Integrative Biology 200A "PRINCIPLES OF PHYLOGENETICS" Spring 2012 University of California, Berkeley

Similar documents
"PRINCIPLES OF PHYLOGENETICS: ECOLOGY AND EVOLUTION" Integrative Biology 200B Spring 2011 University of California, Berkeley

--Therefore, congruence among all postulated homologies provides a test of any single character in question [the central epistemological advance].

Using Trees for Classifications. Introduction

In R. Wilson (ed.), Species: New Interdisciplinary Essays, pp MIT Press Getting Rid of Species? Brent D. Mishler

"PRINCIPLES OF PHYLOGENETICS: ECOLOGY AND EVOLUTION" Integrative Biology 200B Spring 2011 University of California, Berkeley

Outline. Classification of Living Things

Integrative Biology 200A "PRINCIPLES OF PHYLOGENETICS" Spring 2012 University of California, Berkeley

Lecture V Phylogeny and Systematics Dr. Kopeny

Species Are Not Uniquely Real Biological Entities

ESS 345 Ichthyology. Systematic Ichthyology Part II Not in Book

5/31/17. Week 10; Monday MEMORIAL DAY NO CLASS. Page 88

8/23/2014. Phylogeny and the Tree of Life

Chapter 17A. Table of Contents. Section 1 Categories of Biological Classification. Section 2 How Biologists Classify Organisms

Phylogeny and systematics. Why are these disciplines important in evolutionary biology and how are they related to each other?

Fig. 26.7a. Biodiversity. 1. Course Outline Outcomes Instructors Text Grading. 2. Course Syllabus. Fig. 26.7b Table

Chapter 10. Classification and Phylogeny of Animals. Order in Diversity. Hierarchy of taxa. Table Linnaeus introduced binomial nomenclature

Integrative Biology 200A "PRINCIPLES OF PHYLOGENETICS" Spring 2012 University of California, Berkeley

Historical Biogeography. Historical Biogeography. Systematics

Need for systematics. Applications of systematics. Linnaeus plus Darwin. Approaches in systematics. Principles of cladistics

PHYLOGENY & THE TREE OF LIFE

"PRINCIPLES OF PHYLOGENETICS: ECOLOGY AND EVOLUTION" Integrative Biology 200B Spring 2009 University of California, Berkeley

Speciation. Today s OUTLINE: Mechanisms of Speciation. Mechanisms of Speciation. Geographic Models of speciation. (1) Mechanisms of Speciation

Speciation. Today s OUTLINE: Mechanisms of Speciation. Mechanisms of Speciation. Geographic Models of speciation. (1) Mechanisms of Speciation

Lecture 11 Friday, October 21, 2011

BIOL 428: Introduction to Systematics Midterm Exam

The Life System and Environmental & Evolutionary Biology II

ELE4120 Bioinformatics Tutorial 8

Classification, Phylogeny yand Evolutionary History

Integrating Fossils into Phylogenies. Throughout the 20th century, the relationship between paleontology and evolutionary biology has been strained.

AP Biology. Cladistics

Chapter 26: Phylogeny and the Tree of Life Phylogenies Show Evolutionary Relationships

Speciation. Today s OUTLINE: Mechanisms of Speciation. Mechanisms of Speciation. Geographic Models of speciation. (1) Mechanisms of Speciation

9.3 Classification. Lesson Objectives. Vocabulary. Introduction. Linnaean Classification

Biology 211 (2) Week 1 KEY!

Chapter 26. Phylogeny and the Tree of Life. Lecture Presentations by Nicole Tunbridge and Kathleen Fitzpatrick Pearson Education, Inc.

Consensus methods. Strict consensus methods

Reconstructing the history of lineages

Chapter 26 Phylogeny and the Tree of Life

SPECIATION. REPRODUCTIVE BARRIERS PREZYGOTIC: Barriers that prevent fertilization. Habitat isolation Populations can t get together

Classification and Phylogeny

The practice of naming and classifying organisms is called taxonomy.

