Retail Realism and Wholesale Treatments of Theoretical Entities

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Retail Realism and Wholesale Treatments of Theoretical Entities"

Transcription

1 Retail Realism and Wholesale Treatments of Theoretical Entities Jonathon Hricko 1 Short Abstract: According to retail realism, we ought to abandon wholesale arguments, which purport to demonstrate realism or anti-realism about theoretical entities in general, and embrace retail arguments, which purport to demonstrate realism or anti-realism about specific kinds of theoretical entities. My aim is to argue that there is a further wholesale element that retail realism must avoid in order to qualify as a viable position. In order to do so, I distinguish between what I call wholesale and retail treatments of theoretical entities. Wholesale treatments individuate theoretical entities in such a way that the same entity can appear in distinct theories. In that case, realism about a given entity implies realism about that entity as it appears in a number of distinct theories. Retail treatments, on the other hand, individuate theoretical entities more finely, so that distinct theories actually involve distinct entities. In that case, realism about one entity needn t imply realism about a similar, but distinct, entity. I argue that retail realists ought to reject wholesale treatments in favor of retail treatments, and I do so by examining a case from the history of chemistry involving the hypothetical constituent of hydrochloric acid known as the muriatic radical. I argue that there are distinct muriatic radicals in distinct theories, and that we ought to be realists about some, but not others. Hence, in this case, a retail treatment is preferable to a wholesale one, and I conclude by discussing why the combination of retail realism and retail treatments constitutes an attractive position within the scientific realism debate more generally. 1 Institute of European and American Studies, Academia Sinica, jonathon [dot] hricko [at] gmail [dot] com. 1

2 Long Abstract: One of the central questions of the scientific realism debate concerns the existence of theoretical entities. According to retail realism, we ought to abandon wholesale arguments, which purport to demonstrate realism or anti-realism about theoretical entities in general, and embrace retail arguments, which purport to demonstrate realism or anti-realism about specific kinds of theoretical entities. My aim is to argue that there is a further wholesale element that retail realism must avoid in order to qualify as a viable position. In order to do so, I distinguish between what I call wholesale and retail treatments of theoretical entities. Wholesale treatments individuate theoretical entities in such a way that the same entity can appear in distinct theories, which may contain conflicting descriptions of the entity in question. In that case, realism about a given entity implies realism about that entity as it appears in a number of distinct theories. Retail treatments, on the other hand, individuate theoretical entities more finely, so that distinct theories actually involve distinct entities. In that case, realism about one entity needn t imply realism about a similar, but distinct, entity. I argue that retail realists ought to reject wholesale treatments in favor of retail treatments. In order to make this argument, I discuss a case from the history of chemistry, namely, the case of the muriatic radical. In the late eighteenth century, Antoine Lavoisier held that all acids are composed of oxygen and another component, which Lavoisier called the radical; and that acids differ from one another insofar as they have different radicals. Though he couldn t decompose muriatic acid to show that it contains oxygen, he hypothesized that it is composed of oxygen and an unknown radical the muriatic radical. In 1810, Humphry Davy argued, contrary to Lavoisier s hypothesis, that muriatic acid is composed of hydrogen and chlorine, and so it is what we now call hydrochloric acid. After an initial period of opposition to Davy s views, Jöns Jacob Berzelius went on to develop a view of acids that can be seen as a synthesis of Lavoisier s and Davy s views. Lavoisier was correct about so-called oxygenous acids, while Davy was correct about muriatic acid because the latter is not an oxygenous acid, but rather a hydracid. Hydracids are composed of hydrogen combined with a radical, in which case the muriatic radical for Berzelius is chlorine. A wholesale treatment would imply that both Lavoisier and Berzelius were employing the same theoretical entity. A retail treatment, on the other hand, would imply that Lavoisier s radical and Berzelius s radical are distinct theoretical entities. I argue in favor of a retail treatment, on the grounds that 2

3 distinguishing Lavoisier s radical from Berzelius s allows us to be anti-realists about the former, and realists about the latter. In this case, then, a retail treatment yields a desirable kind of selective realism which is unavailable to a proponent of a wholesale treatment. I conclude by discussing why the combination of retail realism and retail treatments constitutes an attractive position within the scientific realism debate more generally. Contents 1 Retail Realism 4 2 Wholesale and Retail Treatments of Theoretical Entities 7 3 The Case of the Muriatic Radical(s) The Prehistory of the Muriatic Radical Lavoisier s Oxygen Theory of Acidity Davy s Work on the Acids Berzelius s Work on Hydracids How Many Muriatic Radicals Are There? Anti-realism About Lavoisier s Radical Realism About Berzelius s Radical A Retail Treatment of the Muriatic Radical(s) Retail Realism and Retail Treatments 23 3

4 1 Retail Realism One of the central questions of the scientific realism debate is whether or not the entities posited in our best scientific theories exist. Realists claim that such theoretical entities do exist, while anti-realists either claim that they don t, or that we ought to be agnostic about whether they do. Magnus and Callender (2004) have pointed out that there are, in fact, two types of arguments that philosophers involved in the realism debate, whether realists or anti-realists, use in order to answer questions about the existence of theoretical entities. On the one hand, there are wholesale arguments, which are arguments about all or most of the entities posited in our best scientific theories ; on the other hand, there are retail arguments which are arguments about specific kinds of things such as neutrinos, for instance (ibid.: 321). Magnus and Callender go on to argue that the only viable way forward in the realism debate requires that we abandon wholesale arguments, and focus on retail arguments. Once we do, we must reject wholesale realism and anti-realism. The only kind of realism that survives is a kind of retail realism about some entities but not others as they put it, there may be good reasons to be a realist about neutrinos, an anti-realist about top quarks, and so on (ibid.: 333). They admit that such a situation may cause discomfort to both realists and anti-realists, but this is a price that Magnus and Callender are willing to pay to make progress in the debate. A glance at recent work in the realism debate shows that there is much of which Magnus and Callender would approve. As Dicken (2013) argues, one can find retail realism in the work of a number of philosophers, including Psillos (2009), Saatsi (2010), and Stanford (2006). Moreover, given that much of the debate has centered on specific kinds of entities, like phlogiston, caloric, and the optical ether, there is no shortage of retail arguments on offer. 1 While wholesale arguments have not been abandoned by all philosophers involved in the debate, it s fair to say that many philosophers have chosen to focus their efforts on retail arguments instead. There are at least two main reasons why philosophers have deemed it a good idea to abandon wholesale arguments in favor of retail arguments. The first has to do with what are perhaps the two most influential arguments in the realism debate, namely, the no-miracles argument and the pessimistic 1 See, for example, the discussion of phlogiston in Ladyman (2011), the discussion of caloric in Chang (2003), and the discussion of the optical ether in Cordero (2011). 4

5 meta-induction. According to the no-miracles argument, the explanatory and predictive success of our best scientific theories would be miraculous if those theories weren t genuinely referential and at least approximately true. This argument is usually taken to support some form of realism. The pessimistic meta-induction, on the other hand, draws upon our past theories, which were successful but false, as an inductive basis for inferring inductively that our current successful theories are false as well. It is usually taken to support some form of anti-realism. A number of philosophers have argued that both arguments are best construed as statistical arguments, and that as such, both suffer from the base rate fallacy. Howson (2000, 52 54) has argued that the no-miracles argument ignores the base rate of true theories in a population, and Lewis (2001) has argued that the pessimistic meta-induction does as well. The unavailability of these base rates is Magnus and Callender s primary reason for thinking that realists and anti-realists are mostly talking past one another, and for abandoning wholesale arguments in favor of retail arguments. The second reason for abandoning wholesale arguments has to do with Laudan s confutation of realism (Laudan, 1981). 2 In the spirit of the nomiracles argument, realists claim that the success of our best theories provides evidence for their approximate truth. Laudan, in response, presents a long list of purported counterexamples to this claim. The list includes the phlogiston theory of combustion, the wave theory of light, and the caloric theory of heat, which were all quite successful in their day. But given that these theories involve terms ( phlogiston, ether, and caloric ) that the realist categorizes as paradigm cases of empty names, these are theories that, by the realist s own lights, presumably fail to be even approximately true. 3 Given that Laudan s argument depends on the details of the theories he discusses, responses to his argument, and responses to those responses, have focused on specific entities posited in specific theories. As such, these responses count as retail arguments, as opposed to wholesale arguments. Laudan s argument has also motivated philosophers to search for other theories that may spell trouble for the realist, which, in turn, has led to even more retail arguments. 4 2 Although it is common to read Laudan as advancing a form of the pessimistic metainduction, Lyons (2002) shows that he is not. 3 But as Frost-Arnold (2011, 2013) has recently argued, this may not render such theories false given some commonly-held views in semantics, such theories may actually lack truth-values. 4 Vickers (2013) provides a useful list of the theories that such philosophers have dis- 5

