Conjectural Variations in Aggregative Games: An Evolutionary Perspective

Similar documents
Basics of Game Theory

Maximin and minimax strategies in symmetric oligopoly: Cournot and Bertrand

On revealed preferences in oligopoly games

Advanced Microeconomics

MS&E 246: Lecture 12 Static games of incomplete information. Ramesh Johari

EconS 501 Final Exam - December 10th, 2018

Bertrand Model of Price Competition. Advanced Microeconomic Theory 1

UC Berkeley Haas School of Business Game Theory (EMBA 296 & EWMBA 211) Summer 2016

A finite population ESS and a long run equilibrium in an n players coordination game

C31: Game Theory, Lecture 1

Static (or Simultaneous- Move) Games of Complete Information

Static Models of Oligopoly

Upstream capacity constraint and the preservation of monopoly power in private bilateral contracting

4. Partial Equilibrium under Imperfect Competition

Volume 35, Issue 4. Group contests and technologies. Dongryul Lee Department of Economics, Sungshin University

Game Theory and Algorithms Lecture 2: Nash Equilibria and Examples

Mathematical Economics - PhD in Economics

Oligopoly. Oligopoly. Xiang Sun. Wuhan University. March 23 April 6, /149

BELIEFS & EVOLUTIONARY GAME THEORY

DISCUSSION PAPER SERIES

Introduction to game theory LECTURE 1

Economics Discussion Paper Series EDP A new look at the classical Bertrand duopoly

Industrial Organization, Fall 2011: Midterm Exam Solutions and Comments Date: Wednesday October

Welfare consequence of asymmetric regulation in a mixed Bertrand duopoly

EVOLUTIONARY GAMES WITH GROUP SELECTION

Pure Strategy Equilibria in Symmetric Two-Player Zero-Sum Games

Oligopoly Theory. This might be revision in parts, but (if so) it is good stu to be reminded of...

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016

EVOLUTIONARY STABILITY FOR TWO-STAGE HAWK-DOVE GAMES

In the Name of God. Sharif University of Technology. Microeconomics 1. Graduate School of Management and Economics. Dr. S.

Industrial Organization

Revealed Preference Tests of the Cournot Model

On the relation between Sion s minimax theorem and existence of Nash equilibrium in asymmetric multi-players zero-sum game with only one alien

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program May 2012

Oligopoly. Molly W. Dahl Georgetown University Econ 101 Spring 2009

Quantity-setting games with a dominant

SF2972 Game Theory Exam with Solutions March 15, 2013

The Lottery Contest is a Best-Response Potential Game

UNIVERSITY OF NOTTINGHAM. Discussion Papers in Economics EVOLUTION IN SYMMETRIC INCOMPLETE INFORMATION GAMES

Cournot and Bertrand Competition in a Differentiated Duopoly with Endogenous Technology Adoption *

Some forgotten equilibria of the Bertrand duopoly!?

Price and Non-Price Competition in Oligopoly: An Analysis of Relative Payoff Maximizers

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 8: Supermodular and Potential Games

Mixed duopolies with advance production

Oligopoly Theory 2 Bertrand Market Games

Economic Growth Centre Working Paper Series

Industrial Organization Lecture 3: Game Theory

Classic Oligopoly Models: Bertrand and Cournot

6.254 : Game Theory with Engineering Applications Lecture 7: Supermodular Games

Incentives versus Competitive Balance

Microeconomics for Business Practice Session 3 - Solutions

A Note on Profitable Mergers. in a Hierarchical Stackelberg Model

Other Equilibrium Notions

Entropic Selection of Nash Equilibrium

Growing competition in electricity industry and the power source structure

Multi-Player Contests with Asymmetric Information Karl Wärneryd

Microeconomics II Lecture 4: Incomplete Information Karl Wärneryd Stockholm School of Economics November 2016

Players as Serial or Parallel Random Access Machines. Timothy Van Zandt. INSEAD (France)

Sharing contests with general preferences

Aggregate Comparative Statics

Bertrand-Edgeworth Equilibrium in Oligopoly

Academic Editor: Ulrich Berger Received: 12 August 2016 ; Accepted: 5 September 2016 ; Published: 9 September 2016

Fixed Point Theorems

SONDERFORSCHUNGSBEREICH 504

4: Dynamic games. Concordia February 6, 2017

Definitions and Proofs

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 10: Introduction to Game Theory 2

Free Entry and Social Inefficiency under Vertical Oligopoly: Revisited

Ergodicity and Non-Ergodicity in Economics

Theory Field Examination Game Theory (209A) Jan Question 1 (duopoly games with imperfect information)

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 11: Introduction to Game Theory 3

First Prev Next Last Go Back Full Screen Close Quit. Game Theory. Giorgio Fagiolo

