The Distribution of Optimal Strategies in Symmetric Zero-sum Games

Similar documents
Computational Properties of Quasi-Strict Equilibrium

6.891 Games, Decision, and Computation February 5, Lecture 2

On the Hardness and Existence of Quasi-Strict Equilibria

Game Theory. Greg Plaxton Theory in Programming Practice, Spring 2004 Department of Computer Science University of Texas at Austin

Computational Aspects of Shapley s Saddles

Chapter 9. Mixed Extensions. 9.1 Mixed strategies

On the Rate of Convergence of Fictitious Play

האוניברסיטה העברית בירושלים

The Computational Complexity of Weak Saddles

Zero-Sum Games Public Strategies Minimax Theorem and Nash Equilibria Appendix. Zero-Sum Games. Algorithmic Game Theory.

Computing Minmax; Dominance

Game Theory: Lecture 2

Computational Game Theory Spring Semester, 2005/6. Lecturer: Yishay Mansour Scribe: Ilan Cohen, Natan Rubin, Ophir Bleiberg*

Monotonic ɛ-equilibria in strongly symmetric games

Learning from paired comparisons: three is enough, two is not

Algorithmic Game Theory and Applications. Lecture 4: 2-player zero-sum games, and the Minimax Theorem

Existence of sparsely supported correlated equilibria

A Generic Bound on Cycles in Two-Player Games

Weak Dominance and Never Best Responses

Justifying Optimal Play via Consistency

Symmetries and the Complexity of Pure Nash Equilibrium

Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium

Mixed Refinements of Shapley s Saddles and Weak Tournaments

Part IB Optimisation

Efficiency and Incentives in Randomized Social Choice

Efficiency, Fairness and Competitiveness in Nash Bargaining Games

Computing Minmax; Dominance

1 PROBLEM DEFINITION. i=1 z i = 1 }.

A Note on the Existence of Ratifiable Acts

Introduction to game theory LECTURE 1

Game Theory: Lecture 3

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics

a i,1 a i,j a i,m be vectors with positive entries. The linear programming problem associated to A, b and c is to find all vectors sa b

Advanced Machine Learning

MATH 521, WEEK 2: Rational and Real Numbers, Ordered Sets, Countable Sets

This article appeared in a journal published by Elsevier. The attached copy is furnished to the author for internal non-commercial research and

A Note on the McKelvey Uncovered Set and Pareto Optimality

On the Tradeoff between Economic Efficiency and Strategyproofness in Randomized Social Choice

Pure Strategy Equilibria in Symmetric Two-Player Zero-Sum Games

CS 573: Algorithmic Game Theory Lecture date: January 23rd, 2008

KAKUTANI S FIXED POINT THEOREM AND THE MINIMAX THEOREM IN GAME THEORY

TI /1 Tinbergen Institute Discussion Paper Maximin Play in Two-Person Bimatrix Games. Vitaly Pruzhansky. Amsterdam, and Tinbergen Institute.

MATH4250 Game Theory 1. THE CHINESE UNIVERSITY OF HONG KONG Department of Mathematics MATH4250 Game Theory

Games and Their Equilibria

Mixed Nash Equilibria

Lecture 6: April 25, 2006

The Index of Nash Equilibria

Static and dynamic stability conditions for structurally stable signaling games

4 Lecture Applications

Game Theory. 2.1 Zero Sum Games (Part 2) George Mason University, Spring 2018

Existence of sparsely supported correlated equilibria

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 7: Supermodular Games

Lecture Notes on Game Theory

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2

Lecture December 2009 Fall 2009 Scribe: R. Ring In this lecture we will talk about

Polynomial-time Computation of Exact Correlated Equilibrium in Compact Games

A Farsighted Stable Set for Partition Function Games

Constructive Proof of the Fan-Glicksberg Fixed Point Theorem for Sequentially Locally Non-constant Multi-functions in a Locally Convex Space

arxiv: v1 [cs.gt] 31 Mar 2019

Bargaining Efficiency and the Repeated Prisoners Dilemma. Bhaskar Chakravorti* and John Conley**

Selecting Efficient Correlated Equilibria Through Distributed Learning. Jason R. Marden

