Introductory notes on stochastic rationality. 1 Stochastic choice and stochastic rationality

Similar documents
Technical Results on Regular Preferences and Demand

Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences. Sums of sets, etc.

PEANO AXIOMS FOR THE NATURAL NUMBERS AND PROOFS BY INDUCTION. The Peano axioms

Convex Analysis and Economic Theory Winter 2018

Linear programming: Theory

Preference, Choice and Utility

Boolean Algebras. Chapter 2

Calculus and Maximization I

Axiomatic Decision Theory

When are Sums Closed?

Important Properties of R

Principles of Real Analysis I Fall I. The Real Number System

Arrow s General (Im)Possibility Theorem

Linear Programming Redux

Homework #2 Solutions Due: September 5, for all n N n 3 = n2 (n + 1) 2 4

Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences. Supergradients. KC Border Fall 2001 v ::15.45

Monetary welfare measurement. 1 Hicks s Compensating and Equivalent Variations

Note 3: LP Duality. If the primal problem (P) in the canonical form is min Z = n (1) then the dual problem (D) in the canonical form is max W = m (2)

2.2 Some Consequences of the Completeness Axiom

SUPPLEMENT TO RANDOM EXPECTED UTILITY (Econometrica, Vol. 74, No. 1, January 2006, )

Constrained maxima and Lagrangean saddlepoints

Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility*

CS 6820 Fall 2014 Lectures, October 3-20, 2014

Final Exam Review. 2. Let A = {, { }}. What is the cardinality of A? Is

Numbers, sets, and functions

MATH 324 Summer 2011 Elementary Number Theory. Notes on Mathematical Induction. Recall the following axiom for the set of integers.

Dominance and Admissibility without Priors

8. Limit Laws. lim(f g)(x) = lim f(x) lim g(x), (x) = lim x a f(x) g lim x a g(x)

Supplementary lecture notes on linear programming. We will present an algorithm to solve linear programs of the form. maximize.

means is a subset of. So we say A B for sets A and B if x A we have x B holds. BY CONTRAST, a S means that a is a member of S.

Today: Linear Programming (con t.)

1. (B) The union of sets A and B is the set whose elements belong to at least one of A

Writing proofs for MATH 51H Section 2: Set theory, proofs of existential statements, proofs of uniqueness statements, proof by cases

Properties of the Integers

Moral hazard in teams

a + b = b + a and a b = b a. (a + b) + c = a + (b + c) and (a b) c = a (b c). a (b + c) = a b + a c and (a + b) c = a c + b c.

Unlinked Allocations in an Exchange Economy with One Good and One Bad

Regular Choice and the Weak Axiom of Stochastic Revealed Preference

Math 564 Homework 1. Solutions.

Math 324 Summer 2012 Elementary Number Theory Notes on Mathematical Induction

Chapter 1. Preliminaries

In this initial chapter, you will be introduced to, or more than likely be reminded of, a

Sets and Functions. (As we will see, in describing a set the order in which elements are listed is irrelevant).

a. Define a function called an inner product on pairs of points x = (x 1, x 2,..., x n ) and y = (y 1, y 2,..., y n ) in R n by

Infinite constructions in set theory

Cowles Foundation for Research in Economics at Yale University

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers

Mathematical Induction

Chapter 1 : The language of mathematics.

Logic, Sets, and Proofs

A NEW SET THEORY FOR ANALYSIS

A strongly polynomial algorithm for linear systems having a binary solution

Risk Aversion over Incomes and Risk Aversion over Commodities. By Juan E. Martinez-Legaz and John K.-H. Quah 1

Vector Spaces. Addition : R n R n R n Scalar multiplication : R R n R n.

Math 4606, Summer 2004: Inductive sets, N, the Peano Axioms, Recursive Sequences Page 1 of 10

Section 3.1: Direct Proof and Counterexample 1

2. Introduction to commutative rings (continued)

MATH31011/MATH41011/MATH61011: FOURIER ANALYSIS AND LEBESGUE INTEGRATION. Chapter 2: Countability and Cantor Sets

Critical Reading of Optimization Methods for Logical Inference [1]

2. The Concept of Convergence: Ultrafilters and Nets

Chapter One. The Real Number System

MATH 51H Section 4. October 16, Recall what it means for a function between metric spaces to be continuous:

Divisibility = 16, = 9, = 2, = 5. (Negative!)

