ(γ m )]. Thus,by a similar argument to that following (*) above (except that this time we use the fact that G; g g G R, as given by the hypothesis of Theorem 2), we obtain a sequence of points g (p) 1,..., g m (p) G m converging to ψ(α 1 ),..., ψ(α m ) as p and satisfying in G; g g G, and so also in R, the formula Φ 3. Notice that for each i = 1,..., m, ψ(α (p) i ) g (p) i 0 as p. We now proceed as in the proof of Lemma 5: we let m = B, C = C((m + m ) Q, m + m, 2N) (cf. Lemma 3) and we choose p large enough so that for each i = 1,..., m and j = 1,..., Q 1 we have that ψ (j) (α (p) i ) δ (p) i,j < ɛ and ψ(α(p) C i ) g (p) i < ɛ. We may suppose further C that a 2N and that a a (2N) 1 for a, a B {α (p) 1,..., α m (p) }, a a. Having fixed such a p we now apply Lemma 3, taking {a 1,..., a n } to be B {α (p) 1,..., α m (p) } (keeping the values ψ (j) (b) fixed for b B, j < Q), to obtain a function ψ 0 B satisfying (i) ψ ψ 0 < ɛ, (ii) ψ (j) 0 (b) = ψ (j) (b) for b B, j = 0,..., Q 1, (iii) ψ (j) 0 (α (p) i ) = δ (p) i,j for i = 1,..., m, j = 1,..., Q 1, and (iv) ψ 0 (α (p) i ) = g (p) i for i = 1,..., m. If we now apply (*) and (**) with θ = ψ 0 and γ i = α (p) i for i = 1,..., m, 12

13 we see from (ii), (iii) and (iv) that A ψ0 ((Φ 1 Φ 2 ) Φ 3 )[α (p) 1,..., α m (p) ] and that ψ 0 is B {α (p) 1,..., α m (p) }, Q -correct, as required. Now to complete the proof of Theorem 2 we let E denote the collection of all quantifier-free fromulas of L + 1 and fix an enumeration, Φ n, a n, g n : n 1 say, of the set E B G. Suppose that the variables occuring in the formula Φ n are amongst v 1,..., v mn. Pick φ 0 V (cf. the remark following Definition 1) and choose ɛ 0 > 0 so small that θ V whenever θ B and φ 0 θ < ɛ 0 (cf. Lemma 4). Let B 0 = {0, 1}, Q 0 = 1. Our aim is to construct inductively a sequence φ n : n N of elements of V, finite subsets B 0 B 1 B n of B and integers Q 0 < Q 1 < < Q n <, such that for each n 0 properties (1) n -(7) n below hold. At this point it is convenient to introduce the notation θ 1 θ 2 (mod B, Q), where θ 1, θ 2 B, B B and Q is a positive integer, to mean that θ (j) 1 (b) = θ (j) 2 (b) for each b B and j < Q. (1) n for all b B, if the constant symbol c b occurs in Φ n then b B n ; (2) n for all j 1, if the function symbol F j occurs in Φ n the j < Q n ; (3) n a n B n and φ 1 n (g n ) B n ; (4) n φ n is B n, Q n -correct; (5) n φ n 1 φ n < 2 ɛ 0 3 n ; (6) n φ n φ n 1 (mod B n 1, Q n 1 ); (7) n either for no θ V with φ n θ < ɛ 0 3 n and θ φ n (mod B n, Q n ) is Φ n satisfiable in the structure A θ, or else there exist b 1,..., b mn B n such that A φn Φ n [b 1,..., b mn ]. Now notice that all these conditions hold when n = 0 (mostly vacuously so). So suppose that φ n, B n and Q n have been constructed to satisfy (1) n -(7) n for some n 0. We proceed to construct φ n+1, B n+1 and Q n+1 as follows. Firstly, by repeated use of Lemma 5 (using sufficiently small ɛ s) we may find B n+1 B n, Q n+1 > Q n so that (1) n+1 -(3) n+1 hold, and a function ψ V such that φ n ψ < ɛ 0 3 n 2, ψ is B n+1, Q n+1 -correct and ψ φ n (mod B n, Q n ). (We are using (4) n here.) 13