6 For these and other reasons, I take it that retail realism represents a genuine step forward in the realism debate. That said, there are a number of ways in which to develop this position, and I ll argue that some ways are better than others. To that end, in section 2, I ll distinguish two ways of developing retail realism, which I call wholesale and retail treatments of theoretical entities. Wholesale treatments individuate theoretical entities in such a way that the same entity can appear in distinct theories, which may contain conflicting descriptions of the entity in question. In that case, realism about a given entity implies realism about that entity as it appears in a number of distinct theories. Retail treatments, on the other hand, individuate theoretical entities more finely, so that distinct theories actually involve distinct entities. In that case, realism about one entity needn t imply realism about a similar, but distinct, entity. My primary goal is to argue that retail realists ought to reject wholesale treatments in favor of retail treatments. My argument will make use of a case from the history of chemistry, namely, the case of the muriatic radical, and in section 3, I discuss the details of that case. In the late eighteenth century, Antoine Lavoisier held that all acids are composed of oxygen and another component, which Lavoisier called the radical; and that acids differ from one another insofar as they have different radicals. Though he couldn t decompose muriatic acid to show that it contains oxygen, he hypothesized that it is composed of oxygen and an unknown radical the muriatic radical. In 1810, Humphry Davy argued, contrary to Lavoisier s hypothesis, that muriatic acid is composed of hydrogen and chlorine, and so it is what we now call hydrochloric acid. After an initial period of opposition to Davy s views, Jöns Jacob Berzelius went on to develop a view of acids that can be seen as a synthesis of Lavoisier s and Davy s views. Lavoisier was correct about so-called oxygenous acids, while Davy was correct about muriatic acid because the latter is not an oxygenous acid, but rather a hydracid. Hydracids are composed of hydrogen combined with a radical, in which case the muriatic radical for Berzelius is chlorine. A wholesale treatment would imply that both Lavoisier and Berzelius were, in one way or another, employing the same theoretical entity, while a retail treatment would imply that Lavoisier s radical and Berzelius s radical are distinct theoretical entities. In section 4, I argue in favor of a retail treatment, on the grounds that distinguishing Lavoisier s radical from Berzelius s cussed, as well as some previously undiscussed cases that are of potential interest. 6

7 allows us to be anti-realists about the former, and realists about the latter. In this case, then, a retail treatment yields a desirable kind of selective realism which is unavailable to a proponent of a wholesale treatment. Finally, in section 5, I conclude by discussing why the combination of retail realism and retail treatments constitutes an attractive position within the scientific realism debate more generally. 2 Wholesale and Retail Treatments of Theoretical Entities My primary goal is to argue that there is a further wholesale element that retail realism must avoid so as to qualify as a viable position. In order to do so, my aim in this section is to introduce the notions of wholesale and retail treatments of theoretical entities. In the remainder of the paper, I will argue that retail realists should avoid the former, and adopt the latter instead. Before we re able to see what these treatments are and how they differ from one another, though, we must start by first recalling that retail realists restrict their arguments to specific kinds of theoretical entities. To take a concrete example, in response to the question Are there atoms?, Magnus and Callender claim that a retail realist will cite the same evidence scientists use to support the atomic hypothesis; e.g., Einstein and Smoluchowski s Brownian motion theory and the experiments by Perrin in 1908 (op. cit.: 321). More generally, retail realists seek to answer questions of the form: Are there xs?, where x stands for some theoretical entity. Realists about x will answer Yes, while anti-realists about x will answer No. In order to avoid familiar puzzles concerning speaking of what is not, I suggest that these questions, along with the notion of a theoretical entity, be understood in a particular way. To a first approximation, realists and anti-realists share an understanding of a given theoretical entity in a sense similar to the one in which theists, atheists, and agnostics share an understanding of God there is some consensus regarding what the entity would be like if it existed, and the debate concerns whether it does, in fact, exist. This notion of a theoretical entity can usefully be understood in terms of what Rheinberger (1997) calls epistemic things and what Chang (2011) calls epistemic objects. In Chang s words, these are objects as we conceive them in our interaction with them, without a presumption that our 7

8 conceptions correspond in some intractable sense to the shape of an external world that is entirely divorced from ourselves (ibid.: 413). As I will use the terminology, then, a theoretical entity is an epistemic object in Chang s sense it s a conception involved in our theorizing about the world. When philosophers engaged in the realism debate ask whether a theoretical entity exists, then, they are not asking whether scientists currently have or previously had such-and-such a conception. Instead, they are asking whether there is the right kind of correspondence between that conception and entities that exist independently of our minds, which I will call empirical entities. 5 Realists claim that there is such a correspondence, while antirealists either deny that there is, or claim that we cannot know. In that case, if retail arguments are to provide any guidance regarding the attitudes which we ought to take towards various theoretical entities, one first needs to know how to individuate theoretical entities. A glance at the history of science shows that this is not as straightforward as one might initially think. Consider, for example, Dalton s atom in contrast to Boscovich s, or Stahl s phlogiston in contrast to Priestley s, or Lavoisier s caloric in contrast to Carnot s, or Dirac s positron in contrast to Anderson s, or Lorentz s electron in contrast to Millikan s. In such cases, one can ask whether the scientists in question were working with the same theoretical entity, or with distinct entities. At this point, we can be clear about what wholesale and retail treatments of theoretical entities amount to. Wholesale treatments are committed to the claim that the same theoretical entity can appear in distinct theories, even if those theories involve conflicting descriptions of the entity in question. Retail treatments, on the other hand, are committed to the claim that distinct theories involve distinct theoretical entities, even if those entities sometimes share striking similarities. Retail treatments, then, commit one to individuating entities as finely as one individuates theories. Wholesale treatments, in contrast, commit one to individuating entities at a grain coarser than the grain at which one individuates theories. Retail and wholesale treatments, then, concern different ways of individuating theoretical entities. These competing ways of individuating theoretical entities have implications for the realism debate, which I ve characterized as involving questions 5 Being more precise about the right kind of correspondence would obviously involve addressing many central issues in philosophy, and for the sake of brevity, I must leave these issues unaddressed and work with an intuitive notion of the correspondence in question. 8

9 about the relations between our theoretical entities and empirical entities that exist in the world. Retail realists are thus faced with a choice concerning which treatment to adopt, and each treatment lends itself to a distinct position regarding realism about a given theoretical entity. On the one hand, if a retail realist adopts a wholesale treatment, then realism about some theoretical entity implies realism about that entity as it appears in a number of distinct theories. On the other hand, if a retail realist adopts a retail treatment, then realism about some theoretical entity needn t imply realism about a similar, but distinct, entity drawn from a distinct theory. And, of course, similar remarks apply to anti-realism about various kinds of entities. In short, then, wholesale treatments lead to either wholesale acceptance or wholesale rejection of a theoretical entity as it appears in a number of distinct theories, while retail treatments allow for the possibility of proceeding on a case-by-case basis, which can lead to a kind of selective realism about some theoretical entities, but not others. While the terminology that I have chosen to adopt here may be new, the ideas themselves are not, and both wholesale and retail treatments have had their defenders. To take a prominent example of a defender of the latter, (Kuhn, 2012/1962, 102) commits himself to a retail treatment of mass when he argues that Newton s mass and Einstein s mass have distinct physical referents. Kuhnian incommensurability thus implies that wholesale treatments ought to be rejected in favor of retail ones. More generally, any holistic view of the meaning of theoretical terms shares this commitment. If the meaning of a theoretical term is fixed entirely by a set of descriptions or operations, then any change in the set of those descriptions or operations results in a distinct entity. To take a recent example, (Worrall, 2011, 169) argues that our knowledge of theoretical entities is purely descriptive, and that the Ramsey sentence of a theory yields the relevant description. Distinct theories with distinct Ramsey sentences will therefore involve distinct theoretical entities, in which case Worrall s position entails a commitment to retail treatments of theoretical entities. Wholesale treatments have had prominent defenders as well. For some time now, scientific realists in the tradition of Boyd (1981) and Putnam (1975) have been opposed to Kuhnian incommensurability and to holistic views of meaning more generally, and have thus embraced wholesale treatments over retail ones. Putnam s work on meaning and reference is particularly important in this regard, as it showed the possibility of distinct theories referring to the same entity. As is well known, Putnam s work, combined with 9

10 that of Kripke (1980), convinced many philosophers that the mechanisms in virtue of which reference is fixed, and those in virtue of which distinct speakers can refer to the same entity, must, at least in part, be causal. This conviction has survived for some time now, as one can see in more recent work by Psillos (1999), and Stanford and Kitcher (2000), who incorporate causal elements into their theories of reference so as to allow for wholesale treatments of theoretical entities. These views, at least as I have discussed them, individuate theoretical entities by appeal to specific views about meaning, and it may seem that such consequences can only result from conflating issues in the philosophy of language with issues in metaphysics. But this is not the case. Given that the notion of theoretical entity at issue here concerns our conceptions, the question of individuation concerns the individuation of those conceptions. The question of realism concerns the correspondence between those conceptions, individuated in a particular way, and empirical entities that exist independently of us. While wholesale and retail treatments are not new, they have, in the past, been wedded to wholesale positions in the realism debate, with wholesale realists generally advocating wholesale treatments and wholesale anti-realists advocating retail treatments. 6 Although this may be well-traveled ground when it comes to wholesale positions in the debate, it s as yet an open question whether retail realists ought to opt for wholesale treatments or retail ones. Given the terminology that I ve introduced, my view that they should opt for the latter should come as no surprise. In the remainder of the paper, I will argue that the commitment to wholesale treatments is a wholesale element that retail realists ought to reject, and I will do so by examining a case from the history of chemistry involving the so-called muriatic radical. My goal is to argue that there are distinct muriatic radicals in distinct theories, and that we ought to be realists about some, but not others. In that case, a retail treatment is preferable to a wholesale one. Given the importance of the historical details to the argument that I aim to give, in the next section, I concern myself with an examination of those details. 6 There are, of course, exceptions for example, Worrall (op. cit.) defends a form of structural realism, while Stanford (2006) has gone on to defend a form of anti-realism. 10