Finite and Infinite Sets

Induction 1 = 1(1+1) = 2(2+1) = 3(3+1) 2

Convex Analysis and Economic Theory Winter 2018

Modeling Random Experiments

Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory)

Static Decision Theory Under Certainty

CSE 20 DISCRETE MATH SPRING

COUNTING NUMERICAL SEMIGROUPS BY GENUS AND SOME CASES OF A QUESTION OF WILF

WEIERSTRASS THEOREMS AND RINGS OF HOLOMORPHIC FUNCTIONS

Proofs. Chapter 2 P P Q Q

ADVANCED CALCULUS - MTH433 LECTURE 4 - FINITE AND INFINITE SETS

Proof Techniques (Review of Math 271)

MATH FINAL EXAM REVIEW HINTS

Background for Discrete Mathematics

Basic Logic and Proof Techniques

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

Homework 1 (revised) Solutions

Arrow s Paradox. Prerna Nadathur. January 1, 2010

Math 3000 Section 003 Intro to Abstract Math Final Exam

CMSC 27130: Honors Discrete Mathematics

Microeconomic Theory -1- Introduction

DR.RUPNATHJI( DR.RUPAK NATH )

Economics 204 Fall 2011 Problem Set 1 Suggested Solutions

Vector Spaces. Chapter Two

Matching with Contracts: The Critical Role of Irrelevance of Rejected Contracts

August 23, 2017 Let us measure everything that is measurable, and make measurable everything that is not yet so. Galileo Galilei. 1.

Discrete Optimization

3 The language of proof

Advanced Microeconomics Note 1: Preference and choice

Entropy and Ergodic Theory Lecture 3: The meaning of entropy in information theory

NOTES (1) FOR MATH 375, FALL 2012

Student s Guide Chapter 1: Choice, Preference, and Utility

CS264: Beyond Worst-Case Analysis Lecture #18: Smoothed Complexity and Pseudopolynomial-Time Algorithms

MATH 220 (all sections) Homework #12 not to be turned in posted Friday, November 24, 2017

Introduction to Metalogic

Proofs. Chapter 2 P P Q Q

Transcription:

Division of the Humanities and Social Sciences Introductory notes on stochastic rationality KC Border Fall 2007 1 Stochastic choice and stochastic rationality In the standard theory of rational choice we start with a set X of alternatives, a family B of nonempty budgets subsets of X, and a choice function c: B cb B In one model of stochastic choice a single element of B is chosen at random 1 So instead of a subset of B the choice gives us a probability measure on B Let pc B denote the probability that the choice from B belongs to C Of course we require that pb B = 1 for all B B This notation is intentionally reminiscent of the notation for the conditional probability C given B, which it may not be, but I don t think you will get confused here When C and/or B are itemized, we may simply omit the braces For example, we may write px x, y instead of the cumbersome p {x} {x, y} To keep things simple, we shall assume that X is finite A special kind of stochastic choice is derived from a stochastic preference Let P denote the set of linear preference relations on X A preference relation is linear if it is total, transitive, irreflexive, and asymmetric The set P is also finite, having X! elements We may when convenient refer to a preference relation by listing its skeleton These notes expand upon Exercise 1D5 in Mas-Colell Whinston Green [8, p 16], and are a simplified I hope exposition of some results in McFadden and Richter [10] 1 There are other models of stochastic choice We could, for instance, assume that a subset of B is chosen at random Indeed McFadden and Richter [10] consider an entirely general framework The case considered here is both natural and simple 1