14 Now if there is no θ V with ψ θ < ɛ 0 3 n 1 and θ ψ (mod B n+1, Q n+1 ) such that Φ n+1 is satisfiable in A θ, then we may set φ n+1 = ψ and (1) n+1 -(7) n+1 are clearly satisfied. Otherwise, choose such a θ. Then we may apply Lemma 6 to obtain a function φ n+1 V such that θ φ n+1 < ɛ 0 3 n 2, φ n+1 θ (mod B n+1, Q n+1 ) and such that there exist b 1,..., b mn B with A φn+1 Φ n [b 1,..., b mn ]. Further, φ n+1 is B n+1 {b 1,..., b mn }, Q n+1 -correct. So if we replace B n+1 by B n+1 {b 1,..., b mn } then (1) n+1 -(4) n+1, (6) n+1 and (7) n+1 are immediate. For (5) n+1 we have φ n+1 φ n φ n θ + θ ψ + ψ φ n < ɛ 0 3 n 2 + ɛ 0 3 n 1 + ɛ 0 3 n 2 < 2 ɛ 0 3 (n+1), which indeed gives (5) n+1 and completes the inductive construction. Now the properties (5) n clearly imply that φ n : n N is a Cauchy sequence in B (consisting of elements of V ) and hence converges to some φ B. By the remarks at the end of Section 4 it follows that the restriction of φ to R satisfies Further, by the properties (6) n these same remarks imply (*) for all n N, φ φ n (mod B n, Q n ). Hence (by the properties (3) n, (4) n ) φ also satisfies 3.5. Finally, to see that φ satisfies 3.6, we require a calculation. For n N let ɛ n := 2 ɛ 0 3 (n+1) φ n φ n+1 so that ɛ n > 0 by (5) n+1. Then for m, n N with m > n we have φ n φ m i=n φ i φ i+1 + φ m+1 φ ɛ n + 2 ɛ 0 m i=n 3 (i+1) + φ m+1 φ (by (5) n+1,..., (5) m+1 ) ɛ n + ɛ 0 3 n (by letting m ). Hence (**) for all n N, φ n φ < ɛ 0 3 n. Notice that by setting n = 0 here it follows, by the definition of ɛ 0, that φ V (so φ V ). Now consider an arbitrary quantifier-free formula of L it will be Φ n (v 1,..., v mn ) for some n - and suppose that it is satisfiable in the structure A φ. By applying (7) n with θ = φ, it follows from (*) and (**) (and the comment following (**)) that A φn Φ n [b 1,..., b mn ] for some b 1,..., b mn B n. But by (1) n, 14

15 (2) n and (*) this clearly implies that A φ Φ n [b 1,..., b mn ]. This establishes 3.6 (recall the comments at the beginning of this section) and completes the proof of the main theorem. References [1] L van den Dries, Remarks on Tarski s problem concerning R, +,, exp, Logic colloquium 1982, North Holland, 1984, [2] M Edmundo, Structure theorems for o-minimal expansions of groups, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 102 (2000), [3] A Gabrielov, Projections of semianalytic sets, Funct. Anal. Appl. 2 (1968), [4] A Gabrielov, Complements of subanalytic sets and existential formulas for analytic functions, Inv. Math. 125 (1996), [5] D Marker,Y Peterzil and A Pillay, Additive reducts of real closed fields, J Symb Logic 57 (1992), [6] C Miller and S Starchenko, A growth dichotomy for o-minimal expansions of ordered groups, TAMS 350 (1998), [7] Y Peterzil, A structure theorem for semibounded sets in the reals, J. Symb. Logic 57 (1992), [8] Y Peterzil, Reducts of some structures over the reals, J. Symb. Logic 58 (1993), [9] Y Peterzil and S Starchenko, On torsion-free groups in o-minimal structures, preprint (September,2003). [10] A Pillay,P Scowcroft and C Steinhorn, Between groups and rings, Rocky Mountain J of Math. 19(3) 1989, [11] A Pillay and C Steinhorn, Definable sets in ordered structures,i, TAMS 295 (1986), [12] R Poston, Defining multiplication in o-minimal expansions of the positive reals, J. Symb. Logic 60 (1995),

16 [13] R Remmert, Classical topics in complex function theory, Springer, [14] A Strzebonski, One-dimensional groups definable in o-minimal structures, J. Pure and Applied Algebra 96 (1994),

An introduction to o-minimality

An introduction to o-minimality An introduction to o-minimality Notes by Tom Foster and Marcello Mamino on lectures given by Alex Wilkie at the MODNET summer school, Berlin, September 2007 1 Introduction Throughout these notes definable

More information

MASTERS EXAMINATION IN MATHEMATICS SOLUTIONS

MASTERS EXAMINATION IN MATHEMATICS SOLUTIONS MASTERS EXAMINATION IN MATHEMATICS PURE MATHEMATICS OPTION SPRING 010 SOLUTIONS Algebra A1. Let F be a finite field. Prove that F [x] contains infinitely many prime ideals. Solution: The ring F [x] of

More information

VC-DENSITY FOR TREES

VC-DENSITY FOR TREES VC-DENSITY FOR TREES ANTON BOBKOV Abstract. We show that for the theory of infinite trees we have vc(n) = n for all n. VC density was introduced in [1] by Aschenbrenner, Dolich, Haskell, MacPherson, and

More information

MATH 722, COMPLEX ANALYSIS, SPRING 2009 PART 5

MATH 722, COMPLEX ANALYSIS, SPRING 2009 PART 5 MATH 722, COMPLEX ANALYSIS, SPRING 2009 PART 5.. The Arzela-Ascoli Theorem.. The Riemann mapping theorem Let X be a metric space, and let F be a family of continuous complex-valued functions on X. We have

More information

INTRODUCTION TO REAL ANALYTIC GEOMETRY

INTRODUCTION TO REAL ANALYTIC GEOMETRY INTRODUCTION TO REAL ANALYTIC GEOMETRY KRZYSZTOF KURDYKA 1. Analytic functions in several variables 1.1. Summable families. Let (E, ) be a normed space over the field R or C, dim E

More information

MASTERS EXAMINATION IN MATHEMATICS

MASTERS EXAMINATION IN MATHEMATICS MASTERS EXAMINATION IN MATHEMATICS PURE MATH OPTION, Spring 018 Full points can be obtained for correct answers to 8 questions. Each numbered question (which may have several parts) is worth 0 points.