11 3 The Case of the Muriatic Radical(s) My goal in this section is to discuss the case of the muriatic radical, which chemists in the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries hypothesized to be a constituent of muriatic acid, now known as hydrochloric acid. Though I ll sometimes write of the muriatic radical for ease of exposition, I will argue in the next section that this locution is a bit misleading since we can and should distinguish different radicals in different theories, it would be more accurate to call it the case of the muriatic radicals. For the time being, though, I will attempt to remain neutral on this issue, and I will focus on the radical as it appears in the work of three chemists, namely, Lavoisier, Davy, and Berzelius. However, before doing so, it will be necessary to say something about the state of chemistry before chemists hypothesized the muriatic radical. 3.1 The Prehistory of the Muriatic Radical Chemists in the later years of the eighteenth century worked with a scheme for classifying substances that included a kind of substance that they called acids, and they used a number of properties in order to distinguish acids from non-acids. Nicholson s Dictionary of Chemistry enumerates these properties as follows: 1. Their taste is sour and corrosive, unless diluted with water. 2. They change blue vegetable colors to a red. 3. Most of them unite with water in all proportions; and many have so strong an attraction to that fluid as not to be exhibited in the solid state. 4. At a moderate temperature, or in the humid way, they combine with alkalis so strongly as to take them from all other substances. 5. They combine with most bodies, and form combinations attended with many interesting phenomena; upon the due explanation of which a great part of the science of chemistry depends. (Nicholson, 1795, 2) The kind acids, then, was delineated, not in terms of the inner constitution of such substances, but phenomenologically, in terms of various properties that chemists at the time could observe. Of all the substances that chemists classified as acids at the time, two will be important in what follows. The first was variously referred to as 11

12 acid of sea-salt, marine acid, and muriatic acid, and it is what we now call hydrochloric acid. The second was variously referred to as dephlogisticated marine acid, oxygenated muriatic acid, and oxymuriatic acid, and it is what we now call chlorine. For the sake of clarity, in what follows I ll settle on a single name for each, and I ll refer to these two substances as muriatic acid and oxymuriatic acid, respectively. Chemists had been working with muriatic acid for some time, but oxymuriatic acid was not isolated until Scheele was the first to do so, and though he classified the substance as an acid, he notes that it has the properties that chemists associated with acidity to a lesser extent than other acids (Scheele, 1786/1774, 92 93). Subsequent chemists both followed Scheele s classification of the substance as an acid, and his acknowledgement that, even so, it wasn t much of an acid. 7 As a proponent of the phlogiston theory, Scheele put forward the view that oxymuriatic acid is muriatic acid devoid of its phlogiston hence the terminology dephlogisticated marine acid (ibid.: 93). On Scheele s view, then, oxymuriatic acid is the simpler substance, and it is a component of muriatic acid. But while chemists followed Scheele s classification of this new substance, not all followed his views regarding the constitution of the two acids. 3.2 Lavoisier s Oxygen Theory of Acidity In the later years of the eighteenth century, Lavoisier developed his oxygen theory of acidity. His central claim regarding acids is that oxygen is an element common to them all, which constitutes their acidity (Lavoisier, 1965/1789, 65). He supports this claim by appealing to three examples of substances that combine with oxygen to form acids: phosphorus, sulphur, and carbon, according to Lavoisier, each combine with oxygen to form phosphoric acid, sulphuric acid, and carbonic acid, respectively (ibid.: 60 65). He concludes that we must therefore, in every acid, carefully distinguish between the acidifiable base, which Mr de Morveau calls the radical, and the acidifying principle or oxygen (ibid.: 65). While all acids for Lavoisier contain oxygen, they contain different bases, or synonymously, radicals these constituent substances are what ground the differences between differ- 7 For the latter point, see, for example, Berthollet (1788, 279), Lavoisier (1965/1789, 73), Nicholson (1795, 27), and Davy (1810a, 70). 12

13 ent kinds of acids, and they can be simple or compound (ibid.: 115). In the examples mentioned above, phosphorus, sulphur, and carbon are the bases phosphoric acid, sulphuric acid, and carbonic acid, respectively. 8 While Lavoisier was able to show that a number of acids contain oxygen, he was unable to show that every acid does. Boracic acid, fluoric acid, and muriatic acid proved to be problematic, but Lavoisier is clear that his theory extends to these substances as well. He claims that these acids are each composed of oxygen combined with a hypothetical radical, and indeed, one finds the boracic radical, the fluoric radical, and the muriatic radical in Lavoisier s table of simple substances (ibid.: 175). Lavoisier hypothesizes the muriatic radical in a particularly striking passage: Although we have not yet been able, either to compose or to decompound this acid of sea-salt, we cannot have the smallest doubt that it, like all other acids, is composed by the union of oxygen with an acidifiable base. We have therefore called this unknown substance the muriatic base, or muriatic radical, deriving this name, after the example of Mr Bergman and Mr de Morveau, from the Latin word muria, which was anciently used to signify sea-salt. (ibid.: 71 72) Lavoisier s reference to Guyton de Morveau is noteworthy, as the latter hypothesizes the radical in a similar passage: Analogy induces us to think that the muriatic acid has an acidifiable base, as well as the carbonic, sulphuric, and phosphoric acids, which like the bases of these latter, serves to give a distinct and particular property to the produce of a combination of oxygen. We could not express this substance otherwise than by the name muriatic radical or muriatic radical principle... (Guyton de Morveau, Lavoisier, Berthollet, and Fourcroy, 1788, 33 34) In accordance with the oxygen theory of acidity, acids are not simple substances, and muriatic acid was no exception. Proponents of that theory 8 This use of terminology was not restricted to acids, but was applied to kinds of substances in general. For example, gases are a kind of substance, and for Lavoisier, all gases contain caloric; different kinds of gases differ from one another in virtue of the fact that they have different bases (oxygen, hydrogen, etc.) (ibid.: 15). 13

14 therefore had to hypothesize that it contains oxygen, like all other acids, and a hypothetical base or radical the muriatic radical. Lavoisier and his followers also theorized about the nature of oxymuriatic acid, which they viewed to be a compound of oxygen and muriatic acid (Lavoisier, 1965/1789, 73; Berthollet, 1788, 279). The view of the oxygen theorists is thus a complete reversal of Scheele s view, according to which oxymuriatic acid is the simpler substance. This makes sense once one recognizes that the substance that phlogiston theorists like Scheele labeled dephlogisticated air is the oxygen of the oxygen theorists. The considerations that led Scheele to classify oxymuriatic acid as muriatic acid devoid of its phlogiston thus led the oxygen theorists to classify it as muriatic acid saturated with oxygen. Thus, the muriatic radical is a constituent, not only of muriatic acid, but of of oxymuriatic acid as well. In sum, Lavoisier s oxygen theory of acidity yields the following view of the two substances: muriatic acid is made up of the muriatic radical and oxygen, while oxymuriatic acid results from adding oxygen to muriatic acid. For Lavoisier and those who shared his views on acidity, the muriatic radical was therefore a hypothetical component of both of these substances. 3.3 Davy s Work on the Acids One of the outstanding issues in chemistry at the time was to decompose these acids and isolate the muriatic radical. One chemist who attempted to do so was Davy, who, for some time, shared Lavoisier s view that both acids contain oxygen. But in 1810, the year in which his work on the acids culminated, Davy rejects Lavoisier s view. In a paper read in July of that year, Davy claims that the presence of oxygen in the acids has not been demonstrated: in the usual cases where oxygene is procured from oxymuriatic acid, water is always present, and muriatic acid gas is formed; now, as it is shewn that oxymuriatic acid gas is converted into muriatic acid gas, by combining with hydrogene, it is scarcely possible to avoid the conclusion, that the oxygene is derived from the decomposition of water, and, consequently, that the idea of the existence of water in muriatic acid gas, is hypothetical, depending upon an assumption which has not yet been proved the existence of oxygene in oxymuriatic acid gas. (Davy, 1810b, 236) 14

