This version will be replaced with the final typeset version in due course. Note that page numbers will change, so cite with caution.

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "This version will be replaced with the final typeset version in due course. Note that page numbers will change, so cite with caution."

Transcription

1 Semantics & Pragmatics Volume 10, Article 3, This is an version of Vasardani, Maria, Lesley Stirling & Stephan Winter The preposition at from a spatial language, cognition, and information systems perspective. Semantics and Pragmatics 10(3). This version will be replaced with the final typeset version in due course. Note that page numbers will change, so cite with caution Maria Vasardani, Lesley Stirling, and Stephan Winter This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of a Creative Commons Attribution License (

2 The preposition at from a spatial language, cognition, and information systems perspective * Maria Vasardani The University of Melbourne Lesley Stirling The University of Melbourne Stephan Winter The University of Melbourne Abstract While both linguistic semantics and geographic information science have struggled to accurately and usefully define the meanings of natural language prepositions, there has been less dialogue between these disciplines than one might expect. In this paper we set out to describe the meaning of the English preposition at using well-established formal models of qualitative spatial relations within geographic information science (GIScience), ultimately proposing an account for its meaning which is novel for both discipline areas, and we relate this description to previous definitions of at from within linguistic semantics. The investigation in this paper illustrates that at cannot be handled using the mathematical formalizations of crisp spatial relations in GIScience. However, the model proposed in this paper based on contrast sets, Voronoi Diagrams and Galton & Hood s (2005) Anchoring theory, contributes to a better understanding of the meaning of at. The model also enables improved automatic interpretations of the preposition by partitioning space into contrast sets and representing at as indicating that a spatial entity is more closely related to a reference object than to any other in the set. We show how the model can be framed within a formal semantics account and how it can in principle be extended to account for spatial uses of other prepositions as well. The paper demonstrates potential areas of fruitful cross-fertilisation between GIScience and linguistic semantics. Keywords: Spatial prepositions, spatial cognition, qualitative spatial relations, geographic information science. 1 Introduction The linguistic semantics of prepositions has been the subject of much discussion but the definitions which have been proposed are not yet sufficient for practical needs, such as those of geographic information science (GIScience), which conceptualizes * We thank the anonymous reviewers and particularly Louise McNally for their valuable feedback.

3 Vasardani, Stirling and Winter qualitative spatial relations in formal mathematical models for qualitative spatial reasoning. On the other hand, the formal mathematical models developed by GI- Science for topological, distance, and direction relationships incorporate semantic definitions which relate only partially to the way that prepositions are used in natural language utterances (D. Mark & M. Egenhofer 1995, D. Mark, Comas, et al. 1995, Worboys 2001). In this paper we seek to bring the work done in these two discipline areas closer together. We take as our case study the qualitative spatial relationship that is expressed by the preposition at, which is not adequately covered by any of these models, raising the question as to why such a prominent preposition has been ignored so far. At is an interesting preposition in that it is highly underspecified, and can correspond to multiple, often more precise types of spatial situation in context. For example, let s meet at the park may imply a meeting point inside the park, a meeting point along its boundaries, or even a point outside the park, but close to it. The interpretation of the preposition depends here solely on the communication partners implicit understanding. If somebody types into a search engine café at the park the relevance or ranking of individual cafés would depend on the unspecified context: is the person interested mostly in cafés in the grounds of the park, attached to the park, or in reasonable proximity to the park? Or is an implicit ranking more appropriate, for example, such that cafés on the grounds of the park are more relevant than cafés within a reasonable distance from it? Hall, Jones & Smart (2015) show that at is the most frequently used spatial preposition in the database of geo-referenced photo captions they analyse. This makes a formal mechanism for processing and generating at particularly desirable: if natural language processing can be improved by capturing the meaning of at by formal models, place descriptions containing at can be interpreted automatically, or in the case of the work being done by Hall, Jones & Smart, photo captions can be generated automatically. As a result, human-machine interaction involving natural language would be improved. Current search engines still ignore spatial prepositions such as at in queries as being too hard to resolve (see example query above). A formal model should also be consistent with cognitive models of the meaning of at, and allow qualitative spatial reasoning over it. In fact, formal models capturing the meaning of at may also contribute to our understanding of cognitive processes and their reflection in qualitative spatial reasoning. This paper starts from the hypothesis that the meaning of at can be formally captured by tools of GIScience. The method applied looks at the discriminatory power of at in comparison to the known qualitative spatial relationships or operators, described in more detail in Section 3. It will reveal that at has no topological discriminatory power, only a ternary distance discriminatory power, and no directional discriminatory power. At least the first two observations may be surprising, given 2

4 The preposition at the usual specializations of at in GIScience by the set of two topological descriptors (coincidence, adjacency) and a binary distance descriptor (proximity), and the approaches to the description of its meaning current in cognitive and formal semantics. The paper then explores whether the meaning of at can be captured by a combination of a contrast set approach (S. Winter & Freksa 2012), the use of Voronoi Diagrams, and the theory of Anchoring (Galton & Hood 2005). We conclude that such an account does provide the tools to capture the lexical meaning of at. In Section 2, we briefly survey relevant previous research on the semantics of at. In Section 3 we work through and evaluate a range of formal models for the spatial meaning of at from GIScience, concluding that a novel model is needed, based on the combination of contrast sets, Voronoi Diagrams and the notion of Anchoring; this is described in Section 4. In Section 5 we relate this account to existing theories within linguistic semantics, and in particular show that it can be incorporated into the kind of compositional model-theoretic formal semantics assumed by Zwarts & Y. Winter (2000). Finally, in Section 6 we look at some complex cases and the issue of over-generation of the account, identifying some questions for ongoing research and arguing that a formal account such as the one we propose requires supplementation with a neo-gricean pragmatic approach. Although our primary focus is on at for the reasons given above, along the way we also illustrate how the proposed account can apply to and distinguish at from other English prepositions, in particular in, on and near. 2 Related work The preposition at has a range of meanings or use types, including at least those listed in Table 1. Like other prepositions, at is thus clearly polysemous; however, we focus on the spatial meanings here (cf. also Herskovits 1986 and others), aiming to give a general unified representation applicable to these uses. We make the assumption that the temporal and metaphorical extensions can be handled by a relatively straightforward mapping of the spatial meaning onto a different domain. The mapping can be done while maintaining the same general properties and with additional conventionalised elements of meaning resulting from contextually common inferences. 1 1 For example, temporal uses appear similar in structure to spatial uses if we assume an ontology of points in time and that intervals of time (e.g.. seasons) can be viewed punctually. Crucially, in See you at 4 o clock it is understood that I am not behaving uncooperatively if I arrive at a few minutes before or after 4. To anticipate our account, the reference time belongs to a relevant contrast set where segments are measured probably in 5 minute units rather than more precisely, while in other contexts a more precise specification may be relevant. 3

5 Vasardani, Stirling and Winter Spatial locational a. I will meet you at Melbourne Central. b. John is at the tram stop. c. The butterflies live at the park. 2 d. Put the posters up at the Engineering buildings. 3 e. We arrive at Heathrow in 30 minutes. Functional f. Are you at your desk? g. My daughter was at the piano when the doorbell rang. h. I ll be at work from 8 am. Temporal i. See you at 4 o clock. j. There aren t many birds at this season. k. The exam begins at precisely 2.00 pm. Other metaphorical extensions / idioms l. At the height of his success, he was struck down with illness. m. The children are at play. n. The chickens have been at the corn again. o. If you look carefully at the painting you can see a reflection in the mirror. p. She yelled at me when I tried to get her to move. q. He was really upset at the news of this company s closure. r. John threw the ball at me. s. We pushed at the door but it would not open. Table 1 Major uses of at. 4

6 The preposition at Lexical items, if meaningful, should carry some discriminatory power. That is, they should have information content in the sense of distinguishing between possible states of the world, and convey the chosen state to a recipient who does not know. This latter aspect of novelty or surprise for the recipient was behind the original definition of information content from information theory, which had a need to distinguish between information and noise in a signal (Shannon 1948, Shannon & Weaver 1949). Closed class words, such as conjunctions and prepositions, have a different effect on human cognition than open class words such as nouns and verbs (Bloom & Keil 2001). Usually the meanings of prepositions do not overlap, thus there is little choice amongst lexical terms for describing the spatial layout of objects (Bryant 1997, Landau & Jackendoff 1993). Some prepositions, however, are less exact, and at is one of them. The precise spatial array referred to with a use of at is determinable based on the context of use rather than residing in the semantics of at itself (Bennett 1975, Herskovits 1985, 1986). The prevalent assumption in linguistics states that at may be used in place of more specific spatial expressions such as on, in, touching, and near (Cienki 1989, Cuyckens 1984, Herskovits 1986), suggesting a relationship of hyponymy a hierarchical or inheritance relationship between these more specific spatial relationships and at, rather than the relationship of mutual opposition assumed in the above characterisation of prepositional meaning. We have previously suggested that preferred meanings of one of these more specific prepositions are prevalent in place descriptions with at, depending on the type and spatial granularity of the referents (Vasardani et al. 2012). Furthermore, it has been shown that there is a good deal of cross-linguistic variation in prepositional meaning (cf. for example Levinson 2003), and it is also worth noting that the preposition at is not universally matched with translation equivalents across languages. For example, Polish has multiple prepositions capturing aspects of the meaning of at (Knas 2006), and in German one would use in some cases an, in others zu or bei. Hence, Cuyckens (1984) calls at a typically English preposition. Other authors have pointed out similar differences between languages for other prepositions, supporting more general views that there must be universal non-linguistic foundations for spatial language, and that there must be language-specific effects on spatial representations (Munnich, Landau & Dosher 2001: 172-3). Much previous work on the semantics of at has attempted to capture our intuitions about the meaning of at within a cognitive semantics framework. Like other accounts within linguistic semantics, this work assumes that in their core meaning prepositions code spatial relationships between two entities. We will refer to these 2 Example as discussed in Galton & Hood (2005). 3 Example from the corpus analyzed in Vasardani et al. (2012). 5