More information

A SIMPLE PROOF OF THE MARKER-STEINHORN THEOREM FOR EXPANSIONS OF ORDERED ABELIAN GROUPS

A SIMPLE PROOF OF THE MARKER-STEINHORN THEOREM FOR EXPANSIONS OF ORDERED ABELIAN GROUPS A SIMPLE PROOF OF THE MARKER-STEINHORN THEOREM FOR EXPANSIONS OF ORDERED ABELIAN GROUPS ERIK WALSBERG Abstract. We give a short and self-contained proof of the Marker- Steinhorn Theorem for o-minimal expansions

More information

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007)

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω 0. Introduction David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007) In its simplest form the Löwenheim-Skolem Theorem for L ω1 ω states that if σ L ω1

More information

Representing Scott Sets in Algebraic Settings

Representing Scott Sets in Algebraic Settings Representing Scott Sets in Algebraic Settings Alf Dolich Kingsborough Community College Julia F. Knight University of Notre Dame Karen Lange Wellesley College David Marker University of Illinois at Chicago

More information

VAUGHT S THEOREM: THE FINITE SPECTRUM OF COMPLETE THEORIES IN ℵ 0. Contents

VAUGHT S THEOREM: THE FINITE SPECTRUM OF COMPLETE THEORIES IN ℵ 0. Contents VAUGHT S THEOREM: THE FINITE SPECTRUM OF COMPLETE THEORIES IN ℵ 0 BENJAMIN LEDEAUX Abstract. This expository paper introduces model theory with a focus on countable models of complete theories. Vaught

More information

MATH FINAL EXAM REVIEW HINTS

MATH FINAL EXAM REVIEW HINTS MATH 109 - FINAL EXAM REVIEW HINTS Answer: Answer: 1. Cardinality (1) Let a < b be two real numbers and define f : (0, 1) (a, b) by f(t) = (1 t)a + tb. (a) Prove that f is a bijection. (b) Prove that any

More information

Chapter 3: Baire category and open mapping theorems

Chapter 3: Baire category and open mapping theorems MA3421 2016 17 Chapter 3: Baire category and open mapping theorems A number of the major results rely on completeness via the Baire category theorem. 3.1 The Baire category theorem 3.1.1 Definition. A

More information

GROUPS DEFINABLE IN O-MINIMAL STRUCTURES

GROUPS DEFINABLE IN O-MINIMAL STRUCTURES GROUPS DEFINABLE IN O-MINIMAL STRUCTURES PANTELIS E. ELEFTHERIOU Abstract. In this series of lectures, we will a) introduce the basics of o- minimality, b) describe the manifold topology of groups definable

More information

Commutative Banach algebras 79

Commutative Banach algebras 79 8. Commutative Banach algebras In this chapter, we analyze commutative Banach algebras in greater detail. So we always assume that xy = yx for all x, y A here. Definition 8.1. Let A be a (commutative)

More information

PRESERVATION THEOREMS IN LUKASIEWICZ MODEL THEORY

PRESERVATION THEOREMS IN LUKASIEWICZ MODEL THEORY Iranian Journal of Fuzzy Systems Vol. 10, No. 3, (2013) pp. 103-113 103 PRESERVATION THEOREMS IN LUKASIEWICZ MODEL THEORY S. M. BAGHERI AND M. MONIRI Abstract. We present some model theoretic results for

More information

Real Analysis Math 131AH Rudin, Chapter #1. Dominique Abdi

Real Analysis Math 131AH Rudin, Chapter #1. Dominique Abdi Real Analysis Math 3AH Rudin, Chapter # Dominique Abdi.. If r is rational (r 0) and x is irrational, prove that r + x and rx are irrational. Solution. Assume the contrary, that r+x and rx are rational.

More information

Representing Scott Sets in Algebraic Settings

Representing Scott Sets in Algebraic Settings Wellesley College Wellesley College Digital Scholarship and Archive Faculty Research and Scholarship 8-2015 Representing Scott Sets in Algebraic Settings Alf Dolich Julia F. Knight Karen Lange klange2@wellesley.edu

More information

Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra

Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra D. R. Wilkins Contents 3 Topics in Commutative Algebra 2 3.1 Rings and Fields......................... 2 3.2 Ideals...............................

More information

MAT1000 ASSIGNMENT 1. a k 3 k. x =

MAT1000 ASSIGNMENT 1. a k 3 k. x = MAT1000 ASSIGNMENT 1 VITALY KUZNETSOV Question 1 (Exercise 2 on page 37). Tne Cantor set C can also be described in terms of ternary expansions. (a) Every number in [0, 1] has a ternary expansion x = a

More information

Solutions to Unique Readability Homework Set 30 August 2011

Solutions to Unique Readability Homework Set 30 August 2011 s to Unique Readability Homework Set 30 August 2011 In the problems below L is a signature and X is a set of variables. Problem 0. Define a function λ from the set of finite nonempty sequences of elements