15 What really happens, then, is that the oxymuriatic acid decomposes the water, combining with the hydrogen to form muriatic acid and leaving oxygen as a byproduct. Since oxymuriatic acid is actually a component of muriatic acid, and since the production of oxygen in various experiments can be traced back to the water, the existence of oxygen in oxymuriatic acid has not been proven. And because of this fact, combined with the fact that the components of muriatic acid are oxymuriatic acid and hydrogen, the existence of oxygen in muriatic acid is similarly hypothetical. Davy s view of muriatic acid, then, is that it is made up of oxymuriatic acid and hydrogen, and in a striking passage, he concludes that Scheele s phlogiston theory yields the correct view of the acids, while Lavoisier s oxygen theory does not: It is evident from this series of observations, that Scheele s view, (though obscured by terms derived from a vague and unfounded general theory,) of the nature of the oxymuriatic and muriatic acids, may be considered as an expression of facts; whilst the view adopted by the French school of chemistry, and which, till it is minutely examined, appears so beautiful and satisfactory, rests in the present state of our knowledge, upon hypothetical grounds. (ibid.: 237) Given that Scheele held that muriatic acid contains oxymuriatic acid and phlogiston, it may not be obvious how his view can be an expression of facts. This becomes clear once one recognizes that many chemists at the time identified phlogiston with hydrogen. Priestley did so as early as 1782 in his correspondences (Priestley, 1892, 33), and Kirwan did as well (Kirwan, 1789, 4 5). By the early nineteenth century, the identification of phlogiston and hydrogen was more-or-less commonplace in the work of many chemists. To take an example from Davy s work, when discussing some hypotheses regarding the constitution of metals, he writes of the adherence of their phlogiston or hydrogene, without pausing to explain the identification of phlogiston and hydrogen (Davy, 1808, 364). Given this identification, Scheele s view amounts to the claim that muriatic acid contains oxymuriatic acid and hydrogen, which is essentially correct. While Davy provides some moderate praise for Scheele s view, he also points to the shortcomings of the oxygen theory. If the principle of acidity, namely, oxygen, isn t present in these two acids, then that theory would seem to be in serious trouble. Davy even goes so far as to speculate that 15

16 oxymuriatic acid may be another principle of acidity, and that on this idea muriatic acid may be considered as having hydrogene for its basis, and oxymuriatic acid for its acidifying principle (Davy, 1810b, 243). Davy, of course, recognized that both oxygen and oxymuriatic acid are attracted to the positive surface of a Voltaic battery, while hydrogen is attracted to the negative surface(ibid.: ). It s probable that this analogy is what led him to speculate that oxymuriatic acid is the acidifying principle, leaving hydrogen as the muriatic radical. In the Bakerian Lecture that he gave in November of 1810, Davy argues for a claim that Gay-Lussac and Thénard considered and rejected about a year earlier, namely, that oxymuriatic acid ought to be considered an element (Gay-Lussac and Thénard, 1809, 358). And in light of the fact that oxymuriatic acid has not as yet been decompounded, and is elementary as far as our knowledge extends (Davy (1811), 1), Davy pushes for a change in terminology: To call a body which is not known to contain oxygene, and which cannot contain muriatic acid, oxymuriatic acid, is contrary to the principles of that nomenclature in which it is adopted... (ibid.: 32) He goes on to suggest the names chlorine, and chloric gas. Davy is thus credited with showing that muriatic acid is composed of hydrogen and chlorine, and that the latter is an element. And although he saw no reason to reject the term muriatic acid (ibid.: 33), his work shows why we now refer to that acid as hydrochloric acid. 3.4 Berzelius s Work on Hydracids While Davy is credited with these achievements today, his views did not go unchallenged. One of his most prominent critics was Berzelius, who, for some time, opposed Davy s views and defended a form of Lavoisier s oxygen theory of acidity. Berzelius frames his view in terms of Dalton s atomic theory, and claims that muriatic acid contains one atom of muriatic radical and two atoms of oxygen, while oxymuriatic acid contains one atom of muriatic radical and three atoms of oxygen (Berzelius, 1813, 254). 9 He 9 Though elsewhere, he puts this in terms of volumes as opposed to atoms (Berzelius, 1816, 276). 16

17 emphasizes that, although pure muriatic acid does not contain water as a component, that acid is incapable of existing without water, and thus the acid with which we are familiar is impure (Berzelius, 1813, 254; Berzelius, 1816, 273). In theory then, one can add oxygen to pure muriatic acid to obtain oxymuriatic acid. But given that muriatic acid is always mixed with water, there s a sense in which one can obtain the impure acid by adding hydrogen to oxymuriatic acid. In such a reaction, the oxymuriatic acid loses a volume of oxygen, and so is converted to pure muriatic acid. That volume of oxygen combines with the hydrogen to form water, and hence the result is impure muriatic acid. Regarding the radical in particular, Berzelius claims that its nature is still unknown, and that chemists have not succeeded in isolating it (Berzelius, 1813, 254; Berzelius, 1816, 263). Berzelius eventually dropped his opposition to Davy, and accepted the latter s view that muriatic acid is made up of hydrogen and chlorine, which he, following Davy, regarded as an element (Berzelius, 1825, ). However, his theorizing about the nature of muriatic acid, and of acids more generally, continued. More specifically, he claims that there is a class of acids, namely, hydracids, of which muriatic acid is an example (ibid.: 181). A hydracid for Berzelius is a combination of a simple or compound body with hydrogen, which, although destitute of oxygen, possesses all the essential characters of the oxygenous acids (ibid.: 180). Berzelius goes on to claim that hydracids must be regarded, therefore, as constituted of hydrogen and a peculiar radical, which, as is the case with the oxygen acids, may be either simple or compound (ibid.: 180). It follows, then, that on Berzelius s view, chlorine is the muriatic radical. Berzelius s view can be seen as a synthesis of the views of both Davy and Lavoisier. On Berzelius s view, Davy, and not Lavoisier, was correct about the constitution of muriatic acid; however, while Lavoisier s theory is incorrect when it comes to muriatic acid and other hydracids, it gives the correct results if restricted to oxygenous acids. Berzelius work on hydracids shows that the muriatic radical still had a place in chemistry well after Davy s determination of the constituents of muriatic acid. But, of course, this was not the case for long, and our current theories of acidity make no reference to the acidifable radicals and bases of the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries. 17

18 4 How Many Muriatic Radicals Are There? My goal at this point is to argue that, when it comes to the case of the muriatic radical(s), a retail treatment is preferable to a wholesale one. More specifically, I ll argue that we ought to view Lavoisier s radical and Berzelius s radical as two distinct theoretical entities, as opposed to one and the same entity with which two scientists worked. The main thrust of my argument is that, if we distinguish Lavoisier s radical from Berzelius s radical, there are good reasons to be anti-realists about the former, and realists about the latter. More specifically, I ll argue that we ought to be anti-realists about Lavoisier s radical, because the right kind of correspondence between this theoretical entity and an empirical entity is lacking; and that we ought to be realists about Berzelius s radical, because there is such a correspondence with an empirical entity, namely, chlorine. If we adopt a wholesale treatment, this kind of selective realism is unavailable, since such treatments do not individuate theoretical entities at a grain fine enough. Retail treatments, however, do individuate theoretical entities at a grain fine enough, and so allow for this kind of selective realism. I conclude, then, that the case of the muriatic radical requires a retail treatment as opposed to a wholesale one. 4.1 Anti-realism About Lavoisier s Radical In light of the fact that Lavoisier s theory of acidity was completely wrong, and the fact that he was completely wrong about the nature of muriatic acid and of oxymuriatic acid, we ought to be anti-realists about Lavoisier s radical. He held that both substances contain oxygen, which, of course, turned out to be false; and he held that both substances share another component, which turned out to be false as well. Moreover, he held that this other component, the muriatic radical, had not been isolated, and so he made no attempt to identify the radical with any well-known substance which chemists could isolate. For Lavoisier, then, the muriatic radical was that substance which combines with oxygen to form both muriatic acid and oxymuriatic acid. If that is what the muriatic radical is, then the most reasonable conclusion to draw is that there is no such thing. In that case, we ought to be anti-realists about Lavoisier s radical there is no empirical entity that corresponds to this theoretical entity. Although the muriatic radical is not often discussed by philosophers of science, Chang is an exception, and his work provides some support for an 18

19 anti-realist attitude towards Lavoisier s radical. Though he doesn t distinguish different radicals in different theories, when he claims that the radical does not exist, he has in mind Lavoisier s radical (Chang 2011, 417; 2012b, 54). A realist about Lavoisier s radical would presumably have to answer the question: which constituent of muriatic acid and of oxymuriatic acid is the radical, and which is the principle of acidity? But as Chang rightly points out, from the standpoint of modern chemistry, it makes no sense to ask such a question (2011, 417). And asking such a question from the standpoint of Lavoisierian chemistry leads to anti-realism about Lavoisier s radical. For Lavoisier, oxygen is the sole principle of acidity, and so there is nothing to point to in order to support the claim that hydrogen is the radical, over the claim that chlorine is, and vice versa. Moreover, since Lavoisier held that muriatic acid is a component of chlorine, the latter substance would be a particularly poor candidate for the radical, since this would entail that the two substances are components of each other. But while hydrogen might then seem to be a better candidate, this is not the case, given that it is not a component of chlorine. Anti-realism about Lavoisier s radical, then, would seem to be the most reasonable option. It may be objected that I m being uncharitable to Lavoisier here, given that there are two perfectly good entities with which one can identify his radical, namely, hydrogen and chlorine. Moreover, one needn t actually choose between them. For example, one might employ Field s (1973) notion of partial denotation, and defend the view that muriatic radical denotes both hydrogen and chlorine. Or one might employ McLeish s (2006) notion of disjunctive partial reference, and claim that muriatic radical denotes either hydrogen or chlorine. In that case, perhaps one can be a realist about Lavoisier s radical after all. These strategies may yield a kind of realism about Lavoisier s radical, but it s not the kind of realism with which I am concerned here. The kind of realism that these strategies yield is a kind of semantic realism that allows for certain claims (e.g., Muriatic acid contains the muriatic radical. ) to be true. But the kind of realism with which I am concerned is a kind of entity realism, which concerns whether there is an empirical entity that corresponds in the right kind of way to Lavoisier s radical, qua theoretical entity. The suggestion that Lavoisier s term muriatic radical partially denotes, in either Field s or McLeish s sense, is really an admission that there is no single empirical entity that corresponds to Lavoisier s radical in the right kind of way. This way of defending semantic realism, then, actually undermines, rather than supports, 19