KC Border Introductory notes on stochastic rationality 2 For instance, if X = {x, y, z}, we may write z x z to refer to the unique linear preference satisfying z x z A stochastic preference is a probability measure on P 2 A stochastic preference gives rise to a stochastic choice as follows Given a linear preference on X and budget B, let B = the unique -maximal element of B 1 Definition For the purposes of this note, a stochastic choice X, B, p is stochastically rational if there is a stochastic preference π on P such that for all B B, In this case we say that π rationalizes p px B = π { P : x = B} The next example shows that not every stochastic choice can be rationalized by a stochastic preference It appears as Exercise 1D5 in Mas-Colell Whinston Green [8, p 16] 2 Example Let X = {x, y, z}, and let B be the set of all two-element subsets of X Then the stochastic choice px x, y = 1 2, py x, y = 1 2 py y, z = 1 2, pz y, z = 1 2 11 pz x, z = 1 2, px x, z = 1 2 is stochastically rational, and is rationalized by π where π = 1/6 for each P But the stochastic choice px x, y = 3 4, py x, y = 1 4 py y, z = 3 4, pz y, z = 1 4 12 pz x, z = 3 4, px x, z = 1 4 is not stochastically rational Perhaps the simplest way to see this is to note that if z x, then there are three choices for where y fits in the preference order: y z x, z y x, or z x y In any event, y x or z y or both In other words, { P : z x} { P : z y} { P : y x} 2 A more general, and more complicated, model would allow indifference

KC Border Introductory notes on stochastic rationality 3 But if p is rationalized by some probability π on P, then 12 implies that left-hand side of the inclusion has probability 3/4, while the union on the right-hand side has probability at most 1/4 + 1/4, a contradiction Both 11 and 12 are special cases of the following stochastic choice px x, y = α, py y, z = α, pz x, z = α, py x, y = 1 α pz y, z = 1 α px x, z = 1 α 13 So when is this stochastically rational? The answer is, whenever 1/3 α 2/3 First we show that this condition is necessary The same argument used above, namely { P : z x} { P : z y} { P : y x} shows that a necessary condition is that α 21 α, or α 2/3 But { P : y x} { P : y z} { P : z x} implies that 1 α 2α, or 1/3 α To show sufficiency, it is enough to exhibit a π that rationalizes p So assume 1/3 α 2/3, and set πx y z = πy z x = πz x y = α 1/3 πx z y = πy x z = πz y x = 2/3 α Simple arithmetic shows that this π rationalizes p 2 The Axiom of Revealed Stochastic Preference The natural follow-up question is what properties must a random choice p satisfy in order to guarantee that it is rationalized by some random preference π? We shall prove that stochastically rational choice functions are characterized by the following axiom, which McFadden and Richter [10] dub the Axiom of Revealed Stochastic Preference, or ARSP for short

KC Border Introductory notes on stochastic rationality 4 3 Axiom of Revealed Stochastic Preference A stochastic choice X, B, p satisfies the ARSP if for every finite sequence C 1, B 1,, C n, B n where repetitions are allowed with each B j B, and each C j B j is nonempty, n j=1 pc j B j max P n 1, C j, B j 21 j=1 where 1 if B C 1, C, B = 0 otherwise Or to put it another way that makes the repetitions explicit, let {C i, B i : i = 1,, N} be an enumeration of all the distinct pairs C, B such that C B B Then for every tuple k i N i=1 of nonnegative integers, N i=1 k i pc i B i max P N k i 1, C i, B i 21 i=1 The right-hand side of 21 begs for some comment What it does is find a single preference relation that would choose an element of C j from B j for the most j The remarkable thing is that an upper bound on the sum of the probabilities is given by the number of choices a single preference relation would make The ARSP looks very different in form from our standard revealed preference axioms, but it is not so alien as it first seems Let s apply it to the singleton-valued non-stochastic choice case Let h: B X be a singleton-valued choice function Let us abuse notation slightly and write x = hb rather than {x} = hb Then 1 if hb C pc B = 0 otherwise is the corresponding {0, 1}-valued stochastic choice function Let S be the strong direct revealed preference relation, defined, as you may recall, by x S y if for some budget B B, we have y B, y x, and x = hb Now assume x 1 S x 2 S x 3 S x n, all the x j distinct, 3 and let B j be such that x j = hb j and x j+1 B j, j = 1,, n 1 3 The only thing the assumption of distinctness rules out is x n = x 1, since if x i = x j for i < j, we may simply omit x i,, x j 1 We deal with the possibility x n = x 1 in the next sentence

