Microeconomic Theory-I Washington State University Midterm Exam #1 - Answer key. Fall 2016

Similar documents
Recitation 2-09/01/2017 (Solution)

Recitation #2 (August 31st, 2018)

Midterm #1 EconS 527 Wednesday, February 21st, 2018

Microeconomics, Block I Part 1

Microeconomic Theory -1- Introduction

EconS Micro Theory I Recitation #4b - Demand theory (Applications) 1

EconS 501 Final Exam - December 10th, 2018

Rice University. Answer Key to Mid-Semester Examination Fall ECON 501: Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Part A

Advanced Microeconomics

Utility Maximization Problem

Chapter 4. Maximum Theorem, Implicit Function Theorem and Envelope Theorem

Solution Homework 1 - EconS 501

; p. p y p y p y. Production Set: We have 2 constraints on production - demand for each factor of production must be less than its endowment

Advanced Microeconomics

Notes I Classical Demand Theory: Review of Important Concepts

1. Suppose preferences are represented by the Cobb-Douglas utility function, u(x1,x2) = Ax 1 a x 2

Utility Maximization Problem. Advanced Microeconomic Theory 2

Adv. Micro Theory, ECON

EconS Microeconomic Theory I Recitation #5 - Production Theory-I 1

Advanced Microeconomics I: Consumers, Firms and Markets Chapters 1+2

ECON501 - Vector Di erentiation Simon Grant

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Homework #9 - Answer key

Hicksian Demand and Expenditure Function Duality, Slutsky Equation

Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Chapter 2: Demand Theory

Advanced Microeconomics Fall Lecture Note 1 Choice-Based Approach: Price e ects, Wealth e ects and the WARP

The Fundamental Welfare Theorems

Econ 121b: Intermediate Microeconomics

Consumer theory Topics in consumer theory. Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais

Advanced Microeconomics Problem Set 1

Solution Homework 1 - EconS 501

PS4-Solution. Mehrdad Esfahani. Fall Arizona State University. Question 1 Question 2 Question 3 Question 4 Question 5

Structural Properties of Utility Functions Walrasian Demand

Advanced Microeconomic Analysis, Lecture 6

The Ohio State University Department of Economics. Homework Set Questions and Answers

Lecture 8: Basic convex analysis

Last Revised: :19: (Fri, 12 Jan 2007)(Revision:

Intro to Economic analysis

Economics 121b: Intermediate Microeconomics Midterm Suggested Solutions 2/8/ (a) The equation of the indifference curve is given by,

1 Objective. 2 Constrained optimization. 2.1 Utility maximization. Dieter Balkenborg Department of Economics

Microeconomics CHAPTER 2. THE FIRM

Microeconomic Theory: Lecture 2 Choice Theory and Consumer Demand

= 2 = 1.5. Figure 4.1: WARP violated

Economics 401 Sample questions 2

Advanced Microeconomic Analysis Solutions to Midterm Exam

Notes on Consumer Theory

Problem Set 5: Expenditure Minimization, Duality, and Welfare 1. Suppose you were given the following expenditure function: β (α

Lecture 3 - Axioms of Consumer Preference and the Theory of Choice

a = (a 1; :::a i )

Limit pricing models and PBE 1

Advanced Microeconomics

Nonlinear Programming (NLP)

Final Examination with Answers: Economics 210A

Econ Review Set 2 - Answers

Preferences and Utility

Microeconomics II Lecture 4. Marshallian and Hicksian demands for goods with an endowment (Labour supply)

Week 9: Topics in Consumer Theory (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 2)

Gi en Demand for Several Goods

EconS Advanced Microeconomics II Handout on Mechanism Design

Duality. for The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd ed. Lawrence E. Blume

The Kuhn-Tucker Problem

i) This is simply an application of Berge s Maximum Theorem, but it is actually not too difficult to prove the result directly.

Lecture 1: Ricardian Theory of Trade

Microeconomic Theory I Midterm

Week 7: The Consumer (Malinvaud, Chapter 2 and 4) / Consumer November Theory 1, 2015 (Jehle and 1 / Reny, 32

Economics 101. Lecture 2 - The Walrasian Model and Consumer Choice

Generalized Convexity in Economics

Midterm Exam, Econ 210A, Fall 2008

Partial Solutions to Homework 2

x 1 1 and p 1 1 Two points if you just talk about monotonicity (u (c) > 0).

Econ 101A Midterm 1 Th 29 September 2004.

ECON0702: Mathematical Methods in Economics

Revealed Preferences and Utility Functions

Department of Agricultural Economics. PhD Qualifier Examination. May 2009

GS/ECON 5010 section B Answers to Assignment 1 September Q1. Are the preferences described below transitive? Strictly monotonic? Convex?