Near-Potential Games: Geometry and Dynamics

On the Structure of Stable Tournament Solutions

Convex Sets Strict Separation. in the Minimax Theorem

Long-Run versus Short-Run Player

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016

Equilibria in Games with Weak Payoff Externalities

SONDERFORSCHUNGSBEREICH 504

Set-Rationalizable Choice and Self-Stability

Stackelberg-solvable games and pre-play communication

A Note on Approximate Nash Equilibria

Brown s Original Fictitious Play

princeton univ. F 13 cos 521: Advanced Algorithm Design Lecture 17: Duality and MinMax Theorem Lecturer: Sanjeev Arora

Large Supports are required for Well-Supported Nash Equilibria

5.2 A characterization of the nonemptiness of the core

CS364A: Algorithmic Game Theory Lecture #13: Potential Games; A Hierarchy of Equilibria

Normal-form games. Vincent Conitzer

IEEE TRANSACTIONS ON INFORMATION THEORY, VOL. 57, NO. 11, NOVEMBER On the Performance of Sparse Recovery

DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS IMPLEMENTATION IN MIXED NASH EQUILIBRIUM

18.10 Addendum: Arbitrary number of pigeons

On the Complexity of Two-Player Win-Lose Games

The Algebraic Degree of Semidefinite Programming

LUCK S THEOREM ALEX WRIGHT

The Computational Aspect of Risk in Playing Non-Cooperative Games

Question 1. (p p) (x(p, w ) x(p, w)) 0. with strict inequality if x(p, w) x(p, w ).

Two-person Pairwise Solvable Games

Theoretical Computer Science

On Popular Random Assignments

We set up the basic model of two-sided, one-to-one matching

Prisoner s Dilemma. Veronica Ciocanel. February 25, 2013

Research Article A Fictitious Play Algorithm for Matrix Games with Fuzzy Payoffs

Lecture notes for Analysis of Algorithms : Markov decision processes

A Multiplayer Generalization of the MinMax Theorem

Settling Some Open Problems on 2-Player Symmetric Nash Equilibria

First Prev Next Last Go Back Full Screen Close Quit. Game Theory. Giorgio Fagiolo

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 8: Supermodular and Potential Games

Zero sum games Proving the vn theorem. Zero sum games. Roberto Lucchetti. Politecnico di Milano

Introduction to Game Theory

Incentives to form the grand coalition versus no incentive to split off from the grand coalition

Boundary Behavior of Excess Demand Functions without the Strong Monotonicity Assumption

Transcription:

The Distribution of Optimal Strategies in Symmetric Zero-sum Games Florian Brandl Technische Universität München brandlfl@in.tum.de Given a skew-symmetric matrix, the corresponding two-player symmetric zero-sum game is defined as follows: one player, the row player, picks a row and the other player, the column player, picks a column. The payoff of the column player is given by the corresponding matrix entry, the row player receives the negative of the column player. A randomized strategy is optimal for the column player if it guarantees an expected payoff of at least 0 independently of the strategy of the row player. We determine the probability that an optimal strategy for the column player randomizes over exactly k columns when the payoffs of the game are i.i.d. random variables that are symmetric around 0 and the game almost surely admits a unique optimal strategy. Our result has consequences for subclasses of symmetric zero-sum games and implies a result by Fisher and Reeves (1995) on tournament games. 1 Introduction A (two-player) zero-sum game is played on a matrix where the row player chooses a row and the column player chooses a column. The payoff of the column player is given by the corresponding matrix entry, the row player receives the negative of the column player. Both players may randomize over their actions. Von Neumann s minimax theorem shows that every zero-sum game admits a value, i.e., the column player can guarantee an expected payoff for himself that is equal to the negative of the expected payoff that the row player can guarantee for himself. A strategy that maximizes the minimal guaranteed expected payoff of a player is a maximin strategy for this player. Pairs of maximin strategies correspond to Nash equilibria of the game. We call a maximin strategy for the column player an optimal strategy. For various classes of games the question about the number of Nash equilibria has been studied. Wilson (1971) showed that the number of equilibria is finite and odd for almost 1

