A proof of Bell s inequality in quantum mechanics using causal interactions

Similar documents
Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox and Bell s inequalities

Bell s Theorem. Ben Dribus. June 8, Louisiana State University

Closing the Debates on Quantum Locality and Reality: EPR Theorem, Bell's Theorem, and Quantum Information from the Brown-Twiss Vantage

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM

Measurement Independence, Parameter Independence and Non-locality

Bell s inequalities and their uses

Has CHSH-inequality any relation to EPR-argument?

EPR Paradox and Bell s Inequality

Spatial Locality: A hidden variable unexplored in entanglement experiments

Introduction to Bell s theorem: the theory that solidified quantum mechanics

Logical difficulty from combining counterfactuals in the GHZ-Bell theorems

Q8 Lecture. State of Quantum Mechanics EPR Paradox Bell s Thm. Physics 201: Lecture 1, Pg 1

Locality and the Hardy theorem

RUNS: A_B, A_B', A'_B,

Measurement: still a problem in standard quantum theory

The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen thought experiment and Bell s theorem

Super-Quantum, Non-Signaling Correlations Cannot Exist

Solving the Einstein Podolsky Rosen puzzle: The origin of non-locality in Aspect-type experiments

Violation of Bell Inequalities

EPR Paradox Solved by Special Theory of Relativity

J = L + S. to this ket and normalize it. In this way we get expressions for all the kets

First-Degree Entailment

Entanglement. arnoldzwicky.org. Presented by: Joseph Chapman. Created by: Gina Lorenz with adapted PHYS403 content from Paul Kwiat, Brad Christensen

226 My God, He Plays Dice! Entanglement. Chapter This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/problems/entanglement

Response to Wiseman, Rieffel, and Cavalcanti on Bell s 1964 Paper

Logical difficulty from combining counterfactuals in the GHZ-Bell theorems

Confounding Causality Principles: comment on Rédei and san Pedro s Distinguishing Causality Principles

David Bohm s Hidden Variables

Bounding the Probability of Causation in Mediation Analysis

The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen thought-experiment and Bell s theorem

Causality and Local Determinism versus Quantum Nonlocality.

Local Realism Explains Bell Violations

Hardy s Paradox. Chapter Introduction

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics CONSISTENT FIRM CHOICE AND THE THEORY OF SUPPLY

Quantum Physics & Reality

6.896 Quantum Complexity Theory September 9, Lecture 2

EPR Paradox and Bell Inequalities

Causation and EPR. But, alas, this hypothesis is mathematically inconsistent with the results of the case b runs, those runs

Hugh Everett III s Many Worlds

Quantum Entanglement. Chapter Introduction. 8.2 Entangled Two-Particle States

arxiv: v2 [quant-ph] 22 Sep 2008

Locality, Causality, and Realism in the Derivation of Bell s Inequality Adrian Wüthrich

Causality II: How does causal inference fit into public health and what it is the role of statistics?

Statistical Models for Causal Analysis

arxiv:quant-ph/ v4 17 Jan 2005

Lecture 29 Relevant sections in text: 3.9

Cosmology Lecture 2 Mr. Kiledjian

Technical Track Session I: Causal Inference

Counterfactuals in Quantum Mechanics

CAT L4: Quantum Non-Locality and Contextuality

Singlet State Correlations

Popper School Methodological Disproof of Quantum Logic

Basics on quantum information

Quantum Computing. Part I. Thorsten Altenkirch

Lecture 4. QUANTUM MECHANICS FOR MULTIPLE QUBIT SYSTEMS

Sensitivity analysis and distributional assumptions

MACROREALISM and WEAK MEASUREMENT

The Relativistic Quantum World

MACROREALISM, NONINVASIVENESS and WEAK MEASUREMENT

arxiv:quant-ph/ v2 21 Jun 2004

Counterfactuals in Quantum Mechanics arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 4 Sep 2007

A possible quantum basis of panpsychism

On Likelihoodism and Intelligent Design

UCLA Department of Statistics Papers

Problems with/failures of QM

Incompatibility Paradoxes

The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics (Handout Eight) between the microphysical and the macrophysical. The macrophysical world could be understood

Timeline: Bohm (1951) EPR (1935) CHSH (1969) Bell (1964) Theory. Freedman Clauser (1972) Aspect (1982) Weihs (1998) Weinland (2001) Zeilinger (2010)

What is the Price for Maintaining It? A. J. Leggett Dept. of Physics University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign

Comments on There is no axiomatic system for the. quantum theory. Noname manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) J.

