Trees and generic absoluteness

Similar documents
Optimal generic absoluteness results from strong cardinals

UNIVERSALLY BAIRE SETS AND GENERIC ABSOLUTENESS TREVOR M. WILSON

An inner model from Ω-logic. Daisuke Ikegami

Generalizing Gödel s Constructible Universe:

Unsolvable problems, the Continuum Hypothesis, and the nature of infinity

Outer Model Satisfiability. M.C. (Mack) Stanley San Jose State

Gödel s Programm and Ultimate L

Absolutely ordinal definable sets

The triple helix. John R. Steel University of California, Berkeley. October 2010

Set Theory and the Foundation of Mathematics. June 19, 2018

The Continuum Hypothesis, Part II

October 12, Complexity and Absoluteness in L ω1,ω. John T. Baldwin. Measuring complexity. Complexity of. concepts. to first order.

The modal logic of forcing

How Philosophy Impacts on Mathematics

Ultrafilters with property (s)

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 7 Dec 2017

Diagonalize This. Iian Smythe. Department of Mathematics Cornell University. Olivetti Club November 26, 2013

Projective well-orderings of the reals and forcing axioms

Part II Logic and Set Theory

Forcing Axioms and Inner Models of Set Theory

Tallness and Level by Level Equivalence and Inequivalence

Initial Ordinals. Proposition 57 For every ordinal α there is an initial ordinal κ such that κ α and α κ.

A Basis Theorem for Perfect Sets

Violating the Singular Cardinals Hypothesis Without Large Cardinals

FORCING AXIOMS AND THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS, PART II: TRANSCENDING ω 1 -SEQUENCES OF REAL NUMBERS

Basic set-theoretic techniques in logic Part III, Transfinite recursion and induction

The constructible universe

INCOMPLETENESS I by Harvey M. Friedman Distinguished University Professor Mathematics, Philosophy, Computer Science Ohio State University Invitation

WHY ISN T THE CONTINUUM PROBLEM ON THE MILLENNIUM ($1,000,000) PRIZE LIST?

GREGORY TREES, THE CONTINUUM, AND MARTIN S AXIOM

ITERATING ALONG A PRIKRY SEQUENCE

Compact subsets of the Baire space

FORCING WITH SEQUENCES OF MODELS OF TWO TYPES

Projective measure without projective Baire

DESCRIPTIVE INNER MODEL THEORY, LARGE CARDINALS, AND COMBINATORICS RESEARCH STATEMENT NAM TRANG

INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS

TEST GROUPS FOR WHITEHEAD GROUPS

Classical Theory of Cardinal Characteristics

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

The Vaught Conjecture Do uncountable models count?

Chain Conditions of Horn and Tarski

CANONICALIZATION BY ABSOLUTENESS

20 Ordinals. Definition A set α is an ordinal iff: (i) α is transitive; and. (ii) α is linearly ordered by. Example 20.2.

Violating the Singular Cardinals Hypothesis Without Large Cardinals

Extremely large cardinals in the absence of Choice

Increasing δ 1 2 and Namba-style forcing

SELF-DUAL UNIFORM MATROIDS ON INFINITE SETS

Inner models and ultrafilters in

Regularity and Definability

Generic Absoluteness. Joan Bagaria and Sy D. Friedman. Abstract. However, this is not true for 1 3 predicates. Indeed, if we add a Cohen real

A NOTE ON THE EIGHTFOLD WAY

Gleason s Theorem for non-separable Hilbert spaces: Extended abstract

Section 7.5: Cardinality

INDEPENDENCE OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS

Diamond, non-saturation, and weak square principles

The Axiom of Choice and Zorn s Lemma

Ordinal Ranks on the Baire and non-baire class functions. Takayuki Kihara

Informal Statement Calculus

EXTERNAL AUTOMORPHISMS OF ULTRAPRODUCTS OF FINITE MODELS

Proof Theory and Subsystems of Second-Order Arithmetic

Set-theoretic potentialism and the universal finite set

The axiom of choice and two-point sets in the plane

Large Cardinals and Higher Degree Theory

2.2 Lowenheim-Skolem-Tarski theorems

Hilbert s problems, Gödel, and the limits of computation

Tutorial 1.3: Combinatorial Set Theory. Jean A. Larson (University of Florida) ESSLLI in Ljubljana, Slovenia, August 4, 2011

