De Jongh s characterization of intuitionistic propositional calculus

Similar documents
Stable formulas in intuitionistic logic

On Jankov-de Jongh formulas

Intuitionistic and Modal Logic

ALL NORMAL EXTENSIONS OF S5-SQUARED ARE FINITELY AXIOMATIZABLE

Modal and temporal logic

On the rules of intermediate logics

SUBALGEBRAS AND HOMOMORPHIC IMAGES OF THE RIEGER-NISHIMURA LATTICE

A Remark on Propositional Kripke Frames Sound for Intuitionistic Logic

Standard Bayes logic is not finitely axiomatizable

Varieties of Heyting algebras and superintuitionistic logics

arxiv:math/ v1 [math.lo] 5 Mar 2007

Logics above S4 and the Lebesgue measure algebra

A generalization of modal definability

Axiomatizing hybrid logic using modal logic

Model Theory of Modal Logic Lecture 5. Valentin Goranko Technical University of Denmark

Rules of Inference. Lecture 2 Wednesday, September 25. Rosalie Iemhoff Utrecht University, The Netherlands

An Introduction to Modal Logic III

Finitely generated free Heyting algebras; the well-founded initial segment

Modal Logic of Forcing Classes

MONADIC FRAGMENTS OF INTUITIONISTIC CONTROL LOGIC

arxiv: v4 [math.lo] 6 Apr 2018

S4.3 AND HEREDITARILY EXTREMALLY DISCONNECTED SPACES. On the occasion of the one hundredth anniversary of the birth of George Chogoshvili.

Inquisitive Logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Ivano Ciardelli Floris Roelofsen

ON THE LOGIC OF CLOSURE ALGEBRA

Axiomatizing hybrid logic using modal logic

On the Complexity of the Reflected Logic of Proofs

Filtrations and Basic Proof Theory Notes for Lecture 5

A NEW PROOF OF THE MCKINSEY-TARSKI THEOREM

Subminimal Logics and Relativistic Negation

Gödel s Completeness Theorem

From Syllogism to Common Sense

CHAPTER 11. Introduction to Intuitionistic Logic

Hypersequent Calculi for some Intermediate Logics with Bounded Kripke Models

On Modal Logics of Partial Recursive Functions

A Discrete Duality Between Nonmonotonic Consequence Relations and Convex Geometries

Krivine s Intuitionistic Proof of Classical Completeness (for countable languages)

Propositional Logics and their Algebraic Equivalents

Applied Logic. Lecture 1 - Propositional logic. Marcin Szczuka. Institute of Informatics, The University of Warsaw

ON CARDINALITY OF MATRICES STRONGLY ADEQUATE FOR THE INTUITIONISTIC PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC

Modal Logic: Exercises

The modal logic of Bayesian belief revision

Subminimal Negation. Almudena Colacito, Dick de Jongh and Ana Lucia Vargas. March 30, 2016

1. Propositional Calculus

1. Propositional Calculus

On Strictly Positive Modal Logics with S4.3 Frames

Axiomatisation of Hybrid Logic

Global vs. Local in Basic Modal Logic

Formal Epistemology: Lecture Notes. Horacio Arló-Costa Carnegie Mellon University

Monotonic Modal Logics

cse371/mat371 LOGIC Professor Anita Wasilewska Fall 2018

An Introduction to Modal Logic V

A Note on Graded Modal Logic

Vietoris bisimulations

Madhavan Mukund Chennai Mathematical Institute

Representable Cylindric Algebras and Many-Dimensional Modal Logics

Kazimierz SWIRYDOWICZ UPPER PART OF THE LATTICE OF EXTENSIONS OF THE POSITIVE RELEVANT LOGIC R +

Logics for Compact Hausdorff Spaces via de Vries Duality

Existential definability of modal frame classes

A Study of Subminimal Logics of Negation and their Modal Companions

Chapter 2 Core Theory

HENNESSY MILNER THEOREM FOR INTERPRETABILITY LOGIC. Abstract

Lattices of intermediate and cylindric modal logics

From Frame Properties to Hypersequent Rules in Modal Logics

Canonical models for normal logics (Completeness via canonicity)