PREAMBLE (Revised) Why Einstein was Mistaken About the Velocity of Light.

A Classification of Hidden-Variable Properties

Quotations from other works that I have written

Honors 225 Physics Study Guide/Chapter Summaries for Final Exam; Roots Chapters 15-18

The paradox of knowability, the knower, and the believer

Deep Metaphysical Indeterminacy

The identification of synergism in the sufficient-component cause framework

Super-Quantum, Non-Signaling Correlations Cannot Exist

Proof of absence of spooky action at a distance in quantum correlations

The controlled-not (CNOT) gate exors the first qubit into the second qubit ( a,b. a,a + b mod 2 ). Thus it permutes the four basis states as follows:

Understanding Long-Distance Quantum Correlations

DEALING WITH MULTIVARIATE OUTCOMES IN STUDIES FOR CAUSAL EFFECTS

Casual Mediation Analysis

Delayed Choice Paradox

3/10/11. Which interpreta/on sounds most reasonable to you? PH300 Modern Physics SP11

Computer Simulation of Einstein-Podolsky. Podolsky-Rosen- Bohm Experiments with Photons.

On the origin of probability in quantum mechanics

COPENHAGEN INTERPRETATION:

Lecture 14, Thurs March 2: Nonlocal Games

Odd Things about Quantum Mechanics: Abandoning Determinism In Newtonian physics, Maxwell theory, Einstein's special or general relativity, if an initi

MINIMAL SUFFICIENT CAUSATION AND DIRECTED ACYCLIC GRAPHS 1. By Tyler J. VanderWeele and James M. Robins. University of Chicago and Harvard University

Quantum Entanglement Through Hidden Dimensions

On a proposal for Quantum Signalling

Empirical and counterfactual conditions for su cient cause interactions

Basics on quantum information

Propositions and Proofs

A No-Go Result on Common Cause Approaches via Hardy s Paradox

BUBBLE, BUBBLE, TOIL AND TROUBLE A fresh look at relativity, uncertainty and compatibility

Entangled Frankenstein Photons

For True Conditionalizers Weisberg s Paradox is a False Alarm

Transcription:

A proof of Bell s inequality in quantum mechanics using causal interactions James M. Robins, Tyler J. VanderWeele Departments of Epidemiology and Biostatistics, Harvard School of Public Health Richard D. Gill Mathematical Institute, Leiden University Abstract We give a simple proof of Bell s inequality in quantum mechanics which, in conjunction with experiments, demonstrates that the local hidden variables assumption is false. The proof sheds light on relationships between the notion of causal interaction and interference between particles. Keywords: Interactions, interference, local reality, quantum physics. 1

Introduction Neyman introduced a formal mathematical theory of counterfactual causation that now has become standard language in many quantitative disciplines, including statistics, epidemiology, philosophy, economics, sociology, and artificial intelligence, but not in physics. Several researchers in these disciplines (Frangakis et al., 2007; Pearl, 2009) have speculated that there exists a relationship between this counterfactual theory and quantum mechanics, but have not provided any substantive formal relation between the two. In this note, we show that theory concerning causal interaction, grounded in notions of counterfactuals, can be used to give a straightforward proof of a result in quantum physics, namely, Bell s inequality. Our proof relies on recognizing that results on causal interaction (VanderWeele, 2010) can be used to empirically test for interference between units (VanderWeele et al., 2011). It should be stressed that a number of extremely short and elegant proofs of both Bell s original inequality (and its generalizations) are already available in the physics literature. In fact some of these proofs are based on reasoning with counterfactuals (Gill et al., 2001). Our contribution is to explicitly show relations to the theory of causal interactions. We motivate our proof with an exceedingly short history of the Bell Inequality that is elaborated upon later. A non-intuitive implication of quantum theory is that pairs of spin 1/2 particles (e.g., electrons) can be prepared in an entangled state with the following property. When the spins of both particles are measured along a common (spatial) axis, the measurement of one particle s spin perfectly predicts the spin of the other; if the first particle s spin is up, then the spin of the second must be down. One explanation would be that the measurement itself of the first particle determined the spin of the second, even if physically separated, perhaps, by many light years. This would mean that reality was not local ; what occurred at one place would affect reality (i.e. the spin of the second electron) at another. However, Einstein believed in local realism and argued that the more plausible explanation was that both particles are carrying with them from their common source hidden correlated spin outcomes which they will exhibit when measured (Einstein 2

