Complexity, Undecidability and Tilings. Chaim Goodman-Strauss Univ Arkansas

Similar documents
Church s undecidability result

Computability Theory

Regular Substitution Systems and. Tilings in the Hyperbolic Plane. C. Goodman-Strauss

Tutorial on Mathematical Induction

Class 24: Computability

CSCI3390-Lecture 6: An Undecidable Problem

GTI. Undecidability. Total Recall 3. Halting. Undecidability. A. Ada, K. Sutner Carnegie Mellon University. Spring 2018

CSE355 SUMMER 2018 LECTURES TURING MACHINES AND (UN)DECIDABILITY

Lecture 14 Rosser s Theorem, the length of proofs, Robinson s Arithmetic, and Church s theorem. Michael Beeson

Computability, Undeciability and the Halting Problem

Introduction to Computer Science and Programming for Astronomers

ON COMPUTAMBLE NUMBERS, WITH AN APPLICATION TO THE ENTSCHENIDUGSPROBLEM. Turing 1936

On some Metatheorems about FOL

Undecidability COMS Ashley Montanaro 4 April Department of Computer Science, University of Bristol Bristol, UK

Automata & languages. A primer on the Theory of Computation. Laurent Vanbever. ETH Zürich (D-ITET) October,

The roots of computability theory. September 5, 2016

Most General computer?

Decidability: Church-Turing Thesis

Great Theoretical Ideas in Computer Science. Lecture 7: Introduction to Computational Complexity

Undecibability. Hilbert's 10th Problem: Give an algorithm that given a polynomial decides if the polynomial has integer roots or not.

Real Analysis Prof. S.H. Kulkarni Department of Mathematics Indian Institute of Technology, Madras. Lecture - 13 Conditional Convergence

Decidability and Undecidability

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Spring 2014 Anant Sahai Note 20. To Infinity And Beyond: Countability and Computability

Gödel s Incompleteness Theorem

Institute for Applied Information Processing and Communications (IAIK) Secure & Correct Systems. Decidability

Undecidability. Andreas Klappenecker. [based on slides by Prof. Welch]

Gödel s Incompleteness Theorem. Overview. Computability and Logic

Complexity Theory Part I

Understanding Computation

15-251: Great Theoretical Ideas in Computer Science Fall 2016 Lecture 6 September 15, Turing & the Uncomputable

Finish K-Complexity, Start Time Complexity

Introduction to Turing Machines

Complexity Theory Part I

Lecture 11: Gödel s Second Incompleteness Theorem, and Tarski s Theorem

Turing Machines Part III

Undecidability and Rice s Theorem. Lecture 26, December 3 CS 374, Fall 2015

Lecture 4: Constructing the Integers, Rationals and Reals

Time-bounded computations

Great Theoretical Ideas

NP-Complete and Non-Computable Problems. COMP385 Dr. Ken Williams

17.1 The Halting Problem

5 + 9(10) + 3(100) + 0(1000) + 2(10000) =

Computability Crib Sheet

The Arithmetical Hierarchy

Decidability. Linz 6 th, Chapter 12: Limits of Algorithmic Computation, page 309ff

CS 361 Meeting 26 11/10/17

Turing s 1935: my guess about his intellectual journey to On Co

CS 301. Lecture 18 Decidable languages. Stephen Checkoway. April 2, 2018

CS187 - Science Gateway Seminar for CS and Math

Peano Arithmetic. CSC 438F/2404F Notes (S. Cook) Fall, Goals Now

Lecture 13: Foundations of Math and Kolmogorov Complexity

Modern Algebra Prof. Manindra Agrawal Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur

1 Reals are Uncountable

2 Computable and Computably Enumerable Sets

Principles of Computing, Carnegie Mellon University. The Limits of Computing

1 Computational problems

Introduction to Turing Machines. Reading: Chapters 8 & 9

Bjorn Poonen. Cantrell Lecture 3 University of Georgia March 28, 2008

Hypothesis testing I. - In particular, we are talking about statistical hypotheses. [get everyone s finger length!] n =

CSC 5170: Theory of Computational Complexity Lecture 9 The Chinese University of Hong Kong 15 March 2010

6.080 / Great Ideas in Theoretical Computer Science Spring 2008

CST Part IB. Computation Theory. Andrew Pitts

Computation. Some history...