Oligopoly Notes. Simona Montagnana

Price vs. Quantity in Oligopoly Games

Product differences and prices

Free and Second-best Entry in Oligopolies with Network

1 Oligopoly: Bertrand Model

Answer Key: Problem Set 3

Game Theory Fall 2003

Bounded Rationality Lecture 2. Full (Substantive, Economic) Rationality

Crowdsourcing contests

1 Games in Normal Form (Strategic Form)

Markov Perfect Equilibria in the Ramsey Model

Microeconomics Qualifying Exam

Sion s minimax theorem and Nash equilibrium of symmetric multi-person zero-sum game

Game Theory. Strategic Form Games with Incomplete Information. Levent Koçkesen. Koç University. Levent Koçkesen (Koç University) Bayesian Games 1 / 15

University of Warwick, Department of Economics Spring Final Exam. Answer TWO questions. All questions carry equal weight. Time allowed 2 hours.

Tijmen Daniëls Universiteit van Amsterdam. Abstract

Aggregate Comparative Statics

SURPLUS SHARING WITH A TWO-STAGE MECHANISM. By Todd R. Kaplan and David Wettstein 1. Ben-Gurion University of the Negev, Israel. 1.

Game Theory. Monika Köppl-Turyna. Winter 2017/2018. Institute for Analytical Economics Vienna University of Economics and Business

Voluntary Leadership in Teams and the Leadership Paradox

Equilibrium Refinements

Equilibria in Games with Weak Payoff Externalities

Pollution Tax and Social Welfare in Oligopoly. Asymmetric Taxation on Identical Polluters

Collaborative Network Formation in Spatial Oligopolies

Durable goods monopolist

GS/ECON 5010 Answers to Assignment 3 W2005

Ex Post Cheap Talk : Value of Information and Value of Signals

A Special Labor-Managed Oligopoly

Transcription:

Conjectural Variations in Aggregative Games: An Evolutionary Perspective Alex Possajennikov University of Nottingham January 2012 Abstract Suppose that in aggregative games, in which a player s payoff depends only on this player s strategy and on an aggregate of all players strategies, the players are endowed with conjectures about the reaction of the aggregate to marginal changes in the player s strategy The players play the equilibrium determined by their conjectures and equilibrium strategies determine the players payoffs, which can be different for players with different conjectures It is shown that with random matching in an infinite population, only consistent conjectures can be evolutionarily stable, where a conjecture is consistent if it is equal to the marginal change in the aggregate at equilibrium, determined by the actual players best responses In the finite population case in which relative payoffs matter, only zero conjectures representing aggregate-taking behavior can be evolutionarily stable The results are illustrated with the examples of the Cournot oligopoly and a rent-seeking game Keywords: conjectures, aggregative games, evolutionary stability JEL Codes: C72 1 Introduction This paper shows that there exist evolutionary foundations behind certain conjectures in aggregative games An aggregative game (see eg Corchón, 1994, and Cornes and Hartley, School of Economics, University of Nottingham, University Park, Nottingham NG7 2RD, United Kingdom Tel: +44 115 9515461, fax: +44 115 9514159, email: alexpossajennikov@nottinghamacuk 1

2009, for a more recent treatment) is a game in which the payoff of a player depends on the player s own strategy and on an aggregate of the strategies of all players For example, in the Cournot oligopoly, a firm s profit depends on the firm s own quantity and on the price, which is determined by the aggregate sum of all firms quantities Conjectures, also called conjectural variations, describe players beliefs, or expectations, about the reaction of other players to a change in one player s strategy In the context of aggregative games, conjectures can be seen as beliefs about the reaction of the aggregate Such beliefs determine players equilibrium strategies In equilibrium each player s strategy is a best response given the conjecture about the reaction of other players (and hence the aggregate) to a deviation Equilibrium strategies lead to some payoffs of the players Generally, players with different conjectures can get different payoffs If there is an evolutionary process selecting players on the basis of these payoffs, then some conjectures would perform better than others Potentially conjectures can be arbitrary; however, it is shown that in well-behaved games the evolutionarily stable (for an infinite population and players randomly matched to play a given finite-player game) conjectures must be consistent ones: the beliefs coincide with the marginal change in the aggregate, derived from the players actual best response functions, in response to a arbitrarily small deviation from equilibrium On the other hand, evolutionary stability for finite populations (where all players interact in the same game) selects zero conjectural variations: players believe that the aggregate does not change if their strategy changes Such behavior is akin to the price-taking behavior in the standard perfect competition model in microeconomics Players with consistent conjectures form correct expectations about the reaction of the aggregate and therefore it may appear intuitive that they have a higher payoff in evolutionary terms Nevertheless, it is not obvious why it should be the case in a strategic context because other players may adjust their equilibrium behavior to the conjectures of all players Having a consistent conjecture, however, does not have a detrimental strategic effect If players are symmetric, the effect of the aggregate is the same on any two players In a finite population, players with zero conjecture ignore such an effect thus behaving as if maximizing the relative payoff, which is what matters in this case The results generalize and combine several previous observations in the literature Working with an infinite population, Dixon and Somma (2003) and Müller and Normann (2005) showed that consistent conjectures have evolutionary foundations in a Cournot duopoly, 2