all n-person normal form games. A different proof for the same statement was given by Harsanyi (1973a). In zero-sum games every convex combination of Nash equilibria is again a Nash equilibrium. Hence there is either a unique Nash equilibrium or infinitely many. However, Wilson s theorem does not imply that Nash equilibria are almost always unique in subclasses of games, e.g., zero-sum games, symmetric zero-sum games, or tournament games. 1 Fisher and Ryan (1992) showed that every tournament game admits a unique Nash equilibrium. This result was generalized by Laffond et al. (1997) and Le Breton (2005) to symmetric zero-sum games where all payoffs are odd integers or satisfy a more general congruency condition, respectively. Nash equilibria are not generally unique in zero-sum games, however, Jonasson (2004) showed that they are almost surely unique if the payoffs are given by continuous i.i.d. random variables that are symmetric around 0. Moreover, he proves that the expected fraction of actions in the support of an optimal strategy is close to 1 /2 when the number of actions goes to infinity. In this paper we give a unified treatment of these questions for symmetric zero-sum games and a large family of subclasses thereof. For these games every maximin strategy of the column player is also a maximin strategy of the row player. Hence there is a unique Nash equilibrium if and only if there is a unique optimal strategy. In this paper we determine the probability that a randomly chosen game admits an optimal strategy that uses a certain set of actions. This also implies a result by Fisher and Reeves (1995). On the way we prove that optimal stratagies are almost surely unique if the payoffs are given by absolutely continuous random variables. 2 Preliminaries For n N, let [n] = {1,..., n}. A zero-sum game G is a matrix in R m n, where m, n N. Both players have a set of actions that consists of choosing a row or column, respectively. The entry in the ith row and jth column of G represents the payoff of the column player if the row player choses row i and the column player choses column j. The set of all probability distributions over a finite set S is denoted by (S), i.e., (S) = {x R S 0 : i S x i = 1}. A (randomized) strategy for the row player or the column player is a probability distribution over the rows or columns of G, respectively. The support p + of a strategy p ([n]) is the set of actions to which p assigns positive probability, i.e., p + = {i [n]: p i > 0}. Analogously, we define p = {i [n]: p i < 0}. This notation extends to all vectors in R n. A strategy p is a maximin strategy for the column player in G if it maximizes his minimum expected payoff, i.e., min q ([m]) qt Gp max min p ([n]) q ([m]) qt Gp. Maximin strategies for the row player are defined analogously. By von Neumann s minimax theorem (von Neumann, 1928) the minimum expected payoff of the column player when 1 Tournament games are symmetric zero-sum games in which all off-diagonal payoffs are either 1 or 1. 2

he plays a maximin strategy is equal to the negative of the minimum expected payoff of the row player when he plays a maximin strategy. This payoff is called the value of the game. We say that p is an optimal strategy of G if it is a maximin strategy for the column player. Note that the set of optimal strategies of G is convex. A zero-sum game is symmetric if G is skew-symmetric, i.e., G = G T. For the remainder of this paper, we will simply use game to denote a symmetric zero-sum game. The set of all games is denoted by G. For a set of actions S, a game G, and a vector v, we denote by G S = (G ij ) i,j S and v S = (v i ) i S the sub-matrix and sub-vector induced by S, respectively. We define extra notation for particular classes of games. The set of games with multiple optimal strategies is denoted by G >1, i.e., G >1 = {G G: G has two distinct optimal strategies}. The set G (S) contains all games that have an optimal strategy with support S, i.e., G (S) = {G G: Gp 0 for some strategy p with p + = S}. We will introduce a probability distribution over the set of games by means of probability distributions over the payoffs. Let X ij, i, j [n], i < j be real-valued random variables and X ij if i < j, X = X ji if i > j, and 0 otherwise. Realizations of X are games and hence, X induces a probability distribution over games. For a set of games G, we denote by P X (G ) the probability that the realization of X is in G. We say that X ij is symmetric around 0 if P Xij (I) = P Xij ( I) for every set I R, where I = { v : v I}. Finally X is symmetric around 0 if all X ij are symmetric around 0. 3 Size of the Optimal Strategy For every set of alternatives, we determine the exact probability that this set is the support of an optimal strategy. The proof requires that the payoffs are given by i.i.d. random variables that are symmetric around 0 and for which the optimal strategy is almost surely unique. This is for example the case if the payoffs follow independent normal distributions. We first state three lemmas to prepare the proof of our main theorem. The proof of Lemma 1 makes use of the equalizer theorem, which states that every action that yields payoff 0 against every optimal strategy is played with positive probability in some optimal strategy. Theorem 1 (Raghavan, 1994). Let G be a game and i N. If (Gp) i = 0 for all optimal strategies p of G, then there is an optimal strategy p of G with p i > 0. 3