7 Vasardani, Stirling and Winter here as the locatum (the located object, identified somewhere in the discourse external to the prepositional phrase), and a reference object, with respect to which a region is identified providing the location of the locatum (usually specified in the noun phrase complement of the preposition). In cognitive semantics, the locatum is called a trajector, and this trajector is located with respect to a landmark. Other terms which have been used for this contrast are figure and ground. Landau & Jackendoff (1993) discuss some differences between the concepts reference object, landmark, and ground. One key insight from the work in linguistics has been that the preposition at expresses a topological relation of co-location coincidence or adjacency between these two entities, with the location conceptualised as a point and without any specification of a direction of orientation of the locatum (Evans 2010, Herskovits 1985, Leech 1970, Tyler & Evans 2003). Evans (2010) specifies a co-location lexical concept licensing spatial uses of at and encoding the co-location parameter, which designates an abstract spatial relation between the trajector and a location defined in terms of contiguity or proximity (this alternative of coincidence or proximity dates back to at least Cuyckens 1984). The explicit acknowledgment of the irrelevance of the landmark s dimension or the perception of it as a point also dates back to early work (Leech 1970, Lindstromberg 1998, Quirk et al. 1985, Tyler & Evans 2003). It is this zero-dimensional (point) status of the location which has been thought to underlie the observation that a spatial situation described by at can have a range of specific instantiations: if the park in the café at park query example given above is treated by at as zero-dimensional, then the description simply says nothing further about where the locatum is with respect to this point, the key complication being that in real life of course the park is not zero-dimensional and hence the true relationship between the locatum and the park must be more specific. Thus it is acknowledged that at affords the most general expression of localisation in space in English (Evans 2010: 243). On the same page Evans also notes that all the more precise expressions of spatial relationships encoded by English prepositions such as by, near, on, in, over, under at times, can be encoded by at. The base generality of at is confirmed by its ability to non-redundantly co-occur with specifiers such as precisely or exactly. In addition to work in cognitive semantics, formal semantic models of prepositional meaning have also been proposed, framed within compositional modeltheoretic approaches (Gärdenfors 2014, Zwarts & Y. Winter 2000). These approaches generally account for the spatial meanings of locational prepositions by treating the preposition as a function over the spatial realisation of the reference object (encoded in the preposition s noun phrase complement), which defines a region within which the locatum is to be found: the preposition then contributes information which allows us to determine how the region (the location of the locatum) is related to the location 6

8 The preposition at of the reference object. Within such approaches, a number of claims have been made about the semantics of at. For example, Zwarts & Y. Winter (2000) propose a model in which spatial meaning of prepositions is accounted for using vector spaces. They make several major claims about the meaning of at, such as that it belongs to a class of prepositions giving rise to regions outside the eigenplace 4 of the reference object and, similarly to the observation about contiguity above, that at imposes the sole additional constraint that the length of the vector (distance between locatum and reference object) is almost zero. However, their account says nothing further about the meaning of at and does not, for instance, distinguish it formally from on, so that for example the formal semantics of they are at the supermarket is not distinguished from that of they are on the supermarket (that is, physically on the roof of the supermarket) (for more information see Section 5). A second feature of the meaning of at identified in the literature has been that at least a subset of uses of at imply a functional relationship which Evans (2010: 243) calls practical association (see also Herskovits 1986): thus, if I am at my desk the implication is that I am working there; if I am at the bus stop that I am waiting for a bus, and if I am at work or school or university that I am there to fulfil the normal functions I would undertake in that place, or even that I work or study there, regardless of where I am actually physically located at the time of utterance (see Table 1f h above). Thus for these uses the type of activity which would normally be undertaken at the locatum is highly relevant. While it is important to account for these interesting uses within a full description of prepositional meaning and usage, it is not clear to us that this should be incorporated within the lexical meaning of the preposition rather than as a generalized conversational implicature. Intention or function remains context delimited, it is just that some contexts are so common as to become typical (when at the piano I would normally be seated facing it in a position to play, but in context I might be understood to have a different orientation to it, for instance if I am about to make a toast or give a speech). Similar pragmatic implications can be found with at least some other prepositions: if I say I am in bed, you are likely to understand me to have retired for sleep for the night or to be unwell, depending on context; if I say I am in the car you will likely understand me to be driving from place to place, while if I am on stage I am likely to be performing in a production however, all these implicatures can be cancelled. We therefore do not tackle these uses here. 4 The eigenplace is the spatial region occupied by the object (Wunderlich 1991). 7

9 Vasardani, Stirling and Winter 3 Evaluating formal GIScience approaches to defining the meaning of at Over the past decades GIScience, in collaboration with artificial intelligence, has developed a rich body of knowledge about conceptual representations and reasoning with qualitative 5 spatial relations (Cohn & Renz 2008, M. J. Egenhofer, A. U. Frank & Jackson 1989, A. U. Frank 1991, Freksa 1991, Kuipers 1994, 1977). The qualitative turn in the discipline was motivated by the recognition that qualitative reasoning is computationally faster, due to its higher level of abstraction, than quantitative evaluations, and in many tasks sufficient. But from the beginning, also, the adequacy of these models for cognition and language was considered (M. J. Egenhofer & D. M. Mark 1995, A. U. Frank & D. M. Mark 1991, D. M. Mark & M. J. Egenhofer 1994, D. Mark, Comas, et al. 1995, D. Mark, A. U. Frank, et al. 1989, D. M. Mark & A. U. Frank 1991). In this section we work through key formal models from GIScience of the qualitative spatial relations of topology, distance, and direction, considering the meaning of at within each of these. Although there is a limited amount of work on at in GIScience, these form the current toolkit available to GIScientists to formally define the meaning of at and other prepositions, and some proposals have been made for at within them (cf. Dube & M. J. Egenhofer 2012). 3.1 Topology GIScience has developed two formal models of topological relations, the 9-intersection model based on point-set topology (M. J. Egenhofer, Sharma & D. M. Mark 1993, M. J. Egenhofer & Franzosa 1991), and the region connection calculus based on first order logic (Cui, Cohn & Randell 1993, Randell, Cui & Cohn 1992). Both models, despite their different foundations, result in definition of the same eight basic topological relations between two simple regions (abstractions of geographic features). Let us pick the 9-intersection model for illustration (Figure 1). In the 9-intersection model these eight relations are called disjoint, meet, overlap, equal, coveredby and its inverse covers, and containedby and its inverse contains. They are characterized uniquely by the observation as to whether the intersection of the interiors, boundaries and exteriors of the two regions are non-empty or empty. For example, the relation overlap is the only relation where the two 5 Qualitative spatial relations are symbolic abstractions of geometric representations of features, while quantitative relations express metric values. Qualitative relations allow spatial analysis, which is independent of, but consistent with the geometric depictions (M. J. Egenhofer 2015). X is 100m away from Y is an example of a quantitative relation, while X is far from Y is an example of a qualitative relation. 8

10 The preposition at X Y X Y X Y X Y disjoint(x,y) overlap(x,y) coveredby(x,y) covers(x,y) meet(x,y) equal(x,y) containedby(x,y) contains(x,y) X Y X Y Y X Y X fine disjoint(x,y) overlap(x,y) equal(x,y) inside(x,y) incorporate(x,y) medium independent(x,y) dependent(x,y) coarse Figure 1 The eight topological relations between simple regions in the 9- intersection model, and their generalizations. interiors intersect, the two boundaries intersect, and parts of each region s interior are outside of the other region. For geographic databases, storing these relationships in addition to the actual geometry of geographic features speeds up search. For example, finding all regions meeting a given specified other region, or all regions overlapping with a specified region, no longer requires costly geometric operations. In the context of the current paper these eight basic topological relations are relevant as possible tools that can be used in order to characterize the meaning of at. When we evaluate the meanings of at with regard to these conceptual models, we find that the various uses of at can cover all eight possible topological relationships between two regions, or that at has no topological discriminatory power, in contrast to, for example, prepositions in, on, and near, each of which corresponding to a single or a small subset of possible topological relations. Dube & M. J. Egenhofer (2012) claim that at can be modelled as the union of equal, coveredby and containedby, but do not discuss natural language examples. If reference object and locatum are disjoint, at is applicable in cases of proximity: If A is near B one may say A is at B, especially if thinking of or looking at A and B from a distance, or where B is a local or global landmark recognizable by many, in contrast to a relatively unknown A. 9

11 Vasardani, Stirling and Winter If reference object and locatum are in contact at their boundaries, this contact can be external contact ( meet ) or internal contact ( overlap, and potentially cases of coveredby, covers, or equal ). Two adjacent buildings that share a wall: The new maternity wing is at the east side of the hospital ( meet ). A complex construction may contain sub-structures visible at street level: I mean the cafeteria at the ground floor of the hospital ( coveredby ). Two buildings extending over a common area: The car park is at the ground floor, leading to the mall from its north exit and to the train station from its south exit ( overlap ). Finally, the sentence: A new hospital wing is being built at the parking lot ( equal ) is also a valid use of at. Example sentences for coveredby and covers relations, requiring a contact at the boundaries, seem to be indistinguishable from sentences that exemplify containedby and contains. Hence, on (surface) or in (container) uses of at, relating indistinguishably to containedby and contains as well as to coveredby and covers relationships, occur in topological examples as well: The new central station was built at the place of first settlement may be an example of contains (or covers ), assuming the areal extent of the central station is significantly larger than the three huts forming the first settlement. I am at home, answering a phone call while sitting in the living room, is an example of containedby (less likely, coveredby ). This observation is even more relevant as the eight topological categories formed by the 9-intersection model (and equivalently by the region connection calculus) have been shown to be the most promising starting point for further investigating how people conceptualize topological knowledge: although grounded in point-set topology (or first-order logic, respectively), their distinctions have been shown to reflect configural situations which humans would cluster together, or situations which language has names for (Knauff, Rauh & Renz 1997, Renz, Rauh & Knauff 2000). Both models, 9-intersection and region connection calculus, have been abstracted to five more general relations, but at this (medium) level of abstraction, 9-intersection and region connection calculus show differences in the way they group the relations. The medium-level 9-intersection model (Figure 1) emerges if boundaries of regions 10