Sets, Models and Proofs. I. Moerdijk and J. van Oosten Department of Mathematics Utrecht University

A Logician s Toolbox

RECENT PROGRESS ON THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS (AFTER WOODIN) PATRICK DEHORNOY

DOWNLOAD PDF FOR SET THEORY

MATHEMATICS: CONCEPTS, AND FOUNDATIONS Vol. II - Model Theory - H. Jerome Keisler

Vienna notes on effective descriptive set theory and admissible sets

A simple maximality principle

DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET

Basic set-theoretic techniques in logic Part II, Counting beyond infinity: Ordinal numbers

Successive cardinals with the tree property

Combinatorial dichotomies and cardinal invariants

Woodin s axiom ( ), or Martin s Maximum, or both?

The Axiom of Infinity, Quantum Field Theory, and Large Cardinals. Paul Corazza Maharishi University

Hilbert s problems, Gödel, and the limits of computation

Statue of Aristotle at the Aristotle University of Thessaloniki, Greece

The Absoluteness of Constructibility

MATH 3300 Test 1. Name: Student Id:

THE TREE PROPERTY AND THE FAILURE OF THE SINGULAR CARDINAL HYPOTHESIS AT ℵ ω 2

The Proper Forcing Axiom: a tutorial

Completeness Theorems and λ-calculus

FORCING (LECTURE NOTES FOR MATH 223S, SPRING 2011)

Model Theory in the Univalent Foundations

Self-reference in computability theory and the universal algorithm

Modal Logic of Forcing Classes

COUNTEREXAMPLES TO THE UNIQUE AND COFINAL BRANCHES HYPOTHESES

Cantor s Letter to Dedekind

AMS regional meeting Bloomington, IN April 1, 2017

The Search for the Perfect Language

STRUCTURES WITH MINIMAL TURING DEGREES AND GAMES, A RESEARCH PROPOSAL

The onto mapping property of Sierpinski

Forcing notions in inner models

An Iterated Forcing Extension In Which All Aleph-1 Dense Sets of Reals Are Isomorphic

On Martin s Conjecture

The Ultrapower Axiom implies GCH above a supercompact cardinal

Transcription:

in ZFC University of California, Irvine Logic in Southern California University of California, Los Angeles November 6, 03

in ZFC Forcing and generic absoluteness Trees and branches The method of forcing in set theory was developed by Paul Cohen in the 960s to prove (among other things) the independence of the Continuum Hypothesis, R = ℵ. Gödel had already showed that CH is consistent: it holds in the constructible universe L. Cohen used the forcing method to produce a model of set theory where CH fails. For example, R can be ℵ. Forcing can be used to prove the independence of many propositions in set theory, but this talk focuses on the limitations of the method.

in ZFC Forcing and generic absoluteness Trees and branches Assuming that we have a model M of ZFC, the forcing method adjoins a new element g to get a larger model M[g] of ZFC, called a generic extension of M. Remark There is a superficial analogy with field extensions: Starting with the field Q we can adjoin, for example, a square root of to get the field Q[ ]. There are limitations on what we can change; for example, we can t change the characteristic of the field. Similar limitations apply to forcing.

in ZFC Forcing and generic absoluteness Trees and branches Definition A statement ϕ is generically absolute if its truth is invariant under forcing: V = ϕ V [g] = ϕ, for every generic extension V [g]. Example Arithmetic statements first-order properties of the structure (N; 0,, +, ) are generically absolute because natural numbers cannot be added by forcing.

in ZFC Forcing and generic absoluteness Trees and branches Example Con(ZFC) is an arithmetic statement (Π 0 ) so it is generically absolute. By Gödel s second incompleteness theorem it is independent of ZFC, but this cannot be proved by forcing. Example The twin prime conjecture is an arithmetic statement (Π 0 ) so if it is independent of ZFC which seems unlikely this cannot be proved by forcing. Many open problems from outside of set theory can be phrased as arithmetic statements, eliminating the possiblility of independence proofs using forcing.

in ZFC Forcing and generic absoluteness Trees and branches Generic absoluteness for some statements beyond arithmetic can be proved using trees. Definition A tree (of height ω) is a partial ordering with a maximal element, such that the elements above any given element form a finite chain. Example

in ZFC Forcing and generic absoluteness Trees and branches Definition For a set X, a tree on X is a set of finite sequences from X, closed under initial segments and ordered by reverse inclusion. Example A tree on the set X = {0,, }: 0 0, 0 0, 0,, 0, 0, 0 Any tree T is isomorphic to a tree on a cardinal number κ, namely the maximum number of children of any node of T.