Following Harsanyi (1973b), an optimal strategy is quasi-strict 2 if it yields strictly positive payoff against every action which is not in its support. It is a well-known fact that if a game only admits quasi-strict optimal strategies, then it in fact has only one optimal strategy. Lemma 1 shows that the converse is also true, i.e., if a game has an optimal strategy that is not quasi-strict, then this cannot be the unique optimal strategy of the game. Lemma 1. Let G be a game and p an optimal strategy of G. If (Gp) i = 0 for some i p +, then G has multiple optimal strategies. Proof. Assume for contradiction that p is the unique optimal strategy of G and (Gp) i = 0 for some i p +. Then it follows from Theorem 1 that G has an optimal strategy p with p i > 0 and, in particular, p p. This contradicts uniqueness of p. The next lemma shows that every strategy that is the unique optimal of some game puts positive probability on an odd number of actions. This does not hold for non-symmetric zero-sum games, e.g., the game known as matching pennies has a unique optimal strategy of size 2. Lemma 2. Let G be a game and p the unique optimal strategy of G. Then p puts positive probability on an odd number of actions. Proof. Assume for contradiction that p puts positive probability on an even number of actions. Without loss of generality, let p + = [k] for some even k N. Since p is the unique optimal strategy of G, it follows from Lemma 1 that (Gp) i > 0 for all i [k]. As k 1 is odd and G [k 1] is skew-symmetric it follows that there is v R n \{0} with v v + [k 1] and G [k 1] v [k 1] = 0. Assume without loss of generality that (Gv) k 0 (otherwise we may take v). Then, for ɛ > 0 small enough, we have that p ɛ = (1 ɛ)p + ɛv ([n]) and Gp ɛ 0, i.e., p ɛ is an optimal strategy of G. This contradicts uniqueness of p. Lastly, we show that if the probability that a randomly chosen game admits two distinct optimal strategies is zero, then also the probability that some sub-game admits two distinct optimal strategies is zero. The proof relies on the fact that the X ij are independent and symmetric around 0. Lemma 3. Let X ij, i, j [n], i < j be independent random variables that are symmetric around 0 and P X (G >1 ) = 0. Then P X ({G G: G S has two distinct optimal strategies}) = 0 for all S [n]. Proof. Let X ij, i, j [n], i < j be i.i.d. random variables that are symmetric around 0 and P X (G >1 ) = 0. Furthermore, let S [n] and G >1 (S) = {G G: G S has two distinct optimal strategies}. 2 Harsanyi introduced the concept of quasi-strong equilibria, which however was referred to as quasi-strict equilibria in subsequent papers to avoid confusion with Aumann s notion of strong equilibria (Aumann, 1959). 4

For G G >1 (S), let p, p ([n]) such that p S and p S are distinct optimal strategies of G S. We define p λ = (1 λ)p + λp. Note that p λ S is an optimal strategy of G S for every λ [0, 1], since the set of optimal strategies is convex. For λ > 0 small enough, we have that (Gp λ ) i < 0 if and only if (Gp) i < 0 or (Gp) i = 0 and (Gp ) i < 0 for all i [n]. Now let G p,p G such that, for all i, j [n], { G G p,p ij if (Gp) i < 0 or (Gp) i = 0 and (Gp ) i < 0, and ij = otherwise. G ij Then p and p λ are optimal strategies in G p,p for small λ > 0. In particular, G p,p has two distinct optimal strategies. Finally, let G >1 = {G p,p G: p, p are optimal strategies of G S }. Because P X (G >1 (S)) > 0 it follows from the fact that the X ij s are independent and symmetric around 0 that P X (G >1 ) > 0. As G >1 G >1, this contradicts the assumption that P X (G >1 ) = 0. We now assume that the probability that a randomly chosen game admits two distinct optimal strategies is 0. Then, it follows quickly from Lemma 2 that the probability that a game has an optimal strategy with even support size is 0. Interestingly, it turns out that the probability that a game has an optimal strategy with a given support of odd size is independent of the chosen support. This is again specific to symmetric zero-sum games and does not hold in general for zero-sum games. Theorem 2. Let X ij, i, j [n], i < j be i.i.d. random variables that are symmetric around 0 and P X (G >1 ) = 0. Then, for every S [n], { P X (G 2 (n 1) if S is odd, and (S)) = 0 otherwise. Note that the number of subsets of odd size of [n] is 2 n 1. P X (G (S)) sum up to 1. Hence, the probabilities Proof. For simplicity, we introduce additional notation. The set of all games that have an optimal strategy on G S with support S is denoted by G(S). Formally, G(S) = {G G: G S p S 0 for some strategy p with p + = S}. Moreover, the set of games with an optimal strategy on G S with support S such that actions in T yield non-negative payoff versus this strategy is denoted by G T (S), i.e., G T (S) = {G G: G S p S 0 and (Gp) i 0 iff i T for some strategy p with p + = S}. 5

