Distributivity of Quotients of Countable Products of Boolean Algebras

Similar documents
Distributivity of the algebra of regular open subsets of βr \ R


Ultrafilters with property (s)

Covering a bounded set of functions by an increasing chain of slaloms

Irredundant Generators

Non-trivial automorphisms from variants of small d

REALCOMPACTNESS IN MAXIMAL AND SUBMAXIMAL SPACES.

A BOREL SOLUTION TO THE HORN-TARSKI PROBLEM. MSC 2000: 03E05, 03E20, 06A10 Keywords: Chain Conditions, Boolean Algebras.

SOME REMARKS ON NON-SPECIAL COHERENT ARONSZAJN TREES

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

GREGORY TREES, THE CONTINUUM, AND MARTIN S AXIOM

Borel cardinals and Ramsey ultrafilters (draft of Sections 1-3)

Tallness and Level by Level Equivalence and Inequivalence

Uncountable γ-sets under axiom CPA game

INSEPARABLE SEQUENCES AND FORCING

SMALL SUBSETS OF THE REALS AND TREE FORCING NOTIONS

A NOTE ON THE EIGHTFOLD WAY

Topology Proceedings. COPYRIGHT c by Topology Proceedings. All rights reserved.

The Proper Forcing Axiom: a tutorial

SMALL COMBINATORIAL CARDINAL CHARACTERISTICS AND THEOREMS OF EGOROV AND BLUMBERG

On absolutely divergent series

A NEW LINDELOF SPACE WITH POINTS G δ

Maharam Algebras. Equipe de Logique, Université de Paris 7, 2 Place Jussieu, Paris, France

Spectra of Tukey types of ultrafilters on Boolean algebras

Katětov and Katětov-Blass orders on F σ -ideals

Slow P -point Ultrafilters

THE NEXT BEST THING TO A P-POINT

Ramsey theory, trees, and ultrafilters

CCC Forcing and Splitting Reals

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007)

Increasing δ 1 2 and Namba-style forcing

FAR POINTS AND DISCRETELY GENERATED SPACES

IDEAL GAMES AND RAMSEY SETS

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

TOPOLOGICAL RAMSEY SPACES DENSE IN FORCINGS

The topology of ultrafilters as subspaces of 2 ω

ON A THEOREM OF BANACH AND KURATOWSKI AND K-LUSIN SETS. Tomek Bartoszyński

STEVO TODORCEVIC AND JUSTIN TATCH MOORE

More on ultrafilters and topological games

Embeddings into P(N)/fin and extension of automorphisms

Cofinalities of Marczewski-like ideals

Forcing notions in inner models

EXTERNAL AUTOMORPHISMS OF ULTRAPRODUCTS OF FINITE MODELS

with the topology generated by all boxes that are determined by countably many coordinates. Then G is a topological group,

Spectra of Tukey types of ultrafilters on Boolean algebras

Almost disjoint families and topology

VARIATIONS FOR SEPARATING CLUB GUESSING PRINCIPLES

Ultrafilters and Set Theory. Andreas Blass University of Michigan Ann Arbor, MI

many). But no other examples were known even Sacks forcing. Also for e.g. V = V = L, we did not know a forcing making it not proper.

COMPACT C-CLOSED SPACES NEED NOT BE SEQUENTIAL

Convergence and submeasures in Boolean algebras

Cardinal characteristics, projective wellorders and large continuum

Cardinal Invariants of Analytic P-Ideals

FORCING AXIOMS AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS, PART II: TRANSCENDING ω 1 -SEQUENCES OF REAL NUMBERS

SOME COMBINATORIAL PRINCIPLES DEFINED IN TERMS OF ELEMENTARY SUBMODELS. 1. Introduction

Tutorial 1.3: Combinatorial Set Theory. Jean A. Larson (University of Florida) ESSLLI in Ljubljana, Slovenia, August 4, 2011

FINITE BOREL MEASURES ON SPACES OF CARDINALITY LESS THAN c

PCF THEORY AND CARDINAL INVARIANTS OF THE REALS

SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS

ON ALMOST COUNTABLY COMPACT SPACES. Yankui Song and Hongying Zhao. 1. Introduction