20 entity realism about Lavoisier s radical. In that case, anti-realism is really the only reasonable option regarding Lavoisier s radical. It could, however, be the case that other chemists had the resources to single out a particular empirical entity as the muriatic radical. I ll now argue that Berzelius was just such a chemist, in which case we ought to be realists about Berzelius s radical. 4.2 Realism About Berzelius s Radical Berzelius s views on the nature of the two substances differ in a number of important respects from Lavoisier s views, and these differences make it reasonable to be a realist about Berzelius s radical. To begin with, Berzelius eventually came to the (correct) belief that muriatic acid is composed of hydrogen and chlorine, and that the latter is an element. As a result, for Berzelius, the muriatic radical is a component of muriatic acid, but not of oxymuriatic acid. Moreover, his views on hydracids gave him a principled way to distinguish the radical of muriatic acid, which he took to be chlorine, from the component common to all other hydracids, namely, hydrogen. And unlike Lavoisier, who held that the nature of the muriatic radical was, at the time, unknown, Berzelius identifies it with a substance that chemists could, in fact, isolate, namely, chlorine. If we are realists about chlorine, then, and if Berzelius s radical just is chlorine, then we ought to be realists about Berzelius s radical. It may be objected that I m being too charitable to Berzelius here. After all, Berzelius s views on acids were eventually discarded, and when it came to the so-called oxygenous acids, he was just as wrong as Lavoisier. Chemists today work with three concepts of acidity: (1) the concept of an Arrhenius acid, which is a substance that increases the concentration of H + ions in water, (2) the concept of a Brønsted-Lowry acid, which is a substance that is an H + donor, and (3) the concept of a Lewis acid, which is a substance that is an electron pair acceptor. None of these concepts of acidity give any sense to the question: which constituent of an acid is the radical? In that case, even if we ought to be realists about chlorine, perhaps our realism shouldn t extend to Berzelius s radical. To be sure, it is certainly correct that current work on acidity has left behind the concept of a radical or acidifiable base. And Berzelius was quite wrong about oxygenous acids, which don t correspond to any category of acids studied by chemists today. But in some cases, it can be reasonable to 20

21 adopt a realist attitude toward some theoretical entity even if the theory in which that entity appears is not completely correct. And in Berzelius s case, there are two considerations that tell in favor of a realist attitude toward his radical. First of all, as stated earlier, Berzelius s beliefs regarding the constitution of muriatic acid and oxymuriatic acid were by-and-large correct. And given that he could point to a sample of chlorine, he could surely identify it with a theoretical entity like his muriatic radical. We may object to the terminology that he used, but it s difficult to deny that he used that terminology to single out a unique kind of empirical entity, namely, chlorine. Moreover, there is no need for anything like partial denotation in the case of Berzelius s radical, and so semantic realism and entity realism line up. Secondly, as Chang (2012a, 692) argues (though without discussing Berzelius s views), it s at least debatable that the notion of a hydracid prefigured two of our current conceptions of acidity. For Berzelius, hydrogen played an essential role in hydracids, and it also plays an essential role when it comes to both Arrhenius acids and Brønsted-Lowry acids. Berzelius s view implies that there is a class of acids, namely, hydracids, all of which contain hydrogen, and which differ from one another in terms of their other constituents, which can be simple or compound. This is basically correct when it comes to Arrhenius acids and Brønsted-Lowry acids, though it s not true of Lewis acids. The fact that Berzelius called the non-hydrogen constituents of these acids radicals doesn t count as a reason to be an anti-realist about those constituents. And given that Berzelius, unlike Lavoisier, successfully pointed to something importantly right regarding the constitution of acids, it s reasonable to be a realist about his muriatic radical. If realism about Berzelius s radical is reasonable, one might wonder whether there s a way to be a realist about Lavoisier s radical after all. More specifically, it might be the case that the reasons for identifying Berzelius s radical with chlorine can also be used in order to identify Lavoisier s radical with chlorine. To be sure, this would be a kind of retroactive identification, and one might be suspicious of it for that reason. But it s not clear that such a position is indefensible, and similar positions have been defended. To take one example, Jackman (1999) argues for a kind of semantic externalist view that he calls temporal externalism, according to which linguistic usage subsequent to some time t can be used in order to determine the referent of a term at t. Perhaps, then, we ought to conclude that Lavoisier s radical is chlorine. 21

Abstract: Scientific realists are committed to the claim that scientific. discourse should be interpreted realistically, so that theoretical terms are

Abstract: Scientific realists are committed to the claim that scientific. discourse should be interpreted realistically, so that theoretical terms are Hypothetical Entities and Realistic Interpretation: The Case of the Muriatic Radical Jonathon Hricko Abstract: Scientific realists are committed to the claim that scientific discourse should be interpreted

More information

PHILOSOPHY OF PHYSICS (Spring 2002) 1 Substantivalism vs. relationism. Lecture 17: Substantivalism vs. relationism

PHILOSOPHY OF PHYSICS (Spring 2002) 1 Substantivalism vs. relationism. Lecture 17: Substantivalism vs. relationism 17.1 432018 PHILOSOPHY OF PHYSICS (Spring 2002) Lecture 17: Substantivalism vs. relationism Preliminary reading: Sklar, pp. 69-82. We will now try to assess the impact of Relativity Theory on the debate

More information

Scientific Rationality: Phlogiston as a Case Study

Scientific Rationality: Phlogiston as a Case Study Scientific Rationality: Phlogiston as a Case Study Jonathon Hricko Penultimate Draft Please cite the published version, which appears in Tzu-Wei Hung & Timothy Lane (Eds.). (2017). Rationality: Constraints

More information

Lecture 12: Arguments for the absolutist and relationist views of space

Lecture 12: Arguments for the absolutist and relationist views of space 12.1 432018 PHILOSOPHY OF PHYSICS (Spring 2002) Lecture 12: Arguments for the absolutist and relationist views of space Preliminary reading: Sklar, pp. 19-25. Now that we have seen Newton s and Leibniz

More information

Critical Notice: Bas van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective Oxford University Press, 2008, xiv pages

Critical Notice: Bas van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective Oxford University Press, 2008, xiv pages Critical Notice: Bas van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective Oxford University Press, 2008, xiv + 408 pages by Bradley Monton June 24, 2009 It probably goes without saying that

More information

How and How Not to Be Whiggish About Phlogiston

How and How Not to Be Whiggish About Phlogiston How and How Not to Be Whiggish About Phlogiston Jonathon Hricko Abstract: Understanding the semantics of theoretical terms from past science involves determining what, if anything, they referred to. Some

More information

CAUSATION CAUSATION. Chapter 10. Non-Humean Reductionism

CAUSATION CAUSATION. Chapter 10. Non-Humean Reductionism CAUSATION CAUSATION Chapter 10 Non-Humean Reductionism Humean states of affairs were characterized recursively in chapter 2, the basic idea being that distinct Humean states of affairs cannot stand in

More information

A Model-theoretic Account for Structural Realism

A Model-theoretic Account for Structural Realism A Model-theoretic Account for Structural Realism Candidate Number: 26386 Programme: MSc in Philosophy of Science Academic adviser: Miklós Rédei August 21, 2014 Word count: 9856 obtained via: (http://app.uio.no/ifi/texcount/online.php)

More information

Ontology on Shaky Grounds

Ontology on Shaky Grounds 1 Ontology on Shaky Grounds Jean-Pierre Marquis Département de Philosophie Université de Montréal C.P. 6128, succ. Centre-ville Montréal, P.Q. Canada H3C 3J7 Jean-Pierre.Marquis@umontreal.ca In Realistic

More information

Scientific Explanation- Causation and Unification

Scientific Explanation- Causation and Unification Scientific Explanation- Causation and Unification By Wesley Salmon Analysis by Margarita Georgieva, PSTS student, number 0102458 Van Lochemstraat 9-17 7511 EG Enschede Final Paper for Philosophy of Science

More information

Marc Lange -- IRIS. European Journal of Philosophy and Public Debate

Marc Lange -- IRIS. European Journal of Philosophy and Public Debate Structuralism with an empiricist face? Bas Van Fraassen s Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective is a rich, masterful study of a wide range of issues arising from the manifold ways in which

More information

The claim that composition is identity is an intuition in search of a formulation.