Equilibrium and Pareto Efficiency in an exchange economy

Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Chapter 6: Partial and General Equilibrium

Chapter 1 Consumer Theory Part II

3. THE EXCHANGE ECONOMY

1 Uncertainty and Insurance

Lecture 7: General Equilibrium - Existence, Uniqueness, Stability

CHAPTER 3: OPTIMIZATION

Demand Theory. Lecture IX and X Utility Maximization (Varian Ch. 7) Federico Trionfetti

Advanced Microeconomic Analysis Solutions to Homework #2

Consumer Theory. Ichiro Obara. October 8, 2012 UCLA. Obara (UCLA) Consumer Theory October 8, / 51

ECON2285: Mathematical Economics

ECONOMICS 001 Microeconomic Theory Summer Mid-semester Exam 2. There are two questions. Answer both. Marks are given in parentheses.

MSc Economics: Economic Theory and Applications I. Consumer Theory

Midterm Examination: Economics 210A October 2011

Problem set 2 solutions Prof. Justin Marion Econ 100M Winter 2012

Microeconomics II. MOSEC, LUISS Guido Carli Problem Set n 3

Alp Simsek (MIT) Recitation Notes: 1. Gorman s Aggregation Th eorem2. Normative Representative November 9, Household Theorem / 16

Lecture 6: Contraction mapping, inverse and implicit function theorems

U b (x b ) = xb 1x b 2 x a 1. means the consumption of good i by an h-type person.

Introductory Microeconomics

BEEM103 UNIVERSITY OF EXETER. BUSINESS School. January 2009 Mock Exam, Part A. OPTIMIZATION TECHNIQUES FOR ECONOMISTS solutions

Microeconomics Fall 2017 Problem set 1: Possible answers

z = f (x; y) f (x ; y ) f (x; y) f (x; y )

Econ 5150: Applied Econometrics Empirical Demand Analysis. Sung Y. Park CUHK

First Welfare Theorem

Microeconomic Theory I Midterm October 2017

Transcription:

Microeconomic Theory-I Washington State University Midterm Exam # - Answer key Fall 06. [Checking properties of preference relations]. Consider the following preference relation de ned in the positive quadrant X = R +. A bundle (x ; x ) is weakly preferred to another bundle (y ; y ), i.e., (x ; x ) % (y ; y ), if and only if min f3x + x ; x + 3x g min f3y + y ; y + 3y g (a) Consider bundle (x ; x ) = (; ). For this bundle, draw the upper contour set (UCS), the lower contour set (LCS), and the indi erence set (IND) of this preference relation. Take a bundle (; ). Then, min f3 + ; + 3 g = min f8; 7g = 7: The upper contour set of this bundle is given by UCS(; ) = f(x ; x ) % (; )g = fmin f3x + x ; x + 3x g 7 min f8; 7gg which is graphically represented by all those bundles in R + which are strictly above both lines 3x + x = 7 and x + 3x = 7. That is, for all (x ; x ) strictly above both lines x = 7 3 x and x = 7 3 3 x : (See gure, which depicts these two lines and shades the set of bundles lying weakly above both lines.) On the other hand, the lower contour set is de ned as LCS(; ) = f(; ) % (x ; x )g = f7 min f3x + x ; x + 3x gg ;

which is graphically represented by all bundles (x ; x ) weakly below the maximum of the lines described above. For instance, bundle (y ; y ) = (:5; 0), which lies on the horizontal axis and between both lines horizontal intercept, implies minf3 :5 + 0; :5 + 3 0g = minf7:5; 5g = 5 thus implying that this consumer prefers bundle (x ; x ) = (; ) than (y ; y ) = (:5; 0). A similar argument applies to all other bundles lying above x = 7 3 x and below x = 7 x 3 3, where bundle (:5; 0) also belongs; see the triangle that both lines form at the right-hand side of the gure. Similarly, bundles such as (0; :5) yield minf3 0 + :5; 0 + 3 :5g = minf5; 7:5g = 5; which implies that the consumer also prefers bundle (; ) to (0; :5). An analogous argument applies to all bundles above line x = 7 3 x but below x = 7 x 3 3 in the triangle at the left-hand side of Figure. Figure. UCS and LCS of bundle (,). Finally, those bundles for which the UCS and LCS overlap are those in IND of bundle (,). (b) Show that this preference relation satis es: (i) completeness, and (ii) transitivity. Completeness. First, note that both of the elements in the minfg operator are real numbers, i.e., (3x + x ) R + and (x + 3x ) R +, thus implying that the minimum min f3x + x ; x + 3x g = a exists and it is also a real number, a R +. Similarly, the minimum min f3y + y ; y + 3y g = b exists and is a real number, b R +. Therefore, we can easily compare a and b, obtaining that either a b, which implies (x ; x ) % (y ; y ); or a b, which implies (y ; y ) % (x ; x ), or both, a = b, which entails (x ; x ) (y ; y ). Hence, the preference relation is complete.

