Is Bell s Locality Condition Necessary for The Derivation of Bell s Inequality?

Similar documents
Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox and Bell s inequalities

Mathematical and Physical Examination of the Locality Condition in Bell s Theorem

RUNS: A_B, A_B', A'_B,

Inequalities for Dealing with Detector Inefficiencies in Greenberger-Horne-Zeilinger Type Experiments

Bell s inequalities and their uses

1.1.1 Bell Inequality - Spin correlation

EPR Paradox and Bell Inequalities

Quantum measurements and Kolmogorovian probability theory

A New Bell Inequality for Two Spin-1 Particle System. Abstract

Singlet State Correlations

NON HILBERTIAN QUANTUM MECHANICS ON THE FINITE GALOIS FIELD

Today s Outline - April 18, C. Segre (IIT) PHYS Spring 2017 April 18, / 23

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM

A Reexamination on Bell s Theorem

KOLMOGOROV s PROBABILITY THEORY IN QUANTUM PHYSICS

Solving the Einstein Podolsky Rosen puzzle: The origin of non-locality in Aspect-type experiments

Bohmian particle trajectories contradict quantum mechanics

arxiv:quant-ph/ v1 10 Jan 1997

Understanding Long-Distance Quantum Correlations

arxiv:quant-ph/ v1 14 Sep 1999

Logical difficulty from combining counterfactuals in the GHZ-Bell theorems

Michael H. Shulman, 2006 (Revisited ) WHY QUANTUM MECHANICS IS NON-LOCAL?

Has CHSH-inequality any relation to EPR-argument?

ON A FORMAL DIFFERENCE BETWEEN THE INDIVIDUAL AND STATISTICAL INTERPRETATION OF QUANTUM THEORY

arxiv: v3 [quant-ph] 20 Jan 2016

The quantum world is not built up from correlations Found. Phys. 36, (2006).

A Bell Theorem Without Inequalities for Two Particles, Using Efficient Detectors. Daniel M. Greenberger City College of New York, New York, NY 10031

Quantum Nonlocality of N-qubit W States

A Geometrical Model of Fermion Spin Correlations

Lecture 29 Relevant sections in text: 3.9

Remarks on Bell s Inequality

Closing the Debates on Quantum Locality and Reality: EPR Theorem, Bell's Theorem, and Quantum Information from the Brown-Twiss Vantage

arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 4 Jun 2018

Time-Symmetrized Counterfactuals in Quantum Theory 1

CLASSIFICATION OF MAXIMALLY ENTANGLED STATES OF SPIN 1/2 PARTICLES

The CHSH game as a Bell test thought experiment

Anomaly in sign function - probability function integration III

Introduction to Bell s theorem: the theory that solidified quantum mechanics

Entanglement of projection and a new class of quantum erasers

An Alternative Commutation Relation Between Position And. Momentum Operators of Massless Particles. H. Razmi. Abstract

On the completeness of quantum mechanics and the interpretation of the state vector

The controlled-not (CNOT) gate exors the first qubit into the second qubit ( a,b. a,a + b mod 2 ). Thus it permutes the four basis states as follows:

arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 11 Dec 2012

arxiv:quant-ph/ v2 21 Oct 2003

Chapter 9. Three No-Go Theorems and the Measurement Problem. If one is convinced by some EPR-like argument, then one might become a

EPR Paradox and Bell s Inequality

arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 15 Feb 2016

PURE QUANTUM SOLUTIONS OF BOHMIAN

A No-Go Result on Common Cause Approaches via Hardy s Paradox

arxiv:quant-ph/ v2 5 May 2003

arxiv: v4 [quant-ph] 28 Feb 2018

Response to Wiseman, Rieffel, and Cavalcanti on Bell s 1964 Paper

Computer Simulation of Einstein-Podolsky. Podolsky-Rosen- Bohm Experiments with Photons.