The claim that composition is identity is an intuition in search of a formulation. Against Composition as Identity KRIS MCDANIEL The claim that composition is identity is an intuition in search of a formulation. The farmer s field is made of six plots, and in some sense is nothing more

More information

Truth, Subderivations and the Liar. Why Should I Care about the Liar Sentence? Uses of the Truth Concept - (i) Disquotation.

Truth, Subderivations and the Liar. Why Should I Care about the Liar Sentence? Uses of the Truth Concept - (i) Disquotation. Outline 1 2 3 4 5 1 / 41 2 / 41 The Liar Sentence Let L be the sentence: This sentence is false This sentence causes trouble If it is true, then it is false So it can t be true Thus, it is false If it

More information

240 Metaphysics. Frege s Puzzle. Chapter 26

240 Metaphysics. Frege s Puzzle. Chapter 26 240 Metaphysics Frege s Puzzle Frege s Puzzle 241 Frege s Puzzle In his 1879 Begriffsschrift (or Concept-Writing ), Gottlob Frege developed a propositional calculus to determine the truth values of propositions

More information

Remarks on Random Sequences

Remarks on Random Sequences Remarks on Random Sequences Branden Fitelson & Daniel Osherson 1 Setup We consider evidence relevant to whether a (possibly idealized) physical process is producing its output randomly. For definiteness,

More information

Universalism Entails Extensionalism

Universalism Entails Extensionalism Universalism Entails Extensionalism Achille C. Varzi Department of Philosophy, Columbia University, New York [Final version published in Analysis, 69 (2009), 599 604] 1. Universalism (also known as Conjunctivism,

More information

Russell s logicism. Jeff Speaks. September 26, 2007

Russell s logicism. Jeff Speaks. September 26, 2007 Russell s logicism Jeff Speaks September 26, 2007 1 Russell s definition of number............................ 2 2 The idea of reducing one theory to another.................... 4 2.1 Axioms and theories.............................

More information

Searle: Proper Names and Intentionality

Searle: Proper Names and Intentionality Searle: Proper Names and Intentionality Searle s Account Of The Problem In this essay, Searle emphasizes the notion of Intentional content, rather than the cluster of descriptions that Kripke uses to characterize

More information

PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AS A PHILOSOPHER S TOOL

PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AS A PHILOSOPHER S TOOL THOMAS HOFWEBER PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AS A PHILOSOPHER S TOOL 1. PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AND HILBERT S PROGRAM Hilbert s program in the philosophy of mathematics comes in two parts. One part is a

More information

Vocabulary atom atomos Dalton's atomic theory law of constant composition law of definite proportions law of multiple proportions matter.

Vocabulary atom atomos Dalton's atomic theory law of constant composition law of definite proportions law of multiple proportions matter. 1.3 Early Atomic Theory Lesson Objectives The student will: define matter and explain how it is composed of building blocks known as atoms. give a short history of how the concept of the atom developed.

More information

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM Michele Caponigro ISHTAR, Bergamo University Abstract From conceptual point of view, we argue about the nature of reality inferred from EPR

More information

Remarks on Random Sequences

Remarks on Random Sequences Australasian Journal of Logic Remarks on Random Sequences Branden Fitelson * and Daniel Osherson ** * Department of Philosophy, Rutgers University ** Department of Psychology, Princeton University Abstract

More information

So, what are special sciences? ones that are particularly dear to the author? ( Oh dear. I am touched. Psychology is just, so, well, special!

So, what are special sciences? ones that are particularly dear to the author? ( Oh dear. I am touched. Psychology is just, so, well, special! Jerry Fodor and his Special Sciences So, what are special sciences? ones that are particularly dear to the author? ( Oh dear. I am touched. Psychology is just, so, well, special! ) The use of special in

More information

What is proof? Lesson 1

What is proof? Lesson 1 What is proof? Lesson The topic for this Math Explorer Club is mathematical proof. In this post we will go over what was covered in the first session. The word proof is a normal English word that you might

More information

Introducing Proof 1. hsn.uk.net. Contents

Introducing Proof 1. hsn.uk.net. Contents Contents 1 1 Introduction 1 What is proof? 1 Statements, Definitions and Euler Diagrams 1 Statements 1 Definitions Our first proof Euler diagrams 4 3 Logical Connectives 5 Negation 6 Conjunction 7 Disjunction

More information

Popper s Measure of Corroboration and P h b

Popper s Measure of Corroboration and P h b Popper s Measure of Corroboration and P h b Darrell P. Rowbottom This paper shows that Popper s measure of corroboration is inapplicable if, as Popper also argued, the logical probability of synthetic

More information

Spring 2017 Ling 620 The Semantics of Control Infinitives: A First Introduction to De Se Attitudes

Spring 2017 Ling 620 The Semantics of Control Infinitives: A First Introduction to De Se Attitudes The Semantics of Control Infinitives: A First Introduction to De Se Attitudes 1. Non-Finite Control Complements and De Se Attitudes (1) Two Sentences that Seem Very Close in Meaning a. Dave expects he

More information

Indicative conditionals

Indicative conditionals Indicative conditionals PHIL 43916 November 14, 2012 1. Three types of conditionals... 1 2. Material conditionals... 1 3. Indicatives and possible worlds... 4 4. Conditionals and adverbs of quantification...

More information

4 Derivations in the Propositional Calculus

4 Derivations in the Propositional Calculus 4 Derivations in the Propositional Calculus 1. Arguments Expressed in the Propositional Calculus We have seen that we can symbolize a wide variety of statement forms using formulas of the propositional

More information

CAUSATION. Chapter 14. Causation and the Direction of Time Preliminary Considerations in Support of a Causal Analysis of Temporal Concepts

CAUSATION. Chapter 14. Causation and the Direction of Time Preliminary Considerations in Support of a Causal Analysis of Temporal Concepts CAUSATION Chapter 14 Causation and the Direction of Time 14.1 Preliminary Considerations in Support of a Causal Analysis of Temporal Concepts What reasons are there for thinking that at least those tenseless

More information

Zeno s Paradox #1. The Achilles

Zeno s Paradox #1. The Achilles Zeno s Paradox #1. The Achilles Achilles, who is the fastest runner of antiquity, is racing to catch the tortoise that is slowly crawling away from him. Both are moving along a linear path at constant

More information

Published in Analysis, 2004, 64 (1), pp

Published in Analysis, 2004, 64 (1), pp Published in Analysis, 2004, 64 (1), pp. 72-81. The Bundle Theory is compatible with distinct but indiscernible particulars GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA 1. The Bundle Theory I shall discuss is a theory about

More information

A brief history of Chemistry. Science 9- Mr. Klasz

A brief history of Chemistry. Science 9- Mr. Klasz A brief history of Chemistry Science 9- Mr. Klasz What is a pure substance? An element is a pure substance. A compound is made up of two or more elements which have been chemically compounded together.

More information

Natural Sciences 1: Laws and Models in Chemistry

Natural Sciences 1: Laws and Models in Chemistry Natural Sciences 1: Laws and Models in Chemistry Natural Sciences 1: Laws and Models in Chemistry, traces the efforts in Western thought to understand what makes up the physical world what remains the

More information

Atomic Theory. Introducing the Atomic Theory:

Atomic Theory. Introducing the Atomic Theory: Atomic Theory Chemistry is the science of matter. Matter is made up of things called atoms, elements, and molecules. But have you ever wondered if atoms and molecules are real? Would you be surprised to

More information

Discrete Structures Proofwriting Checklist

Discrete Structures Proofwriting Checklist CS103 Winter 2019 Discrete Structures Proofwriting Checklist Cynthia Lee Keith Schwarz Now that we re transitioning to writing proofs about discrete structures like binary relations, functions, and graphs,

More information

Euler s Galilean Philosophy of Science

Euler s Galilean Philosophy of Science Euler s Galilean Philosophy of Science Brian Hepburn Wichita State University Nov 5, 2017 Presentation time: 20 mins Abstract Here is a phrase never uttered before: Euler s philosophy of science. Known

More information

The paradox of knowability, the knower, and the believer

The paradox of knowability, the knower, and the believer The paradox of knowability, the knower, and the believer Last time, when discussing the surprise exam paradox, we discussed the possibility that some claims could be true, but not knowable by certain individuals

More information

The No Miracles Argument without the Base Rate Fallacy

The No Miracles Argument without the Base Rate Fallacy The No Miracles Argument without the Base Rate Fallacy Richard Dawid Stephan Hartmann January 25, 2016 Abstract According to an argument by Colin Howson, the no-miracles argument is contingent on committing

More information

Hypothesis testing I. - In particular, we are talking about statistical hypotheses. [get everyone s finger length!] n =

Hypothesis testing I. - In particular, we are talking about statistical hypotheses. [get everyone s finger length!] n = Hypothesis testing I I. What is hypothesis testing? [Note we re temporarily bouncing around in the book a lot! Things will settle down again in a week or so] - Exactly what it says. We develop a hypothesis,

More information

, (1) e i = ˆσ 1 h ii. c 2016, Jeffrey S. Simonoff 1

, (1) e i = ˆσ 1 h ii. c 2016, Jeffrey S. Simonoff 1 Regression diagnostics As is true of all statistical methodologies, linear regression analysis can be a very effective way to model data, as along as the assumptions being made are true. For the regression

More information

Paper read at History of Science Society 2014 Annual Meeting, Chicago, Nov. 9,

Paper read at History of Science Society 2014 Annual Meeting, Chicago, Nov. 9, Euler s Mechanics as Opposition to Leibnizian Dynamics 1 Nobumichi ARIGA 2 1. Introduction Leonhard Euler, the notable mathematician in the eighteenth century, is also famous for his contributions to mechanics.