12 The preposition at are considered to be parts of regions, therefore when the boundaries externally meet or intersect, they are grouped together under (medium-level) overlap. However, since at did not discriminate between the original eight relationships, it also does not discriminate between any of these five medium-level relationships, regardless of the model. Figure 1 shows a further level of abstraction, grouping the five medium-level 9-intersection relations into two clusters only. One cluster aggregates all relations where portions of the boundaries of both regions are outside of the other region, while the other aggregates all relations where the boundary of one region is completely within the other region (remembering that the medium-resolution 9-intersection considers boundaries as part of regions). The same clustering works for the region connection calculus. One can further argue that these two most general clusters, independent and dependent, must represent the coarsest topological distinction, and therefore, a cognitively essential distinction. And yet, cases of applications of at still can be found at both sides of the divide. For example, a meeting at a café that is a separate building, but very close or even attached to the National Museum may be expressed as in Let s meet at the café at the National Museum; this represents the independent case. Alternatively, if two friends want to look for gifts, they can meet at the Museum s gift-store which is part of the museum, so that the relation between museum and gift-store falls under the second general cluster of the dependent relation as in There is a gift-store at the museum, let s go there. Hence, it appears that at has no topological discriminatory power, and is vague in terms of topological meaning, at least assuming it is desirable to practice parsimony with respect to multiple polysemous senses. This conclusion is in accordance with the prevalent assumption in the literature of the irrelevance of the dimension, or the zero-dimensionality, of the perception of the reference object in most spatial uses of at. We will refer again here to the let s meet at the park example. Since at has no topological discriminatory power, it really does not matter whether the sentence is interpreted as meeting inside the park, or just outside of it, and therefore, the park s conceptualization as either point or extended feature is unimportant. What really matters is the mutual knowledge between the conversation participants as to where to meet. In contrast, when in or on are used the higher-than-zero dimensionality of the landmark is important for a topological interpretation. In the same example, let s meet in the park, means that the park is conceptualized as a two- or even three-dimensional feature and the people will meet inside of it. 11

13 Vasardani, Stirling and Winter 3.2 Distance The most prevalent meaning of at is a distance-related one, and this is reflected in the core linguistic semantic definitions of co-location-contiguity / proximity, as well as the near zero length vector in the formal semantic approach of Zwarts & Y. Winter (2000). However, at has not been discussed (perhaps has not been perceived) in the GIScience literature as a qualitative distance relationship (Hernández, Clementini & Di Felice 1995). The qualitative distance relationship closest to the meaning of at is nearness (Brennan & Martin 2002, Worboys 2001). But even if nearness is seen as an abstraction from quantity of distance in such accounts, clearly we still need to distinguish the meaning of at from the meaning of near, because unlike at, near cannot represent the full range of topologically dependent relationships demonstrated above (it cannot include spatial arrays of meeting or containing), because the distance-related dimension of meaning encoded in near is greater than the near zero length vector at is assigned in formal semantics. For example, it is valid to say the café is at/near the museum if the café is very close to the museum. However, if the museum includes a café, it is valid to say the café is at the museum, referring to the collocation of the café with the museum s grounds. But it is not valid in this case to say the café is near the museum. We suggest here that the meaning of at can be more appropriately formalized by starting from the concept of a contrast set of locations (S. Winter & Freksa 2012). With such a set of contrasting locations in mind, the meaning of at a location A is limited to locations which are closer to A than to B or to any other alternative location to A in the given contrast set assuming that the contrast set forms part of the context of the conversation. Taking up an argument by Brennan & Martin (2002), at some level at therefore reflects not a binary absolute proximity relation (cf. near A ), but a ternary comparative proximity relation: X is nearer to A than any other alternative(s) of the contrast set. 6 S. Winter & Freksa (2012) argue that places the elements in these contrast sets are not characterized by boundaries. Places are rather characterized by prototypes or centres, or are even conceived of as dimensionless entities in information space. The spatial extent of a place is only a refinement, not the place s nature. In addition, the spatial extent is frequently vague or contested (Burrough & A. Frank 1996, Cresswell 2004). Thus, this approach of reducing places to points fits well to the observed lack of topological discrimination of at but also to dealing with proximity: distance between, or proximity to, dimensionless entities is cognitively and computationally more directly accessible than distance between a point and 6 Note that something can be both near A and near B even if A and B are not co-located but a locatum cannot be both at A and at B if there is not a close spatial relationship between A and B; see the formal treatment proposed in Section 5. 12

14 The preposition at a spatially extended region (again, abstraction of a geographic feature or place), or between two spatially extended regions. Such distances would require first a commitment to the region s spatial extent, and then more complex calculations such as that of distance between a point x and an extended place A, as in this definition of Mador-Haim & Y. Winter (2015: 448), where y is a point in place A (Eq. 1): (1) d(x,a) = min({d(x,y) : y A}) or for two extended places the Hausdorff distance between extended place A and extended place B (Hausdorff 1914). The Hausdorff distance is the greatest of the distances from any point a in A to the closest point b in B (Eq. 2). The suprema (sup) and infima (inf) are used for calculating the longest distances (suprema) among the closest (infima) of the points between the two places: (2) d H (A,B) = max{sup inf d(a,b),sup inf d(a,b)} b B a A a A The geometric interpretation of the comparative proximity relationship argued for by S. Winter & Freksa (2012) is given by a Voronoi Diagram (Voronoi 1908). A Voronoi Diagram partitions space between seeds such that each point in space closer to one seed than to any other belongs to the cell of that seed. Voronoi diagrams always produce convex cells, and thus this formal model is aligned with Gärdenfors thesis that prepositions represent convex sets of points or paths in a single domain (Gärdenfors 2014: 205), except that it identifies this set of points as a Voronoi cell. It is also in some sense aligned with the near zero length vectors of Zwarts & Y. Winter (2000: 176-7), but with the assumption that specifying the maximum length of these vectors as is done in the Voronoi cell model is essential for their interpretation. And the discussion so far contradicts the assumption of these authors that prepositions are either outward or inward oriented: at appears to be valid outwards (near) as well as inwards (in, on). This will be explained in more detail in Section 4. On this account the seeds of the Voronoi Diagram are the places A, B, and so on, of the current contrast set. For example, Figure 2 shows the Voronoi Diagram of a contrast set of inner city train stations in Melbourne, Australia. According to what has been said above about the distance meaning of at, in a communication context where this is the relevant contrast set say, a person on a train calling home the sentence: I am at Parliament Station is acceptable if used when the speaker is inside of the station as well as when they are on a train approaching this station or departing from this station as long as the train is nearer to Parliament than to the next (Melbourne Central) or previous station (Flinders Street). This example is purely locative, not directional. Cases of direction or orientation are discussed in Section 3.3. b B 13

15 Vasardani, Stirling and Winter Figure 2 The Voronoi Diagram of the set of Melbourne s inner city train stations. It should also be noted that this account aims to represent space partitioning at a cognitive rather than at a physical level. What this means is that at will not be equally used when referring to places closer to the borders of the Voronoi cells as when indicating places closer to the centre. One way to think of this is to see the influence regions surrounding the seeds of the cells as operating like gravitational fields, with forces stronger closer to the centre of the field and decreasing in intensity the farther away one moves from the centre. This in turn affects the likely use of the preposition at according to how close or far one perceives they are from one centre in the influence region. This implies that while we are using the geometry of the Voronoi diagram to delineate the influence regions of a contrast set, we are not claiming that the use of at can partition the physical space fully. Other prepositions such as between may apply better, if the location referred to is closer to the border of the Voronoi cells, and neo-gricean principles of pragmatics will ensure that in such a context speakers will choose the more specific representation of the spatial relationship, if they are aware of it. 7 Brennan & Martin (2002) in their work on nearness, propose the use of Power Diagrams, or weighted Voronoi Diagrams. In Power Diagrams the seeds have various weights, for example, according to their prominence or relevance. However, for 7 As Gärdenfors (2014: 26) points out in his model of conceptual spaces underpinning his theory of linguistic meaning, which makes also use of Voronoi Diagrams, the convex influence regions of the Voronoi cells are not homogeneous, which is what makes them suitable for representing prototype effects; the seed of the cell can be seen as the prototype case for the concept and different positions within the region are describable as more or less central depending on their distance from the seed. 14

16 The preposition at contrast sets this suggestion seems to be inappropriate: a contrast set collects equals as alternatives, features of the same kind, of similar prominence, but most importantly of similar relevance in the given context. If the purpose of a sentence is to position a locatum, the reference object will be chosen from a set of similarly relevant alternatives. If the concert will be played at the city hall, this means just that it will not be played at the other possible well-known event locations in the city. This contrast set does not contain locations that are irrelevant in this context, such as, normally, my office, or Fiji. Contrast sets are chosen pragmatically, and the semantics of the preposition merely tells us that such a set must be appealed to, not what the set is in a particular context. The set chosen reflects the most relevant set of geographic features or placenames among which the referent object can be situated. While this focus is concerned only with selecting features (encoded in noun phrases in language), there are consequences for the interpretation of at, including its validity in a particular communicative context. Imagine the following dialogue as an example (Table 2), where the context, and hence, the contrast set changes with nearly every line (here <> is used to denote not at, and the features listed in the right column represent the possible alternatives in the relevant contrast sets): A I am now at Melbourne Central. (<> Parliament, Flagstaff) B At the Elizabeth St exit? (<> Swanston St exit, platform) A No, at the Swanston St exit (<> Elizabeth St exit, platform) B Ah, I see: You are at the State Library. (<> mall, Lonsdale Street) Table 2 Dialogue with changing context. Clark & Wilkes-Gibbs (1986) have shown the collaborative effort that goes into such a conversation. The first expression may have been used to contrast with the other train stations in Melbourne, as in the example above. The second and third, however, zoom in to a finer level of granularity. They switch to a local contrast set of, say, central elements of the train stations such as their platforms and exits. For the interpretation of at in lines 1 3, it is essential to recognize that the spatial expression in 1 and those in 2 3 belong to different contrast sets. This is signalled in part by use of the definite article in 2 and 3, and in part by other processes of inference in the context of the question-answer sequence in progress. The preposition at in the first expression would be interpreted using the Voronoi cell of Melbourne Central in Figure 2. For the communication partner this was not sufficiently detailed, so the clarifying question At the Elizabeth St exit? switches to the proximity relations of another contrast set represented in the Voronoi diagram of Figure 3. Expressions 2 and 3 do not construct a contrast between the exits and Melbourne Central, but only 15