David Bohm s Hidden Variables

Probabilistic exact cloning and probabilistic no-signalling. Abstract

Contextuality and the Kochen-Specker Theorem. Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics

Super-Quantum, Non-Signaling Correlations Cannot Exist

Quantum correlations from wave-particle unity and locality: Resolution of the EPR puzzle

arxiv:quant-ph/ v1 15 Jun 1999

Spatial Locality: A hidden variable unexplored in entanglement experiments

Quantum mysteries revisited again

arxiv: v3 [quant-ph] 14 Feb 2014

The relation between Hardy s non-locality and violation of Bell inequality

Quantum mechanics and reality

RANDOMNESS, NONLOCALITY AND INFORMATION IN ENTANGLED CORRELATIONS. Krzysztof Wodkiewicz

University of Groningen

Logical difficulty from combining counterfactuals in the GHZ-Bell theorems

Quantum mechanics with the permitted hidden parameters

Take that, Bell s Inequality!

EPR Paradox Solved by Special Theory of Relativity

ON THE EINSTEIN PODOLSKY ROSEN PARADOX* I. Introduction

Photons uncertainty removes Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox. Abstract

Theory and Experiment

PRESELECTED QUANTUM OPTICAL CORRELATIONS

ON EPR PARADOX, BELL S INEQUALITIES AND EXPERIMENTS THAT PROVE NOTHING

Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen Paradox, Bell Inequalities and the Relation to the de Broglie-Bohm Theory

Hardy s Paradox. Chapter Introduction

Analysis of Bell inequality violation in superconducting phase qubits

A computational proof of locality in entanglement.

arxiv:quant-ph/ v1 8 Sep 2006

Causality and Local Determinism versus Quantum Nonlocality.

arxiv: v2 [quant-ph] 22 Sep 2008

Bell inequality for qunits with binary measurements

arxiv:quant-ph/ v2 21 Jun 2004

Is Entanglement Sufficient to Enable Quantum Speedup?

On the origin of probability in quantum mechanics

Odd Things about Quantum Mechanics: Abandoning Determinism In Newtonian physics, Maxwell theory, Einstein's special or general relativity, if an initi

CAT L4: Quantum Non-Locality and Contextuality

arxiv: v2 [quant-ph] 1 Jun 2013

A proof of Bell s inequality in quantum mechanics using causal interactions

A Note on the Geometric Interpretation of Bell s Inequalities

Locality and the Hardy theorem

A history of entanglement

Article. Reference. Bell Inequalities for Arbitrarily High-Dimensional Systems. COLLINS, Daniel Geoffrey, et al.

Relativistic Spin Operator with Observers in Motion

Lab. 1: Entanglement and Bell s Inequalities. Abstract

1. Griffiths Suppose two spin-1/2 particles are known to be in the singlet configuration.

Relation of the Bell inequalities with quantum logic, hidden variables and information theory

Lecture 12c: The range of classical and quantum correlations

PHY3902 PHY3904. Photon Entanglement. Laboratory protocol

Transcription:

Annales de la Fondation Louis de Broglie, Volume 26 no 4, 2001 735 Is Bell s Locality Condition Necessary for The Derivation of Bell s Inequality? M. Golshani, A. Fahmi Institute for Studies in Theoretical Physics and Mathematics (IPM), P.O.Box 19395-5531, Tehran, Iran and Department of Physics Sharif University of Technology, P.O.Box 11365-9061, Tehran, Iran email: golshani@ihcs.ac.ir, fahmi@theory.ipm.ac.ir ABSTRACT. In this paper, we have derived, in a very simple way, the original Bell s and CH s inequalities without using Bell s original locality condition. PACS number : 03. 65. Bz. 1 Introduction Bell s inequality has been derived in different ways [1-10], using the following assumptions: locality, determinism, hidden variables and counterfactual definiteness. From this inequality, Bell concluded the so-called Bell s theorem: In certain experiments all realistic local hidden variable theories are incompatible with quantum mechanics. Clauser and Horne tried to drive an inequality without the assumption of determinism [11] and showed that this inequality isn t consistent with quantum mechanics. In some cases, people have tried to introduce the locality hypothesis as a natural condition ( e. g. the Bell s inequality for the case of a single particle ) and have shown the violation of Bell s inequality [12-15]. Ben-Aryeh used entangled singlet spin-state with spatial spherical wave functions and showed that Bell s inequalities are violated only for subensembles which are not pure states, and he concluded that locality is not violated [16]. G. Lochak [17] analyzed the proof given by J. S. Bell and showed that Bell s reasoning involves not only his locality assumption ( with which he agrees ) but also a statistical hypothesis which is exactly the equivalent to the one introduced by von Neumann. This hypothesis consists in the admitting that such a theory must restore the classical probabilistic pattern simultaneously in the statistics of all measurement results. This leads immediately to a contradiction