More information

Basics of Proofs. 1 The Basics. 2 Proof Strategies. 2.1 Understand What s Going On

Basics of Proofs. 1 The Basics. 2 Proof Strategies. 2.1 Understand What s Going On Basics of Proofs The Putnam is a proof based exam and will expect you to write proofs in your solutions Similarly, Math 96 will also require you to write proofs in your homework solutions If you ve seen

More information

The Fundamental Laws of Chemistry

The Fundamental Laws of Chemistry The Fundamental Laws of Chemistry As we have discussed, matter can be classified into different categories based on directly observable properties, be they physical or chemical. Heterogeneous systems contain

More information

Counterfactuals and comparative similarity

Counterfactuals and comparative similarity Counterfactuals and comparative similarity Jeremy Goodman Draft of February 23, 2015 Abstract An analysis of counterfactuals in terms of the comparative similarity of possible worlds is widely attributed

More information

7.1 Significance of question: are there laws in S.S.? (Why care?) Possible answers:

7.1 Significance of question: are there laws in S.S.? (Why care?) Possible answers: I. Roberts: There are no laws of the social sciences Social sciences = sciences involving human behaviour (Economics, Psychology, Sociology, Political Science) 7.1 Significance of question: are there laws

More information

Do objects depend on structure?

Do objects depend on structure? Do objects depend on structure? Johanna Wolff Abstract Ontic Structural Realists hold that structure is all there is, or at least all there is fundamentally. This thesis has proved to be puzzling: what

More information

Lewis 2 Definitions of T-terms

Lewis 2 Definitions of T-terms Lewis 2 Definitions of T-terms (pp. 431 438, 445 446) Patrick Maher Philosophy 471 Fall 2006 Review The Ramsey sentence of T says T is realized: x 1... x n [x 1... x n ] The Carnap sentence says if T is

More information

Module 03 Lecture 14 Inferential Statistics ANOVA and TOI

Module 03 Lecture 14 Inferential Statistics ANOVA and TOI Introduction of Data Analytics Prof. Nandan Sudarsanam and Prof. B Ravindran Department of Management Studies and Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module

More information

QUANTUM MECHANICS AND 3N-DIMENSIONAL SPACE. November 22, 2004

QUANTUM MECHANICS AND 3N-DIMENSIONAL SPACE. November 22, 2004 QUANTUM MECHANICS AND 3N-DIMENSIONAL SPACE by Bradley Monton bmonton@uky.edu November 22, 2004 Abstract I maintain that quantum mechanics is fundamentally about a system of N particles evolving in three-dimensional

More information

Final Exam Comments. UVa - cs302: Theory of Computation Spring < Total

Final Exam Comments. UVa - cs302: Theory of Computation Spring < Total UVa - cs302: Theory of Computation Spring 2008 Final Exam Comments < 50 50 59 60 69 70 79 80 89 90 94 95-102 Total 2 6 8 22 16 16 12 Problem 1: Short Answers. (20) For each question, provide a correct,

More information

HIGH SCHOOL SCIENCE. Physical Science 9: Atomic Structure

HIGH SCHOOL SCIENCE. Physical Science 9: Atomic Structure HIGH SCHOOL SCIENCE Physical Science 9: Atomic Structure WILLMAR PUBLIC SCHOOL 2013-2014 EDITION CHAPTER 9 Atomic Structure In this chapter you will: 1. Compare and contrast quarks, leptons, and bosons.

More information

Chapter 2. Mathematical Reasoning. 2.1 Mathematical Models

Chapter 2. Mathematical Reasoning. 2.1 Mathematical Models Contents Mathematical Reasoning 3.1 Mathematical Models........................... 3. Mathematical Proof............................ 4..1 Structure of Proofs........................ 4.. Direct Method..........................

More information

Desire-as-belief revisited

Desire-as-belief revisited Desire-as-belief revisited Richard Bradley and Christian List June 30, 2008 1 Introduction On Hume s account of motivation, beliefs and desires are very di erent kinds of propositional attitudes. Beliefs

More information

Measurement Independence, Parameter Independence and Non-locality

Measurement Independence, Parameter Independence and Non-locality Measurement Independence, Parameter Independence and Non-locality Iñaki San Pedro Department of Logic and Philosophy of Science University of the Basque Country, UPV/EHU inaki.sanpedro@ehu.es Abstract

More information

Comments on Markosian s How Fast Does Time Pass?

Comments on Markosian s How Fast Does Time Pass? Comments on Markosian s How Fast Does Time Pass? In 2 of his paper Markosian tries to spell out what he means to say when he says that time passes. Most of his discussion has to do with temporal language

More information

Commentary on Guarini

Commentary on Guarini University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5 May 14th, 9:00 AM - May 17th, 5:00 PM Commentary on Guarini Andrew Bailey Follow this and additional works at: http://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive

More information

Final Exam Extra Credit Opportunity

Final Exam Extra Credit Opportunity Final Exam Extra Credit Opportunity For extra credit, counted toward your final exam grade, you can write a 3-5 page paper on (i) Chapter II, Conceptions in Antiquity, (ii) Chapter V, Newton and Leibniz,

More information

Handout 8: Bennett, Chapter 10

Handout 8: Bennett, Chapter 10 Handout 8: Bennett, Chapter 10 Philosophy 691: Conditionals Northern Illinois University Fall 2011 Geoff Pynn terminology 1. Chapters 10-18 concern subjunctive conditionals, which Bennett distinguishes

More information

Physicalism decomposed

Physicalism decomposed Blackwell Publishing Ltd.Oxford, UK and Malden, USAANALAnalysis0003-26382005 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.January 20056513339ArticlesAndreas Hüttemann and David Papineau Physicalism decomposed Physicalism

More information

(January 6, 2006) Paul Garrett garrett/

(January 6, 2006) Paul Garrett  garrett/ (January 6, 2006)! "$# % & '!)( *+,.-0/%&1,3234)5 * (6# Paul Garrett garrett@math.umn.edu http://www.math.umn.edu/ garrett/ To communicate clearly in mathematical writing, it is helpful to clearly express

More information

SCIENTIFIC REALISM AND THE QUANTUM R&Q2017

SCIENTIFIC REALISM AND THE QUANTUM R&Q2017 SCIENTIFIC REALISM AND THE QUANTUM R&Q2017 School of Philosophy, Religion, and History of Science University of Leeds Keynotes: Doreen Fraser, Carl Hoefer, George Musser, Adrian Kent, Alyssa Ney, David

More information

Amount of Substance and Its Unit Mole- Connecting the Invisible Micro World to the Observable Macro World Part 2 (English, mp4)

Amount of Substance and Its Unit Mole- Connecting the Invisible Micro World to the Observable Macro World Part 2 (English, mp4) Amount of Substance and Its Unit Mole- Connecting the Invisible Micro World to the Observable Macro World Part 2 (English, mp4) [MUSIC PLAYING] Instructor: Hi, everyone. Welcome back. I hope you had some

More information

Modern Algebra Prof. Manindra Agrawal Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur

Modern Algebra Prof. Manindra Agrawal Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur Modern Algebra Prof. Manindra Agrawal Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur Lecture 02 Groups: Subgroups and homomorphism (Refer Slide Time: 00:13) We looked

More information

Algebra Exam. Solutions and Grading Guide

Algebra Exam. Solutions and Grading Guide Algebra Exam Solutions and Grading Guide You should use this grading guide to carefully grade your own exam, trying to be as objective as possible about what score the TAs would give your responses. Full

More information

Math 300: Foundations of Higher Mathematics Northwestern University, Lecture Notes

Math 300: Foundations of Higher Mathematics Northwestern University, Lecture Notes Math 300: Foundations of Higher Mathematics Northwestern University, Lecture Notes Written by Santiago Cañez These are notes which provide a basic summary of each lecture for Math 300, Foundations of Higher

More information

Expressive Power, Mood, and Actuality

Expressive Power, Mood, and Actuality Expressive Power, Mood, and Actuality Rohan French Abstract In Wehmeier (2004) we are presented with the subjunctive modal language, a way of dealing with the expressive inadequacy of modal logic by marking

More information

Relevant Logic. Daniel Bonevac. March 20, 2013

Relevant Logic. Daniel Bonevac. March 20, 2013 March 20, 2013 The earliest attempts to devise a relevance logic that avoided the problem of explosion centered on the conditional. FDE, however, has no conditional operator, or a very weak one. If we

More information

HSSP Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics 08/07/11 Lecture Notes

HSSP Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics 08/07/11 Lecture Notes HSSP Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics 08/07/11 Lecture Notes Outline: 1. Homework 4 (discuss reading assignment) 2. The Measurement Problem 3. GRW theory Handouts: None Homework: Yes Vocabulary/Equations:

More information

Multiple Models, One Explanation

Multiple Models, One Explanation Multiple Models, One Explanation Chiara Lisciandra University of Groningen c.lisciandra@rug.nl Johannes Korbmacher Utrecht University j.korbmacher@uu.nl September 28, 2018 Abstract Complex phenomena often

More information

A theory of everything. Book review of Richard Dawid: String Theory and the Scientific Method

A theory of everything. Book review of Richard Dawid: String Theory and the Scientific Method A theory of everything. Book review of Richard Dawid: String Theory and the Scientific Method Philosophers of science generally assume that theorizing is boundless in principle, but in fact constrained

More information

Correct Resolution of the Twin Paradox

Correct Resolution of the Twin Paradox Correct Resolution of the Twin Paradox Michael Huemer In the following, I explain the Twin Paradox, which is supposed to be a paradoxical consequence of the Special Theory of Relativity (STR). I give the

More information

Aristotle s Definition of Kinêsis: Physics III.1

Aristotle s Definition of Kinêsis: Physics III.1 Aristotle s Definition of Kinêsis: Physics III.1 Background In Physics I.7, Aristotle told us that change (coming to be) involved a subject (that persists through the change and a pair of contraries (the

More information

In Defence of a Naïve Conditional Epistemology

In Defence of a Naïve Conditional Epistemology In Defence of a Naïve Conditional Epistemology Andrew Bacon 28th June 2013 1 The data You pick a card at random from a standard deck of cards. How confident should I be about asserting the following sentences?

More information

130 Great Problems in Philosophy and Physics - Solved? Chapter 10. Induction. This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/problems/induction

130 Great Problems in Philosophy and Physics - Solved? Chapter 10. Induction. This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/problems/induction 130 Great Problems in Philosophy and Physics - Solved? Induction This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/problems/induction The Problem of Induction Induction Francis Bacon described genuine

More information

Boscovich s theory: strict Newtonian physics, by Roger J. Anderton

Boscovich s theory: strict Newtonian physics, by Roger J. Anderton Boscovich s theory: strict Newtonian physics, by Roger J. Anderton R.J.Anderton@btinternet.com I will now look at Boscovich s theory according to Bertrand Russell. Bertrand Russell was one of the pro-einstein

More information

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind. Mind Association Response to Colyvan Author(s): Joseph Melia Source: Mind, New Series, Vol. 111, No. 441 (Jan., 2002), pp. 75-79 Published by: Oxford University Press on behalf of the Mind Association

More information

(Refer Slide Time: 0:21)

(Refer Slide Time: 0:21) Theory of Computation Prof. Somenath Biswas Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology Kanpur Lecture 7 A generalisation of pumping lemma, Non-deterministic finite automata

More information

Response to Kadri Vihvelin s counterfactuals and dispositions

Response to Kadri Vihvelin s counterfactuals and dispositions University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy Philosophy, Department of 2012 Response to Kadri Vihvelin s counterfactuals

More information

Guide to Proofs on Sets

Guide to Proofs on Sets CS103 Winter 2019 Guide to Proofs on Sets Cynthia Lee Keith Schwarz I would argue that if you have a single guiding principle for how to mathematically reason about sets, it would be this one: All sets

More information

First-Degree Entailment

First-Degree Entailment March 5, 2013 Relevance Logics Relevance logics are non-classical logics that try to avoid the paradoxes of material and strict implication: p (q p) p (p q) (p q) (q r) (p p) q p (q q) p (q q) Counterintuitive?

More information

Paradoxes of special relativity

Paradoxes of special relativity Paradoxes of special relativity Today we are turning from metaphysics to physics. As we ll see, certain paradoxes about the nature of space and time result not from philosophical speculation, but from

More information

Cambridge University Press How to Prove it: A Structured Approach: Second edition Daniel J. Velleman Excerpt More information

Cambridge University Press How to Prove it: A Structured Approach: Second edition Daniel J. Velleman Excerpt More information Introduction What is mathematics? High school mathematics is concerned mostly with solving equations and computing answers to numerical questions. College mathematics deals with a wider variety of questions,

More information

TRACING THE ORIGIN OF LIFE

TRACING THE ORIGIN OF LIFE TRACING THE ORIGIN OF LIFE James A. Putnam 2003 There is no natural discontinuity between life and the rest of creation. Scientific conclusions that include discontinuity in the operation of the universe

More information

has been falsified by the development of special relativity. In this paper, I identify and reject an

has been falsified by the development of special relativity. In this paper, I identify and reject an Presentism as an empirical hypothesis Abstract Within philosophy of physics it is broadly accepted that presentism as an empirical hypothesis has been falsified by the development of special relativity.

More information

Nondeterministic finite automata

Nondeterministic finite automata Lecture 3 Nondeterministic finite automata This lecture is focused on the nondeterministic finite automata (NFA) model and its relationship to the DFA model. Nondeterminism is an important concept in the

More information

Sklar s Maneuver. Bradford Skow ABSTRACT

Sklar s Maneuver. Bradford Skow ABSTRACT Brit. J. Phil. Sci. 58 (2007), 777 786 Sklar s Maneuver Bradford Skow ABSTRACT Sklar ([1974]) claimed that relationalism about ontology the doctrine that space and time do not exist is compatible with

More information

Williamson s Modal Logic as Metaphysics

Williamson s Modal Logic as Metaphysics Williamson s Modal Logic as Metaphysics Ted Sider Modality seminar 1. Methodology The title of this book may sound to some readers like Good as Evil, or perhaps Cabbages as Kings. If logic and metaphysics

More information

Conceivability and Modal Knowledge

Conceivability and Modal Knowledge 1 3 Conceivability and Modal Knowledge Christopher Hill ( 2006 ) provides an account of modal knowledge that is set in a broader context of arguing against the view that conceivability provides epistemic

More information

CHAPTER 6 - THINKING ABOUT AND PRACTICING PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC

CHAPTER 6 - THINKING ABOUT AND PRACTICING PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC 1 CHAPTER 6 - THINKING ABOUT AND PRACTICING PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC Here, you ll learn: what it means for a logic system to be finished some strategies for constructing proofs Congratulations! Our system of

More information

Atomic structure. Resources and methods for learning about these subjects (list a few here, in preparation for your research):

Atomic structure. Resources and methods for learning about these subjects (list a few here, in preparation for your research): Atomic structure This worksheet and all related files are licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution License, version 1.0. To view a copy of this license, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/1.0/,

More information

Philosophy of Mathematics Intuitionism

Philosophy of Mathematics Intuitionism Philosophy of Mathematics Intuitionism Owen Griffiths oeg21@cam.ac.uk St John s College, Cambridge 01/12/15 Classical mathematics Consider the Pythagorean argument that 2 is irrational: 1. Assume that

More information

The Rate of Temporal Flow

The Rate of Temporal Flow The Rate of Temporal Flow Edward Freeman There is a familiar problem with the notion of temporal passage. If time flows, it must flow at a rate, as all physical flows do. It is a fact of physical reality

More information

Chemistry. Qualities vs. Quantities. Quantities only, please

Chemistry. Qualities vs. Quantities. Quantities only, please Chemistry The Science of Matter: A development in the later part of the Scientific Revolution 1 Qualities vs. Quantities Chemical properties seem qualitative. Alchemy was almost entirely qualitative. Colour,

More information

The Conjunction and Disjunction Theses

The Conjunction and Disjunction Theses The Conjunction and Disjunction Theses Abstract Rodriguez-Pereyra (2006) argues for the disjunction thesis but against the conjunction thesis. I argue that accepting the disjunction thesis undermines his

More information

Intermediate Logic. Natural Deduction for TFL

Intermediate Logic. Natural Deduction for TFL Intermediate Logic Lecture Two Natural Deduction for TFL Rob Trueman rob.trueman@york.ac.uk University of York The Trouble with Truth Tables Natural Deduction for TFL The Trouble with Truth Tables The

More information

Realism and Idealism External Realism

Realism and Idealism External Realism Realism and Idealism External Realism Owen Griffiths oeg21@cam.ac.uk St John s College, Cambridge 8/10/15 What is metaphysics? Metaphysics is the attempt to: give a general description of the whole of

More information

MATH10040: Chapter 0 Mathematics, Logic and Reasoning

MATH10040: Chapter 0 Mathematics, Logic and Reasoning MATH10040: Chapter 0 Mathematics, Logic and Reasoning 1. What is Mathematics? There is no definitive answer to this question. 1 Indeed, the answer given by a 21st-century mathematician would differ greatly

More information

The Philosophy of Physics. Special Relativity and Minkowski Spacetime

The Philosophy of Physics. Special Relativity and Minkowski Spacetime The Philosophy of Physics Lecture Five Special Relativity and Minkowski Spacetime Rob Trueman rob.trueman@york.ac.uk University of York Special Relativity a quick refresher Special Relativity and Minkowski

More information

A Reply to The Destiny of Atomism in the Modern Science and the Structural Realism

A Reply to The Destiny of Atomism in the Modern Science and the Structural Realism http://social-epistemology.com ISSN: 2471-9560 A Reply to The Destiny of Atomism in the Modern Science and the Structural Realism Elena Trufanova, Institute of Philosophy, Russian Academy of Sciences Trufanova,

More information