17 Vasardani, Stirling and Winter Figure 3 Switch from the original contrast set seed, the Melbourne Central train station, to its possible exits. among the possible exits (and perhaps similar salient features) within the Melbourne Central train station. The fourth expression, however, is different. It refers to a feature of similar spatial granularity and prominence as Melbourne Central the State Library which is at the Swanston St. exit of Melbourne Central: across the street, but actually closer now than the prototype concept of the train station, with its tracks and platforms. A person leaving Melbourne Central through the Swanston St exit, may, due to the relative low prominence of this exit in the local environment, refer to more prominent features in the environment, again switching contrast sets: away from exits, and picking instead local landmarks. Hence, the contrast is here made with Melbourne Central, but the context has switched from a train trip to everything in local walking distance. Accordingly, the contrast set has changed to Figure 4. Thus, over these few lines the way in which each prepositional phrase is interpreted in order to establish a location has changed because the context, represented by the contrast set, has changed. The interpretation of at has not changed; in all cases the Voronoi Diagram has catered to a ternary comparative distance interpretation (exit closer to State Library than anywhere else in the contrast set). Importantly, and similar to the models of topological relations discussed earlier, the lack of discriminatory power of at when it comes to distances relates to the fact that when the actual distance between the locatum and the reference object is important, other prepositions such as near, next to or close by are preferred. In case, however, the notion of general proximity to the specific landmark in implicit contrast to the other landmarks of similar salience is important, then at is the preferred preposition. 16

18 The preposition at Figure 4 Switching to local landmarks, and now the exit is in proximity to the State Library. 3.3 Orientation When mapping linguistic spatial terms onto spatial relations, there exists a starting point with respect to which the rest of the object(s) are spatially defined. This point corresponds to the origin of a reference frame, at the intersection of three orthogonal axes (Carlson-Radvansky & Irwin 1994), whether the reference frame is absolute, intrinsic or relative (Levinson 1996). For example, in the sentence the gym is to the north of the student union, the student union forms the origin of the cardinal direction reference frame, to the north of which along the axis that points North is the gym. With respect to orientation, at does not relate to any frame of reference. Thus, at cannot differentiate within an absolute reference frame, say, of cardinal directions (A. U. Frank 1996), nor can it discriminate within an intrinsic (object-specific) or a relative (projected) reference frame, for example, left-right or front-back (Freksa 1992). However, at can also be used with respect to the qualitative relationship towards, linked to directed action. In a journey scenario, at can be used to identify waypoints along the route, or also the endpoint. For example, if a plane is arriving at Heathrow, a direction of movement (from an unspecified place) towards Heathrow Airport is expressed, reflecting the assignment of the semantic role of a goal, or endpoint along a path invoked by the motion verb arrive, to Heathrow. 8 8 While in such uses at can represent the destination location for a verb implying a trajectory along a bounded path, it is distinct from clearly directional prepositions such as to in that while to represents the path as well as highlighting its endpoint, at just represents the endpoint; at also co-occurs with a more limited range of motion verbs than to. For instance, at does not co-occur with verbs of locomotion with a directional sense Mary walked at the library means only that she walked around 17

19 Vasardani, Stirling and Winter Thus, while at does not discriminate between absolute, intrinsic or relative orientation, expressions containing at can refer to the orientation of the vector, as in arriving at. Here the motion aspect comes from the verb, while at is used to draw attention to the end of the vector, the target place. Then consistency with the other kinds of relationships requires that source and target are disjoint (as in Figure 1), and some notion of proximity must apply to allow the interaction, although a weak one. For the plane interacting with Heathrow it is likely that the plane is near Heathrow, but it is not essential that it is nearer to Heathrow than to another airport in the region (especially considering the high density of international airports around London in this example). Our intuitions are that the contrast set here is likely between source and goal, so, formally, if the plane is in the second half of its journey it is approaching Heathrow. Similarly, on a train ride from Melbourne Central (start) to Flagstaff (goal) the train can be considered to be arriving at Flagstaff after travelling at least half of the route between these two consecutive stations. 9 On a car ride from Melbourne to Adelaide the car can be at the Grampians, even if it is not a stop, if it is in the Voronoi cell of the Grampians among a relevant contrast set (of well-known places between Melbourne and Adelaide) (see formalization in Section 4). The ternary proximity relation that was postulated above to express the essence of at is preserved. Hence, at combined with a directed action verb or noun is compliant with the previous interpretations. The ternary proximity relationship signalled by the preposition is simply applied to the terminal of the interaction vector. 4 Formalizing at with Anchoring relations As mentioned earlier, the geometric partition of space suitable for the comparative proximity relationship assumed by at can be formed with a Voronoi Diagram, the seeds of which are the places that belong to the pragmatically determined contrast set. Each Voronoi cell includes all the points in space at which a locatum X can be placed in relation to a reference object Y, when interpreting the expression X is at Y, and in the influence region defined by the library, and *I am heading at the library is not acceptable. It is presumably this use of at that underlies the metaphorical extension in expressions of looking (look at) and communication (yell at) as well as the sense which contrasts throw at with throw to (see Table 1). See (Jackendoff 1983, Piñón 1993, Snider 2010, Zwarts 2005) for more discussion of paths, directional spatial prepositions and relevant senses. 9 As pointed out by a reviewer and the editor, intuitively there are differences in interpretation between alternative expressions such as X is at Heathrow / arriving at Heathrow / approaching Heathrow / en route to Heathrow (and similarly for any other upcoming stop on a journey, such as Flagstaff station in the example given) primarily in terms of the likely distance from the target at time of utterance. We make the same point here as in Section 3.2, about the greater likelihood of use of at closer to the seeds of the Voronoi cells. The difference between at Heathrow and arriving at Heathrow presumably reflects the meaning contributed by the use of the motion verb, which entails a trajectory ending in the goal. 18

20 The preposition at forms the influence region of Y, against the rest of the reference objects in the same contrast set. The dimension of Y is not important as far as its conceptualization is concerned, Y can be thought of either as a point or a 1-, 2- or 3-dimensional object that occupies an eigenplace (Wunderlich 1991), consistent with the actual location of X; X can in fact be located inside the reference object or within its influence region. With such a space partition, the formalization of at as a comparative proximity relation can be suitably defined using the Anchoring theory developed by Galton & Hood (2005). The main premise of Anchoring is that an object in the information space of the unfolding discourse can be anchored to a location in precise (geometric, coordinate-based) space of the world referred to just by stating what is known with certainty in this information space and leaving the rest for further reasoning, thus allowing for the description of qualitative spatial relations which are less than completely explicit. An object A, of which the location is known only vaguely or with uncertainty, may be anchored to a location in precise space, a region R, by at least the following relations: Definition 1 The anchoring relations: A is anchored in R we know for sure that A is located within R A is anchored over R we know for sure that R falls within the location of A A is anchored alongside R we know for sure that A is located such that it abuts R (and in many cases, R will be a linear feature) A is anchored outside R we know for sure that A and R are disjoint. These anchoring relations are not jointly exhaustive (but are pairwise disjoint), in contrast to the topological relationship models discussed in Section 3.1 above. 10 So while the anchoring relations are closely related to topology models, the precision of the anchoring relations is in the information space of the discourse model, not in the geometric space of precise locations in the world. Because of this quality, anchoring relations seem attractive for formalizing the comparative proximity meaning of at, which cannot adhere to strict geometric precisifications (Lindkvist 1950). We propose therefore that adding the formal model of Anchoring to our analysis of the meaning of at using a space partitioning with Voronoi cells and the concept of a contrast set will allow us to provide a complete account of the spatial senses for this preposition. 10 Not jointly exhaustive means that the union of all anchoring relations will not equal or exhaust all the possible configurations between two regions. For example, in contrast to topology, when A is anchored in R, it can be completely within R, touching its border from the inside, or be equal to R. In topological terms these are three different relations (inside, coveredby, and equals; see Figure 1), with different relations between their interior, boundaries and exterior. 19

21 Vasardani, Stirling and Winter Figure 5 Interpretation of at as anchored in V Y, where V Y is the Voronoi cell or influence region of the reference object Y. Notice that the represented placement of the locatum is not intended to be exact, but indicates it is confined somewhere in V Y, nor do we specify the location of Y here. Having observed this range of anchoring relations, we argue that at can be formalized with the relation anchoring in as follows: Definition 2 A locatum X is at a reference object Y if and only if X is anchored in V Y. In this Definition 2, V Y is the Voronoi cell that corresponds to Y and is part of the Voronoi Diagram created over features of the contrast set Y belongs to this contrast set being contextually determined. The influence regions the Voronoi cells will be possibly different each time at is used, depending on the contrast set of the reference object Y. Formalizing at as anchored in V Y captures the comparative proximity meaning of at through the specification that the locatum is located in the reference object s influence region (Figure 5). Note that this model preserves the comparative, ternary proximity feature described in Section 3. So, if X is anchored in Y, it means that Y is chosen because it is the closest reference object to X from among those in the contrast set. A straightforward example demonstrating the use of at with an anchored in relationship would be an utterance such as The city hall is at the city centre: without being able to specify precise boundaries of the city centre, we state that the city hall is somewhere inside the centre s influence region, as this is defined by contrasting the city centre with other, similarly prominent parts of the city, such as its coastline area, or its suburban areas. This relation would be equivalent to the topological relation inside in Figure 1 except that one cannot prove this without precise boundaries. Other examples of the use of at interpretable in this way are: I am waiting at the tram stop, I will meet you at the library, or the Classics Museum is at the northern end of the city. In all these examples, and in the others we have discussed so far, we see that if trying to place the locatum, it suffices to indicate the Voronoi cell around 20

