DOUBLE-SLIT EXPERIMENT AND BOGOLIUBOV'S CAUSALITY PRINCIPLE D. A. Slavnov

Similar documents
Removing Infrared Divergences

Lecture 6:Feynman diagrams and QED

PHOTON SUPERPOSITION BY INTERACTIONS WITH APPROPRIATE TWO-LEVEL SYSTEMS. Vladan Panković

QUANTUM MECHANICS Intro to Basic Features

TENTATIVE SYLLABUS INTRODUCTION

Quantum Field Theory 2 nd Edition

1 The Quantum Anharmonic Oscillator

_ int (x) = e ψ (x) γμ ψ(x) Aμ(x)

Relativistic corrections of energy terms

THE ANGULAR MOMENTUM CONTROVERSY: WHAT IS IT ALL ABOUT AND DOES IT MATTER? E. Leader

6. QED. Particle and Nuclear Physics. Dr. Tina Potter. Dr. Tina Potter 6. QED 1

NEW INTERPRETATION OF THE HUBBLE LAW 1

NILPOTENT QUANTUM MECHANICS AND SUSY

Lecture notes for QFT I (662)

Treatment of Overlapping Divergences in the Photon Self-Energy Function*) Introduction

Many-Body Problems and Quantum Field Theory

Illustrating the Superposition Principle with Single Photon Interference. Frank Rioux. Department of Chemistry. St.

Introduction to particle physics Lecture 2

On the renormalization-scheme dependence in quantum field theory.

Quantum measurements and Kolmogorovian probability theory

Quantum Field Theory Spring 2019 Problem sheet 3 (Part I)

Question from last week

Citation for published version (APA): Martinus, G. H. (1998). Proton-proton bremsstrahlung in a relativistic covariant model s.n.

Quantum Field Theory II

KOLMOGOROV s PROBABILITY THEORY IN QUANTUM PHYSICS

1 Introduction. 1.1 The Standard Model of particle physics The fundamental particles

PHOTON - REALITY OR FICTION 1

CHAPTER I Review of Modern Physics. A. Review of Important Experiments

I N T R O D U C T I O N T O

DEPARTMENT OF PHYSICS

Maxwell s equations. electric field charge density. current density

Overview. The quest of Particle Physics research is to understand the fundamental particles of nature and their interactions.

Numerical Methods in Quantum Field Theories

Closing the Debates on Quantum Locality and Reality: EPR Theorem, Bell's Theorem, and Quantum Information from the Brown-Twiss Vantage

An Introduction to. Michael E. Peskin. Stanford Linear Accelerator Center. Daniel V. Schroeder. Weber State University. Advanced Book Program

Summary of free theory: one particle state: vacuum state is annihilated by all a s: then, one particle state has normalization:

PHYSICS-PH (PH) Courses. Physics-PH (PH) 1

POLYAKOV LOOP FLUCTUATIONS AND DECONFINEMENT IN THE LIMIT OF HEAVY QUARKS P. M. Lo 1,, K. Redlich 1, C. Sasaki 1,2

REVIEW REVIEW. Quantum Field Theory II

Quantum Field Theory II

On the paper Role of potentials in the Aharonov-Bohm effect. A. M. Stewart

Muon (g 2) Dennis V. Perepelitsa Columbia University Department of Physics (Dated: December 22, 2008)

The particle model for the Higgs condensate and the anomalous geometrical diffraction

The reality of de Broglie s pilot wave

Physics 1C. Modern Physics Lecture

de Sitter Tachyons (at the LHC Era)

THE PROPERTY OF MAXIMAL TRANSCENDENTALITY IN THE N =4SYM A. V. Kotikov

Quantum Field Theory. Chapter Introduction. 8.2 The Many Particle State

LOOP-TREE DUALITY AND QUANTUM FIELD THEORY IN 4D

Lesson Plan. 1) Students will be aware of some key experimental findings and theoretical

Chemistry 271 Quantum Mechanics

Evidence for K mixing in 178 Hf

Lecture 3 (Part 1) Physics 4213/5213

Einstein s Theory Relativistic 0 < v < c. No Absolute Time. Quantization, Zero point energy position & momentum obey Heisenberg uncertainity rule

On particle production by classical backgrounds

Physics 1030 General Physics II

XV Mexican Workshop on Particles and Fields

On Real and Virtual Photons in the Davies Theory of Time-Symmetric Quantum Electrodynamics

Arrangement of Electrons in Atoms

Quantum ElectroDynamics III

Particle Physics 2018 Final Exam (Answers with Words Only)