More information

2.2 Lowenheim-Skolem-Tarski theorems

2.2 Lowenheim-Skolem-Tarski theorems Logic SEP: Day 1 July 15, 2013 1 Some references Syllabus: http://www.math.wisc.edu/graduate/guide-qe Previous years qualifying exams: http://www.math.wisc.edu/ miller/old/qual/index.html Miller s Moore

More information

AN INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY THEORY

AN INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY THEORY AN INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY THEORY SALMAN SIDDIQI Abstract. In this paper, we will introduce some of the most basic concepts in geometric stability theory, and attempt to state a dichotomy theorem

More information

Introduction to Model Theory

Introduction to Model Theory Introduction to Model Theory Charles Steinhorn, Vassar College Katrin Tent, University of Münster CIRM, January 8, 2018 The three lectures Introduction to basic model theory Focus on Definability More

More information

Posets, homomorphisms and homogeneity

Posets, homomorphisms and homogeneity Posets, homomorphisms and homogeneity Peter J. Cameron and D. Lockett School of Mathematical Sciences Queen Mary, University of London Mile End Road London E1 4NS, U.K. Abstract Jarik Nešetřil suggested

More information

Math 320-2: Midterm 2 Practice Solutions Northwestern University, Winter 2015

Math 320-2: Midterm 2 Practice Solutions Northwestern University, Winter 2015 Math 30-: Midterm Practice Solutions Northwestern University, Winter 015 1. Give an example of each of the following. No justification is needed. (a) A metric on R with respect to which R is bounded. (b)

More information

Limit computable integer parts

Limit computable integer parts Limit computable integer parts Paola D Aquino, Julia Knight, and Karen Lange July 12, 2010 Abstract Let R be a real closed field. An integer part I for R is a discretely ordered subring such that for every

More information

METRIC HEIGHTS ON AN ABELIAN GROUP

METRIC HEIGHTS ON AN ABELIAN GROUP ROCKY MOUNTAIN JOURNAL OF MATHEMATICS Volume 44, Number 6, 2014 METRIC HEIGHTS ON AN ABELIAN GROUP CHARLES L. SAMUELS ABSTRACT. Suppose mα) denotes the Mahler measure of the non-zero algebraic number α.

More information

FREMLIN TENSOR PRODUCTS OF CONCAVIFICATIONS OF BANACH LATTICES

FREMLIN TENSOR PRODUCTS OF CONCAVIFICATIONS OF BANACH LATTICES FREMLIN TENSOR PRODUCTS OF CONCAVIFICATIONS OF BANACH LATTICES VLADIMIR G. TROITSKY AND OMID ZABETI Abstract. Suppose that E is a uniformly complete vector lattice and p 1,..., p n are positive reals.

More information

Department of Mathematics, University of California, Berkeley. GRADUATE PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION, Part A Fall Semester 2016

Department of Mathematics, University of California, Berkeley. GRADUATE PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION, Part A Fall Semester 2016 Department of Mathematics, University of California, Berkeley YOUR 1 OR 2 DIGIT EXAM NUMBER GRADUATE PRELIMINARY EXAMINATION, Part A Fall Semester 2016 1. Please write your 1- or 2-digit exam number on

More information

Continued fractions for complex numbers and values of binary quadratic forms

Continued fractions for complex numbers and values of binary quadratic forms arxiv:110.3754v1 [math.nt] 18 Feb 011 Continued fractions for complex numbers and values of binary quadratic forms S.G. Dani and Arnaldo Nogueira February 1, 011 Abstract We describe various properties

More information

Metric Spaces and Topology

Metric Spaces and Topology Chapter 2 Metric Spaces and Topology From an engineering perspective, the most important way to construct a topology on a set is to define the topology in terms of a metric on the set. This approach underlies

More information

PRIME NUMBER THEOREM

PRIME NUMBER THEOREM PRIME NUMBER THEOREM RYAN LIU Abstract. Prime numbers have always been seen as the building blocks of all integers, but their behavior and distribution are often puzzling. The prime number theorem gives

More information

Introduction to Bases in Banach Spaces

Introduction to Bases in Banach Spaces Introduction to Bases in Banach Spaces Matt Daws June 5, 2005 Abstract We introduce the notion of Schauder bases in Banach spaces, aiming to be able to give a statement of, and make sense of, the Gowers

More information

Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005

Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005 Instructions: Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005 If you signed up for Computability Theory, do two E and two C problems. If you signed up for Model Theory, do two E and two M problems. If you signed up

More information

On expansions of the real field by complex subgroups

On expansions of the real field by complex subgroups On expansions of the real field by complex subgroups University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign July 21, 2016 Previous work Expansions of the real field R by subgroups of C have been studied previously.