22 The preposition at the reference object, from the Voronoi Diagram of the same contrast set. We can then be confident that the locatum is somewhere in that cell; otherwise the description would be made using another reference object. The definition given above includes the possibility of the locatum being inside the reference object itself (the strict definition of anchored in), or of it covering an area including the interior of the reference object, as in a sloppy description such as The city centre is at the city hall: the city centre is in the influence region of the city hall, but of course includes this building within it. The shape of the reference object may vary. In an example of a highway which runs alongside the boundaries of a national park (and this can be disjoint, meet or even negligibly overlap in any precise location of both features) such as in The Grampians are at the Glenelg Highway, the reference object is elongated in shape, and we might be tempted to suggest that the anchored-alongside relation is a better representation of the spatial relationship referred to here. However, this case too can be accounted for as an instance of anchoring in it just so happens that the shape of the reference object (the highway) is long and thin, but it is still possible to conceive of the Grampians (locatum X) as being within the influence region of this reference object. We would argue, however, that at is rarely or never used to anchor something strictly outside of a reference feature (anchored outside), since there are more appropriate prepositional expressions, such as near, next to or close by, to indicate the strict disjointness of the locations. Anchored outside is explicitly excluded from Definition 2. This approach combines a well-defined partition of space (Voronoi Diagrams) with a formal model of spatial relations that is actually not precise in geometric space. What is achieved are properly refined acceptable placements of a locatum when it is positioned at the reference object within the contextually defined Voronoi cell while remaining true to the often non-exact nature of the spatial configuration described using the preposition at. Conveniently, even when the placement of the locatum is meant to be precise, as in The arrow hit the target at the centre, the inclusive nature of the Voronoi cell accommodates these cases equally well. Formalizing at this way provides a means of locating features without the need to provide a more specific location. However, by limiting the possible locations to the influence region here the Voronoi cell we remain true to the way in which at is used in natural language place descriptions. Thinking of at in terms of anchored in V Y has the benefit of overcoming the lack of discriminatory power in topology, orientation and distance illustrated previously. Anchored in, the use of contrast sets, and the Voronoi Diagrams built on them provide a means of formalizing with existing tools a spatial relation that has otherwise eluded 21

23 Vasardani, Stirling and Winter the existing formalizations, even though it is the most commonly used when referring to a relative location. Using Anchoring theory to formalize at also helps to clarify the subtle differences between this preposition and some of the other prepositions most closely related to it in meaning, namely in, on and near. For on, the concept of a supporting surface of the reference object is also important, and so while there are cases where on would also be interpreted with anchoring relations, the element of its meaning encoding the force dynamics of gravity (and extended senses based on this) 11 deserves closer investigation, outside the scope of this work. Using the anchoring relations to define the spatial meaning of in and near however, one would have to consider the actual spatial dimensions of the reference object. Then, definitions for in and near could be given as in Definition 3 and Figure 6. Thus, in Figure 6b the Voronoi cell for interpreting near has a hole, if (or where) the reference object is considered spatially extended, thus capturing a major distinction between near and at, which is that near is not applicable when the location is known to be inside the reference object. It appears that near is more concerned with (outer) distance, while at is more concerned with contact or possible interaction. In contrast, in Figure 6a, the interpretation for in requires precisely that the locatum is situated in the reference object. Definition 3 The spatial meaning of in and near: X is in Y, if and only if X is anchored in E Y (Figure 6a); and X is near Y, if and only if X is anchored in [V Y E Y ] (Figure 6b). where V Y is, as before, the Voronoi cell around Y (its influence region) and E Y is the reference object s eigenplace, or the region occupied by the reference object itself in the geometric space. It becomes clear then, that using at to refer to a location in a context where the focus is on the fact that it is either clearly within or clearly outside and at some (small but definite) distance from the actual (physical boundaries) of the reference object would be misleading in the conversation context, as at is the only one of these prepositions that can actually cover in meaning the whole influence region, including the extent of the reference object itself. Thus for pragmatic reasons, it would be uncooperative to choose at when these more specific meanings are intended, and prepositions in or near would be chosen instead. Although our observations here are based on linguistic interpretation and formal models, they are relevant to our understanding of cognitive mechanisms. It appears 11 Clearly on can be used in contexts where the supporting role of the reference object is not based on the force dynamics of gravity, for example the picture on the wall; we take such senses to retain the notion of support but to represent an extension from the more prototypical use. 22

24 The preposition at Figure 6 Interpretation of prepositions (a) in, and (b) near using the anchored in relation. Figure 7 Distinct topological relations disjoint (a), meet (b) and containedby (c), but examples can be given where each image is a valid representation of at. that we could speculatively suggest that the preposition at has a strong spatial connotation (is deeply rooted in the spatial processes in the mind), but one cannot easily depict the relation it implies. While it has a capacity to anchor objects or events with respect to a general location, neither the spatial dimension of the reference object nor the actual spatial relation can be easily depicted graphically. Lindstromberg (1998) links this characteristic to the frequent necessity to mentally zoom out when using at in its spatial sense, so that the relation between locatum and reference object is conceptualised in an abstract way that renders the spatial meaning of at barely discernable: it could be near the landmark but not touching it, near and touching it, or simply co-located with (exactly, partially or surrounded by) the landmark (Figure 7). Thus, image schemata (Johnson 1987) as they are taken to underlie, for example, the topological relations that represent the meaning of in (container schema) or on (surface schema), cannot be readily or nonabstractly used to represent the meaning of at. Hence, we argue that at conveys a spatial meaning, but not an easy to visualize image schema. In visual terms, at remains ambivalent. This is perhaps why it has been difficult to capture the meaning of at within cognitive semantics. A cognitive grounding for the preposition must point to linguistic-cognitive schematizations (Talmy 1983) that are not easily imaginable. 23

Convex Hull-Based Metric Refinements for Topological Spatial Relations

Convex Hull-Based Metric Refinements for Topological Spatial Relations ABSTRACT Convex Hull-Based Metric Refinements for Topological Spatial Relations Fuyu (Frank) Xu School of Computing and Information Science University of Maine Orono, ME 04469-5711, USA fuyu.xu@maine.edu

More information

Alexander Klippel and Chris Weaver. GeoVISTA Center, Department of Geography The Pennsylvania State University, PA, USA

Alexander Klippel and Chris Weaver. GeoVISTA Center, Department of Geography The Pennsylvania State University, PA, USA Analyzing Behavioral Similarity Measures in Linguistic and Non-linguistic Conceptualization of Spatial Information and the Question of Individual Differences Alexander Klippel and Chris Weaver GeoVISTA

More information

Maintaining Relational Consistency in a Graph-Based Place Database

Maintaining Relational Consistency in a Graph-Based Place Database Maintaining Relational Consistency in a Graph-Based Place Database Hao Chen Department of Infrastructure Engineering, Geomatics The University of Melbourne Email: hchen@student.unimelb.edu.au Introduction

More information

Exploring Spatial Relationships for Knowledge Discovery in Spatial Data

Exploring Spatial Relationships for Knowledge Discovery in Spatial Data 2009 International Conference on Computer Engineering and Applications IPCSIT vol.2 (2011) (2011) IACSIT Press, Singapore Exploring Spatial Relationships for Knowledge Discovery in Spatial Norazwin Buang

More information

Intelligent GIS: Automatic generation of qualitative spatial information

Intelligent GIS: Automatic generation of qualitative spatial information Intelligent GIS: Automatic generation of qualitative spatial information Jimmy A. Lee 1 and Jane Brennan 1 1 University of Technology, Sydney, FIT, P.O. Box 123, Broadway NSW 2007, Australia janeb@it.uts.edu.au

More information

Mappings For Cognitive Semantic Interoperability

Mappings For Cognitive Semantic Interoperability Mappings For Cognitive Semantic Interoperability Martin Raubal Institute for Geoinformatics University of Münster, Germany raubal@uni-muenster.de SUMMARY Semantic interoperability for geographic information

More information

Place Syntax Tool (PST)

Place Syntax Tool (PST) Place Syntax Tool (PST) Alexander Ståhle To cite this report: Alexander Ståhle (2012) Place Syntax Tool (PST), in Angela Hull, Cecília Silva and Luca Bertolini (Eds.) Accessibility Instruments for Planning

More information

Breaking de Morgan s law in counterfactual antecedents

Breaking de Morgan s law in counterfactual antecedents Breaking de Morgan s law in counterfactual antecedents Lucas Champollion New York University champollion@nyu.edu Ivano Ciardelli University of Amsterdam i.a.ciardelli@uva.nl Linmin Zhang New York University

More information

Must... stay... strong!