Transitivity. We need to show that, for any three bundles (x ; x ), (y ; y ) and (z ; z ) such that (x ; x ) % (y ; y ) and (y ; y ) % (z ; z ), then (x ; x ) % (z ; z ) First, note that (x ; x ) % (y ; y ) implies a min f3x + x ; x + 3x g min f3y + y ; y + 3y g b and (y ; y ) % (z ; z ) implies that b min f3y + y ; y + 3y g min f3z + z ; z + 3z g c Combining both conditions we have that a b c, which implies that a c. Hence, we have that min f3x + x ; x + 3x g min f3z + z ; z + 3z g and thus (x ; x ) % (z ; z ), implying that this preference relation is transitive.. [Infering the utility function from the indirect utility.] Consider an individual facing price vector p = (p ; p ) >> 0 and income w > 0. After solving his UMP, the individual nds that his indirect utility function is v(p; w) = p p w: Show that his utility function u(x ; x ) must have a Cobb-Douglas representation. [Hint: Use duality, where we learned that the indirect utility function evaluated at the expenditure function is v (p; e(p; u)) = u. Afterwards, use another result from duality: the Hicksian demand evaluated at u = v(p; w) coincides with the Walrasian demand, i.e., h i (p; v(p; w)) = x i (p; w) for every good i = ;.] Short proof. From duality, the indirect utility function evaluated at w = e(p; u) yields v (p; e(p; u)) = u which in this case entails p p e(p; u) = u. Solving for e(p; u), we obtain u e(p; u) = p p = p h (p; u) + p h (p; u) where the second equality is due to the de nition of e(p; u), and where h i (p; u) denotes the Hicksian demand of good i = f; g. Di erentiating e(p; u) with respect to p yields @e(p; u) u = @p p + p = h (p; u). By duality, we know that the Hicksian demand evaluated at u = v(p; w) coincides with the Walrasian demand, i.e., h i (p; v(p; w)) = x i (p; w). Therefore, evaluating the above Hicksian demand at u = v(p; w), where w = e(p; u), yields h (p; v(p; w)) = x (p; w) = p p 3 w p + p = w p :

And a similar argument applies if we di erentiate e(p; u) with respect to p, nd the Hicksian demand for good, h (p; u), and then evaluate it at u = v(p; w) to obtain the Walrasian demand x (p; w) = ( ) w p. These Walrasian demands are clearly of the Cobb-Douglas type, since the consumer spends a constant fraction of his income on each good. Then, u(x ; x ) = x x. Long proof (EMP approach). First, recall from duality that u(x) min v(p; p x) () pr + Since v(p; w) is homogeneous of degree zero, we can divide both arguments by px to obtain that the indirect utility function v(p; w) is una ected, i.e., v(p; w) = p v ;. Let p p, and thus v(p; w) = v (p; ). As a consequence, if price px px vector p minimizes v(p; p x) for an income level p x = w, then price vector p minimizes v (p; ) for an income level p x =. That is, we can rewrite program () as u(x) min v(p; ) subject to p x = () pr + We can now nd the price vector p = (p ; p ) that solves program (). Plugging them afterwards in the indirect utility function v(p; ) will yield the original utility function u(x) that this consumer maximized in his UMP (as stated in ()). Since program () is a constrained minimization problem, we set up the Lagrangian L = p p (p x + p x ) Taking rst-order conditions with respect to p and p yields, respectively dl = p p x = 0 dp dl = ( )p p x = 0 dp and dl d = p x p x + = 0 and simultaneously solving for p and p we obtain p = x and p = x We can nally plug these two prices, which solve (), into the indirect utility funciton v(p; ), yielding! v(p ; p ; ) = () x x = ( ) x x which is clearly of the Cobb-Douglas type. For instance, labeling A ( ) yields v(p ; p ; ) = Ax x, thus taking a more familiar format. 4