AN ALGORITHM FOR FINDING FINITE AXIOMATIZATIONS OF FINITE INTERMEDIATE LOGICS BY MEANS OF JANKOV FORMULAS. Abstract

Přednáška 12. Důkazové kalkuly Kalkul Hilbertova typu. 11/29/2006 Hilbertův kalkul 1

RELATIONS BETWEEN PARACONSISTENT LOGIC AND MANY-VALUED LOGIC

INSTANTIAL NEIGHBOURHOOD LOGIC

185.A09 Advanced Mathematical Logic

admissible and derivable rules in intuitionistic logic

Basic Algebraic Logic

Interpretability Logic

Computational Logic and Applications KRAKÓW On density of truth of infinite logic. Zofia Kostrzycka University of Technology, Opole, Poland

Generalizing the Goldblatt-Thomason Theorem and Modal Definability

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007)

Basic Model Theory for Memory Logics

Rules of Inference. Lecture 1 Tuesday, September 24. Rosalie Iemhoff Utrecht University, The Netherlands

AN ALTERNATIVE NATURAL DEDUCTION FOR THE INTUITIONISTIC PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

The Relation Reflection Scheme

Classical Propositional Logic

SMALL SUBSETS OF THE REALS AND TREE FORCING NOTIONS

Natural Deduction. Formal Methods in Verification of Computer Systems Jeremy Johnson

The modal logic of forcing

Goldblatt-Thomason-style Theorems for Graded Modal Language

Diploma Thesis on The Modal Logic of Forcing. by Colin Jakob Rittberg

ON MODAL LOGICS BETWEEN K K K AND S5 S5 S5

Inquisitive Logic. Ivano Ciardelli.

Finite Models Constructed From Canonical Formulas

Modal systems based on many-valued logics

CHARACTERIZATION THEOREM OF 4-VALUED DE MORGAN LOGIC. Michiro Kondo

Semantics of intuitionistic propositional logic

The logic of subset spaces, topologic and the local difference modality K

The non-logical symbols determine a specific F OL language and consists of the following sets. Σ = {Σ n } n<ω

A SEQUENT SYSTEM OF THE LOGIC R FOR ROSSER SENTENCES 2. Abstract

Positive provability logic

Introduction to Modal and Temporal Logic

UNITARY UNIFICATION OF S5 MODAL LOGIC AND ITS EXTENSIONS

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

Transcription:

De Jongh s characterization of intuitionistic propositional calculus Nick Bezhanishvili Abstract In his PhD thesis [10] Dick de Jongh proved a syntactic characterization of intuitionistic propositional calculus IPC in terms of the Kleene slash. In this note we give a proof of this result using the technique of the universal models. 1 Introduction The problem of a syntactic characterization of intuitionistic propositional calculus IPC goes back to Lukasiewicz. In [14], Lukasiewicz conjectured that IPC is the only intermediate logic 1 having the disjunction property, i.e., if φ ψ, then φ or ψ. However, Kreisel and Putnam [13] disproved this conjecture by constructing a proper extension of intuitionistic logic satisfying the disjunction property. Later, Wronski [17] showed that there are in fact continuum many intermediate logics with the disjunction property. In [12], Kleene defined the Kleene slash which is a stronger notion than, i.e., for every set of fomulas Γ, Γ φ implies Γ φ. He proved that in intuitionistic logic, φ φ iff φ has the disjunction property and conjectured that this property uniquely characterizes intuitionistic logic among intermediate logics. In his PhD thesis [10], de Jongh confirmed this conjecture, thus providing a pure syntactic characterization of IPC. Recently, Iemhoff obtained a different syntactic characterization of IPC in terms of admissible rules (see [6] and [7]). In this note we will give a proof of the de Jongh theorem using the technique of the universal models. The proof is the same as in [10] and [11], with the single difference that our proof uses universal and Henkin models, unlike the original one, which used algebraic terminology. For the basic notions such as intuitionistic Kripke frames (models), generated subframes (submodels), p-morphism, bisimulations, etc., the reader is referred to [3] and [2]. The paper is organized as follows. In 2, we recall the structure of the n-universal model and its main properties. The de Jongh formulas will be introduced and a connection with Jankov s characteristic formulas will be shown. In 3, we prove de Jongh s characterization theorem. 1 Recall that an intermediate logic L is a set of formulas closed under substitution and modus ponens such that IPC L CPC, where CPC is the classical propositional calculus. 1