Must... stay... strong! Alex Goebel 620 Spring 2016 Paper Presentation of von Fintel & Gillies (2010) Synopsis Must... stay... strong! Von Fintel & Gillies (vf&g) argue against a weakened semantics of must and propose an alternative

More information

Deriving place graphs from spatial databases

Deriving place graphs from spatial databases 25 Deriving place graphs from spatial databases Ehsan Hamzei ehamzei@student.unimelb.edu.au Hua Hua Research School of Computer Science Australian National University hua.hua@anu.edu.au Martin Tomko tomkom@unimelb.edu.au

More information

From Language towards. Formal Spatial Calculi

From Language towards. Formal Spatial Calculi From Language towards Formal Spatial Calculi Parisa Kordjamshidi Martijn Van Otterlo Marie-Francine Moens Katholieke Universiteit Leuven Computer Science Department CoSLI August 2010 1 Introduction Goal:

More information

Location Based Concierge Service with Spatially Extended Topology for Moving Objects

Location Based Concierge Service with Spatially Extended Topology for Moving Objects The Journal of GIS Association of Korea, Vol. 17, No. 4, pp. 445-454, December 2009 Location Based Concierge Service with Spatially Extended Topology for Moving Objects Byoungjae Lee* ABSTRACT Beyond simple

More information

Introduction to Pragmatics

Introduction to Pragmatics Introduction to Pragmatics Summer 2016 Tuesdays 2:30--4:00pm @ 2321.HS 3H INSTRUCTOR Todor Koev (Todor.Koev@uni-duesseldorf.de) Presupposition projection Presupposition is a prevalent type of inference

More information

Preferred Mental Models in Qualitative Spatial Reasoning: A Cognitive Assessment of Allen s Calculus

Preferred Mental Models in Qualitative Spatial Reasoning: A Cognitive Assessment of Allen s Calculus Knauff, M., Rauh, R., & Schlieder, C. (1995). Preferred mental models in qualitative spatial reasoning: A cognitive assessment of Allen's calculus. In Proceedings of the Seventeenth Annual Conference of

More information

Implementing Visual Analytics Methods for Massive Collections of Movement Data

Implementing Visual Analytics Methods for Massive Collections of Movement Data Implementing Visual Analytics Methods for Massive Collections of Movement Data G. Andrienko, N. Andrienko Fraunhofer Institute Intelligent Analysis and Information Systems Schloss Birlinghoven, D-53754

More information

Takeaway Notes: Finite State Automata

Takeaway Notes: Finite State Automata Takeaway Notes: Finite State Automata Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 Basics and Ground Rules 2 2.1 Building Blocks.............................. 2 2.2 The Name of the Game.......................... 2 3 Deterministic

More information

A Way of Getting Rid of Things:

A Way of Getting Rid of Things: A Way of Getting Rid of Things: Higher-order Langauges, Priorian Nominalism, and Nihilism: Cian Dorr Rutgers Workshop on Structural Realism and the Metaphysics of Science 1. Higher-order quantification

More information

Spatial Reasoning With A Hole

Spatial Reasoning With A Hole Spatial Reasoning With A Hole Max J. Egenhofer and Maria Vasardani National Center for Geographic Information and Analysis and Department of Spatial Information Science and Engineering University of Maine

More information

Spatial relations in natural language. A constraint-based approach

Spatial relations in natural language. A constraint-based approach Spatial relations in natural language A constraint-based approach Øyvind Nordsted Wedøe Master s Thesis Spring 2014 Spatial relations in natural language Øyvind Nordsted Wedøe 30th April 2014 ii Contents

More information

7.1 What is it and why should we care?

7.1 What is it and why should we care? Chapter 7 Probability In this section, we go over some simple concepts from probability theory. We integrate these with ideas from formal language theory in the next chapter. 7.1 What is it and why should

More information

Math 541 Fall 2008 Connectivity Transition from Math 453/503 to Math 541 Ross E. Staffeldt-August 2008

Math 541 Fall 2008 Connectivity Transition from Math 453/503 to Math 541 Ross E. Staffeldt-August 2008 Math 541 Fall 2008 Connectivity Transition from Math 453/503 to Math 541 Ross E. Staffeldt-August 2008 Closed sets We have been operating at a fundamental level at which a topological space is a set together

More information

Cognitive Engineering for Geographic Information Science

Cognitive Engineering for Geographic Information Science Cognitive Engineering for Geographic Information Science Martin Raubal Department of Geography, UCSB raubal@geog.ucsb.edu 21 Jan 2009 ThinkSpatial, UCSB 1 GIScience Motivation systematic study of all aspects

More information

Designing and Evaluating Generic Ontologies

Designing and Evaluating Generic Ontologies Designing and Evaluating Generic Ontologies Michael Grüninger Department of Industrial Engineering University of Toronto gruninger@ie.utoronto.ca August 28, 2007 1 Introduction One of the many uses of

More information

CHAPTER 6 - THINKING ABOUT AND PRACTICING PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC

CHAPTER 6 - THINKING ABOUT AND PRACTICING PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC 1 CHAPTER 6 - THINKING ABOUT AND PRACTICING PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC Here, you ll learn: what it means for a logic system to be finished some strategies for constructing proofs Congratulations! Our system of

More information

Cognitive semantics and cognitive theories of representation: Session 6: Conceptual spaces

Cognitive semantics and cognitive theories of representation: Session 6: Conceptual spaces Cognitive semantics and cognitive theories of representation: Session 6: Conceptual spaces Martin Takáč Centre for cognitive science DAI FMFI Comenius University in Bratislava Príprava štúdia matematiky

More information

Introducing Proof 1. hsn.uk.net. Contents

Introducing Proof 1. hsn.uk.net. Contents Contents 1 1 Introduction 1 What is proof? 1 Statements, Definitions and Euler Diagrams 1 Statements 1 Definitions Our first proof Euler diagrams 4 3 Logical Connectives 5 Negation 6 Conjunction 7 Disjunction

More information

How to Handle Incomplete Knowledge Concerning Moving Objects

How to Handle Incomplete Knowledge Concerning Moving Objects B B is How to Handle Incomplete Knowledge Concerning Moving Objects Nico Van de Weghe 1, Peter Bogaert 1, Anthony G. Cohn 2, Matthias Delafontaine 1, Leen De Temmerman 1, Tijs Neutens 1, Philippe De Maeyer

More information

A new Approach to Drawing Conclusions from Data A Rough Set Perspective

A new Approach to Drawing Conclusions from Data A Rough Set Perspective Motto: Let the data speak for themselves R.A. Fisher A new Approach to Drawing Conclusions from Data A Rough et Perspective Zdzisław Pawlak Institute for Theoretical and Applied Informatics Polish Academy

More information

Metrics and topologies for geographic space

Metrics and topologies for geographic space Published in Proc. 7 th Intl. Symp. Spatial Data Handling, Delft, Netherlands. Metrics and topologies for geographic space Michael F Worboys Department of Computer Science, Keele University, Staffs ST5

More information

Deriving place graphs from spatial databases. Ehsan Hamzei Hao Chen Hua Hua Maria Vasardani Martin Tomko Stephan Winter

Deriving place graphs from spatial databases. Ehsan Hamzei Hao Chen Hua Hua Maria Vasardani Martin Tomko Stephan Winter Deriving place graphs from spatial databases Ehsan Hamzei Hao Chen Hua Hua Maria Vasardani Martin Tomko Stephan Winter Introduction Human place knowledge vs spatial databases / maps e.g., The Convention

More information

GeoVISTA Center, Department of Geography, The Pennsylvania State University, PA, USA

GeoVISTA Center, Department of Geography, The Pennsylvania State University, PA, USA Formally grounding spatio-temporal thinking Klippel, A., Wallgrün, J. O., Yang, J., Li, R., & Dylla, F. (in print, 2012). Formally grounding spatio temporal thinking. Cognitive Processing. Alexander Klippel

More information

Mathmatics 239 solutions to Homework for Chapter 2

Mathmatics 239 solutions to Homework for Chapter 2 Mathmatics 239 solutions to Homework for Chapter 2 Old version of 8.5 My compact disc player has space for 5 CDs; there are five trays numbered 1 through 5 into which I load the CDs. I own 100 CDs. a)

More information

Everything Old Is New Again: Connecting Calculus To Algebra Andrew Freda

Everything Old Is New Again: Connecting Calculus To Algebra Andrew Freda Everything Old Is New Again: Connecting Calculus To Algebra Andrew Freda (afreda@deerfield.edu) ) Limits a) Newton s Idea of a Limit Perhaps it may be objected, that there is no ultimate proportion of

More information

A General Framework for Conflation

A General Framework for Conflation A General Framework for Conflation Benjamin Adams, Linna Li, Martin Raubal, Michael F. Goodchild University of California, Santa Barbara, CA, USA Email: badams@cs.ucsb.edu, linna@geog.ucsb.edu, raubal@geog.ucsb.edu,

More information

Fuzzy Systems. Introduction

Fuzzy Systems. Introduction Fuzzy Systems Introduction Prof. Dr. Rudolf Kruse Christoph Doell {kruse,doell}@iws.cs.uni-magdeburg.de Otto-von-Guericke University of Magdeburg Faculty of Computer Science Department of Knowledge Processing

More information

Chapter 3. Cartesian Products and Relations. 3.1 Cartesian Products

Chapter 3. Cartesian Products and Relations. 3.1 Cartesian Products Chapter 3 Cartesian Products and Relations The material in this chapter is the first real encounter with abstraction. Relations are very general thing they are a special type of subset. After introducing

More information

Fuzzy Systems. Introduction

Fuzzy Systems. Introduction Fuzzy Systems Introduction Prof. Dr. Rudolf Kruse Christian Moewes {kruse,cmoewes}@iws.cs.uni-magdeburg.de Otto-von-Guericke University of Magdeburg Faculty of Computer Science Department of Knowledge

More information

A Computable Language of Architecture

A Computable Language of Architecture A Computable Language of Architecture Description of Descriptor Language in Supporting Compound Definitions Introduction Sora Key Carnegie Mellon University, Computational Design Laboratory, USA http://www.code.arc.cmu.edu

More information

1 More finite deterministic automata

1 More finite deterministic automata CS 125 Section #6 Finite automata October 18, 2016 1 More finite deterministic automata Exercise. Consider the following game with two players: Repeatedly flip a coin. On heads, player 1 gets a point.

More information

Similarities and differences between outdoor and indoor space from the perspective of navigation

Similarities and differences between outdoor and indoor space from the perspective of navigation Similarities and differences between outdoor and indoor space from the perspective of navigation (Extended Abstract) Liping Yang, Michael Worboys Department of Spatial Information Science and Engineering,

More information

E QUI VA LENCE RE LA TIONS AND THE CATEGORIZATION OF MATHEMATICAL OBJECTS

E QUI VA LENCE RE LA TIONS AND THE CATEGORIZATION OF MATHEMATICAL OBJECTS E QUI VA LENCE RE LA TIONS AND THE CATEGORIZATION OF MATHEMATICAL OBJECTS ANTON DOCHTERMANN Abstract. In [2] Lakoff and Nuñez develop a basis for the cognitive science of embodied mathematics. For them,

More information

? 4. Like number bonds, a formula is useful because it helps us know what operation to use depending on which pieces of information we have.