while Possajennikov (2009) generalized the result to arbitrary well-behaved two-player games This paper extends the result from two-player games to n-player aggregative games On the other hand, for the finite population case Possajennikov (2003) provided evolutionary background for aggregate-taking behavior in aggregative games In the context of conjectures, aggregate-taking behavior is equivalent to zero conjectural variation about the change in the aggregate 1 2 Aggregative Games and Conjectures An aggregative game on the real line is given by G = ({1,, n}, {X i } n i=1, {u i} n i=1 ), where {1,, n} is the set of players, X i R is the strategy set of Player i and u i (x i, X) : X i R R is the payoff function of player i Here, X = f(x 1,, x n ) : X 1 X n R is the aggregate of players strategies The payoff of each player depends on the player s own strategy and this aggregate only: other players strategies influence a player s payoff only through the aggregate It is assumed that the games are well behaved: the sets X i are convex and the functions u i and f are differentiable as many times as required A player s conjecture r i R i, where R i is a convex subset of the real line R, is a number representing the player s belief, or expectation, about the change in the aggregate in response to a marginal change in the player s own strategy If B i [ ] denotes the belief of Player i, r i = B i [ dx dx i ] Note that the conjecture is about the total differential: the reactions of other players are incorporated in dx, and only the final change in X matters for the player s payoff It is assumed that players entertain constant conjectures: r i does not vary with x 1,, x n This assumption may imply that players are boundedly rational: dx dx i derived from the players reaction functions may vary with x 1,, x n in general On the other hand, if arbitrary dependence of conjectures on strategies is allowed then almost any strategy combination can be rationalized as an equilibrium (see eg Laitner, 1980) Equilibrium selection assumptions would be needed then to get a relatively sharp prediction for a game with given conjectures Given the conjecture r i, a player maximizes payoff u i (x i, X) If the solution of the [ maximization problem is interior, then the first-order condition u i ] (x i, X)+ u i (x i, X)B dx i dx i = 1 Müller and Normann (2007) show that in a Cournot duopoly, finite population evolutionary stability indeed leads to a result that would be obtained with zero conjectures about the aggregate 3

[ ] 0 holds Since the conjecture is constant, r i = B dx i dx i (x 1,, x n ) for any x 1,, x n, the condition is F i (x i, X; r i ) := u i (x i, X) + u i (x i, X) r i = 0 (1) Suppose that all n players have some conjectures, given by r 1,, r n Denote the vector of conjectures by r = (r 1,, r n ) The vector will sometimes be denoted by r = (r 1, r 1 ) = (r i, r i ) to emphasized which player is being considered If each player s solution of the payoff maximization problem is interior, then the equilibrium is characterized by the following equations: F 1 (x 1, X; r 1 ) = 0 F n (x n, X; r n ) = 0 X f(x 1,, x n ) = 0 (2) The first n equations are the n first-order conditions for the maximization problems of the n players; the last equation is the equation defining the aggregate The equations implicitly define equilibrium strategies x i (r 1,, r n ) and an equilibrium value of the aggregate X = f(x 1,, x n) = f(x 1 (r),, x n(r)) It is assumed that such an equilibrium selection exists and well defined for the possible values of conjectures While conjectures seem to imply a dynamic process of reaction, the equilibrium concept has the following static interpretation Suppose that currently players are playing or contemplating to play a certain strategy profile (x 1,, x n ), which is common knowledge Player i considering an (arbitrarily small) deviation from it believes that other players would have time to react leading to the change in the aggregate equal to r i times the change in x i before any payoffs accrue After these reactions, payoffs are realized A necessary condition for the profile (x 1,, x n ) to be an equilibrium is that no player expects to get a higher payoff after a marginal deviation and reactions to it, and that is what Equations (2) capture [ A zero conjectural variation r i = 0 means that a player with such conjecture has beliefs B dx i = 0 For such a player, a change in his or her own action does not affect the dx i ] aggregate, which can be termed the aggregate-taking behavior (Possajennikov, 2003) To define a consistent conjecture, imagine that the Player i s strategy can be varied freely while the remaining n 1 players behave optimally 4 Then there are n equations