MORE ABOUT SPACES WITH A SMALL DIAGONAL

A NEW CLASS OF RAMSEY-CLASSIFICATION THEOREMS AND THEIR APPLICATION IN THE TUKEY THEORY OF ULTRAFILTERS, PART 1

Ultrafilters maximal for finite embeddability

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES

TUKEY CLASSES OF ULTRAFILTERS ON ω

The Arkhangel skiĭ Tall problem under Martin s Axiom

Independence of Boolean algebras and forcing

Playing with forcing

Large Sets in Boolean and Non-Boolean Groups and Topology

The axiom of choice and two-point sets in the plane

Diagonalize This. Iian Smythe. Department of Mathematics Cornell University. Olivetti Club November 26, 2013

M ath. Res. Lett. 15 (2008), no. 00, NN c International Press 2008 A UNIVERSAL ARONSZAJN LINE. Justin Tatch Moore. 1.

Topological homogeneity and infinite powers

CH AND THE MOORE-MROWKA PROBLEM

HOW DO ULTRAFILTERS ACT ON THEORIES? THE CUT SPECTRUM AND TREETOPS

On the Length of Borel Hierarchies

MONOTONICALLY COMPACT AND MONOTONICALLY

ITERATIONS WITH MIXED SUPPORT

SOME CALKIN ALGEBRAS HAVE OUTER AUTOMORPHISMS

DENSELY k-separable COMPACTA ARE DENSELY SEPARABLE

GAMES ON BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS

GENERALIZED ELLENTUCK SPACES AND INITIAL CHAINS IN THE TUKEY STRUCTURE OF NON-P-POINTS

TOPOLOGIES GENERATED BY CLOSED INTERVALS. 1. Introduction. Novi Sad J. Math. Vol. 35, No. 1, 2005,

Adam Kwela. Instytut Matematyczny PAN SELECTIVE PROPERTIES OF IDEALS ON COUNTABLE SETS. Praca semestralna nr 3 (semestr letni 2011/12)

The seed order. Gabriel Goldberg. October 11, 2018

Homogeneous spaces and Wadge theory

The ideal of Sierpiński-Zygmund sets on the plane

TIE-POINTS, REGULAR CLOSED SETS, AND COPIES OF N

The Bounded Axiom A Forcing Axiom

INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS

COMPLETE NORMALITY AND COUNTABLE COMPACTNESS

Higher dimensional Ellentuck spaces

PSEUDO P-POINTS AND SPLITTING NUMBER

WHY Y-C.C. DAVID CHODOUNSKÝ AND JINDŘICH ZAPLETAL

BPFA and BAAFA. Their equiconsistency and their nonequivalence. Thilo Weinert. February 4, 2009

Forcing Axioms and Inner Models of Set Theory

HECHLER'S THEOREM FOR TALL ANALYTIC P-IDEALS

Singular Failures of GCH and Level by Level Equivalence

ON VAN DOUWEN SPACES AND RETRACTS OF βn

Transcription:

Rend. Istit. Mat. Univ. Trieste Volume 41 (2009), 27 33. Distributivity of Quotients of Countable Products of Boolean Algebras Fernando Hernández-Hernández Abstract. We compute the distributivity numbers of algebras of the type B ω / Fin where B is the trivial algebra {0, 1}, the countable atomless Boolean algebra, P (ω), P (ω) /fin and (P (ω) /fin) ω. Keywords: Distributivity of Boolean Algebras, Cardinal Invariants of the Continuum, Stone-Čech Compactification, Tree π-base. MS Classification 2000: 03E17, 06E15, 54G05, 54A35 1. Introduction Given a Boolean algebra B, the completion of B is denoted by r.o. (B). Formally, r.o. (B) is defined as the Boolean algebra of regular open subsets of B (see [12, p. 152]). Given a cardinal κ, r.o. (B) is called κ-distributive if and only if the equality { } u α,i : α < κ = { uα,f(α) : f } I α i I α α<κ holds for every family u α,i : i I α & α < κ of members of B. It is well known (see [12, p. 158]) that the following four statements are equivalent: 1. B is κ-distributive. 2. The intersection of κ open dense sets in B + (= B\{0}) is dense. 3. Every family of κ maximal antichains of B + has a refinement. 4. Forcing with B does not add a new subset of κ. The distributivity number of B is defined as the least κ such that r.o. (B) is not κ-distributive. The distributivity number of B is usually denoted by h (B). We are interested in computing the distributivity number of algebras of the type B ω / Fin. Here, B ω is the Boolean algebra of all functions f : ω B with pointwise operation. As usual, the support of an element f B ω is the set of