736 M. Golshani, A. Fahmi with the calculation of mean values in quantum mechanics. E. Santos ( and others) [18-19], considers experimental restrictions, and argues that from actual experiments, with low efficiency detectors, one cannot conclude the violation of Bell s inequality. In deriving Bell s inequality most authors assume the locality condition. Some authors use a weaker locality condition, For example, Helman [20] constructed a model with an almost ideal correlation and an almost determinism, and showed that this should suffice to derive an approximate Bell-type inequality. In this model, outcome-independence and factorizability of joint probability are not assumed, but rather an approximate from of factorizability is derived. Elby and Jones [21] used K.S. theorem, and derived a simple algebraic contradiction between various locality assumptions and the predictions of quantum mechanics. In this paper, we consider non-locality in a special form and drive Bell and CH inequalities. Consequently, our proof rules out a broader class of hidden variable theories. 2 Locality Condition and Bell s Inequality A typical Bell-type experiment consists of two particles which originate from a source and propagate in opposite directions towards their corresponding measurement apparatuses and detectors. Each detector detects a dichotomic variable which takes the values ±1. We represent the parameters which characterize the measurement apparatuses (1) and (2) by â and ˆb respectively (â, e.g., is the direction of magnetic field in a Stern-Gerlach experiment). The measurement results depend on the controllable variables â and ˆb and a set of uncontrollable variables, the so-called hidden variables, which we collectively represent by λ. In Bell s original approach [2], the result A of the spin measurement on particle 1 was taken to depend on â, ˆb and λ, i.e. we have A(â, ˆb, λ). Similarly, B(â, ˆb, λ) represents the result of a spin measurement on the particle 2. Bell, then, applied Einstein s locality in the following form: A(â, ˆb, λ) =A(â, λ) B(â, ˆb, λ) =B(ˆb, λ) (1) In our approach, we replace Bell s locality condition by the following condition: A(â, ˆb, λ)=f A (â, λ)g A (ˆb, λ) B(â, ˆb, λ)=f B (â, λ)g B (ˆb, λ) (2)

Is Bell s Locality Condition Necessary... 737 Here, Shimony s parameter independence is clearly violated. We are, as in Bell s case [2], interested in the correlation of the results of joint spin measurements performed on particles 1 and 2. Thus, we define the correlation function C(â, ˆb) in the form: C(â, ˆb) = A(â, ˆb, λ)b(â, ˆb, λ)ρ(λ) dλ (3) where the probability distribution function for the uncontrollable hidden variables λ is represented by ρ(λ), with ρ(λ) dλ =1, ρ(λ) 0 (4) A(â, ˆb, λ) =±1, B(â, ˆb, λ) =±1 If the parameter of the measurement apparatus (1) can take values â or â and that of the measurement apparatus (2) can take values ˆb or ˆb, then, we have: C(â, ˆb) C(â, ˆb )= ρ(λ) dλ{a(â, ˆb, λ)b(â, ˆb, λ) A(â, ˆb, λ)b(â, ˆb,λ)} = ρ(λ) dλ{a(â, ˆb, λ)b(â, ˆb, λ)[ 1 ± A(â, ˆb,λ)B(â, ˆb,λ)] A(â, ˆb,λ)B(â, ˆb,λ)[ 1 ± A(â, ˆb, λ)b(â, ˆb, λ)] } (5) Taking the absolute values of both sides and using A(â, ˆb, λ) = B(â, ˆb, λ) = A(â, ˆb,λ) = B(â, ˆb,λ) =1 1 ± A(â, ˆb, λ)b(â, ˆb, λ) =1± A(â, ˆb, λ)b(â, ˆb, λ) 1 ± A(â, ˆb,λ)B(â, ˆb,λ) =1± A(â, ˆb,λ)B(â, ˆb,λ) (6) We have: C(â, ˆb) C(â, ˆb ) ρ(λ) dλ{ [1± A(â, ˆb,λ)B(â, ˆb,λ)] +[ 1 ± A(â, ˆb, λ)b(â, ˆb, λ)] } 2 ± [ C(â, ˆb )+C(â, ˆb)] (7) or C(â, ˆb) C(â, ˆb ) + C(â, ˆb )+C(â, ˆb) 2 (8)