2 N-UNIVERSAL MODELS 2 2 n-universal models 2.1 The structure of U(n) Fix a propositional language L n consisting of finitely many propositional letters p 1,..., p n for n ω, the connectives, and, and the constant. Let M be an intuitionistic Kripke model. With every point w of M, we associate a sequence i 1... i n such that for k = 1,..., n: { 1 if w = pk, i k = 0 if w = p k We call the sequence i 1... i n associated with w the color of w and denote it by col(w). Colors are ordered according to the relation such that i 1... i n i 1... i n if for every k = 1,..., n we have that i k i k. Thus, the set of colors of length n ordered by forms an n-element Boolean algebra. We write i 1... i n < i 1... i n if i 1... i n i 1... i n and i 1... i n i 1... i n. For a Kripke frame F = (W, R) and w, v W, we say that a point w is an immediate successor of a point v if w v, vrw, and there does not exist u W with u v, u w, vru and urw. We say that a set A totally covers a point v and write v A if A is the set of all immediate successors of v. We say that v w if v A and w A, that is if w is an immediate successor of v. It is easy to see that R is the reflexive and transitive closure of. Therefore, R is uniquely defined by and vice versa. Thus, to define a Kripke frame (W, R), it is sufficient to define the relation. A W is an anti-chain if A > 1 and for every w, v A, w v implies (wrv) and (vrw). A point w of a Kripke frame (Kripke model) is called maximal if wrv implies w = v for every v W. The set of all maximal points of a frame F (model M) we denote by max(f) (max(m)). Now we are ready to define the n-universal model of IPC for every n ω. As we mentioned above, to define U(n) = (U(n), R, V ), it is sufficient to define the set U(n), relation and valuation V on U(n). The n-universal model U(n) is the smallest Kripke model satisfying the following three conditions: 1. max(u(n)) consists of 2 n points of distinct colors. 2. If w U(n) and col(w) 0. {{.. 0, then for every color i 1... i n < col(w), n times there exists v U(n) such that v w and col(v) = i 1... i n. 3. For every finite anti-chain A U(n) and every color i 1... i n, such that i 1... i n col(u) for all u A, there exists v U(n) such that v A and col(v) = i 1... i n. In the remainder of this section, we state the main properties of the n- universal model without proof. All the proofs can be found in [3, Sections 8.6 and 8.7], [4], [1], [16] or [15].

2 N-UNIVERSAL MODELS 3 If two models M and M are bisimilar in the language L n we call them L n -bisimilar. Now we state the crucial property of n-universal models. Theorem 2.1. 1. For every Kripke model M = (F, V ), there exists a Kripke model M = (F, V ) such that M is a generated submodel of U(n), M and M are L n -bisimilar and F is a p-morphic image of F. 2. For every finite Kripke frame F, there exists a valuation V, and n F such that M = (F, V ) is a generated submodel of U(n). Theorem 2.1(1) immediately implies the following corollary. Corollary 2.2. For every formula φ in the language L n, we have that IPC φ iff U(n) = φ. We say that a frame F = (W, R) is of depth n < ω, and write d(f) = n if there is a chain of n points in F and no other chain in F contains more than n points. If for every n ω, F contains a chain consisting of n points, then F is said to be of infinite depth. The depth of a point w W is the depth of the w-generated subframe of F, i.e. the depth of the subframe of F based on the set R(w) = {v W : wrv. The depth of w we denote by d(w). Let H(n) = (H(n), R, V ) be the Henkin model of IPC in the language L n (for details about the Henkin model see, e.g, [3, 5.1]). Then, the generated sumbodel of H(n) consisting of all the points of finite depth is (isomorphic to) U(n). Therefore, H(n) can be represented as a union H(n) = U(n) T (n), where T (n) is a submodel of H(n) consisting of all the points of infinite depth. Moreover, it can be shown that for every point w in T (n), there exists a point v U(n) such that wrv. In other words, universal models are upper parts of Henkin models. As we saw in Corollary 2.2, the n-universal model of IPC carries all the information about the formulas in n-variables. Unfortunately, this is not the case for intermediate logics. The analogue of Corollary 2.2 holds for an intermediate logic L iff L has the finite model property. Nevertheless, using the standard Henkin construction one can prove: Theorem 2.3. For every intermediate logic L and every formula φ in the language L n : L φ iff H L (n) = φ where H L (n) is the Henkin model of L in the language L n. The next technical facts will be used in the proof of Theorem 3.1 below. Proposition 2.4. For every intermediate logic L, H L (n) is a generated submodel of H(n). Proposition 2.5. For every n ω and 1 k n, the submodels of U(n) with the carrier sets V (p k ) = {w U(n) : w = p k and ˆV (p k ) = {w H(n) : w = p k are isomorphic to U(n 1) and H(n 1), respectively.