in ZFC Forcing and generic absoluteness Trees and branches Definition A tree is well-founded if every subset has a minimal element. Well-foundedness is equivalent to existence of a rank function assigning to each node an ordinal rank that is greater than the ranks of its children. Example 0 3 0 0 0

in ZFC Forcing and generic absoluteness Trees and branches Remark For infinitely branching well-founded trees the values of the rank function may be transfinite ordinals. Example ω + ω 0 3 0 0 0 n < ω

in ZFC Forcing and generic absoluteness Trees and branches Definition A tree is ill-founded if it is not well-founded. Ill-foundedness is equivalent to having an infinite branch. Example 0 0 0.

in ZFC Forcing and generic absoluteness Trees and branches Trees provide an important class of examples of generically absolute statements. Example For a tree T the statement T is well-founded (or T is ill-founded ) is generically absolute: If T is well-founded, then any rank function for T in V is also a rank function for T in any generic extension V [g]. If T is ill-founded, then any branch of T in V is also a branch of T in any generic extension V [g].

in ZFC Forcing and generic absoluteness Trees and branches Some statements beyond arithmetic can be shown to be generically absolute by considering appropriate trees. Definition Let p ω ω be a real parameter. A Σ (p) statement is one of the form x ω ω θ(x, p) where θ is an arithmetic formula. Σ means Σ (p) for trivial p = 0, 0, 0,.... means Σ (p) for some p ω ω. Remark Without loss of generality θ may be taken to be Π 0.

in ZFC Forcing and generic absoluteness Trees and branches Given a statement ϕ: x ω ω θ(x, p) where θ is a Π 0 formula, there is a tree T of finite attempts to build a real x ω ω satisfying θ(x, p). T is ill-founded (has an infinite branch x) if and only if the statement ϕ holds. Therefore statements are generically absolute. (Due to Mostowski, and holds for all transitive models.)

in ZFC Forcing and generic absoluteness Trees and branches At the next step of complexity we reach the limit of generic absoluteness that is provable in ZFC. Definition A statement is one of the form y ω ω x ω ω θ(x, y, p) where θ is an arithmetic formula and p is a real parameter. Theorem (Shoenfield) statements are generically absolute. The theorem is proved by reducing the truth of statements to the ill-foundedness of trees on ℵ. Most statements encountered in real analysis can be phrased as statements.

in ZFC 3 generic absoluteness R (Π )ub generic absoluteness Definition A 3 statement is one of the form z ω ω y ω ω x ω ω θ(x, y, z, p) where θ is an arithmetic formula and p is a real parameter. Remark The statement there is a non-constructible real is a Σ 3 statement that can fail to be generically absolute: If V = L then it is false, but it is true in any generic extension that adds a real.

in ZFC 3 generic absoluteness R (Π )ub generic absoluteness Remark Although Σ 3 generic absoluteness may fail in V, it always holds in some generic extension of V. Next we consider generic absoluteness. We can allow real 3 parameters from V or from generic extensions of V. Definition One-step generic absoluteness for says that every 3 3 statement (with parameter p V ) is generically absolute. Two-step generic absoluteness for says that one-step 3 generic absoluteness holds in every generic extension. To show these principles are consistent we need assumptions beyond ZFC, such as large cardinals (strong axioms of infinity.)

in ZFC 3 generic absoluteness R (Π )ub generic absoluteness Theorem (Feng Magidor Woodin) The following statements are equiconsistent.. There is a Σ -reflecting cardinal.. One-step generic absoluteness holds. 3 Theorem (Martin Solovay, Woodin ) The following statements are equivalent:. Every set has a sharp.. Two-step generic absoluteness holds. 3

in ZFC 3 generic absoluteness R (Π )ub generic absoluteness Generic absoluteness is also related to the extent of the universally Baire sets of reals. Definition A set of reals A ω ω is universally Baire if there are continuous functions x T x and x T x such that For every real x in V, x A T x is ill-founded T x is well-founded, and For every real x in every generic extension of V, T x is ill-founded T x is well-founded.

in ZFC 3 generic absoluteness R (Π )ub generic absoluteness Example Every set of reals A is universally Baire. Remark Universally Baire sets have many regularity properties, e.g. the Baire property, Lebesgue measurability, and the Bernstein property.