TURING MAHINES

Decidability. Human-aware Robotics. 2017/10/31 Chapter 4.1 in Sipser Ø Announcement:

Standing on the Shoulders of a Giant

6-1 Computational Complexity

A non-turing-recognizable language

Gödel s Incompleteness Theorem. Overview. Computability and Logic

Turing Machine Recap

23.1 Gödel Numberings and Diagonalization

6.045: Automata, Computability, and Complexity Or, Great Ideas in Theoretical Computer Science Spring, Class 8 Nancy Lynch

17.1 Correctness of First-Order Tableaux

Algebra Exam. Solutions and Grading Guide

CSE 105 THEORY OF COMPUTATION

Computability Theory. CS215, Lecture 6,

The P-vs-NP problem. Andrés E. Caicedo. September 10, 2011

Against the F-score. Adam Yedidia. December 8, This essay explains why the F-score is a poor metric for the success of a statistical prediction.

1 Showing Recognizability

1 Acceptance, Rejection, and I/O for Turing Machines

Large Numbers, Busy Beavers, Noncomputability and Incompleteness

WHY WORD PROBLEMS ARE HARD

DR.RUPNATHJI( DR.RUPAK NATH )

Turing Centenary Lecture

Hilbert s problems, Gödel, and the limits of computation

CSCE 551: Chin-Tser Huang. University of South Carolina

Finite Automata Theory and Formal Languages TMV027/DIT321 LP4 2018

Lecture 6: Finite Fields

STOP. Biggest Number Game. Countdown Clock. Computers before WWII. Toaster Science? What s so special about computers?

Limits of Computation. Antonina Kolokolova

One sided tests. An example of a two sided alternative is what we ve been using for our two sample tests:

The Integers. Peter J. Kahn

Introducing Proof 1. hsn.uk.net. Contents

There are two main techniques for showing that problems are undecidable: diagonalization and reduction

CSCI3390-Assignment 2 Solutions

The Turing machine model of computation

Friday Four Square! Today at 4:15PM, Outside Gates

258 Handbook of Discrete and Combinatorial Mathematics

(2) Generalize De Morgan s laws for n sets and prove the laws by induction. 1

Section 14.1 Computability then else

Transcription:

Complexity, Undecidability and Tilings Chaim Goodman-Strauss Univ Arkansas strauss@uark.edu

Why are tiling puzzles difficult?

Why are tiling puzzles difficult? (And how difficult are they anyway?)

There is nothing particularly special about tilings in this regard:

There is nothing particularly special about tilings in this regard: Every combinatorial system, if it is rich enough, will pose computationally complex problems, in a manner we can define precisely.

There is nothing particularly special about tilings in this regard: Every combinatorial system, if it is rich enough, will pose computationally complex problems, in a manner we can define precisely. In essence, the question is: Can our system emulate arbitrary computations?

There is nothing particularly special about tilings in this regard: Every combinatorial system, if it is rich enough, will pose computationally complex problems, in a manner we can define precisely. In essence, the question is: Can our system emulate arbitrary computations? Tilings give a nice model, and in turn, the theory of computation illuminates some classical tiling problems.

Consider a simple question:

Consider a simple question: Can this tile be used to form a tiling of the entire plane? trivial example

Consider a simple question: Can this tile be used to form a tiling of the entire plane? How can you tell? trivial example

Consider a simple question: Can this tile be used to form a tiling of the entire plane? How can you tell? certainly not

Consider a simple question: Can this tile be used to form a tiling of the entire plane? How can you tell? Myers (23)

Consider a simple question: Can this tile be used to form a tiling of the entire plane? How can you tell? Myers (23)

Consider a simple question: Can this tile be used to form a tiling of the entire plane? How can you tell? Myers (23)

Consider a simple question: Can this tile be used to form a tiling of the entire plane? How can you tell? Mann (27)

Consider a simple question: Can this tile be used to form a tiling of the entire plane? How can you tell? Mann (27)

Consider a simple question: Can this tile be used to form a tiling of the entire plane? How can you tell? Mann (27) Is there a general method to tell whether or not a given tile admits a tiling?