2 N-UNIVERSAL MODELS 4 2.2 Formulas characterizing point generated subsets In this section, we will introduce the so-called De Jongh formulas of IPC and prove that they define point generated submodels of universal models. We will also show that they do the same job as Jankov s characteristic formulas for IPC. For more details on this topic, we refer to [5, 2.5]. Let w be a point in the n-universal model (a point of finite depth in the Henkin model). Let R(w) = {v U(n) : wrv and R 1 (w) = {v U(n) : vrw. Now we define formulas φ w and ψ w inductively. If d(w) = 1 then let and φ w := {p k : w = p k { p j : w = p j for each k, j = 1,..., n ψ w = φ w. If d(w) > 1, then let {w 1,..., w m be the set of all immediate successors of w. Let prop(w) := {p k : w = p k and Let and newprop(w) := {p k : w = p k and for all i such that 1 i m, w i = p k. φ w := ( prop(w) ( ) m m newprop(w) ψ wi ) φ wi ψ w := φ w m i=1 We call φ w and ψ w the de Jongh formulas. Theorem 2.6. For every w U(n) (w H(n) such that d(w) is finite): φ wi i=1 R(w) = {v U(n) : v = φ w, i.e., φ w defines R(w). U(n) \ R 1 (w) = {v U(n) : v = ψ w, i.e., ψ w defines U(n) \ R 1 (w). Proof. We will prove the theorem only for universal models. The proof for Henkin models is similar. We prove the theorem by induction on the depth of w. If the depth of w is 1, the theorem holds (every element of the maximum of U(n) is defined by φ w ). Now suppose the depth of w is greater than 1 and the theorem holds for those points with depth strictly less than d(w). This means that the theorem holds for every w i, i.e., for each i = 1,..., m, φ wi defines R(w i ) and ψ wi defines U(n) \ R 1 (w i ). First note that by the induction hypothesis, w = m i=1 ψ w i ; hence w = m newprop(w) i=1 ψ w i. Therefore, w = φ w. On the other hand, if v U(n), i=1