in ZFC 3 generic absoluteness R (Π )ub generic absoluteness Theorem (Feng Magidor Woodin) The following statements are equivalent: One-step generic absoluteness holds. 3 Every set of reals is universally Baire. The following statements are equivalent: Two-step generic absoluteness holds. 3 Every set of reals is universally Baire.

in ZFC 3 generic absoluteness R (Π )ub generic absoluteness Next we consider an similar situation, but higher up in terms of large cardinals and descriptive complexity. Assume: There is a cardinal λ that is a limit of Woodin cardinals. We define a local version of universally Baire : Definition Let A be a set of reals and let λ be a cardinal. Then A is λ-universally Baire, written A ub λ, if it is universally Baire with respect to generic extensions by posets of size < λ.

Definition in ZFC 3 generic absoluteness R (Π )ub generic absoluteness A ( )ub λ statement is one of the form B ub λ (HC;, B) = θ(p). A R (Π )ub λ statement is one of the form x ω ω B ub λ (HC;, B) = θ(x, p). Here θ is any formula and p is a real parameter. Analogy: Π ( (Π )ub λ )ub λ = 3 R Π R (Π )ub λ

in ZFC 3 generic absoluteness R (Π )ub generic absoluteness An analogue of Shoenfield absoluteness for : Theorem (Woodin) If λ is a limit of Woodin cardinals, then ( )ub λ statements are generically absolute with respect to generic extensions by posets of size < λ. Remark As before, this generic absoluteness can be explained in terms of a continuous reduction to ill-foundedness of trees.

in ZFC 3 generic absoluteness R (Π )ub generic absoluteness Generic absoluteness for R (Π ) ub λ is different: It is not known to follow from any large cardinal hypothesis. Many large cardinals can be accomodated in L-like inner models where R (Π ) ub λ generic absoluteness fails, much as Σ 3 generic absoluteness fails in L. Questions How is generic absoluteness for R (Π )ub λ related to: The extent (or closure properties) of the pointclass of λ-universally Baire sets? Large cardinals? The absoluteness of well-foundedness for trees?

in ZFC One-step generic absoluteness for R (Π )ub λ is related to closure properties of the ub λ sets. Proposition (W.) For a limit λ of Woodin cardinals, the following statements are equivalent:. One-step R (Π )ub λ generic absoluteness holds with respect to generic extensions by posets of size < λ.. Every ( )ub λ set of reals is λ-universally Baire.

in ZFC What is its consistency strength? Proposition (W.) Con() = Con(), where. There is a limit λ of Woodin cardinals and a cardinal δ < λ that is Σ -reflecting in V λ.. There is a limit λ of Woodin cardinals such that one-step R (Π )ub λ generic absoluteness holds with respect to generic extensions by posets of size < λ. Open Question Con() = Con()?

in ZFC Two-step generic absoluteness for R (Π )ub λ is also related to closure properties of the ub λ sets. Proposition (W.) Let λ be a limit of Woodin cardinals. Then () = (), where. Every ( )ub λ set of reals is λ-universally Baire.. Two-step R (Π )ub λ generic absoluteness holds with respect to generic extensions by posets of size < λ. Open Question () = ()?

in ZFC What is the consistency strength of two-step absoluteness? Theorem (Woodin) Con() = Con(), where. There is a limit λ of Woodin cardinals and a cardinal δ < λ that is <λ-strong.. There is a limit λ of Woodin cardinals such that two-step R (Π )ub λ generic absoluteness holds with respect to generic extensions by posets of size < λ. Remark If the answer to Open Question is yes then Con() = Con().

in ZFC A partial yes answer to Open Question : Proposition (W.) Let λ be a measurable cardinal that is a limit of Woodin cardinals. If two-step R (Π )ub λ generic absoluteness holds with respect to generic extensions by posets of size < λ, then some such generic extension satisfies every ( )ub λ set of reals is λ-universally Baire.

in ZFC From this we get something close to an equiconsistency involving two-step R (Π )ub λ generic absoluteness. Theorem (W.) Con( ) = Con(), where. There is a limit λ of Woodin cardinals and a cardinal δ < λ that is <λ-strong.. There is a measurable cardinal λ that is a limit of Woodin cardinals, and such that two-step R (Π )ub λ generic absoluteness holds with respect to generic extensions by posets of size < λ.