The units of phylogenetic analysis. Species and speciation

Classification and Phylogeny

Integrative Biology 200A "PRINCIPLES OF PHYLOGENETICS" Spring 2008

How Biological Diversity Evolves

J. Hey - Genetic Species

Species concepts and species reality: salvaging a Linnaean rank

Phylogenetic Analysis

Phylogenetic Analysis

Phylogenetic Analysis

Species as Ranked Taxa

ESTIMATION OF CONSERVATISM OF CHARACTERS BY CONSTANCY WITHIN BIOLOGICAL POPULATIONS

Taxonomy and Biodiversity

Biology 2. Lecture Material. For. Macroevolution. Systematics

Name: Class: Date: ID: A

Homework Assignment, Evolutionary Systems Biology, Spring Homework Part I: Phylogenetics:

GENETICS - CLUTCH CH.22 EVOLUTIONARY GENETICS.

Biologists use a system of classification to organize information about the diversity of living things.

Consilience and a Hierarchy of Species Concepts: Advances Toward Closure on the Species Puzzle 1

Integrative Biology 200 "PRINCIPLES OF PHYLOGENETICS" Spring 2018 University of California, Berkeley

CLASSIFICATION AND OTHER WAYS OF KNOWLEDGE ORGANIZATION

Branches in the lines of descent: Charles Darwin and the evolution of the species concept

Macroevolution Part I: Phylogenies

Lecture 6 Phylogenetic Inference

Life Sciences For NET & SLET Exams Of UGC-CSIR. Section B and C. Volume-16. Contents A. PRINCIPLES AND METHODS OF TAXONOMY 1

C.DARWIN ( )

Chapter 26 Phylogeny and the Tree of Life

CHAPTER 10 Taxonomy and Phylogeny of Animals

POPULATION GENETICS Winter 2005 Lecture 17 Molecular phylogenetics

Algorithmic Methods Well-defined methodology Tree reconstruction those that are well-defined enough to be carried out by a computer. Felsenstein 2004,

Chapter 27: Evolutionary Genetics

Amira A. AL-Hosary PhD of infectious diseases Department of Animal Medicine (Infectious Diseases) Faculty of Veterinary Medicine Assiut

A Phylogenetic Network Construction due to Constrained Recombination

The process by which the genetic structure of populations changes over time.

Introduction to Biosystematics - Zool 575

Organizing Life s Diversity

(Stevens 1991) 1. morphological characters should be assumed to be quantitative unless demonstrated otherwise

CLASSIFICATION. Why Classify? 2/18/2013. History of Taxonomy Biodiversity: variety of organisms at all levels from populations to ecosystems.

Biology 1B Evolution Lecture 2 (February 26, 2010) Natural Selection, Phylogenies

Wake Acceleration Academy - Biology Note Guide Unit 6: Evolution & The Diversity of Life

The Classification of Plants and Other Organisms. Chapter 18

The use of hierarchies as organizational models in systematics

Phylogenies & Classifying species (AKA Cladistics & Taxonomy) What are phylogenies & cladograms? How do we read them? How do we estimate them?

PHYLOGENY AND SYSTEMATICS

CHAPTER 26 PHYLOGENY AND THE TREE OF LIFE Connecting Classification to Phylogeny

Chapter 19: Taxonomy, Systematics, and Phylogeny

This course covers mammals (as loosely defined above). To classify the cheetah, we would do the following:

Announcements: 1. Labs meet this week 2. Lab manuals have been ordered 3. Some slides from each lecture will be on the web 4. Study questions will be

9/19/2012. Chapter 17 Organizing Life s Diversity. Early Systems of Classification

UON, CAS, DBSC, General Biology II (BIOL102) Dr. Mustafa. A. Mansi. The Origin of Species

How should we organize the diversity of animal life?