Loop corrections in Yukawa theory based on S-51

CHAPTER 28 Quantum Mechanics of Atoms Units

Vacuum Energy and Effective Potentials

40 Wave Functions and Uncertainty

Before we go to the topic of hole, we discuss this important topic. The effective mass m is defined as. 2 dk 2

Quantum Mechanics without Complex Numbers: A Simple Model for the Electron Wavefunction Including Spin. Alan M. Kadin* Princeton Junction, NJ

Review of scalar field theory. Srednicki 5, 9, 10

THERMAL BOGOLIUBOV TRANSFORMATION IN NUCLEAR STRUCTURE THEORY A.I.Vdovin, A.A.Dzhioev

FASTER-THAN-LIGHT TRANSFER OF A SIGNAL IN ELECTRODYNAMICS

FI 3103 Quantum Physics

Probability: The Heisenberg Uncertainty Principle *

Lecture 4. Beyound the Dirac equation: QED and nuclear effects

Introduction. Introductory Remarks

A single quantum cannot be teleported

Part I. Many-Body Systems and Classical Field Theory

Quantum Field Theory. Kerson Huang. Second, Revised, and Enlarged Edition WILEY- VCH. From Operators to Path Integrals

Quantum Field Theory. and the Standard Model. !H Cambridge UNIVERSITY PRESS MATTHEW D. SCHWARTZ. Harvard University

Dr Victoria Martin, Spring Semester 2013

Notes on Quantum Mechanics

What is the "truth" about light? Is it a wave or is it a particle?

Fundamental Interactions (Forces) of Nature

Scattering amplitudes and the Feynman rules

1 Equal-time and Time-ordered Green Functions

MASTER OF SCIENCE IN PHYSICS

Existence is Difference and is expressed and transformed by Information

Lecture 2: Quantum Mechanics and Relativity

Conclusion. 109m Ag isomer showed that there is no such broadening. Because one can hardly

Photons uncertainty removes Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox. Abstract

Lecture 14 (11/1/06) Charged-Particle Interactions: Stopping Power, Collisions and Ionization

Lagrangian Description for Particle Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics Single-Particle Case

Particle nature of light & Quantization

EPR Paradox Solved by Special Theory of Relativity

Beyond Bohr Model. Wave-particle duality, Probabilistic formulation of quantum physics Chap. 28

arxiv: v2 [hep-th] 21 Oct 2013

10/27/2017 [pgs ]

Final reading report: BPHZ Theorem

Quantum Mechanics: Fundamentals

Electric systems, energy and non dualistic logic

1.1.1 Bell Inequality - Spin correlation

Transcription:

ˆ ˆŠ Œ ˆ ˆ Œ ƒ Ÿ 2010.. 41.. 6 DOUBLE-SLIT EXPERIMENT AND BOGOLIUBOV'S CAUSALITY PRINCIPLE D. A. Slavnov Department of Physics, Moscow State University, Moscow In the Bogoliubov approach the causality principle is the basic constructive element of quantum ˇeld theory. At the same time, this principle has obvious classical interpretation. On the other hand, it is well-known Feynman statement that the double-slit experiment is impossible, absolutely impossible to explain in classical way, and has in it the heart of quantum mechanics. We describe how taking into account of infrared singularities allows one to give quite evident interpretation to double-slit experiment. And this interpretation agrees with the Bogoliubov's causality principle. PACS: 03.65.Ud In the Bogoliubov [1] approach the causality principle is the basic constructive element of quantum ˇeld theory. This principle is closely related to locality and states that any excitation in one domain of the Minkowski space does not affect physical processes in another space-like separated domain. At the same time, this principle has obvious classical interpretation. On the other hand, it is well-known Feynman [2] statement that the doubleslit experiment is impossible, absolutely impossible to explain in classical way, and has in it the heart of quantum mechanics. We describe how taking into account of infrared singularities allows one to give quite evident interpretation to double-slit experiment. And this interpretation agrees with the Bogoliubov's causality principle. Further we consider how we can describe particle scattering by two slits a and b. We note that in contrast to considering the same experiment in the standard quantum mechanics, we consider that the scattered particle hits either the domain of slit a or the domain of slit b in each separate case, not passing in a mysterious way through both slits simultaneously. This means that we consider a particle well localized in each separate act. An interference pattern is vividly observed in this experiment. Physically, this means that the scattering on one slit depends on the presence or absence of the other slit, i.e., a nonlocality is present here. E-mail: slavnov@theory.sinp.msu.ru