More information

Topological properties of Z p and Q p and Euclidean models

Topological properties of Z p and Q p and Euclidean models Topological properties of Z p and Q p and Euclidean models Samuel Trautwein, Esther Röder, Giorgio Barozzi November 3, 20 Topology of Q p vs Topology of R Both R and Q p are normed fields and complete

More information

MASTERS EXAMINATION IN MATHEMATICS

MASTERS EXAMINATION IN MATHEMATICS MASTERS EXAMINATION IN MATHEMATICS PURE MATHEMATICS OPTION FALL 2007 Full points can be obtained for correct answers to 8 questions. Each numbered question (which may have several parts) is worth the same

More information

Geometry of subanalytic and semialgebraic sets, by M. Shiota, Birkhäuser, Boston, MA, 1997, xii+431 pp., $89.50, ISBN

Geometry of subanalytic and semialgebraic sets, by M. Shiota, Birkhäuser, Boston, MA, 1997, xii+431 pp., $89.50, ISBN BULLETIN (New Series) OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 36, Number 4, ages 523 527 S 0273-0979(99)00793-4 Article electronically published on July 27, 1999 Geometry of subanalytic and semialgebraic

More information

RIEMANN MAPPING THEOREM

RIEMANN MAPPING THEOREM RIEMANN MAPPING THEOREM VED V. DATAR Recall that two domains are called conformally equivalent if there exists a holomorphic bijection from one to the other. This automatically implies that there is an

More information

ISAAC GOLDBRING AND THOMAS SINCLAIR

ISAAC GOLDBRING AND THOMAS SINCLAIR ON THE AXIOMATIZABILITY OF C -ALGEBRAS AS OPERATOR SYSTEMS ISAAC GOLDBRING AND THOMAS SINCLAIR Abstract. We show that the class of unital C -algebras is an elementary class in the language of operator

More information

Exercise Solutions to Functional Analysis

Exercise Solutions to Functional Analysis Exercise Solutions to Functional Analysis Note: References refer to M. Schechter, Principles of Functional Analysis Exersize that. Let φ,..., φ n be an orthonormal set in a Hilbert space H. Show n f n

More information

NOTES ON O-MINIMALITY

NOTES ON O-MINIMALITY NOTES ON O-MINIMALITY 1. O-minimality In what follows, < is a binary relation symbol and L ord is the language with just this symbol, that is to say, L ord is the language of ordered structures. We will

More information

* 8 Groups, with Appendix containing Rings and Fields.

* 8 Groups, with Appendix containing Rings and Fields. * 8 Groups, with Appendix containing Rings and Fields Binary Operations Definition We say that is a binary operation on a set S if, and only if, a, b, a b S Implicit in this definition is the idea that

More information

MORLEY S CATEGORICITY THEOREM

MORLEY S CATEGORICITY THEOREM MORLEY S CATEGORICITY THEOREM NICK RAMSEY Abstract. A theory is called κ-categorical, or categorical in power κ, if it has one model up to isomorphism of cardinality κ. Morley s Categoricity Theorem states

More information

Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory

Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory Department of Mathematics Bachelor Thesis (7.5 ECTS) Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory Author: Dionijs van Tuijl Supervisor: Dr. Jaap van Oosten June 15, 2016 Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 Preliminaries

More information

MODEL THEORY FOR ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY

MODEL THEORY FOR ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY MODEL THEORY FOR ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY VICTOR ZHANG Abstract. We demonstrate how several problems of algebraic geometry, i.e. Ax-Grothendieck, Hilbert s Nullstellensatz, Noether- Ostrowski, and Hilbert s

More information

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory Part V 7 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets Lebesgue Integration Theory Definition 7. (Preliminary). A measure on a set is a function :2 [ ] such that. () = 2. If { } = is a finite

More information

WEIERSTRASS THEOREMS AND RINGS OF HOLOMORPHIC FUNCTIONS

WEIERSTRASS THEOREMS AND RINGS OF HOLOMORPHIC FUNCTIONS WEIERSTRASS THEOREMS AND RINGS OF HOLOMORPHIC FUNCTIONS YIFEI ZHAO Contents. The Weierstrass factorization theorem 2. The Weierstrass preparation theorem 6 3. The Weierstrass division theorem 8 References

More information

08a. Operators on Hilbert spaces. 1. Boundedness, continuity, operator norms

08a. Operators on Hilbert spaces. 1. Boundedness, continuity, operator norms (February 24, 2017) 08a. Operators on Hilbert spaces Paul Garrett garrett@math.umn.edu http://www.math.umn.edu/ garrett/ [This document is http://www.math.umn.edu/ garrett/m/real/notes 2016-17/08a-ops

More information

Categoricity Without Equality

Categoricity Without Equality Categoricity Without Equality H. Jerome Keisler and Arnold W. Miller Abstract We study categoricity in power for reduced models of first order logic without equality. 1 Introduction The object of this

More information

tp(c/a) tp(c/ab) T h(m M ) is assumed in the background.

tp(c/a) tp(c/ab) T h(m M ) is assumed in the background. Model Theory II. 80824 22.10.2006-22.01-2007 (not: 17.12) Time: The first meeting will be on SUNDAY, OCT. 22, 10-12, room 209. We will try to make this time change permanent. Please write ehud@math.huji.ac.il

More information

Fundamentals of Model Theory

Fundamentals of Model Theory Fundamentals of Model Theory William Weiss and Cherie D Mello Department of Mathematics University of Toronto c 2015 W.Weiss and C. D Mello 1 Introduction Model Theory is the part of mathematics which

More information

Basic counting techniques. Periklis A. Papakonstantinou Rutgers Business School

Basic counting techniques. Periklis A. Papakonstantinou Rutgers Business School Basic counting techniques Periklis A. Papakonstantinou Rutgers Business School i LECTURE NOTES IN Elementary counting methods Periklis A. Papakonstantinou MSIS, Rutgers Business School ALL RIGHTS RESERVED