28 FERNANDO HERNÁNDEZ-HERNÁNDEZ all n ω for which f (n) 0 B. Finally, Fin is the ideal of all functions with finite support and B ω / Fin is the quotient algebra. Boolean algebras of the type B ω / Fin have been recently an object of study, see for example [9], [1], [5], [4]. We are going to focus in some of the most natural algebras B such as {0, 1}, P (ω), P (ω) /fin and the atomless countable Boolean algebra. The algebra B ω / Fin for these Boolean algebras correspond to the Stone-Čech remainders (X = βx \ X) of some well known spaces. It is easy to see that {0, 1} ω /Fin is isomorphic to P (ω) /fin and it is well known that its distributivity number is denoted by h, that ℵ 1 h c and that ZFC does not determine the exact value of h. For example, Martin s Axiom implies h = c; on the other hand, h = ℵ 1 holds in the Cohen model for the failure of the Continuum Hypothesis. As {0, 1} ω /Fin is isomorphic to P (ω) /fin it follows that {0, 1} ω /Fin corresponds to the Stone-Čech remainder, ω, of the compactification of the naturals. The study of the distributivity for this space was initiated in [2]. (P (ω)) ω / Fin topologically corresponds to (βω ω). The topological correspondent of (P (ω) /fin) ω / Fin is (ω ω ) and one of the first papers studying the distributivity of this space is [7] where this space is denoted by ω 2. Finally, one can choose to work with, A, the Boolean algebra of clopen subsets of the Cantor set 2 ω as the representative of the atomless countable Boolean algebra; then one can see that A ω / Fin is isomorphic to the algebra of clopen subsets of β (2 ω ω) \ (2 ω ω). This space is, in particular, coabsolute with βr \ R. The study of the distributivity number of βr \ R was initiated in [8]. 2. Computing h (B ω / Fin) Our terminology and notation are mostly standard and follows that of [12] and [3]. We refer the reader to those sources for undefined notions here. The phrase for almost all will mean for all but, possibly, finitely many of. Since P (ω) /fin is regularly embedded in B ω / Fin for any Boolean algebra B. In [1] the authors showed that B ω / Fin can be written as an iteration of P (ω) /fin and an ultra-power of B modulo U. For the sake of completeness we present here their result together with their short proof. Proposition 2.1 ([1]). B ω / Fin is forcing equivalent to the iteration P (ω) /fin B ω / U, where U is the P (ω) /fin-name for the Ramsey ultrafilter added by P (ω) /fin. Proof. Define a function Φ : B ω / Fin P (ω) /fin B ω / U by putting Φ (f) = supp (f), [ f] U, where [ f ]U is a P (ω) /fin-name for {g B ω : {n ω : f (n) =g (n)} U}. It is easy to verify that Φ is a dense embedding.