Conceptually, we define species as evolutionary units :

Phylogeny 9/8/2014. Evolutionary Relationships. Data Supporting Phylogeny. Chapter 26

Classification Systems. - Taxonomy

UoN, CAS, DBSC BIOL102 lecture notes by: Dr. Mustafa A. Mansi. The Phylogenetic Systematics (Phylogeny and Systematics)

Chapter Chemical Uniqueness 1/23/2009. The Uses of Principles. Zoology: the Study of Animal Life. Fig. 1.1

Systematics Lecture 3 Characters: Homology, Morphology

Phylogenetic analysis. Characters

The Origin of Species

Modern Evolutionary Classification. Section 18-2 pgs

Transcription:

Integrative Biology 200A "PRINCIPLES OF PHYLOGENETICS" Spring 2012 University of California, Berkeley B.D. Mishler April 10, 2012: Species Concepts I. Importance of the species problem: a. nomenclatorial requirements (all organisms must belong to a species). b. practicality -- need to organize diversity, summarize information, communicate, give names to things. c. public perception -- species deeply ingrained in Western thought d. legal issues -- endangered species legislation; conservation e. connection to evolutionary theory -- desire to have species as units functioning in process theories (but which process theories? how to connect units and theories without circularity?) f. philosophical concerns -- need to be clear about properties of units: sets vs. individuals, universalism vs. pluralism. II. Quasi-historical outline: a. typological or essentialist approach (i.e., systematics through Linnaeus); logical division b. phenetic, morphological, or "natural" approach - older botanists (Gray, Bentham, Hooker) plus many recent botanists (Cronquist, Levin, Sokal & Crovello) - some recent cladists (!) (Nelson & Platnick, Cracraft, Nixon & Wheeler) c. "biological" species concept: interbreeding groups - classic isolation approach (most zoologists, e.g., Mayr, Dobzhansky) - newer recognition approach (some zoologists, see Paterson) d. "evolutionary" species concept: lineages (Simpson, Wiley) e. "ecological" species concept: niches (Van Valen) f. "species as individual": integrated, cohesive units with spatio-temporal boundaries (Ghiselin, Hull) g. "phylogenetic" species concepts of various types: lineages, homogeneous groups, basal monophyletic groups. etc. (will return later) 1

III. Reason for the existence of a species problem: a. most of the above concepts and criteria conflict in most real cases -- different concepts (and processes) "pick out" different groups in each particular case, thus the implied correspondence between different criteria relied on by the BSC (and General Lineage Concept) is abundantly falsified. b. operationality -- how to apply various concepts in a practical sense. c. what causes integration/cohesion of species? -- concerns: - breeding relationships are often clinal and/or non-transitive (what does "potential" interbreeding mean?) - gene flow is often very limited or lacking (what causes the evident distinctness of many asexual species?) - ecological limits; stabilizing selection; adaptive constraints. What is a niche? - developmental constraints (phylogenetic inertia)? d. what are the spatio-temporal boundaries of species? - monophyly? - origin? - extinction? IV. The winning argument for phylogenetic classification (review) The debate over classification has a long and checkered history (see Hull 1988; Stevens, 1994). A conceptual upheaval in the 1970's and 80's resulted in a true scientic revolution -- Hennigian Phylogenetic Systematics. Many issues were at stake in that era, foremost of which was the nature of taxa. Are they just convenient groupings of organisms with similar features, or are they lineages, marked by homologies? A general, if not completely universal consensus has been reached, that taxa are (or at least should be) the latter (Hennig, 1966; Nelson, 1973; Farris, 1983; Sober, 1988). A summary of the arguments for why formal taxonomic names should be used solely to represent phylogenetic groups is as follows: evolution is the single most powerful and general process underlying biological diversity. The major outcome of the evolutionary process is the production of an ever-branching phylogenetic tree, through descent with modification along the branches. This results in life being organized as a hierarchy of nested monophyletic groups. Since the most effective and natural classification systems are those that "capture" entities resulting from processes generating the things being classified, the general biological classification system should be used to reflect the tree of life. This isn't to say that phylogeny is the only important organizing principle in biology, There are many ways of classifying organisms into a hierarchy, because of the many biological processes impinging on organisms. Many kinds of non-phylogenetic biological groupings are unquestionably useful for special purposes (e.g., "producers," "rain forests," "hummingbird pollinated plants," "bacteria"). However, it is generally agreed that there should be one consistent, general-purpose, reference system, for which the Linnaean hierarchy should be 2