More information

4.6 Montel's Theorem. Robert Oeckl CA NOTES 7 17/11/2009 1

4.6 Montel's Theorem. Robert Oeckl CA NOTES 7 17/11/2009 1 Robert Oeckl CA NOTES 7 17/11/2009 1 4.6 Montel's Theorem Let X be a topological space. We denote by C(X) the set of complex valued continuous functions on X. Denition 4.26. A topological space is called

More information

Margulis Superrigidity I & II

Margulis Superrigidity I & II Margulis Superrigidity I & II Alastair Litterick 1,2 and Yuri Santos Rego 1 Universität Bielefeld 1 and Ruhr-Universität Bochum 2 Block seminar on arithmetic groups and rigidity Universität Bielefeld 22nd

More information

Lecture 2: Syntax. January 24, 2018

Lecture 2: Syntax. January 24, 2018 Lecture 2: Syntax January 24, 2018 We now review the basic definitions of first-order logic in more detail. Recall that a language consists of a collection of symbols {P i }, each of which has some specified

More information

Math 396. Quotient spaces

Math 396. Quotient spaces Math 396. Quotient spaces. Definition Let F be a field, V a vector space over F and W V a subspace of V. For v, v V, we say that v v mod W if and only if v v W. One can readily verify that with this definition

More information

On divisibility in definable groups

On divisibility in definable groups On divisibility in definable groups Margarita Otero Departamento de Matemáticas Universidad Autónoma de Madrid 28049 Madrid, Spain margarita.otero@uam.es December 10, 2008 Abstract Let M be an o minimal

More information

Properties of O-minimal Exponential Fields

Properties of O-minimal Exponential Fields 1 Universität Konstanz, Fachbereich Mathematik und Statistik 11 September 2017 19th ÖMG Congress and Annual DMV Meeting 1 Supported by DVMLG-Nachwuchsstipendium 1 Preliminary Notions 2 Decidability of

More information

FINITE MODEL THEORY (MATH 285D, UCLA, WINTER 2017) LECTURE NOTES IN PROGRESS

FINITE MODEL THEORY (MATH 285D, UCLA, WINTER 2017) LECTURE NOTES IN PROGRESS FINITE MODEL THEORY (MATH 285D, UCLA, WINTER 2017) LECTURE NOTES IN PROGRESS ARTEM CHERNIKOV 1. Intro Motivated by connections with computational complexity (mostly a part of computer scientice today).

More information

Math 259: Introduction to Analytic Number Theory Functions of finite order: product formula and logarithmic derivative

Math 259: Introduction to Analytic Number Theory Functions of finite order: product formula and logarithmic derivative Math 259: Introduction to Analytic Number Theory Functions of finite order: product formula and logarithmic derivative This chapter is another review of standard material in complex analysis. See for instance

More information

Lebesgue Measure on R n

Lebesgue Measure on R n CHAPTER 2 Lebesgue Measure on R n Our goal is to construct a notion of the volume, or Lebesgue measure, of rather general subsets of R n that reduces to the usual volume of elementary geometrical sets

More information

Definability in the Enumeration Degrees

Definability in the Enumeration Degrees Definability in the Enumeration Degrees Theodore A. Slaman W. Hugh Woodin Abstract We prove that every countable relation on the enumeration degrees, E, is uniformly definable from parameters in E. Consequently,

More information

11 COMPLEX ANALYSIS IN C. 1.1 Holomorphic Functions

11 COMPLEX ANALYSIS IN C. 1.1 Holomorphic Functions 11 COMPLEX ANALYSIS IN C 1.1 Holomorphic Functions A domain Ω in the complex plane C is a connected, open subset of C. Let z o Ω and f a map f : Ω C. We say that f is real differentiable at z o if there

More information

Math 225A Model Theory. Speirs, Martin

Math 225A Model Theory. Speirs, Martin Math 5A Model Theory Speirs, Martin Autumn 013 General Information These notes are based on a course in Metamathematics taught by Professor Thomas Scanlon at UC Berkeley in the Autumn of 013. The course

More information

Math 676. A compactness theorem for the idele group. and by the product formula it lies in the kernel (A K )1 of the continuous idelic norm

Math 676. A compactness theorem for the idele group. and by the product formula it lies in the kernel (A K )1 of the continuous idelic norm Math 676. A compactness theorem for the idele group 1. Introduction Let K be a global field, so K is naturally a discrete subgroup of the idele group A K and by the product formula it lies in the kernel

More information

Compact operators on Banach spaces

Compact operators on Banach spaces Compact operators on Banach spaces Jordan Bell jordan.bell@gmail.com Department of Mathematics, University of Toronto November 12, 2017 1 Introduction In this note I prove several things about compact

More information

MASTERS EXAMINATION IN MATHEMATICS

MASTERS EXAMINATION IN MATHEMATICS MASTERS EXAMINATION IN MATHEMATICS PURE MATHEMATICS OPTION FALL 2010 Full points can be obtained for correct answers to 8 questions. Each numbered question (which may have several parts) is worth 20 points.