2 N-UNIVERSAL MODELS 5 wrv and w v, so again by the induction hypothesis, v = m i=1 φ w i, and thus v = φ w. Therefore, every point in R(w) satisfies φ w. Now let v / R(w). We specify two cases: either there exists a point u U(n) such that vru and u / R(w) m i=1 R 1 (w i ) or such a point does not exist. In the first case, by the induction hypothesis, u = m i=1 ψ w i and u = m i=1 φ w i. Therefore, v = φ w. In the latter case, we again specify two cases: there exists k ω such that either v. {{.. w or v. {{.. A where A is a finite anti-chain k times k times containing w and for every u A we have u {w 1,..., w m. In the first case, by the definition of U(n), col(v) < col(w); hence v = prop(w). In the latter case, there exists a point u U(n) such that vru and u and w are totally covered by the same anti-chain. If col(u ) col(w), then by the definition of we have that u = prop(w), which implies that v = prop(w). If col(u ) > col(w), then by the definition of U(n) we have that u = newprop(w) and u = m i=1 φ w i. Hence v = φ w. Thus, φ w defines R(w). Finally, we show that ψ w defines U(n)\R 1 (w). For every v U(n), v = ψ w iff there exists u U(n) such that u = φ w and u = m i=1 φ w i, which holds iff u R(w) and u / m i=1 R(w i), which, in turn, holds iff u = w. Hence, v = ψ w iff v R 1 (w). This finishes the proof of the theorem. 2.3 The Jankov formulas In this subsection we show that the de Jongh formulas do the same job as Jankov s characteristic formulas for IPC. We first recall the theorem of Jankov. Theorem 2.7. (see Jankov [8] and [9]) For every finite rooted frame F there exists a formula χ(f) such that for every frame G G = χ(f) iff F is a generated subframe of a p-morphic image of G. Now we will give an alternative proof of this theorem using the de Jongh formulas. Proof of Theorem 2.7: By Theorem 2.1(2) there exists n ω such that F is (isomorphic to) a generated subframe of U(n). Let w U(n) be the root of F. We show that for every frame G: G = ψ w iff F is a generated subframe of a p-morphic image of G. Suppose F is a generated subframe of a p-morphic image of G. Clearly, w = ψ w ; hence F = ψ w, and since p-morphisms preserve the validity of formulas G = ψ w. Now suppose G = ψ w. Then, there exists a model M = (G, V ) such that M = ψ w. By Theorem 2.1(1), there exists a submodel M = (G, V ) of U(n) such that G is a p-morphic image of G and M and M are L n -bisimilar. This means that M = ψ w. Now, M = ψ w iff there exists v in G such that vrw, which holds iff w belongs to G. Therefore, w is in G, and F is a generated subframe of G. Thus, F is a generated subframe of a p-morphic image of G.

3 CHARACTERIZATION OF IPC 6 Remark 2.8. Note that there is one essential difference between the Jankov and de Jongh formulas: the number of propositional variables used in the Jankov formula depends on (is equal to) the cardinality of F, whereas the number of variables in the de Jongh formula depends on which U(n) contains F as a generated submodel. Therefore, in general, the de Jongh formula contains fewer variables than the Jankov formula. 3 Characterization of IPC 3.1 Characterization using the de Jongh formulas In this subsection, we prove a characterization of IPC using the de Jongh formulas. Let L be an intermediate logic. A formula φ is said to have the L-disjunction property if for all ψ and χ, if L φ ψ χ, then L φ ψ or L φ χ. Theorem 3.1. Let L be an intermediate logic. L = IPC iff for all m ω, φ 1,..., φ m, and ψ then m if L ( φ j ψ) φ i for every i m, j=1 m φ j ψ has the L-disjunction property. j=1 Proof. Suppose L = IPC and there are m ω, φ 1,..., φ m and ψ falsifying the right hand side of the bi-conditional statement of the theorem. Let φ := m j=1 φ j ψ. Then for every i m IPC φ φ i, and there exist χ 1 and χ 2 such that IPC φ χ 1 χ 2, but IPC φ χ 1 and IPC φ χ 2. Therefore, there exist finite rooted Kripke models M 1,..., M m and M 1, M 2 such that w i = φ and w i = φ i, where w i is the root of M i, and v k = φ and v k = χ k for k = 1, 2, where v 1 and v 2 are the roots of M 1 and M 2, respectively. Take the disjoint union of the models M 1,..., M n, M 1 and M 2 and add a new root w to it. Extend the valuation to w (this can be done by letting w = p k for every proposition letter p k ). Then, w = m j=1 φ j; hence, w = φ. On the other hand, w = χ 1 χ 2, therefore w = φ χ 1 χ 2, which is a contradiction. Suppose L IPC. Since IPC is complete with respect to finite rooted Kripke frames, there exists a finite rooted Kripke frame F such that F is not an L-frame. Without loss of generality, we can assume that every proper generated subframe of F is an L-frame. Let n be the smallest natural number such that F is (isomorphic to) a generated subframe of U(n). Let w U(n) be the root of F and {w 1,..., w m be the set of all immediate successors of w. We can assume that m > 1; otherwise, instead of F we take the disjoint union of F minus w with itself and add a new root to it. First, we show that in this case the de Jongh formula φ w can be simplified. As we mentioned above, we can assume that w has at least two successors. If there