characterizing the optimal choices: F j (x j, X; r j ) = 0, j i (3) X f(x 1,, x n ) = 0 Treating x i as a parameter and x j, j i and X as variables, this system implicitly defines reaction functions x j (x i) and X (x i ) = f(x 1, x 2 (x 1),, x n(x 1 )) Again, it is assumed that the reaction functions are well defined for the relevant values of conjectures Then Definition 1 A conjecture r i is consistent if r i = dx dx i (x 1,, x n) The definition means that a conjecture is consistent if it, ie the expected change in the aggregate, is equal to the actual change in the aggregate that would arise from marginal changes from reactions to a deviation from the profile (x 1,, x n) This actual change is derived from the reaction functions of other players, which depend on the conjectures those other players are holding 3 Evolutionary Stability of Conjectures 31 Conjectures of Individual Players Imagine that players are endowed with some conjectures The previous section characterized the equilibrium strategies that the players use if the solution of their payoff maximization problems are interior Player i is then u i (x i (r), X (r)) Substituting the solution into the payoff functions, the payoff of Suppose that players other than Player i have some fixed conjectures r j Consider the following interpretation of the choice of conjectures for Player i There is a large population of agents that can potentially be Player i Each of the agents is endowed with a conjecture Agents with different conjectures will get different payoff in the game if selected to play An evolutionary interpretation is that the agents that get a higher payoff are more likely to survive or to reproduce Thus, Definition 2 A conjecture r ES i is evolutionarily stable for Player i against given conjectures of other players if u i (x (r ES i r i r ES i, r i ), X (ri ES, r i )) > u i (x (r i, r i ), X (r i, r i )) for any 5

The definition requires that a player with the evolutionarily stable conjectures gets a higher payoff that a player with any other conjecture If other conjectures could get the same payoff, there would be no selection pressure against them The definition is adapted from the evolutionarily stable strategy (ESS) definition for asymmetric games (Selten, 1980) maximizes function u i (x (r i, r i ), X (r i, r i )) as a func- The definition means that ri ES tion of r i A necessary condition for an interior maximum is that du i dr i or at r i = r ES i If u i 0 and x i r i = 0 at r i = r ES i, u i x i (r i, r i ) + u i dx (r i, r i ) = 0 (4) r i dr i 0, the left hand side can be rewritten as u i / u i / + dx /dr i x i / r i From Equation (1), at the solution of Player i s maximization problem u i/ u i / = r i Thus if ri ES is an evolutionarily stable conjecture, then ri ES = dx /dr i x i / r (res i i, r i ) Speaking somewhat loosely in mathematical terms, if one treats dr i = r i (since r i is an independent variable, its total and partial changes are equal) as a small change in r i, one can cancel it from the above expression Then r ES i = 0 = dx dx Recalling that a conjecture is i consistent if r i = dx dx i (x 1,, x n), if a conjecture is evolutionarily stable, then it has to be consistent Using implicit function theorems, the intuition can be made precise To simplify notation, consider i = 1 (the reasoning for the other players is analogous) From the system of equations (2) F 1 x 1 + 0 + + 0 + F 1 dx + F 1 = 0 0 + F 2 x 2 + + 0 + F 2 dx = 0 0 + 0 + + F n x n + F n x 1 + x 2 + + x n + dx = 0 dx = 0 6

Let A = F 1 F 1 F 2 0 0 F 0 2 0 Then A = n i=1 F i + n f F i i=1 Suppose that A 0 By Cramer s rule, x 1 = 1 A ( ) or x 1 = 1 A F 1 A 1, where F n F n 0 0 1 A 1 = F j j i x j F 1 0 0 F 0 2 0 F n F 1 F 2 F n 0 0 0 1 F 2 F 2 0 F n F n 0 1 and thus A 1 = n i=2 F i + n f F i F j i=2 j i,j 1 x j Also, F 1 x 1 0 0 F 1 dx = 1 A 0 or dx = 1 F 1 f F j A j 1 x j Therefore, F 2 0 0 F n 0 0 0 0,, dx / x 1 / = F 1 f F j j 1 x j ( F 1 ) ( n i=2 F i + n i=2 f F i ), F j j i,j 1 x j 7

or dx / x 1 / = 1 f A 1 j 1 F j x j, provided that A 1 0 (from Equation (1) F 1 = u 1 and thus F 1 0) The reaction of the aggregate to independent changes in the strategy of Player 1 is found from system (3) Using the implicit function theorem, dx dx 1 can be found from Then or dx dx 1 = 1 F 2 x 2 + + 0 + F 2 dx = 0 dx 1 0 + + F n x n + F n x 2 + + x n + f A 1 i 1 F i Therefore it holds that dx dx dx 1 = 1 A 1 dx 1 = dx / x 1 / F 2 0 0 0 dx = 0 dx 1 dx + = 0 dx 1 F n 0 f, Thus if res 1 is an evolutionarily stable conjecture, then r1 ES = u 1/ u 1 / = dx / x 1 / r = dx 1 dx 1, ie r1 ES is consistent Since the index 1 was used only to make notation simpler, the result holds for any index Proposition 1 Suppose that players conjectures are given by r = (r 1,, r n ), r i is interior in R i Under the regularity conditions (i) There exist a solution x i (r), X (r) of system (2); (ii) u i 0 at x i (r), X (r); (iii) A = n i=1 F i + n i=1 (iv) A i = j i F j x j + j i f F i F j j i x j f F j F k x j k i,k j x k 0 0 at r and x i (r), X (r); if r i is an evolutionarily stable conjecture, then r i is consistent Thus only consistent conjectures can generally be evolutionarily stable Note that only the necessary first-order condition was used; it may happen that such a condition is not 8