More information

Walker Ray Econ 204 Problem Set 3 Suggested Solutions August 6, 2015

Walker Ray Econ 204 Problem Set 3 Suggested Solutions August 6, 2015 Problem 1. Take any mapping f from a metric space X into a metric space Y. Prove that f is continuous if and only if f(a) f(a). (Hint: use the closed set characterization of continuity). I make use of

More information

CHEVALLEY S THEOREM AND COMPLETE VARIETIES

CHEVALLEY S THEOREM AND COMPLETE VARIETIES CHEVALLEY S THEOREM AND COMPLETE VARIETIES BRIAN OSSERMAN In this note, we introduce the concept which plays the role of compactness for varieties completeness. We prove that completeness can be characterized

More information

2 Lecture 2: Logical statements and proof by contradiction Lecture 10: More on Permutations, Group Homomorphisms 31

2 Lecture 2: Logical statements and proof by contradiction Lecture 10: More on Permutations, Group Homomorphisms 31 Contents 1 Lecture 1: Introduction 2 2 Lecture 2: Logical statements and proof by contradiction 7 3 Lecture 3: Induction and Well-Ordering Principle 11 4 Lecture 4: Definition of a Group and examples 15

More information

On the strong cell decomposition property for weakly o-minimal structures

On the strong cell decomposition property for weakly o-minimal structures On the strong cell decomposition property for weakly o-minimal structures Roman Wencel 1 Instytut Matematyczny Uniwersytetu Wroc lawskiego ABSTRACT We consider a class of weakly o-minimal structures admitting

More information

Partial Collapses of the Σ 1 Complexity Hierarchy in Models for Fragments of Bounded Arithmetic

Partial Collapses of the Σ 1 Complexity Hierarchy in Models for Fragments of Bounded Arithmetic Partial Collapses of the Σ 1 Complexity Hierarchy in Models for Fragments of Bounded Arithmetic Zofia Adamowicz Institute of Mathematics, Polish Academy of Sciences Śniadeckich 8, 00-950 Warszawa, Poland

More information

Basics of Model Theory

Basics of Model Theory Chapter udf Basics of Model Theory bas.1 Reducts and Expansions mod:bas:red: defn:reduct mod:bas:red: prop:reduct Often it is useful or necessary to compare languages which have symbols in common, as well

More information

Immerse Metric Space Homework

Immerse Metric Space Homework Immerse Metric Space Homework (Exercises -2). In R n, define d(x, y) = x y +... + x n y n. Show that d is a metric that induces the usual topology. Sketch the basis elements when n = 2. Solution: Steps

More information

Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields

Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields Thomas Scanlon University of California, Berkeley 8 June 2010 Thomas Scanlon (University of California, Berkeley) Model theory, algebraic dynamics and

More information

SOLUTION TO RUBEL S QUESTION ABOUT DIFFERENTIALLY ALGEBRAIC DEPENDENCE ON INITIAL VALUES GUY KATRIEL PREPRINT NO /4

SOLUTION TO RUBEL S QUESTION ABOUT DIFFERENTIALLY ALGEBRAIC DEPENDENCE ON INITIAL VALUES GUY KATRIEL PREPRINT NO /4 SOLUTION TO RUBEL S QUESTION ABOUT DIFFERENTIALLY ALGEBRAIC DEPENDENCE ON INITIAL VALUES GUY KATRIEL PREPRINT NO. 2 2003/4 1 SOLUTION TO RUBEL S QUESTION ABOUT DIFFERENTIALLY ALGEBRAIC DEPENDENCE ON INITIAL

More information

Math 426 Homework 4 Due 3 November 2017

Math 426 Homework 4 Due 3 November 2017 Math 46 Homework 4 Due 3 November 017 1. Given a metric space X,d) and two subsets A,B, we define the distance between them, dista,b), as the infimum inf a A, b B da,b). a) Prove that if A is compact and

More information

Definable henselian valuation rings

Definable henselian valuation rings Definable henselian valuation rings Alexander Prestel Abstract We give model theoretic criteria for the existence of and - formulas in the ring language to define uniformly the valuation rings O of models

More information

BERNARD RUSSO. University of California, Irvine

BERNARD RUSSO. University of California, Irvine A HOLOMORPHIC CHARACTERIZATION OF OPERATOR ALGEBRAS (JOINT WORK WITH MATT NEAL) BERNARD RUSSO University of California, Irvine UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, IRVINE ANALYSIS SEMINAR OCTOBER 16, 2012 KEYWORDS

More information

CHAPTER 8: EXPLORING R

CHAPTER 8: EXPLORING R CHAPTER 8: EXPLORING R LECTURE NOTES FOR MATH 378 (CSUSM, SPRING 2009). WAYNE AITKEN In the previous chapter we discussed the need for a complete ordered field. The field Q is not complete, so we constructed

More information

Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers

Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers Chapter 1. Sets and Numbers 1. Sets A set is considered to be a collection of objects (elements). If A is a set and x is an element of the set A, we say x is a member of A or x belongs to A, and we write

More information

Math 328 Course Notes

Math 328 Course Notes Math 328 Course Notes Ian Robertson March 3, 2006 3 Properties of C[0, 1]: Sup-norm and Completeness In this chapter we are going to examine the vector space of all continuous functions defined on the

More information

More Model Theory Notes

More Model Theory Notes More Model Theory Notes Miscellaneous information, loosely organized. 1. Kinds of Models A countable homogeneous model M is one such that, for any partial elementary map f : A M with A M finite, and any