et al., 1935). He therefore argued for local realism and rejected the previous explanation. Bohr disagreed with Einstein and his local realist assumption. Neither Einstein nor Bohr apparently realized that the hypothesis of local realism was subject to empirical test. In 1964, John Bell showed that a test was possible; he proved that if strict locality were true, there would be certain inequality relations between measurable quantities that must hold (Bell, 1964); quantum theory predicted that these inequalities must be violated. Experiments found Bell s inequalities were indeed violated (though see discussion below for further comments). Einstein was wrong; local realism is false. A Proof of Bell s Inequality Using Causal Interactions We now show how results on causal interaction can be used to produce an alternative proof of Bell s theorem. Suppose we have two particles and can use devices to measure the spin of each, along any axis of our choosing. Let X 1 and X 2 be two interventions each taking values in {0, 1, 2}, where X 1 records the angle (i.e. axis in space) at which particle 1 is measured, and X 2 records the angle at which particle 2 is measured, and where 0, 1, 2 correspond to three particular angles. Let Y 1 (x 1, x 2 ) be the binary spin (up= 1 or down= 1) of particle 1 and Y 2 (x 1, x 2 ) be the spin for particle 2, when particle 1 is measured at angle x 1 and particle two is measured at x 2. In the language of the Neyman model Y i (x 1, x 2 ) is the counterfactual response of particle i under the joint intervention (x 1, x 2 ). Let M(x 1, x 2 ) = 1{Y 1 (x 1, x 2 ) = Y 2 (x 1, x 2 )} be an indicator function that the spin directions agree so that M(x 1, x 2 ) = 1 if the spin direction agree and M(x 1, x 2 ) = 0 if they disagree. Suppose that the particles are in a maximally entangled state. Then, according to quantum mechanics of the 2 particle system, for i, j = 0, 1, 2, E[M(x 1 = i, x 2 = j)] = sin 2 ( ij /2), where ij is the angle between angles i and j. This result has been confirmed by experiments in which the angles of measurement were randomized (though see discussion below for further comments). Therefore in what follows we take {E[M(x 1, x 2 )]; x 1 {0, 1, 2}, x 2 {0, 1, 2}} as known, based on the data from experiment. Since sin (0) = 0, M(i, i) = 0, i = 0, 1, 2, with 3

probability 1 and, therefore, also Y 1 (i, i) = Y 2 (i, i) = 0, with probability 1, as mentioned earlier. We formalize the hypothesis of local hidden variables by the hypothesis that spin measured on one particle does not depend on the angle at which the other particle is measured. This can be stated as: for all angles (x 1, x 2 ) Y 1 (x 1, x 2 ) = Y 1 (x 1 ) Y 2 (x 1, x 2 ) = Y 2 (x 2 ). In some of the experiments referenced above the times of the two measurements were sufficiently close and the separation of the particles sufficiently great that even a signal traveling at the speed of light could not inform one particle of the result of the other s spin measurement. Therefore, refuting the hypothesis of local hidden variables implies reality is not local and therefore we can essentially treat the hypothesis of local hidden variable and local reality as the same; we return to this point in the discussion. The hypothesis asserts both locality and reality. It asserts locality because the angle x 2 at which particle 2 is measured has no effect the spin Y 1 (x 1 ) of particle 1. It asserts reality because the spin Y i (x) of a particle measured along axis x is assumed to exist for every x,even though for each i, only one of the Y i (x) is observed; the one corresponding to the axis along which particle was actually measured. All other Y i (x) are missing data in the language of statisticians or, equivalently, hidden variables in the language of physicists. The counterfactuals Y i (x) correspond exactly to what Einstein called elements of reality. In the language of counterfactual theory, the hypothesis of local reality is, by definition, the hypothesis of no interference between treatments. In the following a unit may be taken to be a pair of entangled particles. Theorem 1. If for some unit, M (0, 0) = 0, M(1, 2) = 1, M(0, 2) = 0, M(1, 0) = 0 then the hypothesis of local hidden variables is false. Proof. By contradiction: Suppose the hypothesis holds. Now M(1, 2) = 1 implies either 4