1826 SLAVNOV D. A. We see how this nonlocality can be explained in the framework of a local ˇeld theory. For clarity, we here discuss the example of the process of scattering of an electron on a nucleus, well studied both theoretically and experimentally. Because the electron is much lighter than the nucleus, this process is well approximated by the electron scattering on a classical source. In what follows, we discuss exactly this process in the framework of the perturbation theory in the standard quantum electrodynamics. In the ˇrst order of the perturbation theory in the electron charge, this process is described by the Feynman diagram a shown in Fig. 1. In this ˇgure, straight lines correspond to the electron, wavy lines correspond to the photon, and the crossed circle corresponds to the source of the classical electromagnetic ˇeld. Calculating the differential scattering cross section when taking diagram a into account causes no troubles and results in the celebrated Rutherford formula corrected by taking the electron spin into account. The obtained formula describes the experimental situation well. But both theory and experiment have now gone far beyond the accuracy level ensured by the ˇrst correction to the perturbation theory. Fig. 1. Diagrams describing the elastic scattering The next order of the perturbation expansion that contributes to the process under study is the third order. There, we must take contributions coming from diagrams b and c in Fig. 1 into account. Taking these diagrams into account results in substantial theoretical difˇculties. First, the so-called ultraviolet divergences appear because the intermediate (virtual) particles can carry arbitrarily large energies and momenta. In quantum ˇeld theory, a well-deˇned algorithm (the renormalization theory) was developed to overcome this difˇculty. We do not discuss this problem in what follows. Second, diagram b results in the socalled infrared divergences caused by the presence of massless particles in the complete particle set. In the example under consideration, such particles are the

DOUBLE-SLIT EXPERIMENT AND BOGOLIUBOV'S CAUSALITY PRINCIPLE 1827 photons. Quantum ˇeld theory also provides an algorithm for overcoming this difˇculty. We discuss it in more detail. The algorithm is based on the following experimental fact. The elastic scattering process described by diagrams aäc cannot be experimentally separated from the process of bremsstrahlung depicted in diagrams däf in Fig. 2. In this process, electron scattering is accompanied by emitting one (diagrams d and e) or more (diagram f) photons. The contribution of diagrams of such a type to the scattering cross section cannot be experimentally separated from the contributions of diagrams aäc if the total energy of photons emitted in the bremsstrahlung is below the sensitivity threshold of the measuring device. Fig. 2. Diagrams describing the bremsstrahlung Calculations show that if we take diagrams d and e into account together with diagrams aäc, then infrared singularities are compensated. But the scattering cross section then becomes dependent on a parameter characterizing the sensitivity of the measuring device. We can take the total energy E max of additionally emitted photons as such a parameter. This is an absolutely physical parameter, and the dependence of the measured scattering cross section on this parameter should therefore not cause any principal objection. But taking diagrams aäe alone into account results in one more difˇculty. The dependence of the scattering cross section on the parameter E max is singular, and the cross section can become negative at sufˇciently small E max. In modern theory, this difˇculty is attributed to an artifact related to using the perturbation theory. Indeed, if higher orders of the perturbation theory are considered taking contributions from diagrams of type (f) with an inˇnitely increasing number of emitted photons into account and summing all these contributions, then the cross-section dependence on the parameter E max becomes regular. Moreover, this cross section tends to zero as E max 0. This does not cause objections from the physical standpoint. The purely elastic scattering in which no bremsstrahlung photons are emitted is just one among inˇnitely many channels along which this

1828 SLAVNOV D. A. process may proceed. It is therefore not amazing that each of these channels contributes inˇnitesimally to the total cross section. Here we need a new insight into the process called elastic scattering. In reality, this process is never purely elastic. Electron scattering is always accompanied by the bremsstrahlung, which cannot be registered even by a measuring device with very high sensitivity. Moreover, the result of the experiment becomes strongly dependent on the device sensitivity if the latter is too high. When the sensitivity becomes inˇnitely high, the registered scattering cross section must tend to zero because we study the measuring device in this case and not the physical object (electron) under investigation. The above example teaches us several useful lessons. Lesson 1. Separating characteristics of a physical object under study are somewhat conditional. These characteristics cannot be separated completely from the characteristics of the measuring device with which this object interacts. Lesson 2. A physical object (electron in the above example) with which we associate deˇnite physical characteristics (differential cross section of elastic scattering) is accompanied by a ˇeld (bremsstrahlung photons) that is not registered by the measuring device but affects the result of the measurement of the characteristics under study. Lesson 3. The presence of the accompanying ˇeld does not contradict locality axioms of quantum ˇeld theory. In the above example, both the electron and the bremsstrahlung photons propagate in the future light cone with the vertex at the scattering point. Lesson 4. The result of measuring the characteristics (scattering cross section) ascribed to a well-localized object under study (electron) may depend on the characteristics of physical objects (bremsstrahlung photons) that are located in the domain that is space-like with respect to the localization domain of the object under study. This may be interpreted as a nonlocality of the object under study. The above lessons result in the following conclusion. We can split the physical problem under study into two parts as regards the measurement process. The ˇrst part, called the kernel in what follows, is registered by a measuring device. The second part, called the dark ˇeld in what follows, is not directly registered by the measuring device, but the instrument reading can depend on characteristics of the dark ˇeld. The separation into these two parts is not absolute and depends on the measurement procedure. This mobility of the boundary ˇnds its partial realization in the renormalization group formalism in the mathematical apparatus of quantum ˇeld theory. Each quantum particle reveals itself through the corresponding observable quantities or, more precisely, through local observables whose values can be found by performing measurements in a bounded domain O of the Minkowski space. The domain O can be naturally considered to be a localization domain for the quantum particle under consideration. In any case, the domain O must contain