Many of these examples are very badly behaved. This example (Myers 23) has isohedral number 1, the current world record

Many of these examples are very badly behaved. That is, the tile can form periodic tilings, but the tiles fall into at least ten orbits; equivalently, the smallest possible fundamental domain has ten tiles! An isohedral number 1 example

Many of these examples are very badly behaved. This example (Mann 1999) doesn t admit a tiling, but you can form quite large patches before things fall apart.

Many of these examples are very badly behaved. It has Heesch number 5, the current world record it can form a patch with five coronas" and no more.

Many of these examples are very badly behaved. There is no reason to suppose these are the worst possible examples

Many of these examples are very badly behaved. There is no reason to suppose these are the worst possible examples We have no idea (really) how they work, or what obstructions, if any, there are to creating increasingly terrible tiles.

Many of these examples are very badly behaved. There is no reason to suppose these are the worst possible examples We have no idea (really) how they work, or what obstructions, if any, there are to creating increasingly terrible tiles. Again, Is there a way to tell whether a given tile admits a tiling of the entire plane?

The obvious algorithm to try is See how far you can get!

The obvious algorithm to try is See how far you can get! More precisely, we might enumerate all possible configurations by the tile, trying to cover larger and larger regions.

The obvious algorithm to try is See how far you can get! More precisely, we might enumerate all possible configurations by the tile, trying to cover larger and larger regions. If the tile does not admit a tiling, then there will be some largest region that we can cover. Thm: If we can cover arbitrarily large regions, we can cover the entire plane.

The obvious algorithm to try is See how far you can get! More precisely, we might enumerate all possible configurations by the tile, trying to cover larger and larger regions. If the tile does not admit a tiling, then there will be some largest region that we can cover. But this algorithm will never halt if the tile does admit a tiling.

The obvious algorithm to try is See how far you can get! More precisely, we might enumerate all possible configurations by the tile, trying to cover larger and larger regions. If the tile does not admit a tiling, then there will be some largest region that we can cover. But this algorithm will never halt if the tile does admit a tiling. So we make a modification.

The obvious algorithm to try is See how far you can get! More precisely, we might enumerate all possible configurations by the tile, trying to cover larger and larger regions. If the tile does not admit a tiling, then there will be some largest region that we can cover. As we proceed, we check to see if any of our configurations could be a fundamental domain. If the tile admits a periodic tiling, we can discover this too.

The obvious algorithm to try is See how far you can get! More precisely, we might enumerate all possible configurations by the tile, trying to cover larger and larger regions. If the tile does not admit a tiling, then there will be some largest region that we can cover. As we proceed, we check to see if any of our configurations could be a fundamental domain. If the tile admits a periodic tiling, we can discover this too. This works fine the algorithm will halt with a yes or no answer, so long as nothing falls through the gaps so long as every tile either doesn t admit a tiling or admits a periodic tiling.

Surely this is the case!?

Surely this is the case!? Surely it is impossible for there to exist an aperiodic tile, that is, a tile that does admit a tiling of the plane, but never a periodic tiling.

Surely this is the case!? Surely it is impossible for there to exist an aperiodic tile, that is, a tile that does admit a tiling of the plane, but never a periodic tiling. Such a tile would have to force some sort of bad behavior at all scales.

Surely this is the case!? Surely it is impossible for there to exist an aperiodic tile, that is, a tile that does admit a tiling of the plane, but never a periodic tiling. Such a tile would have to force some sort of bad behavior at all scales. And surely there is a general procedure (or theorem, or theory, or algorithm) that can determine whether a given monotile admits a tiling of the plane.

Surely this is the case!? Surely it is impossible for there to exist an aperiodic tile, that is, a tile that does admit a tiling of the plane, but never a periodic tiling. Such a tile would have to force some sort of bad behavior at all scales. And surely there is a general procedure (or theorem, or theory, or algorithm) that can determine whether a given monotile admits a tiling of the plane. How hard can this be?

Surely this is the case!? Surely it is impossible for there to exist an aperiodic tile, that is, a tile that does admit a tiling of the plane, but never a periodic tiling. Such a tile would have to force some sort of bad behavior at all scales. And surely there is a general procedure (or theorem, or theory, or algorithm) that can determine whether a given monotile admits a tiling of the plane. How hard can this be? The examples we see here should make us cautious.