3. [Finding the compensating and equivalent variation with little information.] Consider a consumer who, facing a initial price vector p 0 R n ++ for n commodities, purchases a bundle x R n + with an income of w > 0 dollars. Assume that the price of all goods experiences a common increase measured by factor >. (a) Compute the compensating variation (CV) of this price increase. Using the expenditure function, the CV is CV = e(p ; u 0 ) e(p 0 ; u 0 ) where p and p 0 denote the nal and initial price vector, respectively, and u 0 represents the utility level that the consumer achieves at the initial pricewealth pair (p 0 ; w). In this exercise, we are informed that nal prices p satisfy p = p 0, thus implying that the above expression for CV can be rewritten as CV = e(p 0 ; u 0 ) e(p 0 ; u 0 ) Recall that the expenditure function is homogeneous of degree one in prices, i.e., e(p 0 ; u 0 ) = e(p 0 ; u 0 ). In words, increasing the prices of all goods by a common factor increases the consumer s minimal expenditure (the expenditure he needs to reach utility level u 0 ) by exactly. In addition, the consumer spends w dollars, i.e., e(p 0 ; u 0 ) = w. These properties reduce the expression of the CV to CV = e(p 0 ; u 0 ) e(p 0 ; u 0 ) = = e(p 0 ; u 0 ) {z } w e(p 0 ; u 0 ) = {z } w = w w = w( ) (b) Compute the equivalent variation (EV) of this price increase. Using the expenditure function, the EV is EV = e(p ; u ) e(p 0 ; u ) where u represents the utility level that the consumer achieves at the nal price-wealth pair (p ; w). In this exercise, we are informed that p = p 0, or p 0 = p, implying that the above expression for EV can be rewritten as EV = e(p ; u ) e p ; u Since the expenditure function is homogeneous of degree one in prices, i.e., e p ; u = e (p ; u ), and the consumer spends w dollars, e(p ; u ) = w. These properties reduce the EV to EV = e(p ; u ) e p ; u = = e(p 0 ; u 0 ) {z } e p ; u = {z } w w = w w = w 5

Following the same numerical example as in section (a), if all prices experience a 50% increase, i.e., = :5, the equivalent variation would be EV = 0:3w, thus suggesting that, before the price increase, the consumer would need to give up a third of his wealth in order to be as worse o as he will be after the price increase. (c) Evaluate your results from parts (a) and (b) if the common increase in prices is, speci cally, = :5 (that is, a 50% increase). Interpret the CV and EV in this speci c case. For instance, increasing all prices by 50%, i.e., = :5, yields a compensating variation of CV = w(:5 ) = 0:5w, which implies that the consumer needs to receive half of his initial wealth in order to be able to reach the same utility level as before the price change. The equivalent variation would be EV = w :5 = 0:3w, thus suggesting that, before the price increase, the consumer would need to give up a third of his wealth in order to be as worse o as he will be after the price increase. 4. [Aggregation with additively separable preferences] Consider a society with N individuals, and suppose that every individual i N has preferences representable by the same additively separable utility function u i (x ; x ; :::; x L ) = LX u i (x j ) where u i (x j ) denotes the utility that every individual i obtains from consuming x j units of good j = ; ; :::; L. Assume that all functions u i (x j ) are (twice continuously) di erentiable for every good j, and that marginal utility is strictly positive, i.e., u 0 i(x j ) > 0 for every j. Assume that the price vector p >> 0 (i.e., it is positive in every component), and that every individual has the same wealth level w > 0. Last, assume that the utility maximization problem has a unique and interior solution. Show that we cannot guarantee that a positive representative consumer exists. That is, aggregate demand cannot be expressed as a function of p and aggregate wealth w = P N i= w alone, or more compactly NX x i (p; w) 6= x(p; w): [Hint: An example su ces.] i= No. Recall that, for a representative consumer to exist, the wealth expansion paths of all individuals in this economy must be straight and parallel to each other. We can nd, however, several examples of separable utility functions whose wealth expansion paths are not straight. Here is one example: j= u(x ; x ) = p x + ln x : Taking rst order conditions with respect to x and x, we obtain p x = p, and 6

which implies x = p x p x = p p Solving for x, we nd the equation x = p p p x, which represents the relationship between the utility-maximizing values of x and x, i.e., the wealth expansion path. (Recall that wealth expansion path connects the utility maximizing bundles (x ; x ) for a given wealth level with those arising under a di erent wealth level.) Equation x = p p p x is depicted in Figure. Figure. Wealth expansion path of u(x ; x ) = p x + ln x. The wealth expansion path, is, hence, not a straight line. Thus, no representative consumer exists. Alternative approach. An alternative way to show this result is by testing whether preferences are not homothetic: if they are not, the separable utility function will not generate a straight wealth expansion path. In particular, recall that to test for homotheticity, we need to check that the MRS is homogeneous of degree one. In this case, MRS ; (x ; x ) = MU (x ; x ) MU (x ; x ) = p x = x x p. x And increasing all arguments by a common factor, the MRS becomes thus implying that MRS ; (x ; x ) = MU (x ; x ) MU (x ; x ) = x p x = p x p x MRS ; (x ; x ) = p MRS ; (x ; x ) Finally, since p is not necessarily equal to, this separable utility function is not homothetic, thus not guaranteeing straight wealth expansion paths. 7

Several popular preferences (such as the Stone-Geary, Cobb-Douglas, quasilinear for L = goods, CES etc) can be represented by separable utility functions, and also by indirect utility functions of the Gorman form, for which a positive representative consumer exists. However, the representation of a consumer preference by an additively separable utility function is insu cient to guarantee the existence of a positive representative consumer, even if all consumers have identical utility functions. 8