DISTRIBUTIVITY OF QUOTIENTS 29 A consequence of the regular embedding of P (ω) /fin into B ω / Fin is that h (B ω / Fin) h (1) for any Boolean algebra B. As we said before, for B = {0, 1} ZFC does not determines the value of h. One more comment we can make about this is that the natural forcing to increase h is the Mathias forcing; thus in the Mathias model h is ℵ 2. For B = A, the best known result is in [1]; it is a nice theorem which improves the result in [8] which says that h (A ω /Fin) = ℵ 1 in the Mathias model. Theorem 2.2 ([1]). h (A ω / Fin) min {h,add (M)}. In [11] we use a natural modification of Mathias forcing which increases h (A ω / Fin) the same way that Mathias forcing increases h; that is, we produce a model where there is a tree π-base for A ω / Fin of height ω 2 without branches of length ω 2.Atree π-base for a space X is a dense subset of the regular open algebra of subsets of X which forms a tree when ordered by reverse inclusion. The forcing used in [11] uses a lot of the topological structure of the reals but in the general case it can be defined as follows: M B is the forcing whose conditions are pairs s, B where s is a finite subset of B + and B is a regular open subset of B with s B = and with the ordering s, B r, A if and only if r s r A and B A. Recall that B B is regular open if whenever a b and b B we have a B, and for every b/ B there is a b such that B a B =, where B a = {x B : x a}. The first computation we do is for P (ω) ω /Fin. We wish to thank Professor Jörg Brendle for his help to fix a previous proof. This algebra is isomorphic to the algebra P (ω) /fin P (ω). Proposition 2.3. h (P (ω) ω /Fin) = h. Proof. For the purpose of the proof, for a function f : A ω and A ω denote by A f the set { n, f (n) : n A}. Then it is easy to see that the family D = { A f : A [ω] ω,f ω A} is a dense subset of P (ω) ω /Fin. It follows that h (P (ω) ω /Fin) h by (1). To prove the other inequality let κ< h and consider a family {A α : α < κ} of maximal antichains in D. Given A f A 0, let C α,f be a maximal antichain in P (ω) ω /Fin below A f and below A α. Fix a maximal almost disjoint family B κ,f = { B ω : B f C α,f } on A. Since κ< h there is B κ,f which is a common refinement of the families B α,f for α < κ. Letting A κ = { B f B : B B κ,f & f A 0 } we obtain a common refinement for each A α, as we wanted to show. We pass now to compute h ((P (ω) /fin) ω / Fin); for short we write h ( ω 2 ), see the introduction. Dow showed that a tree π-base for ω 2 cannot be ω 2 -closed and that Martin s Axiom (actually p = c) implies that the boolean algebra

30 FERNANDO HERNÁNDEZ-HERNÁNDEZ (P (ω) /fin) ω / Fin (which by the way is isomorphic to P (ω) /fin fin) is c- distributive, and hence h ( ω 2 ) = c. We are showing now that exact value of h ( ω 2 ) cannot be decided. At first glance one would think that h ( ω 2 ) = h; however in the Mathias model they differ. To show that we are going to use a game theoretical characterization of h (B). For more on games and distributivity laws in Boolean algebras see [6]. Let us consider the following game first introduced in [10]. For a homogeneous Boolean algebra B and for any ordinal α, G (B,α) is the game of length α between Player I and Player II, who alternatively choose non-zero elements b I β,bii β B for β < α such that for β < β <α: b I β b II β b I β bii β. In the end, Player II wins if and only if the sequence of moves has no lower bound (this might happen if at some step β < α, Player I does not have a legal move). Lemma 2.4. h (B) is the minimum cardinal κ such that in the game G (B,κ) Player II has a winning strategy. The main result in [13] follows from the next two propositions which are going to be used in the sequel. We introduce some notation needed. Firstly, S1 2 is the set of all ordinals α < ω 2 with cf (α) =ω 1 ; while P β denotes the countable support iteration of length β ω 2 of Mathias forcing, M, and Ġα denotes the P α -name for the P α -generic filter. Also, the quotient forcing P ω2 /Ġα is denoted by P αω2. Recall that ultrafilters U 0 and U 1 are Rudin-Keisler equivalent if exists a bijection f : ω ω such that U 1 = {f [U] :U U 0 }. An ultrafilter R is a Ramsey ultrafilter if for every k, n ω and every partition ϱ :[ω] n k there exists H R homogeneous for ϱ; that is, ϱ [H] n is constant. Ramsey ultrafilters are also known as selective ultrafilters. See [12, p. 478] and [3, p. 235] for more on Ramsey ultrafilters. Proposition 2.5 ([13]). There exists an ω 1 -club C S1 2 such that for every α C the following holds: If ṙ is a P αω2 -name such that P αω2 ṙ induces a Ramsey ultrafilter on ([ω] ω ) V ] [Ġα], then there is a P αω2 -name ṙ such that ṙ V [Ġα+1, ṙ and ṙ generate the same ultrafilter on ([ω] ω ) V [Ġα]. P αω2 Proposition 2.6 ([13]). Suppose that V is a model of CH and that ṙ is a M- name such that M ṙ induces a Ramsey ultrafilter Ṙ on ([ω]ω ) V. Then M U and Ṙ are Rudin-Keisler equivalent by some function f (ωω ) V, where U is the Ramsey ultrafilter added by P (ω) /fin. Theorem 2.7. Assume V is a model of CH. If G is P ω2 -generic over V, then V [G] h ( ω 2 ) = ℵ 1.