The algorithm we outlined (enumerate all configurations, covering larger and larger disks, until we either crash, or find a fundamental domain) succeeds if there is no aperiodic tile. If there is no aperiodic tile, then this algorithm solves both the Domino Problem and the Period Problem for any given monotile: The Domino Problem for Monotiles: Given a tile, does it fail to admit a tiling? The Period Problem for Monotiles: Given a tile, does it admit a periodic tiling?

That is: The Period Problem is decidable for monotiles The Domino Problem is decidable for monotiles There is no aperiodic monotile

That is: The Period Problem is undecidable for monotiles The Domino Problem is undecidable for monotiles There is an aperiodic monotile

Moreover, suppose there is a bound H on Heesch number; i.e., suppose every tile that does not admit a tiling has Heesch number less than H.

Moreover, suppose there is a bound H on Heesch number; i.e., suppose every tile that does not admit a tiling has Heesch number less than H. Then we would have an algorithm for checking whether a given tile does not admit a tiling:

Moreover, suppose there is a bound H on Heesch number; i.e., suppose every tile that does not admit a tiling has Heesch number less than H. Then we would have an algorithm for checking whether a given tile does not admit a tiling: Simply enumerate larger and larger configurations, increasing the number of coronas (shells). If we find a configuration with more than H coronas, we know the tile admits a tiling.

Similarly, suppose there is a bound I on isohedral number; i.e. suppose that every tile that admits a periodic tiling has isohedral number less than I.

Similarly, suppose there is a bound I on isohedral number; i.e. suppose that every tile that admits a periodic tiling has isohedral number less than I. Then we would have an algorithm for checking whether a given tile admits a periodic tiling:

Similarly, suppose there is a bound I on isohedral number; i.e. suppose that every tile that admits a periodic tiling has isohedral number less than I. Then we would have an algorithm for checking whether a given tile admits a periodic tiling: Simply enumerate all configurations with up to I tiles; if we fail to find a fundamental domain, then the tile does not admit a periodic tiling.

And so we have Isohedral number is unbounded for monotiles Heesch number is unbounded for monotiles The Period Problem is undecidable for monotiles The Domino Problem is undecidable for monotiles There is an aperiodic monotile

And so we have Isohedral number? is unbounded for monotiles Heesch number? is unbounded for monotiles The Period Problem? is undecidable for monotiles The Domino Problem? is undecidable for monotiles There is an aperiodic monotile? These are all open questions.

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA A

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA B 1

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA B 1 1

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA C 1

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA A 1

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA B 1 1

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA C 1 1

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA C 1 1

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA C 1 1 1

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA A 1 1 1

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA B 1 1 1 1

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA C 1 1 1

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA A 1 1 1

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA B 1 1 1 1

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA C 1 1 1

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA A 1 1 1

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA B 1 1 1 1

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA C 1 1 1

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA C 1 1 1 1

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA C 1 1 1 1 1

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA A 1 1 1 1 1

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA H 1 1 1 1 1

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA H 1 1 1 1 1

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA H 1 1 1 1 1

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA H 1 1 1 1 1 As mysterious as this little example is, it is not too difficult to see how they capture anything we might reasonably mean by computation";

Computation and Complexity The wellspring of all discussions of computational complexity is Alan Turing s 1935 construction of a simple, universal model of computation: φ A B C 1RB 1LB 1LC 1 1RH RC LA H 1 1 1 1 1 As mysterious as this little example is, it is not too difficult to see how they capture anything we might reasonably mean by computation"; this is the essence of the famous Church-Turing thesis.

And of course the most important undecidable problem is the Halting Problem: Does machine M eventually halt? A simple diagonalization trick shows no machine can take as input M and always halt with the correct answer the problem is not decidable. (It s not hard to discover if a machine halts just run it until it does the impossibility is discovering that any given machine will not halt.)

We can mechanically enumerate machines; let M n be the nth machine in any fixed, mechanical enumeration. Then take the following function: H(n) = { time for Mn to halt if M n does halt if M n does not halt

We can mechanically enumerate machines; let M n be the nth machine in any fixed, mechanical enumeration. Then take the following function: H(n) = { time for Mn to halt if M n does halt if M n does not halt Then no computable function can bound H(n). For suppose some computable f(n) > H(n) for all n; then we can calculate whether or not M n halts by calculating f(n) and running M n for up to f(n) steps; if M n hasn t halted by that point, we can be sure it never will. Hence no such f exists. This all has some interesting consequences.