sufficient to find the maximum of a function Appropriate assumptions on the concavity of functions can ensure that a consistent conjecture is indeed evolutionarily stable Examples in Section 4 demonstrate this While the result may appear reasonable (players with consistent conjectures correctly anticipate the reaction of the aggregate), one needs to keep in mind that it is not necessarily intuitive Players with given conjectures get payoffs from strategies used in equilibrium and there is no obvious reason why payoffs from equilibrium with consistent conjectures should be higher than from other conjectures Also, consistent conjectures are not necessarily the most rational ones from other viewpoints As the examples in Section 4 illustrate, in particular they do not necessarily lead to the standard Nash equilibrium concept For example, in a linear Cournot duopoly, a zero conjecture about the reaction of the other firm is not consistent because the slope of the reaction function is non-zero at equilibrium Similarly, in a linear Cournot oligopoly a consistent conjecture about the aggregate production is smaller than unity thus making the equilibrium with consistent and evolutionarily stable conjectures different from the Nash equilibrium (where the aggregate changes exactly by the change in any one player s production level) 32 Symmetric Games and Infinite and Finite Populations of Players An aggregative game is symmetric if the strategy spaces are the same for all players, X i = X j for all i, j, the aggregate is symmetric, X(π(x 1 ),, π(x n )) = X(x 1,, x n ) for any permutation π, and the payoff functions are symmetric, u i (x i, X) = u j (x j, X) if x i = x j, for any i, j Suppose further that the conjecture spaces are the same for all players, R i = R j for all i, j If the situation is symmetric, one can suppress the indices of players and consider only one generic player, say Player 1 In a symmetric game, one can compare payoffs of different players and thus one can consider one population of players for evolutionary analysis Consider an infinite population of players randomly matched to play an n-player aggregative game G In a symmetric situation, a slight strengthening of the Maynard Smith and Price (1973) definition of evolutionary stability, adapted to the current model, is Definition 3 A conjecture r ES is evolutionarily stable if r i = r ES for all i and it holds that u 1 (x (r ES 1, r ES 1 ), X (r ES 1, r ES 1 )) > u 1(x (r 1, r ES 1 ), X (r 1, r ES 1 )) for any r 1 r ES The condition of the definition requires r ES to be the best choice if the other players use 9

r ES Then Equation (4) again provides the necessary condition for a conjecture to be evolutionarily stable Therefore the analysis of the previous subsection still applies: Proposition 2 Under the regularity conditions of Proposition 1, if r ES is an interior evolutionarily stable conjecture in a symmetric aggregative game with random matching in infinite population, then r ES is consistent If the population is finite and all n players participate in the same interaction, Schaffer (1988) proposed a finite population evolutionary stability concept, based on relative payoffs Adapted to the present context of symmetric aggregative game, Definition 4 A conjecture r fes is finite-population evolutionarily stable (fes) if r i = r fes for all i and it holds that u 1 (x 1 (rfes n ), X (r fes n )) > u 1(x 1 (rfes 1 ), X (r fes 1 )), where r fes n = (rfes, r fes,, r) and r fes 1 = (r, r fes,, r fes ), for any r r fes The idea of the definition is that if any one player has a conjecture r different from r fes, then that player will get a lower payoff than the players who have conjecture r fes in an equilibrium of the game with 1 player having conjecture r and n 1 players having conjecture r fes Schaffer (1988) shows that a fes conjecture r fes maximizes relative payoff current context, it is a solution of the problem max r 1 u 1 (x 1(r 1, r fes 1 ), X (r, r fes 1 )) u j(x j(r 1, r fes 1 ), X (r 1, r fes 1 )) for j 1 The first-order condition of this maximization problem is In the u 1 x 1 + u 1 dx u j x j u j dx = 0 (5) x j If r fes is the solution of the maximization problem, then the above condition is satisfied at r 1 = r fes Since the game is symmetric and all players have the same conjectures and play the same strategies x i, then u 1 = u j x j and u 1 ( u 1 dx 1 dx j = u j ) = 0 The equation (5) reduces to Consider the last term in the expression For dx 1 dx j = 0 to hold, both Players 1 and j should react in the same way to a change in conjecture of Player 1 Recall that 10