KC Border Introductory notes on stochastic rationality 5 We now ask, can we have x n S x 1? If so, let x n = hb n where x 1 B n Then n px j B j = n j=1 Now consider any linear order Transitivity and irreflexivity rule out x 1 x n x 1, so n 1, x j, B j n 1 j=1 Thus x n S x 1 implies that 21 is violated, so ARSP implies that x 1 S x 2 S x 3 S x n = x n S x 1, which is just the Strong Axiom of Revealed Preference! McFadden [9] discusses some additional intuition behind this axiom 4 Example Let s apply the ARSP to Example 2 Consider the sequence {x}, {x, y}, {y}, {y, z}, {z}, {x, z} For this sequence the left-hand side of 21 is α + α + α = 3α Now consider the linear preference given by x y z The corresponding sum for the right-hand side of 21 is 1, {x}, {x, y} + 1, {y}, {y, z} + 1, {z}, {x, z} = 1 + 1 + 0 = 2 By symmetry, this is the maximum value for the right-hand sum Thus in order for 21 to hold it is necessary that 3α 2, or α 2/3 Similarly, for the sequence {y}, {x, y}, {z}, {y, z}, {x}, {x, z}, we see that 21 implies 31 α 2, or 1/3 α Now we would like to show that if 1/3 α 2/3, then 21 holds It is clear that a pair C, B with C = B contributes 1 to each side of 21, so we need only consider sequences of pairs of the form {a}, {a, b} Even so, it s not apparent how to proceed I ll postpone further discussion until after the proof

KC Border Introductory notes on stochastic rationality 6 3 Characterization of stochastic rationality 5 Theorem McFadden Richter [10] A stochastic choice p is rationalized by a random preference π on P if and only it satisfies ARSP Proof : ARSP = stochastic rationality: We shall prove this part by contraposition Let I be the set of all distinct pairs C, B with B B and C B Construct the matrix with rows indexed by I, and columns indexed by P Now append a row of ones Then p is rationalized by a random preference if and only if the following system of equations has a nonnegative solution π R P C,B 1, C, B 1 π = pc B 1 31 So to prove the contrapositive, we assume that stochastic rationality fails that is, 31 has no solution By Farkas Lemma see, eg, Gale [4, Theorem 26, p 44], the alternative is that there exists a vector y =, yc, B, ; y 0 R I R such that ] 1, C, B [, yc, B, ; y0 0, 1 ] pc B [, yc, B, ; y0 > 0 1 or writing it out, for each P, C,B I yc, B1, C, B + y 0 0, 32 and yc, BpC B + y 0 > 0 33 C,B I Together 32 and 33 imply that for every P, yc, B1, C, B < yc, BpC B 34 C,B I C,B I

KC Border Introductory notes on stochastic rationality 7 Let I + = {C, B I : yc, B 0} and I = {C, B I : yc, B < 0} Then 34 becomes yc, B1, C, B yc, B 1, C, B C,B I + C,B I < yc, BpC B yc, B pc B C,B I + C,B I 35 Since this is a finite system of strict inequalities, if there is a solution y, then there is a solution where the coordinates of y are rational numbers By multiplying by a common denominator, we can find a solution y with integer coordinates Moreover every coefficient yc, B > 0 for C, B I + and of course yc, B > 0 for C, B I Define the nonnegative integers yc, B C, B I + kc, B = yc, B C, B I Then we may rewrite 35 as kc, B1, C, B kc, B1, C, B C,B I + C,B I < kc, BpC B kc, BpC B C,B I + C,B I 36 Now observe that 1, C, B = 1 1, B \ C, B and pc B = 1 pb \ C B, so 36 can be written as kc, B1, C, B + kc, B1, B \ C, B C,B I + C,B I < kc, BpC B + kc, BpB \ C B C,B I + C,B I 37 Now consider the finite collection consisting of kc, B instances of C, B for C, B I + and kc, B instances of B \ C, B for C, B I Then since 37 holds for each P, we have a violation of 21 This proves that if p is not stochastically rational, then ARSP is violated That is, if p satisfies ARSP, then it is stochastically rational Stochastic rationality = ARSP: We could run the argument in reverse to prove the converse, but a direct argument is more instructive Assume that the probability