More information

Stanford Mathematics Department Math 205A Lecture Supplement #4 Borel Regular & Radon Measures

Stanford Mathematics Department Math 205A Lecture Supplement #4 Borel Regular & Radon Measures 2 1 Borel Regular Measures We now state and prove an important regularity property of Borel regular outer measures: Stanford Mathematics Department Math 205A Lecture Supplement #4 Borel Regular & Radon

More information

Theorems. Theorem 1.11: Greatest-Lower-Bound Property. Theorem 1.20: The Archimedean property of. Theorem 1.21: -th Root of Real Numbers

Theorems. Theorem 1.11: Greatest-Lower-Bound Property. Theorem 1.20: The Archimedean property of. Theorem 1.21: -th Root of Real Numbers Page 1 Theorems Wednesday, May 9, 2018 12:53 AM Theorem 1.11: Greatest-Lower-Bound Property Suppose is an ordered set with the least-upper-bound property Suppose, and is bounded below be the set of lower

More information

Discrete Mathematics. Benny George K. September 22, 2011

Discrete Mathematics. Benny George K. September 22, 2011 Discrete Mathematics Benny George K Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology Guwahati ben@iitg.ernet.in September 22, 2011 Set Theory Elementary Concepts Let A and

More information

Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr.

Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr. Notes for Math 290 using Introduction to Mathematical Proofs by Charles E. Roberts, Jr. Chapter : Logic Topics:. Statements, Negation, and Compound Statements.2 Truth Tables and Logical Equivalences.3

More information

First In-Class Exam Solutions Math 410, Professor David Levermore Monday, 1 October 2018

First In-Class Exam Solutions Math 410, Professor David Levermore Monday, 1 October 2018 First In-Class Exam Solutions Math 40, Professor David Levermore Monday, October 208. [0] Let {b k } k N be a sequence in R and let A be a subset of R. Write the negations of the following assertions.

More information

The constructible universe

The constructible universe The constructible universe In this set of notes I want to sketch Gödel s proof that CH is consistent with the other axioms of set theory. Gödel s argument goes well beyond this result; his identification

More information

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers Chapter 1 The Real Numbers 1.1. Some Preliminaries Discussion: The Irrationality of 2. We begin with the natural numbers N = {1, 2, 3, }. In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need

More information

Contents Ordered Fields... 2 Ordered sets and fields... 2 Construction of the Reals 1: Dedekind Cuts... 2 Metric Spaces... 3

Contents Ordered Fields... 2 Ordered sets and fields... 2 Construction of the Reals 1: Dedekind Cuts... 2 Metric Spaces... 3 Analysis Math Notes Study Guide Real Analysis Contents Ordered Fields 2 Ordered sets and fields 2 Construction of the Reals 1: Dedekind Cuts 2 Metric Spaces 3 Metric Spaces 3 Definitions 4 Separability

More information

Introduction to Arithmetic Geometry Fall 2013 Lecture #18 11/07/2013

Introduction to Arithmetic Geometry Fall 2013 Lecture #18 11/07/2013 18.782 Introduction to Arithmetic Geometry Fall 2013 Lecture #18 11/07/2013 As usual, all the rings we consider are commutative rings with an identity element. 18.1 Regular local rings Consider a local

More information

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers Chapter The Real Numbers.. Some Preliminaries Discussion: The Irrationality of 2. We begin with the natural numbers N = {, 2, 3, }. In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend

More information

Bernstein s analytic continuation of complex powers

Bernstein s analytic continuation of complex powers (April 3, 20) Bernstein s analytic continuation of complex powers Paul Garrett garrett@math.umn.edu http://www.math.umn.edu/ garrett/. Analytic continuation of distributions 2. Statement of the theorems

More information

Algebras with finite descriptions

Algebras with finite descriptions Algebras with finite descriptions André Nies The University of Auckland July 19, 2005 Part 1: FA-presentability A countable structure in a finite signature is finite-automaton presentable (or automatic)

More information

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year Part II Year 2018 2017 2016 2015 2014 2013 2012 2011 2010 2009 2008 2007 2006 2005 2018 60 Paper 4, Section II 16G State and prove the ǫ-recursion Theorem. [You may assume the Principle of ǫ- Induction.]

More information

CONSTRUCTION OF THE REAL NUMBERS.

CONSTRUCTION OF THE REAL NUMBERS. CONSTRUCTION OF THE REAL NUMBERS. IAN KIMING 1. Motivation. It will not come as a big surprise to anyone when I say that we need the real numbers in mathematics. More to the point, we need to be able to

More information

Complex Analysis Qualifying Exam Solutions

Complex Analysis Qualifying Exam Solutions Complex Analysis Qualifying Exam Solutions May, 04 Part.. Let log z be the principal branch of the logarithm defined on G = {z C z (, 0]}. Show that if t > 0, then the equation log z = t has exactly one

More information

Discriminating groups and c-dimension

Discriminating groups and c-dimension Discriminating groups and c-dimension Alexei Myasnikov Pavel Shumyatsky April 8, 2002 Abstract We prove that every linear discriminating (square-like) group is abelian and every finitely generated solvable

More information