(a) that Y 1 (1) = Y 2 (2) = 1 or (b) that Y 1 (1) = Y 2 (2) = 1. Suppose that (a) holds: then M(0, 2) = 0 and Y 2 (2) = 1 imply Y 1 (0) = 1. But, M(1, 0) = 0 and Y 1 (1) = 1 imply Y 2 (0) = 1 and thus,by M (0, 0) = 0, that Y 1 (0) = 1, a contradiction. Suppose instead that (b) holds. Then M(0, 2) = 0 and Y 2 (2) = 1 implies Y 1 (0) = 1. But M(1, 0) = 0 and Y 1 (1) = 1 implies Y 2 (0) = 1 and thus, by M (0, 0) = 0, that Y 1 (0) = 1, again a contradiction. Thus it cannot be the case that Y i (x 1, x 2 ) = Y i (x i ), i = 1, 2. The next result is given in VanderWeele (2010) in the context of testing for a causal interaction, sometimes referred to as epistasis in genetics. It relates the empirical data E[M(x 1, x 2 )] to the existence of a unit satisfying M(1, 2) = 1, M(0, 2) = M(1, 0) = M(0, 0) = 0. Within the counterfactual framework, this would constitute a causal interaction for the variable M. Since the proof of the result relating observed data E[M(x 1, x 2 )] to units such that M(1, 2) = 1, M(0, 2) = M(1, 0) = M(0, 0) = 0 is essentially one line, we give it here also for completeness. Theorem 2. If E[M(1, 2)] E[M(0, 2)] E[M(1, 0)] E[M(0, 0)] > 0, then there must exist a unit with M(1, 2) = 1, M(0, 2) = M(1, 0) = M(0, 0) = 0. Proof. By contradiction. Suppose there were no unit with M(1, 2) = 1, M(0, 2) = M(1, 0) = M(0, 0) = 0. Then, for all units, M(1, 2) M(0, 2) M(1, 0) M(0, 0) 0 which implies E[M(1, 2)] E[M(0, 2)] E[M(1, 0)] E[M(0, 0)] 0, a contradiction. An immediate corollary of Theorems 1 and 2 is then: Corollary. If E[M(1, 2)] E[M(0, 2)] E[M(1, 0)] E[M(0, 0)] > 0, then the the hypothesis of local hidden variables is false. This corollary is referred to as Bell s theorem in the physics literature. Its premise is referred to as Bell s inequality. As noted above, from the quantum mechanics of the 2- particle system, and confirmed by experiment, E[M(x 1 = i, x 1 = j)] = sin 2 ( ij /2). Thus we have that: 5

E[M(1, 2)] E[M(0, 2)] E[M(1, 0)] E[M(0, 0)] = sin 2 ( 12 /2) sin 2 ( 02 /2) sin 2 ( 10 /2) 0 From this it follows that the local hidden variables assumption is rejected if sin 2 ( 12 /2) > sin 2 ( 02 /2) + sin 2 ( 10 /2) but the angles 0, 1, 2 can easily be chosen to satisfy this inequality. Thus the hypothesis of local hidden variables is false. The prototypical Bell inequality, and accompanying experiment, has in recent years spawned a multitude of variations involving more than two particles, measurements with more than two outcomes, and more than two possible measurements at each location; see for instance Zohren, et al. (2010) for a striking version of Bell obtained simply by letting the number of outcomes be arbitrarily large. Popular inequalities and experiments are compared in terms of statistical efficiency by Van Dam et al. (2005). Other connections to statistics (missing data theory) and open problems are surveyed in Gill (2007). Discussion We claimed above that there were experimental results that violated Bell s inequality and therefore ruled out local hidden variables. However, there remains several small possible loopholes. Perhaps the most important one of which is the following: in these experiments for every entangled pair that we measure we often fail to detect one of the two particles because the current experimental set-up is imperfect. The experimental results we noted above are actually the results conditional on both particles spins being measured. If those pairs were not representative of all pairs, that is, if the missing pairs are not missing at random, it is logically possible that the experimental results can be explained by local hidden variables where the values of Y 1 (x 1 ) and Y 2 (x 2 ) also determine the probability of the spin of both being 6