3 CHARACTERIZATION OF IPC 7 exists a propositional letter p k such that for every i m we have w i = p k, then every w i belongs to the set V (p k ) = {u U(n) : u = p k. By Proposition 2.5 the submodel of U(n) with the carrier set V (p k ) is isomorphic to U(n 1). Therefore, m i=1 R(w i) is (isomorphic to) a generated subframe of U(n 1). Then, there exists a point v U(n 1) totally covered by {w 1,..., w m. This implies that R(v) is isomorphic to F. This is a contradiction since n is the least natural number such that F is a generated subframe of U(n). Therefore, for every proposition letter p k, there is an immediate successor of w falsifying p k. This implies that newprop(w) =. On the other hand, if there is a p k such that w = p k, then every immediate successor of w also satisfies p k, which is a contradiction. Hence, prop(w) =. Thus, the formula φ w is equal to the formula m i=1 ψ w i m i=1 φ w i. Let φ i := ψ wi for i m and ψ := m j=1 φ w j. Now we show that the de Jongh formula φ w = m j=1 φ j ψ does not have the L-disjunction property, even though, for each i m we have L φ w φ i. Let χ 1 := m 1 j=1 φ w j and χ 2 := φ wm. The following three claims will finish the proof of the theorem: 1. L φ w ψ wi for each i m. 2. L φ w χ 1 χ 2, i.e., L ψ w. 3. L φ w χ 1 and L φ w χ 2. (1) By the definition of φ w and ψ w, for each i m, we have that w i = φ w and w i = ψ wi. Every proper generated subframe of F is an L-frame; thus, L φ w ψ wi for each i m. (2) By Theorem 2.3, it is sufficient to show that H L (n) = ψ w. By Proposition 2.4, we know that H L (n) is a generated subframe of H(n). It is well known that if a finite model M = (F, V ) is a generated submodel of H L (n), then F is an L-frame (see, e.g., [2, Lemma 3.27]). Suppose there is a point v H L (n) such that v = ψ w. Then, by Theorem 2.6, we have vrw. But then the submodel of H(n) with the carrier set R(w) is a finite generated submodel of H L (n). This implies that F (which is isomorphic to the subframe of H(n) with the carrier set R(w)) is an L-frame. This is a contradiction, since F is not an L-frame. (3) As we mentioned above, w i = φ w for each i m. On the other hand, w 1 = φ wm and w m = φ wi for each i m 1. Therefore, L φ w χ 1 and L φ w χ 2. 3.2 The Characterization of IPC by the Kleene slash In this subsection, we prove the de Jongh characterization of IPC. Let L be an intermediate logic. Recall from [12] the defintion of the Kleene slash. Definition 3.2. For every intermediate logic L and a set of formulas Γ we say that

3 CHARACTERIZATION OF IPC 8 Γ L if Γ. Γ L p if p Γ for every proposition letter p. Γ L φ ψ if Γ L φ and Γ L ψ. Γ L φ ψ if Γ L φ or Γ L ψ. Γ L φ ψ if (Γ L φ implies Γ L ψ) and Γ L φ ψ. 2 Theorem 3.3. For every intermediate logic L, every set of formulas Γ and every formula φ, we have Γ L φ implies Γ L φ. Proof. A straightforward induction on the complexity of φ. If Γ consists of formulas with the L-disjunction property, then the converse of Theorem 3.3 also holds. We formulate this result only for the case in which Γ is a singleton set. Theorem 3.4. For every intermediate logic L and formulas φ and ψ. If φ has the L-disjunction property, then 1. φ L ψ iff φ L ψ. 2. φ L φ. Proof. (1) easy induction on the complexity of ψ. (2) follows from (1). Now we show that the converse to Theorem 3.4(2), i.e., if φ L φ, then φ has the L-disjunction property, holds only in the case of IPC. Theorem 3.5. For every set of formulas Γ such that for every ψ Γ we have Γ IPC ψ, it is the case that for every formula φ, Γ IPC φ implies Γ IPC φ. Proof. The theorem is proved by a straightforward induction on the depth of the proof of φ. First, one has to choose his/her favorite proof system of IPC and then check that the theorem holds for every axiom of IPC and that the required property is preserved by the rules of inference. Theorem 3.6. Let L be an intermediate logic. Then L = IPC iff for every formula φ, φ L φ iff φ has the L-disjunction property. Proof. Suppose L = IPC. By Theorem 3.5 φ IPC φ and φ IPC ψ χ together imply that φ IPC ψ χ. By the definition of the Kleene slash, this implies that φ IPC ψ or φ IPC χ. By Theorem 3.3 we then have that φ IPC ψ or φ IPC ψ. P.C.) 2 The condition Γ L φ ψ was added by Aczel, in order to prove Theorem 3.3 (de Jongh,