reserved. Phylogeny is the best criterion for the general purpose classification, both theoretically (the tree of life is the single universal outcome of the evolutionary process) and practically (phylogenetic relationship is the best criterion for summarizing known data about attributes of organisms and predicting unknown attributes). The other possible ways to classify can of course be used simultaneously, but should be regarded as special purpose classifications and clearly distinguished from phylogenetic formal taxa. V. Important concepts in phylogenetic classification to revisit: 1. Different ways of defining monophyly: synchronic (i.e., " all and only descendants of a common ancestor") or diachronic (i.e., " an ancestor and all of its descendants"). Which is better? Should the word "species" appear in the definition of monophyly? Does it matter? 2. Clade versus Lineage (see figure below for illustration). They are not the same thing -- "clade" is a synchronic concept, a snapshot of a lineage at one time -- while a "lineage" is a diachronic concept, a series of replicators. (from Cellinese et al. in press.) The distinction between clades and lineages, showing the incompatibility of different views of species. A clade is a synchronic, monophyletic set of lineage-representatives, where monophyly is defined synchronically as "all and only descendants of a common ancestor" (represented by A' in this case). Note that the terminal-most named clade is a "species" in the sense of Mishler and Theriot (2000a, 2000b, 2000c). A lineage is a diachronic ancestor-descendant path (grey line up the left side of the tree), whereas a lineage segment is a part of a lineage that connects two nodes (A and D in this example), note that the latter are species in the de Queiroz (2007) sense. Redrawn from Mishler (2010) VI. A phylogenetic solution under the current codes of nomenclature Recognize that there is no species problem per se in systematics. Rather, there is a taxon problem. Once one has decided what taxon names are to represent in general, then species taxa should be the same kind of things -- just the least inclusive. The field of systematics in general 3

has settled on restricting the use of formal taxonomic names to represent phylogenetically natural, monophyletic groups. So "species" should be the smallest one of those Grouping vs. ranking. There are two necessary parts to any species definition. The criteria by which organisms are grouped into taxa must be specified, as well as the criteria by which a taxon is ranked as a species rather than some other hierarchical level. Following the arguments given previously supporting a Hennigian phylogenetic system of classification, the grouping criterion that should be used is monophyly. Under this view, apomorphies are considered to be the necessary empirical evidence for unambiguous phylogenetic species, as for phylogenetic taxa at all levels. There are difficulties applying the concept of monophyly at this level. As you consider less inclusive levels in the genealogical hierarchy there is an increasing probability that reticulating ("hybridizing") events will occur, rather than the diverging phylogenetic relationships assumed by the cladistic approach. However, the problem of reticulation is not specific to the species level; indeed reticulation can occur throughout the hierarchy of life, and so is one of more general difficulty, and one that is receiving a lot of attention in the professional literature. It is becoming clear that while a certain amount of reticulation does not preclude cladistic reconstructions of phylogeny, extensive reticulation can cause major problems. How do we know when we have reticulation going on? We can only detect it by doing phylogenetics. Note in passing that reproductive criteria cannot be used to group organisms into phylogenetic species. The fundamental inappropriateness of using breeding compatibility in cladistic analysis is because the ability to interbreed (potential or actual), is a plesiomorphy by definition, thus not a phylogenetically valid grouping criterion. The ranking decision should involve practical criteria such as the amount of character support for a group and may also involve biological criteria in better known organisms, including reproductive criteria, e.g., the origin of a distinctive mating system at a particular node or the acquisition of exclusivity (a condition in which each allele in a lineage is more closely related to another allele in the lineage than it is to an allele outside the lineage). This ranking decision is forced because systematists have legislatively constrained themselves to use a ranked Linnaean hierarchy. A larger issue are recent calls for reforming the Linnaean system to remove the concept of ranks. This move would keep the hierarchy of named phylogenetic groups, but remove the ranks (including species) associated with the names. This move would decrease the arbitrariness of ranking decisions at the "species level," and will probably happen some day, but for now we assume that the current Linnaean system of ranked classifications is to remain in place (more on the possibility of getting rid of species in a couple weeks). A phylogenetic species concept can be defined based on these considerations (from Mishler and Theriot. 2000). First, organisms should be grouped into species on the basis of evidence for monophyly, as at all taxonomic levels; breeding criteria in particular have no business being used for grouping purposes. Second, ranking criteria used to assign species rank to certain monophyletic groups must vary among different organisms, but might well include ecological criteria or presence of breeding barriers in particular cases. The grouping concept (monophyly) in this view is monistic, while the ranking concept is pluralistic: The Phylogenetic Species Concept: A species is the least inclusive taxon recognized in a formal phylogenetic classification. As with all hierarchical levels of taxa in such a classification, organisms are grouped into species because of evidence of monophyly. Taxa are ranked as species rather than at some higher level because they are the smallest monophyletic groups deemed worthy of formal recognition, because of the amount of support for their monophyly and/or their importance in biological processes operating on the lineage in question. 4