Lastly, let G = (S) be the set of games with a vector in the null space where only entries in S are positive, i.e., G = (S) = {G G: Gv = 0 for some v R n with v + = S}. Note that the union over all non-empty S of G = (S) is G if n is odd, since no game of odd size has full rank. It follows directly from Lemma 2 that P X (G (S)) = 0 if S is even, since, by assumption, P X (G >1 ) = 0. Next, we determine the probability that X has an optimal strategy with full support if n is odd. For every set of actions S, let S be its complement with respect to [n], i.e., S = [n] \ S. We define a function φ S on the set of games where { G ij if i, j S or i, j (φ S (G)) ij = S, and otherwise. G ij Intuitively, φ S changes the sign of the payoffs that correspond to pairs of actions where one action is in S and the other one is not. Thus, φ S is self-inverse, i.e., φ S = φ 1 S. If Xv = 0 and v i = 0 for some v R n and i [n], then φ v (X)v = 0, where v [n]\v = v [n]\v and v v = v v. Then, v / v is an optimal strategy of φ v (X) with v i = 0 and φ v (X) v / v = 0. It follows from Lemma 1 that φ v (X) has multiple optimal strategies. This is, by assumption, as probability-zero event. As X is symmetric around 0, v has almost surely no zero entry. This implies that P X (G = (S) \ G = ( S)) = 0 for all S [n]. If X G = (S) G = (T ) with S T, T, there are v, w R n with v + = S and w + = T and Xv = Xw = 0. Then, there is c R such that (v + cw) i = 0 for some i [n] and, clearly, X(v + cw) = 0. As before, this is a probability-zero event by Lemma 1. So we get that { P X (G = (S) G = P X (G = (S)) if S = T or (T )) = S = T, and 0 otherwise. The next step is to show that P X (G = (S)) = P X (G = (T )) for all sets of actions S, T of odd size: the cases S = T and S = T are already covered by the above statement. Now let T S, S. If φ S (X) G = (S), then φ T (X) G = (T ) or, equivalently, if X G = (S), then φ S φ T (X) = φ S T (X) G = (T ), where S T denotes the symmetric difference of S and T. Thus, G = (T ) can be obtained from G = (S) by negating all entries that correspond to pairs of actions where one action is in S T and the other one is not for all games in G = (S). Since X is symmetric around 0, we get that P X (G = (S)) = P X (G = (T )) as desired. In summary, we have G = (S)) = G, P X (G = (S) \ G = ( S)) = 0 for all S [n], and S [n] P X (G = (S)) = P X (G = (T )) if S and T are odd. 6

Thus, P X (G ([n])) = P X (G = ([n])) = 2 (n 1). Now, let n N, S [n], and k = S. We want to show that P X (G (S)) = 2 (n 1) if k is odd and 0 otherwise. Note that, if X has an optimal strategy with support S, then X S has an optimal strategy with support S. It follows from what we have shown above and Lemma 3 that the probability that X S has an optimal strategy with support S is 2 (k 1) if k is odd and 0 otherwise. So P X (G (S)) = 0 if k is even. Hence we consider the case where k is odd. Note that G T (S) can only be non-empty if S T and thus, for at most 2 n k distinct T. Suppose that X G T (S) G T (S), where T and T are distinct. Then, there are strategies p and p such that X S p S = X S p S = 0 and T = {i [n]: (Xp) i 0} and T = {i [n]: (Xp ) i 0}. Hence, p and p are distinct and thus X S has two distinct optimal strategies, which is a probability zero event by Lemma 3. From this it follows that P (G T (S) G T (S)) = 0 for all distinct T and T. Moreover, the union over all T of G T (S) is equal to G(S). Lastly, we show that P (G T (S)) = P (G T (S)) for all T and T. It suffices to consider the case where T = T {i } for some i T. The rest follows from repeated application of this case. Assume X G T (S) with witness p, i.e., X S p S = 0 and (Xp) i 0 if and only if i T. Furthermore, let X be equal to X except that the sign of all payoffs that correspond to pairs of actions {i, i } where i S is reversed. Then (X p) i 0 if and only if i T. Hence, G T (S) can be obtained from G T (S) by reversing the sign of all payoffs that correspond to pairs of actions {i, i } where i S for all games. Since X is symmetric around 0, it follows that P (G T (S)) = P (G T (S)). In summary we have that P (G T (S)) = 2 (n k) P (G(S)) = 2 (n 1), as there are 2 n k distinct sets of actions T that contain S. From the fact that G N (S) = G (S) we get the desired statement. As we have noted before, Theorem 2 does not hold for non-symmetric zero-sum games. Experiments by Faris and Maier (1987) suggest that the size of the optimal strategy of a uniformly at random chosen zero-sum game approximately follows a binomial distribution with parameters n and 1 /2. Finding the exact distribution of optimal strategies for the general case is still an open problem. A precondition for Theorem 2 is that P X (G >1 ) = 0. We show that this condition is satisfied for a large class of distributions, i.e., all absolutely continuous distributions. This for example covers the case that all X ij are random normal variables. Lemma 4. Let X ij, i, j [n], i < j be absolutely continuous (w.r.t. the Lebesgue measure) random variables. Then P X (G >1 ) = 0. Proof. We will show that there is an even-sized square sub-matrix of X that is singular if X G >1. If there is an optimal strategy of X with even-sized support, say p, then X supp(p) is an even-sized square matrix of X that is singular. Second, we consider the case when there are two optimal strategies of X, say p and q, with distinct support of odd size. Without loss of generality there is i supp(q) \ supp(p) such that (Xp) i = 0. Then, the matrix X supp(p) {i} is singular and even sized. The remaining case is that all optimal strategies of G have the same support and this support contains an odd number of actions. 7