REFERENCES 9 Now suppose L IPC. Then take the formula φ w = m j=1 φ j ψ constructed in the proof of Theorem 3.1. As was shown in the proof of Theorem 3.1, φ w does not have the L-disjunction property. Now we will show that φ w L φ w. Since φ w = m j=1 φ j ψ, for showing φ w L φ w, we need to prove m that φ w L j=1 φ m j ψ and that if φ w L j=1 φ j, then φ w L ψ. It is obvious m that φ w L φ w. Thus, φ w L i=1 φ i ψ. In the proof of Theorem 3.1 we m showed that for each i m, φ w φ i. This implies that φ w L i=j φ j. Hence, m if φ w L j=1 φ j, then φ w L ψ. This, by the definition of the Kleene slash, yields φ w L φ w. Therefore, we have found a formula φ w such that φ w L φ w and φ w does not have the L-disjunction property. Acknowledgements I thank Dick de Jongh for guiding me through the subject and explaining to me the proofs and techniques used in his thesis. Special thanks go to Clemens Kupke, David Ahn and my brother Guram for carefully reading the note. References [1] F. Bellissima, Finitely generated free algebras, Journal of Symbolic Logic, 51 (1986), pp. 152-165. [2] P. Blackburn, M. de Rijke, Y. Venema, Modal Logic, Cambridge University Press, 2001. [3] A. Chagrov and M. Zakharyaschev, Modal Logic, Oxford University Press, 1997. [4] R. Grigolia, Free Algebras of Non-Classical Logics (in Russian), Mecniereba Press, Tbilisi, 1987. [5] L. Hendriks, Computations in Propositional Logic, PhD Thesis, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam, 1996. [6] R. Iemhoff, Provability Logic and Admissible Rules, PhD Thesis, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam, 2001. [7] R. Iemhoff, A(nother) characterization of intuitionistic propositional logic, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 113 (2001), pp. 161-173. [8] V.A. Jankov, On the relation between deducibility in intuitionistic propositional calculus and finite implicative structures. (Russian) Dokl. Akad. Nauk SSSR 151 (1963), pp. 1293 1294. [9] V.A. Jankov, The construction of a sequence of strongly independent superintuitionistic propositional calculi, Soviet Math. Dokl. 9 (1968), pp. 806-807.

REFERENCES 10 [10] D. de Jongh, Investigation on the Intiutionistic propositional Calculus, PhD Thesis, University of Wisconsin, Madison 1968. [11] D. de Jongh, A characterization of the intuitionistic propositional calculus, in Kino, Myhil, (eds.), Intuitionism in Proof Theory, North-Holland, Amsterdam 1970, pp. 211-217. [12] S.C. Kleene, Disjunction and existence under implications in elementary intuitionistic formalisms, Journal of Symbolic Logic, 27 (1962), pp.11-18. [13] G. Kreisel and H. Putnam, Eine Unableitbarkeitbeweismethode für den intuitionistischen Aussagenkalkül, Archiv f. Math. Logik u. Grundl. Forsch. 4 (1957), pp. 74-78. [14] J. Lukasiewicz, On the intuitionistic theory of deduction, Indagazione Mathematica, 14 (1952), pp. 92-130. [15] V.V. Rybakov, Rules of inference with parameters for intuitionistic logic, Journal of Symbolic Logic, 57 (1992), pp.33-52. [16] V.B. Shehtman, Rieger-Nishimura lattices, Soviet Mathematics Doklady, 19 (1978), pp. 1014-1018. [17] A. Wronski, Intermediate logics and the disjunction property. Reports on Mathematical Logic 1 (1973), pp. 39 51. Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam Plantage Muidergracht 24, 1018 TV Amsterdam The Netherlands nbezhani@science.uva.nl