[Does the ranking part of this sound arbitrary?? It is -- see below.] Monophyly is here defined synchronically to be: all and only descendants of a common ancestor, existing in any one slice in time. This ancestor was not an ancestral species, but rather a less inclusive C entity such as an organism, kin group, or population. Only "clades" can be monophyletic, not "lineages" (see diagram in fig. 1). The synchronic approach is necessary to avoid the time paradoxes that arise when classifying ancestors with descendants [i.e., questions like: Was your grandmother your grandmother before your parents were born?]. The evidence required for a hypothesis of monophyly is primarily corroborated patterns of synapomorphy (but possibly also including other factors, such as geography). Can a group arising by hybridization be monophyletic? Given B this synchronic definition it can, as long as it only arose once. In the diagram at right, in the first time-slice (A) there is one clade, (B) then two, then (C) one again. A VII. The winning argument for rank-free classification (review from previous lecture) As discussed in class earlier, a number of recent calls have been made for the reformation of the Linnaean hierarchy (e.g., De Queiroz & Gauthier, 1992). These authors have emphasized that the existing system is based in a non-evolutionary world-view; the roots of the Linnaean hierarchy are in a specially-created world-view. Perhaps the idea of fixed ranks made some sense under that view, but under an evolutionary world view they don't make sense. There are several problems with the current nomenclatorial system: 1. The current system, with its single type for a name, cannot be used to precisely name a clade. E.g., you may name a family based on a certain type specimen, and even if you were clear about what node you meant to name in your original publication, the exact phylogenetic application of your name would not be clear subsequently, after new clades are added. 2. There are not nearly enough ranks to name the thousands of levels of monophyletic groups in the tree of life. Therefore people are increasingly using informal rank-free names for higherlevel nodes, but without any clear, formal specification of what clade is meant. 3. Most aspects of the current code, including priority, revolve around the ranks, which leads to instability of usage. For example, when a change in relationships is discovered, several names often need to be changed to adjust, including those of groups whose circumscription has not changed. E.g., when it was detected that the Cactaceae is nested inside of the Portulacaceae, one of these well-known family names has to be abandoned. Frivolous changes in names often occur when authors merely change the rank of a group without any change in postulated relationships. 4. While practicing systematists know that groups given the same rank across biology are not comparable in any way (i.e., in age, size, amount of divergence, diversity within, etc.), many users do not know this. For example, ecologists and macroevolutionists often count numbers of taxa at a particular rank as an erroneous measure of "biodiversity." The non-equivalence of ranks means that at best (to those who are knowledgeable) they are a meaningless formality and perhaps not more than a hindrance. At worst, in the hands of a user of classifications who naively assumes groups at the same rank are comparable in some way, formal ranks lead to bad science -- removing the ranks would serve the same purpose as child-proof door locks for the back seat of your car! 5