Let p and q be two such optimal strategies and p λ = (1 + λ)p λq. Then, there are λ 0 and i [n] \ supp(p) such that p λ 0 and (Xp λ ) i = 0. Hence, X supp(p) {i} is even-sized and singular. Thus, in any case, X has an even-sized square sub-matrix that is singular. Since the X ij are absolutely continuous, every even-sized square sub-matrix of X is almost surely regular. Since the number of sub-matrices of X is finite, the claim follows. Theorem 2 applies to a wide range of distributions over payoffs. By Lemma 4 it holds for all absolutely continuous distributions that are symmetric around 0, e.g., a normal distribution or a uniform distribution on [ 1, 1]. Moreover, if the X ij s are uniformly distributed on { 1, 1}, we obtain a uniform distribution over tournament games. Fisher and Ryan (1992) showed that optimal strategies are unique in tournament games. Thus, Theorem 2 implies a result by Fisher and Reeves (1995). Acknowledgements This material is based upon work supported by Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft under grant BR 2312/10-1 and TUM Institute for Advanced Study through a Hans Fischer Senior Fellowship. The author thanks Felix Brandt for helpful discussions. References R. J. Aumann. Acceptable points in general cooperative n-person games. In A. W. Tucker and R. D. Luce, editors, Contributions to the Theory of Games IV, volume 40 of Annals of Mathematics Studies, pages 287 324. Princeton University Press, 1959. W. G. Faris and R. S. Maier. The value of a random game: The advantage of rationality. Complex Systems, 1:235 244, 1987. D. C. Fisher and R. B. Reeves. Optimal strategies for random tournament games. Linear Algebra and its Applications, 217:83 85, 1995. D. C. Fisher and J. Ryan. Optimal strategies for a generalized scissors, paper, and stone game. American Mathematical Monthly, 99(10):935 942, 1992. J. C. Harsanyi. Oddness of the number of equilibrium points: A new proof. International Journal of Game Theory, 2(1):235 250, 1973a. J. C. Harsanyi. Games with randomly disturbed payoffs: A new rationale for mixedstrategy equilibrium points. International Journal of Game Theory, 2(1):1 23, 1973b. J. Jonasson. On the optimal strategy in a random game. Electronic Communications in Probability, 9:132 139, 2004. 8

G. Laffond, J.-F. Laslier, and M. Le Breton. A theorem on symmetric two-player zero-sum games. Journal of Economic Theory, 72(2):426 431, 1997. M. Le Breton. On the uniqueness of equilibrium in symmetric two-player zero-sum games with integer payoffs. Économie publique, 17(2):187 195, 2005. T. E. S. Raghavan. Zero-sum two person games. In R. J. Aumann and S. Hart, editors, Handbook of Game Theory with Economic Applications, chapter 20. North-Holland, 1994. J. von Neumann. Zur Theorie der Gesellschaftspiele. Mathematische Annalen, 100(1): 295 320, 1928. R. Wilson. Computing equilibria in n-person games. SIAM Journal on Applied Mathematics, 21(1):80 87, 1971. 9