DISTRIBUTIVITY OF QUOTIENTS 31 Proof. Suffices to define a winning strategy for Player II in the game G ((P (ω) /fin) ω / Fin,ω 1 ) played in V [G]. In order to do that, fix a ω 1 -club C S 2 1 as in Proposition 2.5. For every x V [G], let o (x) = min {α < ω 2 : x V [G α ]} and fix a Γ: ω 1 ω 1 ω 1 bijection such that Γ (α) = β, δ implies β α. Since V [G α ] CH, for each α < ω 2, there is a function g α : ω 1 V [G α ] which enumerates all triples a, ϱ, f V [G α ] such that a [ω] ω, ϱ :[ω] n k for some k, n ω and f : ω ω is a function. The winning strategy for Player II is as follows: If p I ξ,pii ξ : ξ < ω 1 is a play, there is α C such that p II ξ (n) :ξ < ω 1 generates Ramsey ultrafilters on ([ω] ω ) V [Gα] for each n ω such that any two of them are not Rudin-Keisler equivalent by any f (ω ω ) V [Ga]. The α-th move of Player II in a given play p I ξ,pii ξ : ξ < ω 1 is in such a way that if Γ (α) = β, δ, ξ C is minimal with the property that ξ sup { o ( p I η(n) :η < β & n ω )}, and g ξ (δ) = a, ϱ, f, then 1. p II α (n) p I α (n) for almost all n ω, 2. p II α (n) a or p II α (n) a =, 3. p II α (n) is ϱ-homogeneous, 4. f [ p II α (n) ] p II α (m) =, for all m, n ω. To see that this is possible suppose we have chosen p II α (k) for k < n satisfying (1), (2), (3) and (4) for i, j < n: f [ p II α (i) ] p II α (j) =. To choose p II α (n) start by choosing some Bn n p I α (n) which is ϱ-homogeneous and either Bn n a or Bn n a =. Then we keep choosing sets Bm n for m> n as follows: Assuming Bm n has been defined, let Bm+1 n be Bm n if f [Bm] n p I α (m + 1) =, otherwise let Bm+1 n be some infinite subset of Bm n such that p I α (m + 1) \ f [ Bm+1] n and shrink p I α (m + 1) to become p I α (m + 1) \ f [ Bm+1] n. (Here we abuse of the notation and we call this new set again p I α (m + 1).) Finally let B be some infinite B Bm n for all m n. Since the set f[b] is almost disjoint from each p I α (m) for m > n and the new sets p II α (m) are going to be subsets of p I α (m) the clause (4) will be preserved if we let p II α (n) be any infinite subset of B.