How exactly to write the new phylogenetic code of nomenclature is not completely clear at this point, especially as applied to species (see draft of the Phylocode and other materials at: http://www.ohio.edu/phylocode/index.html, but the basics are clear. Such a new code should maintain the principle of priority (the first name for a lineage should be followed) and other aspects of the current code that promote effective communication of new names to the community. However, two major changes would be made: 1. The Linnaean ranks would be abandoned, Instead, names of clades would be hierarchically nested uninomials regarded as proper names. A clade would retain its name regardless of where new knowledge might change its phylogenetic position, thus increasing nomenclatorial stability. Furthermore, since clade names would be presented to the community without attached ranks, users would be encouraged to look at the actual attributes of the clades they compare, thus improving research in comparative biology. 2. Two or more types (called "specifiers") would be used, for efficient and accurate representation of phylogenetic relationships. There are two types of specifiers, internal and external. Two or more of the former are used to name node-based groups. two or more of the former and one of the latter are used to name stem-based groups. Apomorphy-based names are controversial, and really shouldn't be used. VIII. How could rank-free classification be applied to terminal taxa? At the moment, the species rank is the most controversial topic among Phylocode advocates. Some (primarily zoologists) want to retain it as one fundamental rank in an otherwise rank-free system, others (primarily botanists) want to get rid of it (see Cellinese et al. in press). Debate about removing species from the Phylocode rages at this very moment... 1. Names of clades (including the terminal level), could be regarded be hierarchicallynested uninomials regarded as proper names (as at all levels in the Phylocode, current usage should be followed as much as possible to retain links to the literature, databases, and collections). 2. As at all taxonomic levels, recommended to use node-based names with two or more internal type specimens. 3. To deal with the rampant homonyms that will result from treating current species eipthets as uninomials, several proposals have been made. My preference would be to regard all the higher clades to which a taxon belongs as part of its complete name. Thereby each clade would have a uninomial given name, but also a set of more and more inclusive family names, " thus homonyms could be told apart by higher-level clade names. 6

IX. Rank-Free Conservation (summary here -- much more in IB 200B) Hypothetical cladogram illustrating the importance of phylogeny in setting conservation priorities. Shown is a phylogeny of 43 terminal phylogenetic taxa (Smallest NAmed and Registered Clades or SNARCs); the branch lengths are proportional in the vertical direction to the number of evolutionary character changes along that branch. From the standpoint of preserving the maximum amount of phylogenetic diversity (and its closely associated genetic, morphological, physiological, and ecological diversity), clade one would have a lower conservation priority than clade two. Three groups of seven SNARCs each are also marked on the cladogram. By the same criterion, group A would have a lower conservation priority than group B. Group C, consisting of the same number of SNARCs scattered across the cladogram, would have a much higher conservation priority than either group A or B. In fact, group C would have a higher conservation priority than groups A and B taken together. Thus, the number of SNARCs in a locality is by itself a poor indicator of its priority for conservation. Some papers drawn on heavily for these notes (see also online reference list). Mishler, B. D. 1999. Getting rid of species? Pp.307-315 in R. Wilson (ed.), Species: new interdisciplinary essays. MIT Press. Mishler, B. D. and E. Theriot. 2000. The phylogenetic species concept sensu Mishler and Theriot: monophyly, apomorphy, and phylogenetic species concepts. Pp.44-54, 119-132, 179-184 in Q.D. Wheeler & R. Meier (eds.), Species concepts and phylogenetic theory: a debate. Columbia University Press, NY. [three chapters] Mishler, B. D. 2010. Species are not uniquely real biological entities. In F. Ayala and R. Arp (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Biology, pp. 110-122. Wiley- Blackwell. Cellinese, N., D.A. Baum, and B.D. Mishler. In press. Species and phylogenetic nomenclature. Systematic Biology. 7