( ) ( dx 1 = 1 A F n 1 i=2 F i + n i=2 x n = 1 A f F i F j j i,j 1 x j ) From system (2), F 1 0 F 1 F 1 F 0 2 F 0 2, F 0 0 0 n 0 1 or x n = 1 F 1 f F n F j A j n,j 1 x j In the symmetric case, indices n and any j 1 are interchangeable The expression above can be simplified to give is u 1 If dx 1 dx j dx 1 dx j = F 1/ ( F 1 / ) n 2 A ( F1 + n f ) F 1 0, then the necessary condition for finite population evolutionary stability = 0 But recall that a necessary condition for a player to maximize the payoff in the game is u 1 + u 1 r 1 = 0 If u 1 r 1 = 0 0, then the only way to satisfy the two conditions is Proposition 3 Suppose that players conjectures in a symmetric aggregative game are given by r = (r 1,, r n ), r i is interior in R i, r i = r j for all i, j Under the regularity conditions of Proposition 1 and (v) F i 0 at r and x i (r), X (r); (vi) F i + n f F i 0 at r and x i (r), X (r) if r i is a finite population evolutionarily stable conjecture, then r i = 0 The result is related to the result in Possajennikov (2003), where the coincidence of first-order conditions for the aggregate-taking and the finite-population evolutionarily stable behaviors is shown In the current setting, zero conjectural variation r i = 0 means aggregate-taking behavior, ie Player i believes that the aggregate does not change if the player changes his or her strategy The finite-population evolutionarily stable conjecture r fes is a way of committing to the finite-population evolutionarily stable behavior That r fes = 0 is then another manifestation of the connection between aggregate-taking and finite-population evolutionarily stable behaviors 11

4 Examples 41 Cournot oligopoly Consider a typical economic example of an aggregative game, the Cournot oligopoly Players are firms that choose production quantity levels q i The aggregate production is Q = q 1 + + q n Suppose that price is determined by a linear inverse demand function P = a bq, a, b > 0 and that cost of production is quadratic, C(q) = c 2 q2, c > 0 The payoff of Firm i is its profit π i (q i, Q) = (a bq)q i c 2 q2 i If firms other that Firm 1 all have the same conjecture r = dq dq i, necessary conditions for profit maximization for each of the firms are a bq cq i bq i r = 0 The secondorder conditions br c br < 0 is satisfied for r > c 2b Q = (n 1)b+c+br q 1 + is then characterized by Adding up the first-order conditions for n 1 firms gives (n 1)a (n 1)bQ c(q q 1 ) br(q q 1 ) = 0 Therefore c+br (n 1)a dq c+br (n 1)b+c+br and dq 1 = (n 1)b+c+br A symmetric consistent conjecture r = c + br (n 1)b + c + br This equation has one root r C between 0 and 1 because at r = 0 the right hand side is c c+b (n 1)b+c > 0, and at r = 1 the right hand side is (n 1)b+c+b < 1 The other root is r < c 2b, violating the second-order condition for the maximization problem Thus for any n > 1 there is a unique symmetric consistent r C (0, 1) The condition for r to be consistent can be rewritten as (n 1)br C +cr C +br 2 C c br C = 0 Then dr C dn = br C (n 2)b+c+2br C < 0 for r C (0, 1) Symmetric consistent conjecture decreases as n increases One can also observe that as n, then r C 0 If all players have the same conjecture r, the equilibrium is characterized by n first-order conditions a bq cq i bq i r = 0 Adding them up gives na nbq cq brq = 0, or Q = na nb+c+br Note that the standard Nash equilibrium is obtained by taking conjectures r = 1, since then dq dq 1 = 1 The quantity level with consistent conjecture r C < 1 for a given n is larger than for Nash conjectures r = 1 na nb+c+br C and dq dn = c+br C nab dr C /dn (nb+c+br C ) 2 > 0: quantity monotonically increases with n if conjectures adjust If all players have consistent conjectures, then Q = Since dr C dn to be consistent dq < 0, then dn 12