observed. The results of experiments that close this loophole by observing a higher fraction of the pairs should be available within the next several years. Nearly all physicists believe that the results of these experiments will be precisely as predicted by quantum mechanics and thus violate Bell s inequality. Henceforth, we assume Bell s inequality is violated and that we have therefore ruled out local hidden variables. We now return to the question of whether this rules out local reality. As noted above, experiments have been conducted such that the times of the two measurements were sufficiently close and the separation of the particles sufficiently great that even a signal traveling at the speed of light could not inform one particle of the result of the other s spin measurement. Since physical signals cannot be transmitted faster than the speed of light, the effect of the measurement of the first particle on the outcome of the second cannot be explained by any physical mechanism. Therefore ruling out local hidden variable would also effectively rule out local reality. Since the hypothesis of local reality is false, we conclude that the alternative is true and angle at which particle 1 is measured has a causal effect on the spin of particle 2. Note, even under the alternative, we have assumed that Y 1 (x 1, x 2 ) exists for all (x 1, x 2 ). Thus our assumption of reality remains; the hypothesis that reality is local has been rejected. However, quantum mechanics is generally assumed to be irreducibly stochastic. We could have accommodated this assumption by positing stochastic counterfactuals p 1 (x 1, x 2 ) and p 2 (x 1, x 2 ) defined for all (x 1, x 2 ) with the measured spin Y i (x 1, x 2 ) being the realization of a Bernoulli random with success probability p i (x 1, x 2 ). That is, we could assume that the elements of reality are the counterfactual probabilities p i (x 1, x 2 ). Our hypothesis of stochastic locality is then p 1 (x 1, x 2 ) = p 1 (x 1 ) and p 2 (x 1, x 2 ) = p 2 (x 2 ). The proof given above, again combined with the experimental results, can be used to reject this hypothesis by using a coupling argument as in VanderWeele and Robins (2011). A perhaps more radical point of view is that is often attributed to the Copenhagen school: the mathematical theory of quantum mechanics successfully predicts the results of 7

experiments, without positing any elements of reality (counterfactuals), even the above non-local stochastic ones. Thus the question of their existence is not a scientific question, as it is not subject to empirical test and our most successful scientific theory, quantum mechanics, has no need of them. This is appealing to physicists because it restores locality in the following sense. To become entangled two particles must interact and this interaction, even in the laws of quantum mechanics, occurs locally. Entanglement leads to correlated measurements. Once entangled, these correlations will persist irrespective of the particles separation as described earlier. However, following the Copenhagen school, to say counterfactuals Y i (x 1, x 2 ) do not exist is to say that question of whether the measurement of the spin of particle 1 had an effect on the spin on particle 2 cannot be asked; not every event has a cause. In all physical theories prior to quantum theory, it was possible to imagine, alongside the actual measurements of actual experiments, what would have been observed had we done something differently (i.e. counterfactuals), while still preserving locality. This is not possible with quantum mechanics. In summary, Bell s inequality (and its experimental support) show that the Copenhagen standpoint of abandoning counterfactuals is not only possible, it is also necessary to take this standpoint if we want to retain locality as a fundamental part of our world picture. Acknowledgements. This research was funded by NIH grant ES017876. References Bell, J.S. (1964). On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen paradox. Physics 1:195-200. Einstein, A., Podolsky, B. and Rosen, N. (1935). Can quantum-mechanical description of physical reality be considered complete? Physical Review, 47:777-780. Frangakis, C.E., Rubin, D.B., An, M.W. and MacKenzie, E. (2007). Principal stratification designs to estimate input data missing due to death (with discussion). Biometrics, 63:641-662. 8

Gill, R.D. (2007).Better Bell inequalities (passion at a distance). IMS Lecture Notes Monograph Series, Vol. 55, 135-148. Gill, R.D., Weihs, G., Zeilinger, A., and Zukowski, M. (2001). No time loophole in Bell s theorem: The Hess-Philipp model is nonlocal. Proceeding of the National Academy of Sciences, 99:14632-14635. Pearl, J. (2009). Causality: Models, Reasoning, and Inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2nd edition. van Dam, W., Grunwald, P. and Gill, R.D. (2005). The statistical strength of nonlocality proofs. IEEE-Transactions on Information Theory 51, 2812-2835. VanderWeele, T.J. (2010). Epistatic interactions. Statistical Applications in Genetics and Molecular Biology, 9, Article 1:1-22. VanderWeele, T.J. and Robins, J.M. (2011). Stochastic counterfactuals and sufficient causes. Statistica Sinica, in press. VanderWeele, T.J., Tchetgen Tchetgen, E.J., and Robins, J.M. (2011). A mapping between interactions and interference: implications for vaccine trials. Technical Report. Zohren, S., Reska, P., Gill, R.D., and Westra, W. (2010). A tight Tsirelson inequality for infinitely many outcomes. Europhysics Letters 90:10002. 9