KC Border Introductory notes on stochastic rationality 8 π on P stochastically rationalizes the stochastic choice p, and consider the collection of distinct pairs C i, B i N i=1 with k i instances of each For each i, by stochastic rationality, so pc i B i = P π 1, C i, B i N N k i pc i B i = k i π 1, C i, B i i=1 i=1 P = N π k i 1, C i, B i P i=1 N π max k i 1, C i, B i P P i=1 }{{} =1 N = max k i 1, C i, B i, P i=1 which is just 21 Thus stochastic rationality implies ARSP The proof is a bit disappointing because it does not seem to use at all the intuition from the example It is possible that the symmetry in the example is atypical, and the reasoning there does not generalize well I need to think hard about this 4 Effectivity The ARSP imposes infinitely many restrictions on a stochastic choice even when X is finite, so you might ask whether it is feasible to verify it In fact, there is a computational procedure for checking stochastic rationality directly in the finite case the simplex method of linear programming The system 31 of equations is of the form where p 0 Consider the following linear program Aπ = p 41 minimize 1 z subject to Aπ + z = p, π 0, z 0 42 The system 41 has a nonnegative solution π = π if and only if π = π, z = 0 is a solution of 42 In fact, if 41 has no solution, then the solution of the dual program will imply 32 and 33 The program 42 is ideally set up to solve with the simplex algorithm since π = 0, z = p is an obvious initial feasible point

KC Border Introductory notes on stochastic rationality 9 5 Related literature Thurstone [11, 12] and Luce [7] do not frame the problem quite the same way we have, but their work paved the way for random utility models McFadden [9] and Falmagne [3], address the question of stochastic rationality much as we have defined it Gul and Pessendorfer [5, 6] take the alternatives themselves to be lotteries There are many other related papers McFadden [9] has an extensive bibliography and literature survey References and related literature [1] H D Block and J Marschak 1959 Random orderings and stochastic theories of response Cowles Foundation Discussion Paper 66, Cowles Foundation, New Haven, Connecticut http://cowleseconyaleedu/p/cp/p01a/p0147pdf [2] R Corbin and A A J Marley 1974 Random utility models with equality: An apparent, but not actual, generalization of random utility models Journal of Mathematical Psychology 113:274 293 DOI: 101016/0022-24967490023-6 [3] J C Falmagne 1978 A representation theorem for finite random scale systems Journal of Mathematical Psychology 181:52 72 DOI: 101016/0022-24967890048-2 [4] D Gale 1989 Theory of linear economic models Chicago: University of Chicago Press Reprint of the 1960 edition published by McGraw-Hill [5] F Gül and W Pesendorfer 2006 Random expected utility Econometrica 741:121 146 http://wwwjstororg/stable/3598925pdf [6] 2006 Supplement to Random expected utility http://wwweconometricsocietyorg/ecta/supmat/ecta4734supppdf [7] R D Luce 1958 A probabilistic theory of utility Econometrica 26:193 224 http://wwwjstororg/stable/1907587 [8] A Mas-Colell, M D Whinston, and J R Green 1995 Microeconomic theory Oxford: Oxford University Press [9] D L McFadden 2004 Revealed stochastic preference: A synthesis Economic Theory 262:245 264 DOI: 101007/s00199-004-0495-3

KC Border Introductory notes on stochastic rationality 10 [10] D L McFadden and M K Richter 1990 Stochastic rationality and revealed preference In J S Chipman, D L McFadden, and M K Richter, eds, Preferences, Uncertainty, and Optimality: Essays in Honor of Leonid Hurwicz, pages 163 186 Boulder, Colorado: Westview Press [11] L L Thurstone 1927 A law of comparative judgement Psychological Review 344:273 286 DOI: 101037/h0070288 [12] 1927 Psychophysical analysis American Journal of Psychology 383:368 389 http://wwwjstororg/stable/1415006