If conjectures are r = 0, then Q = na nb+c This is the perfectly competitive outcome arising from price-taking behavior: since marginal cost is cq i, in this case the individual supply is P = cq i, or q i = P/c The total supply is Q S = n c P and inverse supply is P = c n Q S Equating demand and supply gives c nq = a bq, or Q = na nb+c Thus zero conjectures about aggregate, which characterize aggregate-taking behavior, mean competitive (Walrasian) equilibrium for any number n of firms Proposition 2 shows that only a consistent conjecture r C can be evolutionarily stable To check whether the consistent conjecture is indeed evolutionarily stable in the current setting, consider the maximization problem max r 1 π 1 = (a bq (r 1, r 1 ))q 1(r 1, r 1 ) c 2 (q 1(r 1, r 1 )) 2, (6) where the conjectures of n 1 firms r 1 = r C The equilibrium values of Q and q 1 are found from the conditions a bq (c+br 1 )q 1 = 0 and n 1 conditions a bq cq i bq i r 1 = 0 for i 1 The latter conditions add up to (n 1)a (n 1)bQ c(q q 1 ) br 1(Q q 1 ) = 0, or (n 1)a ((n 1)b + c + br 1)Q + (c + br 1 )q1 = 0 From these two conditions, b dq + (c + br 1 ) dq 1 + bq1 = 0 ((n 1)b + c + br 1 ) dq + (c + br 1 ) dq 1 = 0 Let A = b(c + br 1 ) (c + br 1 )((n 1)b + c + br 1 ) Then dq dq 1 = 1 A bq 1 ((n 1)b + c + br 1) = 1 A bq 1 (c + br 1) and Maximizing function (6), the first order condition is dπ 1 = (a bq ) dq 1 + q1 dq ( b ) ( cq1 dq1 = 0, or dπ 1 = bq1 dq1 r 1 dq ) If q1 0, the only solution of this equation is if r 1 ((n 1)b + c + br 1 ) = c + br 1 If r 1 = r C, this means that r 1 = r C The second-order condition for maximization is d2 π dr 2 1 d r 2 q1 1 d2 Q dr1 2 dr1 2 d 2 π = bq dq dr1 2 1 1 = b dq 1 (r 1 dq 1 ) At r 1 = r C, the first term is zero, and also r 1 d 2 q 1 dr 2 1 dq ) + bq 1 ( dq 1 + d2 Q dr 2 1 = 0 Thus Since at r 1 = r C, dq 1 = bq 1 2br C c < 0, the second-order condition is satisfied For finite populations, only the conjecture r = 0 can be evolutionarily stable Consider the maximization problem max r 1 (a bq (r 1, r 1 ))(q 1(r 1, r 1 ) q n(r 1, r 1 )) c 2 ((q 1(r 1, r 1 )) 2 (q n(r 1, r 1 )) 2 ) (7) 13

where the conjecture of n 1 firms is r 1 = 0 The equilibrium values of Q, q 1 and q i are found from the conditions a bq (c + br 1 )q1 = 0 and n 1 conditions a bq cqi = 0 for i 1 The last conditions add up to (n 1)a (n 1)bQ c(q q1 ) = 0, or (n 1)a ((n 1)b + c)q + cq1 = 0 From these two conditions, b dq + (c + br 1 ) dq 1 + bq1 = 0 ((n 1)b + c) dq + c dq 1 = 0 Let A = bc (c + br 1 )((n 1)b + c) Since r 1 > c dq 2b, A < 0 Then = 1 A bq 1 c < 0 and dq 1 = 1 A bq 1 ((n 1)b + c) < 0 at interior q 1 Note also that since q n = 1 n 1 (Q q1 ), dqn = 1 A ( b2 q1 ) > 0 Maximizing function (7), the first order condition is (a bq )( dq 1 dq n ) b dq (q1 qn) cq1 dq1 + cqn dqn = 0, or bq1 r 1 dq 1 b dq (q1 q n) = 0 If r 1 > 0, then the first term is negative and since q1 < q n then, the second term is also negative Similarly, if r 1 < 0, then the first term is positive and since q 1 > q n, the second term is also positive Thus the only solution is r 1 = 0 Note also that the signs of terms show that the function is indeed maximized at r 1 = 0 The results can be summarized as Proposition 4 In the linear-quadratic Cournot oligopoly (i) the consistent conjecture r C (0, 1) satisfying r C = is the unique evolutionarily stable conjecture for infinite population; c+br C (n 1)b+c+br C (ii) the aggregate-taking conjecture r = 0 is the unique evolutionarily stable conjecture for finite population 42 Rent-seeking game Consider the following rent-seeking game Players choose expenditures x i The probability x that Player i wins a prize of value V is n i j=1 x The payoff of Player i is j where X = x 1 + + x n is the aggregate u i (x i, X) = x i X V x i, 14