In particular we can now sketch a proof of Gödel s theorem, that there are true but unprovable theorems:

In particular we can now sketch a proof of Gödel s theorem, that there are true but unprovable theorems: 1) Fix a (presumably consistent) formal logical system that captures arithmetic.

In particular we can now sketch a proof of Gödel s theorem, that there are true but unprovable theorems: 1) Fix a (presumably consistent) formal logical system that captures arithmetic. Now 2) We can mechanically enumerate all proofs, and hence, all theorems.

In particular we can now sketch a proof of Gödel s theorem, that there are true but unprovable theorems: 1) Fix a (presumably consistent) formal logical system that captures arithmetic. Now 2) We can mechanically enumerate all proofs, and hence, all theorems. 3) For every program M, one or the other of M halts" or M does not halt" is true.

In particular we can now sketch a proof of Gödel s theorem, that there are true but unprovable theorems: 1) Fix a (presumably consistent) formal logical system that captures arithmetic. Now 2) We can mechanically enumerate all proofs, and hence, all theorems. 3) For every program M, one or the other of M halts" or M does not halt" is true. 4) These are statements in our logical system (since running a program, in memory with data, is just arithmetic on giant binary numbers)

In particular we can now sketch a proof of Gödel s theorem, that there are true but unprovable theorems: 1) Fix a (presumably consistent) formal logical system that captures arithmetic. Now 2) We can mechanically enumerate all proofs, and hence, all theorems. 3) For every program M, one or the other of M halts" or M does not halt" is true. 4) These are statements in our logical system (since running a program, in memory with data, is just arithmetic on giant binary numbers) But then if every true statement were provable, we d have a procedure for settling the halting problem: run through all proofs, until you reach one for either M halts" or M does not halt".

In particular we can now sketch a proof of Gödel s theorem, that there are true but unprovable theorems: 1) Fix a (presumably consistent) formal logical system that captures arithmetic. Now 2) We can mechanically enumerate all proofs, and hence, all theorems. 3) For every program M, one or the other of M halts" or M does not halt" is true. 4) These are statements in our logical system (since running a program, in memory with data, is just arithmetic on giant binary numbers) But then if every true statement were provable, we d have a procedure for settling the halting problem: run through all proofs, until you reach one for either M halts" or M does not halt". QED

In fact, if M does halt, then the theorem M halts" can be proven: just run the program! But the complexity of these theorems cannot be bounded by any computable function!

In fact, if M does halt, then the theorem M halts" can be proven: just run the program! But the complexity of these theorems cannot be bounded by any computable function! For suppose that the proof of the nth theorem of this kind takes no more than some computable f(n) steps. Then again, the Halting Problem would be decidable: given n, calculate f(n) and enumerate all proofs up to length f(n). If we find a proof of the theorem, we know M n halts. On the other hand, if we don t find a proof, we know there ll never be one and M n does not halt!

With this in hand, we can ask, is our [[whatever]] powerful enough to capture Turing machines?

With this in hand, we can ask, is our [[whatever]] powerful enough to capture Turing machines? The generic answer is Yes! Conway s Presumption If enough is going on, your setting is computationally universal.

With this in hand, we can ask, is our [[whatever]] powerful enough to capture Turing machines? The generic answer is Yes! Conway s Presumption If enough is going on, your setting is computationally universal. And if if your problem is universal, then one will have true but unprovable theorems, short theorems with astoundingly lengthy proofs, and generally inscrutable behavior.

In 1961, Hao Wang gave a simple undecidable tiling problem: The Completion Problem: Given a set of tiles and a start configuration, can the configuration be completed to a tiling of the entire plane. (Wang was carrying out a larger program of settling the decididability of the remaining cases of Hilbert s satisfiability" problem: is there an algorithm to decide whether any given first order formula can be satisfied?)