32 FERNANDO HERNÁNDEZ-HERNÁNDEZ Notice that the fact that C is an ω 1 -club implies that the strategy is as desired. To finish the proof we show that this strategy is a winning strategy for Player II. Suppose that p β : β < ω 1 are the moves of Player II according to the strategy, and suppose that the game is won by Player I. Then, there exists r V [G] such that r (n) [ω] ω for almost all n ω and r (n) p β (n) for almost all n ω and all β < ω 1. Fix α C and Ramsey ultrafilters U (n) on ([ω] ω ) V [Gα] for n<ω such that each U (n) is generated by p β (n) :β < ω 1 and no two of them are Rudin-Keisler equivalent for any f ω ω V [G α ]. Then U (n) is generated by r (n). By Proposition 2.5, r V [G α+1 ] and by Proposition 2.6 U (n) is Rudin-Keisler equivalent to U by functions in ω ω V [G α ]. However, by construction this is impossible. 3. Final Remarks The results presented here can be the beginning of a whole research on the cardinal invariants of algebras of the type B/I where B is a subalgebra of P(ω) and I is an ideal over the natural numbers. As an instance of this, recall that by a result of Mazur an ideal I is an F σ ideal if and only if it is equal to Fin (ϕ) ={I ω : ϕ (I) < }, for some lower semicontinuous submeasure ϕ. This can be used to easily show that P (ω) /I is σ-closed and hence h I = h (P (ω) /I) > ℵ 0. We would like to know how to compute h I for F σ ideals I. The base tree matrix lemma of Balcar, Pelant and Simon [2] has proved to be an important tool, so we ask: Problem 3.1: For which ideals is the base tree matrix lemma still true for P (ω) /I? Problem 3.2: Does the base tree matrix lemma imply the collapse of c to the respective h? Problem 3.3: What is the relationship between h and h I for F σ ideals I? Going back to P (ω) ω /Fin, observe that if A is a maximal almost disjoint family of subsets of ω and for each A A we define f A P (ω) ω by { ω, if n A f A (n) =., if n/ A. then {f A : A A} is a maximal antichain in P (ω) ω /Fin. a (P (ω) ω /Fin) a. Problem 3.4: Does a a (P (ω) ω /Fin)? Problem 3.5: Does b a (P (ω) ω /Fin)? Similar arguments to the above one shows that It follows that p (P (ω) ω /Fin) p, t (P (ω) ω /Fin) t and s (P (ω) ω /Fin) s.

DISTRIBUTIVITY OF QUOTIENTS 33 Problem 3.6: Does t (P (ω) ω /Fin) t? Problem 3.7: Does s (P (ω) ω /Fin) s? Acknowledgements. We would like to thank M. Hrušák and J. Brendle for useful discussions on this topic. References [1] B. Balcar and M. Hrušák, Distributivity of the algebra of regular open subsets of βr \ R, Topology App. 149 (2005), 1 7. [2] J. Pelant, B. Balcar and P. Simon, The space of ultrafilters on N covered by nowhere dense sets, Fund. Math. 110 (1980), 11 24. [3] T. Bartoszyński and H. Judah, Set theory: On the structure of the real line, A.K. Peters Ltd., Wellesley (1995). [4] J. Brendle, Distributivity numbers of P(ω)/fin and its friends, Suuri kaiseki kenkyuusho koukyuuroku 1471 (2006), 9 18. [5] J. Brendle, Independence for distributivity numbers, Algebra, Logic, Set Theory, Festschrift für Ulrich Felgner, Amsterdam (2007), pp. 63 84. [6] N. Dobrinen, Games and general distributive laws in Boolean algebras, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 131 (2003), 309 318 (electronic). [7] A. Dow, Tree π-bases for βn N in various models, Topology Appl. 33 (1989), 3 19. [8] A. Dow, The regular open algebra of βr \ R is not equal to the completion of P(ω)/fin, Fund. Math. 157 (1998), 33 41. [9] I. Farah, Analytic quotients: theory of liftings for quotients over analytic ideals on the integers, Mem. Amer. Math. Soc. 148 (2000), no. 702. [10] M. Foreman, Games played on Boolean algebras, J. Symbolic Logic 48 (1983), 714 723. [11] F. Hernández-Hernández, A tree π-base for R without cofinal branches, Comment. Math. Univ. Carolin. 46 (2005), 721 734. [12] T. Jech, Set theory, second ed., Perspectives in Mathematical Logic, Springer, Berlin (1997). [13] S. Shelah and O. Spinas, The distributivity numbers of P(ω)/fin and its square, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 352 (2000), 2023 2047 (electronic). Author s address: Fernando Hernández-Hernández Facultad de Ciencias Físico Matemáticas Univ. Michoacana de San Nicolás de Hidalgo 58060 Morelia Michoacán, México E-mail: fhernandez@fismat.umich.mx Received June 19, 2009 Revised October 21, 2009