An interior solution of the maximization problem of Player i is characterized by 1 X V 1 x i X 2 V dx dx i = 0, or X x i r i X 2 V 1 = 0 The local second order condition (X x ir i )2Xr i V < 0 is satisfied for r X 4 i 0 The first-order condition can be rewritten as XV x i r i V X 2 = 0 Consider the n 1 players other than Player 1 having conjecture r Adding up the n 1 first order conditions, (n 1)XV rv (X x 1 ) (n 1)X 2 = 0 Then dx dx 1 = rv (n 1)V rv 2(n 1)X With a symmetric conjecture, all players have the same conjecture and thus adding up the n first-order conditions nxv rxv nx 2 = 0, or X = n r V The consistency n rv condition from the previous paragraph becomes r = (n 1)V rv 2(n 1)(n r)v/n, or r r = n 1 r 2(n 1) n r n The condition further simplifies to n 1 r 2(n 1) n r n = 1, or (n r)(2 n) = 0 If n = 2, then the condition is satisfied for any r and thus any conjecture r is consistent In Possajennikov (2009) it is shown that any r is then evolutionarily stable If n 2, then only r = n can be consistent However, then X = 0 which is not an interior solutions and thus the analysis is not applicable to it Nevertheless, it can be said that no conjecture leading to an interior solution can be evolutionarily stable for infinite population because no such conjecture is consistent To analyze the evolutionary stability in finite population, recall that only conjecture r = 0 can be evolutionarily stable Consider the maximization problem max r 1 x 1 (r 1, r 1 ) X (r 1, r 1 ) V x 1(r 1, r 1 ) x n(r 1, r 1 ) X (r 1, r 1 ) V x n(r 1, r 1 ) (8) where the conjecture of n 1 players is r 1 = 0 The equilibrium values of X, x 1 and x i are found from the conditions X V x 1 r 1V (X ) 2 = 0 and n 1 conditions X V (X ) 2 = 0 for i 1 From the latter conditions X = V Then the first condition becomes x 1 r 1V = 0 and thus r 1 = 0 is the only solution if x 1 > 0 If r 1 > 0, then the first order condition for Player 1 would imply non-interior x 1 = 0 Player 1 would have a lower payoff then than the other players Thus r 1 = 0 is indeed the solution of the maximization problem even though it is not interior 15

Proposition 5 In the rent-seeking game with probability of winning x i X, (i) if n = 2, then any conjecture r is consistent and evolutionarily stable for infinite population; if n > 2, then no conjecture leading to an interior solution is consistent or evolutionarily stable; (ii) the aggregate-taking conjecture r = 0 is the unique evolutionarily stable conjecture for finite population 5 Conclusion In this paper I consider conjectural variations for aggregative games as beliefs about the change in the aggregate in response to a (marginal) change in a player s strategy I show that if players are endowed with conjectures, play an equilibrium of the game with these conjectures and obtain some payoff in this equilibrium, then only consistent conjectures can be evolutionarily stable in infinite population This means that a player with a different conjecture would get a lower payoff than a player with consistent conjecture if players are randomly matched in groups of n to play the game In a finite population, zero conjectures are evolutionarily stable Zero conjecture here means that a player does not expect the aggregate to change in response to a change in the player s own strategy Such a conjecture commits the player to choose a behavior that maximizes the difference between the player s payoffs and the payoff of any other player (in a symmetric game with the other players using the same strategy, it does not matter which other player is considered) This is because in this situation the influence on player s own payoff and on another player s payoff through the aggregate cancel out, thus if the player is concerned about relative payoff, the change in the aggregate can be ignored The results are illustrated on two typical aggregative games, Cournot oligopoly and rentseeking games In the linear-quadratic Cournot oligopoly the consistent conjecture leads to more production than the Nash equilibrium conjecture, which implies zero response of the other players This conjecture is shown to be evolutionarily stable The zero conjecture leading to the aggregate-taking behavior (which means price-taking behavior in this context) is finite population evolutionarily stable In rent-seeking games no conjecture is consistent if n > 2, while if n = 2 any conjecture is consistent and evolutionarily stable Aggregatetaking behavior implied by the finite population evolutionarily stable conjecture lead to full 16

dissipation of the rent for any n References Dixon, HD, Somma, E (2003) The Evolution of Consistent Conjectures, Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 51, 523-536 Corchón, LC (1994) Comparative Statics for Aggregative Games The Strong Concavity Case, Mathematical Social Sciences 28, 151-165 Cornes, R, Hartley, R (2009) Fully Aggregative Games, Australian National University, School of Economics Working Paper 2009-505 Laitner, J (1980) Rational Duopoly Equilibria, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 95, 641-662 Maynard Smith, J, Price, GR (1973) The Logic of Animal Conflict, Nature 246 (Nov 2), 15-18 Müller, W, Normann, H-T (2005) Conjectural Variations and Evolutionary Stability: A Rationale for Consistency, Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 161, 491-502 Müller, W, Normann, H-T (2007) Conjectural Variations and Evolutionary Stability in Finite Populations, Journal of Evolutionary Economics 17(1), 53-61 Possajennikov, A (2003) Evolutionary Foundations of Aggregate-taking Behavior, Economics Theory 21, 921-928 Possajennikov, A (2009) The Evolutionary Stability of Constant Consistent Conjectures, Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization 72, 21-29 Schaffer, M (1988) Evolutionarily Stable Strategies for a Finite Population and a Variable Contest Size, Journal of Theoretical Biology 132, 469-478 Selten, R (1980) A Note on Evolutionarily Stable Strategies in Asymmetric Animal Conflicts, Journal of Theoretical Biology 84, 93-101 17