738 M. Golshani, A. Fahmi which is Bell s original inequality [2]. This shows that one can obtain Bell s inequality without appealing to Bell s locality condition (1). Furthermore, it shows that if there is any non-locality in nature it is not in the form of the eq. (2). 3 Locality Condition and CH s Inequality Here, we first review the locality condition for the CH inequality. The schematic diagram for the experiment is the same as CH s experiment given in ref.[5]: A source produces two correlated particles at the origin O. Each particle goes through an analyzer and a detector. For the case of spin 1 2 particles, the analyzers are simply Stern-Gerlach magnetic apparatuses and for the case of photons the analyzers are simply polarization filters. The detectors discover only the number of particles. We assume that the probability for the detection of a particle by detector D 1 depends only on the parameter of it s corresponding analyzer and a set of uncontrollable variables (the so-called hidden variables), which we represent collectively by λ. The probability of the detection of particle 1 is represented, by P 1 (â, λ) and that for the particle 2 by P 2 (ˆb, λ). The joint probability function for detection of both particles is represented by P 12 (â, ˆb, λ). The distribution function for the uncontrollable hidden variable λ is represented by ρ(λ) which satisfies the following relations: ρ(λ) dλ =1, ρ(λ) 0 Averaging P 1 (â, λ),p 2 (ˆb, λ) and P 12 (â, ˆb, λ) over λ, we get: P 1 (â) = P 1 (â, λ)ρ(λ) dλ P 2 (ˆb) = P 12 (â, ˆb) = P 2 (ˆb, λ)ρ(λ) dλ P 12 (â, ˆb, λ)ρ(λ) dλ (9) Clauser and Horne applied Einstein s locality condition in the following form: P 12 (â, ˆb, λ) =P 1 (â, λ)p 2 (ˆb, λ) (10)

Is Bell s Locality Condition Necessary... 739 Now we replace CH s locality condition by the following conditions. P 1 (â, ˆb, λ)=f 1 (â, λ)g 1 (ˆb, λ) P 2 (â, ˆb, λ)=f 2 (â, λ)g 2 (ˆb, λ) (11) then by considering the following inequality, which is always true, x a x b y a y b x a x b y a y b + x a x b y a y b + x a x b y a y b x a y b 0 0 x i,y j 1 i, j = a, a,b,b x a = f 1 (â, λ), x b = g 1 (ˆb, λ), y b = g 2 (ˆb, λ), y a = f 2 (â, λ) We can drive CH s inequality. Here, we don t follow this path; rather, we use the approach of Arthur Fine in ref.[22], i.e. we begin from Bell s inequality and derive CH s inequality. representing the average values of measurements on particles (1) and (2) by E 1 (â, ˆb, λ) and E 2 (â, ˆb, λ), respectively, is: E 1 (â, ˆb, λ)e 2 (â, ˆb, λ) =P 12 (â, ˆb, λ) P 12 (â, ˆb, λ) P 12 ( â, ˆb, λ)+p 12 ( â, ˆb, λ) (12) Of course, the assumptions of the previous section for A s and B s can be adopted for E i, i.e. they are in product form, and all results of Sec. (2) hold for E 1 and E 2.But we have neither assumed parameter or outcome independence, nor have made the assumption of there about the form of P 12. Now, we know that: P 12 (â, ˆb) =P 1 (â) P 12 (â, ˆb) P 12 ( â, ˆb) =P 2 (ˆb) P 12 (â, ˆb) (13) P 12 ( â, ˆb) =1 P 12 ( â, ˆb) P 12 (â, ˆb) P 12 (â, ˆb) From equations (3), (12) and (13), we get: C(â, ˆb) =4P 12 (â, ˆb) 2P 1 (â) 2P 2 (ˆb) + 1 (14)