? 4. Like number bonds, a formula is useful because it helps us know what operation to use depending on which pieces of information we have. UNIT SIX DECIMALS LESSON 168 PROBLEM-SOLVING You ve covered quite a distance in your journey through our number system, from whole numbers through fractions, to decimals. Today s math mysteries all have

More information

A Guide to Proof-Writing

A Guide to Proof-Writing A Guide to Proof-Writing 437 A Guide to Proof-Writing by Ron Morash, University of Michigan Dearborn Toward the end of Section 1.5, the text states that there is no algorithm for proving theorems.... Such

More information

Special Theory of Relativity Prof. Dr. Shiva Prasad Department of Physics Indian Institute of Technology, Bombay

Special Theory of Relativity Prof. Dr. Shiva Prasad Department of Physics Indian Institute of Technology, Bombay (Refer Slide Time: 00:36) Special Theory of Relativity Prof. Dr. Shiva Prasad Department of Physics Indian Institute of Technology, Bombay Lecture - 7 Examples of Length Contraction and Time Dilation Hello,

More information

Efficient Approximate Reasoning with Positive and Negative Information

Efficient Approximate Reasoning with Positive and Negative Information Efficient Approximate Reasoning with Positive and Negative Information Chris Cornelis, Martine De Cock, and Etienne Kerre Fuzziness and Uncertainty Modelling Research Unit, Department of Applied Mathematics

More information

Algebra Exam. Solutions and Grading Guide

Algebra Exam. Solutions and Grading Guide Algebra Exam Solutions and Grading Guide You should use this grading guide to carefully grade your own exam, trying to be as objective as possible about what score the TAs would give your responses. Full

More information

Singularities in Qualitative Reasoning

Singularities in Qualitative Reasoning Singularities in Qualitative Reasoning Björn Gottfried Centre for Computing Technologies University of Bremen, Germany bg@tzi.de Abstract. Qualitative Reasoning is characterised by making knowledge explicit

More information

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Pronouns and Variable Assignments 1. We ve seen that implicatures are crucially related to context.

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Pronouns and Variable Assignments 1. We ve seen that implicatures are crucially related to context. Pronouns and Variable Assignments 1 1. Putting this Unit in Context (1) What We ve Done So Far This Unit Expanded our semantic theory so that it includes (the beginnings of) a theory of how the presuppositions

More information

An inquisitive approach to occasion-sensitivity

An inquisitive approach to occasion-sensitivity An inquisitive approach to occasion-sensitivity Tamara Dobler ILLC November 6, 2017 Tamara Dobler (ILLC) An inquisitive approach to occasion-sensitivity November 6, 2017 1 / 37 Outline 1 Introduction 2

More information

Modeling Discrete Processes Over Multiple Levels Of Detail Using Partial Function Application

Modeling Discrete Processes Over Multiple Levels Of Detail Using Partial Function Application Modeling Discrete Processes Over Multiple Levels Of Detail Using Partial Function Application Paul WEISER a and Andrew U. FRANK a a Technical University of Vienna Institute for Geoinformation and Cartography,

More information

Introductory Analysis I Fall 2014 Homework #5 Solutions

Introductory Analysis I Fall 2014 Homework #5 Solutions Introductory Analysis I Fall 2014 Homework #5 Solutions 6. Let M be a metric space, let C D M. Now we can think of C as a subset of the metric space M or as a subspace of the metric space D (D being a

More information

Some Background Material

Some Background Material Chapter 1 Some Background Material In the first chapter, we present a quick review of elementary - but important - material as a way of dipping our toes in the water. This chapter also introduces important

More information

On the Arbitrary Choice Regarding Which Inertial Reference Frame is "Stationary" and Which is "Moving" in the Special Theory of Relativity

On the Arbitrary Choice Regarding Which Inertial Reference Frame is Stationary and Which is Moving in the Special Theory of Relativity Regarding Which Inertial Reference Frame is "Stationary" and Which is "Moving" in the Special Theory of Relativity Douglas M. Snyder Los Angeles, CA The relativity of simultaneity is central to the special

More information

Cognitive OpenLS Extending XML for location services by a high-level cognitive framework

Cognitive OpenLS Extending XML for location services by a high-level cognitive framework Cognitive OpenLS Extending XML for location services by a high-level cognitive framework Diplomarbeit Fachbereich Informatik, Universität Bremen April 10, 2006 Stefan Hansen Betreuer: Dr. Alexander Klippel

More information

Geographers Perspectives on the World

Geographers Perspectives on the World What is Geography? Geography is not just about city and country names Geography is not just about population and growth Geography is not just about rivers and mountains Geography is a broad field that

More information

Application of Topology to Complex Object Identification. Eliseo CLEMENTINI University of L Aquila

Application of Topology to Complex Object Identification. Eliseo CLEMENTINI University of L Aquila Application of Topology to Complex Object Identification Eliseo CLEMENTINI University of L Aquila Agenda Recognition of complex objects in ortophotos Some use cases Complex objects definition An ontology

More information

An Ontology-based Framework for Modeling Movement on a Smart Campus

An Ontology-based Framework for Modeling Movement on a Smart Campus An Ontology-based Framework for Modeling Movement on a Smart Campus Junchuan Fan 1, Kathleen Stewart 1 1 Department of Geographical and Sustainability Sciences, University of Iowa, Iowa City, IA, 52242,

More information

PHYSICS 107. Lecture 10 Relativity: The Postulates

PHYSICS 107. Lecture 10 Relativity: The Postulates PHYSICS 107 Lecture 10 Relativity: The Postulates Introduction Relativity represents yet a further step in the direction of abstraction and mathematization of the laws of motion. We are getting further

More information

Can Vector Space Bases Model Context?

Can Vector Space Bases Model Context? Can Vector Space Bases Model Context? Massimo Melucci University of Padua Department of Information Engineering Via Gradenigo, 6/a 35031 Padova Italy melo@dei.unipd.it Abstract Current Information Retrieval

More information

Mathematical Logic Prof. Arindama Singh Department of Mathematics Indian Institute of Technology, Madras. Lecture - 15 Propositional Calculus (PC)

Mathematical Logic Prof. Arindama Singh Department of Mathematics Indian Institute of Technology, Madras. Lecture - 15 Propositional Calculus (PC) Mathematical Logic Prof. Arindama Singh Department of Mathematics Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Lecture - 15 Propositional Calculus (PC) So, now if you look back, you can see that there are three

More information

MITOCW watch?v=fkfsmwatddy

MITOCW watch?v=fkfsmwatddy MITOCW watch?v=fkfsmwatddy PROFESSOR: We've seen a lot of functions in introductory calculus-- trig functions, rational functions, exponentials, logs and so on. I don't know whether your calculus course

More information

Computational Tasks and Models

Computational Tasks and Models 1 Computational Tasks and Models Overview: We assume that the reader is familiar with computing devices but may associate the notion of computation with specific incarnations of it. Our first goal is to

More information

DM-Group Meeting. Subhodip Biswas 10/16/2014

DM-Group Meeting. Subhodip Biswas 10/16/2014 DM-Group Meeting Subhodip Biswas 10/16/2014 Papers to be discussed 1. Crowdsourcing Land Use Maps via Twitter Vanessa Frias-Martinez and Enrique Frias-Martinez in KDD 2014 2. Tracking Climate Change Opinions

More information

Spatial Computing. or how to design a right-brain hemisphere. Christian Freksa University of Bremen

Spatial Computing. or how to design a right-brain hemisphere. Christian Freksa University of Bremen Spatial Computing or how to design a right-brain hemisphere Christian Freksa University of Bremen 1 Acknowledgments 2 Some Examples of Spatial Problems (How) can I get the piano into my living room? How

More information

Machine Learning for Interpretation of Spatial Natural Language in terms of QSR

Machine Learning for Interpretation of Spatial Natural Language in terms of QSR Machine Learning for Interpretation of Spatial Natural Language in terms of QSR Parisa Kordjamshidi 1, Joana Hois 2, Martijn van Otterlo 1, and Marie-Francine Moens 1 1 Katholieke Universiteit Leuven,

More information

Energy Transformations IDS 101

Energy Transformations IDS 101 Energy Transformations IDS 101 It is difficult to design experiments that reveal what something is. As a result, scientists often define things in terms of what something does, what something did, or what

More information

A Comparison of Inferences about Containers and Surfaces in Small-Scale and Large-Scale Spaces *

A Comparison of Inferences about Containers and Surfaces in Small-Scale and Large-Scale Spaces * A Comparison of Inferences about Containers and Surfaces in Small-Scale and Large-Scale Spaces * M. Andrea Rodríguez and Max J. Egenhofer National Center for Geographic Information and Analysis and Department

More information

Motion and Forces. Describing Motion

Motion and Forces. Describing Motion CHAPTER Motion and Forces LESSON 1 Describing Motion What do you think? Read the two statements below and decide whether you agree or disagree with them. Place an A in the Before column if you agree with

More information

Languages, regular languages, finite automata

Languages, regular languages, finite automata Notes on Computer Theory Last updated: January, 2018 Languages, regular languages, finite automata Content largely taken from Richards [1] and Sipser [2] 1 Languages An alphabet is a finite set of characters,

More information

Fundamentals of Mathematics I

Fundamentals of Mathematics I Fundamentals of Mathematics I Kent State Department of Mathematical Sciences Fall 2008 Available at: http://www.math.kent.edu/ebooks/10031/book.pdf August 4, 2008 Contents 1 Arithmetic 2 1.1 Real Numbers......................................................