DOUBLE-SLIT EXPERIMENT AND BOGOLIUBOV'S CAUSALITY PRINCIPLE 1829 the particle localization domain. More precisely, the localization domain of a particle must be associated with its kernel. However, as explained above, the registered values of observables may depend on the characteristics of the dark ˇeld. This ˇeld is not necessarily localized in the domain O. On the other hand, observable values are determined by the state of physical system. The matter carrier of the state is therefore not only the kernel of the quantum object under study but also the associated dark ˇeld. The state therefore cannot be regarded as being localized in the domain O. But it is the dark ˇeld localization. We note that not every dark ˇeld affects the result of measuring observables (the scattering cross section in the above example); only the one that is created together with the kernel does, i.e., only the dark ˇeld coherent to the kernel is essential. We now return to discussing the experiment on the scattering from two slits. We regard the electron as the scattered particle. We consider the screen with two slits as a classical device which forms quantum ensemble of electrons. This ensemble has certain structure. Firstly, when the ensemble is formed, each electron localized either in the domain of slit a or in the domain of slit b (it is better to speak about the electron kernel, not the electron itself). Second, during interaction with the screen each electron somehow feels both slits. The ˇrst condition for electron localization is self-evident and does not need additional comments. We only note that it will certainly provoke frantic objections from orthodox followers of the standard quantum mechanics, who will insist on that we cannot speak about electron localization before performing a measurement. Why not? Only because they cannot say anything meaningful on this subject? To explain the second condition qualitatively, we can propose the following model of how the electron interacts with the slits or, more precisely, with the screen in which these silts are cut. In the scattering process, not only the electron kernel but also the companion dark ˇeld that is coherent with the kernel approach the screen. Because this ˇeld is massless, it reaches the screen even before the kernel. This ˇeld generates collective oscillations of the screen that are also coherent with the kernel. The arising oscillations are very weak, but because of the coherence, they may interact resonantly with the kernel. At least, they may play the role of a random force participating in creating the probability distribution of the scattered electron momentum. In contrast to the electron kernel, the dark ˇeld reaches both slits, and the character of the random force depends essentially on whether only one slit is open or both slits are open simultaneously. This can be a physical reason for the appearance of the interference pattern. Summarizing, we can draw the following conclusions. Quantum theory, both relativistic and nonrelativistic, can be formulated such that it does not contradict the locality condition accepted in quantum ˇeld theory. The measurement process also does not contradict this condition.

1830 SLAVNOV D. A. From the measurement standpoint, a physical system under study can be separated into two parts: the so-called kernel and the accompanying dark ˇeld. The kernel is the material carrier of corpuscular properties of the physical system. The kernel is localized in the Minkowski space. The algebra of local observables is the mathematical representation of the kernel. The structure of the dark ˇeld does not contradict the relativistic condition of locality, but the dark ˇeld has a localization worse than that of the kernel. The state of a physical system is determined by both the kernel and the dark ˇeld structure. The dark ˇeld is the material carrier of the wave properties of the physical system. In the report, I have told only about physical essence of the problem. Discussion of a mathematical side of the problem can be found in paper [4]. REFERENCES 1. Bogoliubov N. N., Shirkov D. V. Introduction to the Theory of Quantized Fields. N. Y.: Wiley, 1980. 2. Feynman R. P., Robert B., Sands L. M. The Feynman Lectures on Physics. Addison- Wesley, 1998. 3. Peskin M. E., Schroeder D. V. An Introduction to Quantum Field Theory. Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, 1995. 4. Slavnov D. A. // Theor. Math. Phys. 2008.V. 155. P. 788Ä800.