740 M. Golshani, A. Fahmi and from the equation (14) and similar equations for C(â, ˆb ), C(â, ˆb ) and C(â, ˆb),and using Bell s inequality (8), we get: 2 [4P 12 (â, ˆb) 2P 1 (â) 2P 2 (ˆb)+1 4P 12 (â, ˆb )+2P 1 (â)+2p 2 (ˆb ) 1] +[ 4P 12 (â, ˆb) 2P 1 (â ) 2P 2 (ˆb)+1 +4P 12 (â, ˆb ) 2P 1 (â ) 2P 2 (ˆb )+1] 2 (15) or 1 P 12 (â, ˆb) P 12 (â, ˆb )+P 12 (â, ˆb )+P 12 (â, ˆb) P 1 (â ) P 2 (ˆb) 0 which is the usual CH inequality [5]. 4 Conclusion In this paper,we have replaced Bell s locality condition by a more general condition to obtain the Bell s and CH s inequalities. The least conclusion we can draw is that if there were any non-locality in nature it would not be of the restricted form of eq.(2), and that for all hidden variable theories in which non-locality is assumed in the aforementioned form, one can obtain Bell s inequality. In other words, one can obtain CH s inequality without using the factorizability condition. Thus, we can conclude that the violation of Bell s inequalities is not necessarily the violation of Bell s locality condition, and that if there is any non-locality in nature, it is not in the form of the relation (2). Furthermore, all hidden variable theories of this sort are inconsistent with quantum mechanics. In a paper in progress, we shall study some more general cases of non-locality References [1] D.J.S. Bell, In Proceedings of the International School of Physics, (Enrico Fermi, Course II, Varenna 1970). [2] J.s. Bell, Physics 1, P. 195 (1964). [3] D. Bohm, Quantum Theory, (Prentice Hall 1951). [4] L. Ballentine, Quantum Mechanics, P. 443-444 (Prentice-Hall 1990). [5] J.S. Bell, Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics, (Cambridge 1987). [6] D. Bohm, Phys. Rev. 85, P. 165 and P. 180 (1952). [7] P.H. Eberhard, IL Nuovo Cimento, Vol. 38 B, N. 1, P. 75 (1977). [8] H.P. Stapp, Found. Phys. Vol. 18, No. 4, P. 427 (1988).

Is Bell s Locality Condition Necessary... 741 [9] H.P. Stapp, Found. Phys. Vol. 21, No. 1, P. 1 (1991). [10] H.P. Stapp, Am. J. Phys. 53, P. 306 (1985). [11] J.F. Clauser, and M.A. Horne, Phys. Rev. D,Vol10, P. 526 (1974). [12] M. Revzen, and A. Mann, Found. Phys., Vol 26, No. 6, P. 847 (1996). [13] D. Fivel, Phys. Rev. Lett. 74, P.835 (1995). [14] D. Home, and S. Sengupta, Phys. Lett. A, 102, P.159 (1984). [15] A. Shafiee, and M. Golshani, quant-ph/9907017 ( to apper in phys. rev. A ). [16] Y. Ben-Aryeh, Found. Phys. Let. Vol. 6, No. 4, P. 317 (1993). [17] G. Lochak, Found. Phys. Vol. 6, No.2, P. 173 (1976). [18] E. Santos, Found. Phys. Vol. 21, No.2, P.221 (1991). [19] E. Santos, Phys. Rev. Lett., Vol. 66, No.11, P. 1388 (1991). [20] G. Hellman, Found. Phys., Vol. 22, No. 6, P.807 (1992). [21] A. Elby, and M.R. Jones, Phys. Lett. A, 171, P. 11 (1992). [22] A. Fine, Phys. Rev. Lett., 48. P. 291 (1982). (Manuscrit reçu le 4 janvier 2001)