More information

Lecture 1: Geospatial Data Models

Lecture 1: Geospatial Data Models Lecture 1: GEOG413/613 Dr. Anthony Jjumba Introduction Course Outline Journal Article Review Projects (and short presentations) Final Exam (April 3) Participation in class discussions Geog413/Geog613 A

More information

3 The Semantics of the Propositional Calculus

3 The Semantics of the Propositional Calculus 3 The Semantics of the Propositional Calculus 1. Interpretations Formulas of the propositional calculus express statement forms. In chapter two, we gave informal descriptions of the meanings of the logical

More information

INVESTIGATING GEOSPARQL REQUIREMENTS FOR PARTICIPATORY URBAN PLANNING

INVESTIGATING GEOSPARQL REQUIREMENTS FOR PARTICIPATORY URBAN PLANNING INVESTIGATING GEOSPARQL REQUIREMENTS FOR PARTICIPATORY URBAN PLANNING E. Mohammadi a, *, A. J.S. Hunter a a Geomatics Department, Schulich School of Engineering, University of Calgary, Calgary, T2N 1N4,

More information

Basics of conversational implicatures

Basics of conversational implicatures Semantics I, Rutgers University Week 12 Yimei Xiang November 19, 2018 1. Implication relations Basics of conversational implicatures Implication relations are inferential relations between sentences. A

More information

Towards Usable Topological Operators at GIS User Interfaces

Towards Usable Topological Operators at GIS User Interfaces Towards Usable Topological Operators at GIS User Interfaces Catharina Riedemann Institute for Geoinformatics, University of Münster Münster, Germany riedemann@ifgi.uni-muenster.de SUMMARY The topological

More information

Set, functions and Euclidean space. Seungjin Han

Set, functions and Euclidean space. Seungjin Han Set, functions and Euclidean space Seungjin Han September, 2018 1 Some Basics LOGIC A is necessary for B : If B holds, then A holds. B A A B is the contraposition of B A. A is sufficient for B: If A holds,

More information

Guide to Proofs on Sets

Guide to Proofs on Sets CS103 Winter 2019 Guide to Proofs on Sets Cynthia Lee Keith Schwarz I would argue that if you have a single guiding principle for how to mathematically reason about sets, it would be this one: All sets

More information

Modern Algebra Prof. Manindra Agrawal Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur

Modern Algebra Prof. Manindra Agrawal Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur Modern Algebra Prof. Manindra Agrawal Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur Lecture 02 Groups: Subgroups and homomorphism (Refer Slide Time: 00:13) We looked

More information

Qualitative Spatial-Relation Reasoning for Design

Qualitative Spatial-Relation Reasoning for Design Qualitative Spatial-Relation Reasoning for Design Max J. Egenhofer National Center for Geographic Information and Analysis Department of Spatial Information Science and Engineering Department of Computer

More information

DATA DISAGGREGATION BY GEOGRAPHIC

DATA DISAGGREGATION BY GEOGRAPHIC PROGRAM CYCLE ADS 201 Additional Help DATA DISAGGREGATION BY GEOGRAPHIC LOCATION Introduction This document provides supplemental guidance to ADS 201.3.5.7.G Indicator Disaggregation, and discusses concepts

More information

Natural Language Processing Prof. Pawan Goyal Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kharagpur

Natural Language Processing Prof. Pawan Goyal Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kharagpur Natural Language Processing Prof. Pawan Goyal Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kharagpur Lecture - 18 Maximum Entropy Models I Welcome back for the 3rd module

More information

Midterm 1 Review. Distance = (x 1 x 0 ) 2 + (y 1 y 0 ) 2.

Midterm 1 Review. Distance = (x 1 x 0 ) 2 + (y 1 y 0 ) 2. Midterm 1 Review Comments about the midterm The midterm will consist of five questions and will test on material from the first seven lectures the material given below. No calculus either single variable

More information

The role of multiple representations in the understanding of ideal gas problems Madden S. P., Jones L. L. and Rahm J.

The role of multiple representations in the understanding of ideal gas problems Madden S. P., Jones L. L. and Rahm J. www.rsc.org/ xxxxxx XXXXXXXX The role of multiple representations in the understanding of ideal gas problems Madden S. P., Jones L. L. and Rahm J. Published in Chemistry Education Research and Practice,

More information

DIMENSIONS OF QUALITATIVE SPATIAL REASONING

DIMENSIONS OF QUALITATIVE SPATIAL REASONING In Qualitative Reasoning in Decision Technologies, Proc. QUARDET 93, N. Piera Carreté & M.G. Singh, eds., CIMNE Barcelona 1993, pp. 483-492. DIMENSIONS OF QUALITATIVE SPATIAL REASONING Christian Freksa

More information

Probabilistic models

Probabilistic models Kolmogorov (Andrei Nikolaevich, 1903 1987) put forward an axiomatic system for probability theory. Foundations of the Calculus of Probabilities, published in 1933, immediately became the definitive formulation

More information

Accelerated Observers

Accelerated Observers Accelerated Observers In the last few lectures, we ve been discussing the implications that the postulates of special relativity have on the physics of our universe. We ve seen how to compute proper times

More information

The Road to Improving your GIS Data. An ebook by Geo-Comm, Inc.

The Road to Improving your GIS Data. An ebook by Geo-Comm, Inc. The Road to Improving your GIS Data An ebook by Geo-Comm, Inc. An individual observes another person that appears to be in need of emergency assistance and makes the decision to place a call to 9-1-1.

More information

NEW YORK DEPARTMENT OF SANITATION. Spatial Analysis of Complaints

NEW YORK DEPARTMENT OF SANITATION. Spatial Analysis of Complaints NEW YORK DEPARTMENT OF SANITATION Spatial Analysis of Complaints Spatial Information Design Lab Columbia University Graduate School of Architecture, Planning and Preservation November 2007 Title New York

More information

A Class of Star-Algebras for Point-Based Qualitative Reasoning in Two- Dimensional Space

A Class of Star-Algebras for Point-Based Qualitative Reasoning in Two- Dimensional Space From: FLAIRS- Proceedings. Copyright AAAI (www.aaai.org). All rights reserved. A Class of Star-Algebras for Point-Based Qualitative Reasoning in Two- Dimensional Space Debasis Mitra Department of Computer

More information

The Logical Approach to Randomness

The Logical Approach to Randomness The Logical Approach to Randomness Christopher P. Porter University of Florida UC Irvine C-ALPHA Seminar May 12, 2015 Introduction The concept of randomness plays an important role in mathematical practice,

More information

FUZZY ASSOCIATION RULES: A TWO-SIDED APPROACH

FUZZY ASSOCIATION RULES: A TWO-SIDED APPROACH FUZZY ASSOCIATION RULES: A TWO-SIDED APPROACH M. De Cock C. Cornelis E. E. Kerre Dept. of Applied Mathematics and Computer Science Ghent University, Krijgslaan 281 (S9), B-9000 Gent, Belgium phone: +32

More information

Ontology on Shaky Grounds

Ontology on Shaky Grounds 1 Ontology on Shaky Grounds Jean-Pierre Marquis Département de Philosophie Université de Montréal C.P. 6128, succ. Centre-ville Montréal, P.Q. Canada H3C 3J7 Jean-Pierre.Marquis@umontreal.ca In Realistic

More information

Stochastic Histories. Chapter Introduction

Stochastic Histories. Chapter Introduction Chapter 8 Stochastic Histories 8.1 Introduction Despite the fact that classical mechanics employs deterministic dynamical laws, random dynamical processes often arise in classical physics, as well as in

More information

Global Machine Learning for Spatial Ontology Population

Global Machine Learning for Spatial Ontology Population Global Machine Learning for Spatial Ontology Population Parisa Kordjamshidi, Marie-Francine Moens KU Leuven, Belgium Abstract Understanding spatial language is important in many applications such as geographical

More information

Pragmatic effects in processing superlative and comparative quantifiers: epistemic-algorithmic approach

Pragmatic effects in processing superlative and comparative quantifiers: epistemic-algorithmic approach Pragmatic effects in processing superlative and comparative quantifiers: epistemic-algorithmic approach Maria Spychalska, Institute of Philosophy II, Ruhr-University Bochum September 27, 2013 1 2 3 Superlative

More information

Spatial Intelligence. Angela Schwering

Spatial Intelligence. Angela Schwering Spatial Intelligence Angela Schwering What I do What I do intelligent representation and processing of spatial information From the Cognitive Perspective How do humans perceive spatial information? How

More information

Elementary Linear Algebra, Second Edition, by Spence, Insel, and Friedberg. ISBN Pearson Education, Inc., Upper Saddle River, NJ.

Elementary Linear Algebra, Second Edition, by Spence, Insel, and Friedberg. ISBN Pearson Education, Inc., Upper Saddle River, NJ. 2008 Pearson Education, Inc., Upper Saddle River, NJ. All rights reserved. APPENDIX: Mathematical Proof There are many mathematical statements whose truth is not obvious. For example, the French mathematician

More information

Lecture 12: Arguments for the absolutist and relationist views of space

Lecture 12: Arguments for the absolutist and relationist views of space 12.1 432018 PHILOSOPHY OF PHYSICS (Spring 2002) Lecture 12: Arguments for the absolutist and relationist views of space Preliminary reading: Sklar, pp. 19-25. Now that we have seen Newton s and Leibniz

More information

Transformation of Geographical Information into Linguistic Sentences: Two Case Studies

Transformation of Geographical Information into Linguistic Sentences: Two Case Studies Transformation of Geographical Information into Linguistic Sentences: Two Case Studies Jan T. Bjørke, Ph.D. Norwegian Defence Research Establishment P O Box 115, NO-3191 Horten NORWAY jtb@ffi.no Information

More information

Data Cleaning and Query Answering with Matching Dependencies and Matching Functions

Data Cleaning and Query Answering with Matching Dependencies and Matching Functions Data Cleaning and Query Answering with Matching Dependencies and Matching Functions Leopoldo Bertossi 1, Solmaz Kolahi 2, and Laks V. S. Lakshmanan 2 1 Carleton University, Ottawa, Canada. bertossi@scs.carleton.ca

More information