To show the Completion Problem is undecidable, Wang constructed, for any Turing machine, a set of tiles T so that a certain seed configuration could be completed to a tiling if and only if the machine fails to halt. Since the Halting Problem is undecidable, so too is the Completion Problem. A A B 1 B 1 t = t = 1 t = 2 t = 3 φ A B C RB 1LA 1RB 1 1RB RC LH C 1 B t = 4 t = 5 A 1 1 t = 6

To show the Completion Problem is undecidable, Wang constructed, for any Turing machine, a set of tiles T so that a certain seed configuration could be completed to a tiling if and only if the machine fails to halt. Since the Halting Problem is undecidable, so too is the Completion Problem. φ A B C RB 1LA 1RB 1 1RB RC LH A B A 1 φ(a) φ(b) φ(a) B1 φ(b1) C φ(c) 1 B

1 C1 The real point is that Turing machines act in a purely local manner. These tiles perfectly emulate this machine, in tilings containing the seed tile. φ A B C RB 1LA 1RB 1 1RB RC LH A A 1 A C # 1 A B1 φ(a) φ(b) φ(a1) φ(a) 1 A1 B # B 1 A1 φ(b) φ(a1) φ(b1) φ(b1) C 1 φ(a) B1 B φ(b) 1 1 # B1 A1 φ(a1) 1 φ(b1) C1 H

Wang noted that if the Domino Problem were undecidable (for sets of tiles) then there would exist aperiodic sets of tiles; he conjectured no such sets exist. In a few years, his student R. Berger proved his conjecture incorrect, and gave the first aperiodic sets of tiles.

Wang noted that if the Domino Problem were undecidable (for sets of tiles) then there would exist aperiodic sets of tiles; he conjectured no such sets exist. In a few years, his student R. Berger proved his conjecture incorrect, and gave the first aperiodic sets of tiles. We can define the Heesch number of a non-tiling set of tiles to be the maximum radius disk it can cover; just as with the halting times of machine, as we enumerate tile sets, there can be no computable bound on Heesch number.

Wang noted that if the Domino Problem were undecidable (for sets of tiles) then there would exist aperiodic sets of tiles; he conjectured no such sets exist. In a few years, his student R. Berger proved his conjecture incorrect, and gave the first aperiodic sets of tiles. We can define the Heesch number of a non-tiling set of tiles to be the maximum radius disk it can cover; just as with the halting times of machine, as we enumerate tile sets, there can be no computable bound on Heesch number. We can define the isohedral number of a periodically tiling set of tiles to be the minimum sized fundamental domain; as we enumerate tile sets, this too can not be bounded by any computable function.

Wang noted that if the Domino Problem were undecidable (for sets of tiles) then there would exist aperiodic sets of tiles; he conjectured no such sets exist. In a few years, his student R. Berger proved his conjecture incorrect, and gave the first aperiodic sets of tiles. We can define the Heesch number of a non-tiling set of tiles to be the maximum radius disk it can cover; just as with the halting times of machine, as we enumerate tile sets, there can be no computable bound on Heesch number. We can define the isohedral number of a periodically tiling set of tiles to be the minimum sized fundamental domain; as we enumerate tile sets, this too can not be bounded by any computable function. Similarly, the minimum length proof that a given set of tiles admits a periodic tiling, or no tiling, cannot be bounded by any computable bound.

Finally, these are asymptotic results, What can one say about the marginal cases? This brings up back to the complexity of our original puzzles. What can you do with a single tile?

Finally, these are asymptotic results, What can one say about the marginal cases? This brings up back to the complexity of our original puzzles. What can you do with a single tile? Is tiling by a single tile computationally universal?

Finally, these are asymptotic results, What can one say about the marginal cases? This brings up back to the complexity of our original puzzles. What can you do with a single tile? Is tiling by a single tile computationally universal? Are Heesch numbers and isohedral numbers unbounded, and if so, do they have computable bounds?

But again, there is nothing intrinsically special about tilings, or Turing machines Complexity and undecidability are ubiquitous in combinatorial settings (i.e. in all mathematics)! We see this already in simple recreational puzzles!

But again, there is nothing intrinsically special about tilings, or Turing machines Complexity and undecidability are ubiquitous in combinatorial settings (i.e. in all mathematics)! We see this already in simple recreational puzzles! You may keep the toys...

A quick advertisement The Symmetries of Things with John H. Conway & Heidi Burgiel

The Symmetries of Things with John H. Conway & Heidi Burgiel

mathbun.com

The Math Factor mathfactor.uark.edu