Supplement. Algebraic Closure of a Field

Similar documents
Section V.3. Splitting Fields, Algebraic Closure, and Normality (Supplement)

Section 0.7. The Axiom of Choice, Order, and Zorn s Lemma

ABOUT THE CLASS AND NOTES ON SET THEORY

Section VI.31. Algebraic Extensions

Section II.1. Free Abelian Groups

Section VII.39. Free Groups

Extension fields II. Sergei Silvestrov. Spring term 2011, Lecture 13

Section VI.33. Finite Fields

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals

Section I.6. Symmetric, Alternating, and Dihedral Groups

Chapter 0. Introduction: Prerequisites and Preliminaries

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

Econ Lecture 2. Outline

Factorization in Polynomial Rings

SOLUTIONS TO EXERCISES FOR. MATHEMATICS 205A Part 1. I. Foundational material

Economics 204 Summer/Fall 2011 Lecture 2 Tuesday July 26, 2011 N Now, on the main diagonal, change all the 0s to 1s and vice versa:

Economics 204. Lecture 2, July 28, 2009

1. (B) The union of sets A and B is the set whose elements belong to at least one of A

The Axiom of Choice. Contents. 1 Motivation 2. 2 The Axiom of Choice 2. 3 Two powerful equivalents of AC 4. 4 Zorn s Lemma 5. 5 Using Zorn s Lemma 6

Section V.6. Separability

Properties of the Integers

a + b = b + a and a b = b a. (a + b) + c = a + (b + c) and (a b) c = a (b c). a (b + c) = a b + a c and (a + b) c = a c + b c.

Chapter 1. Wedderburn-Artin Theory

Clearly C B, for every C Q. Suppose that we may find v 1, v 2,..., v n

Weak Choice Principles and Forcing Axioms

VI I : The Axiom of Choice and related properties

Supplement. Dr. Bob s Modern Algebra Glossary Based on Fraleigh s A First Course on Abstract Algebra, 7th Edition, Sections 0 through IV.

On the Prime Ideals of C[0,1]

Well-Ordered Sets, Ordinals and Cardinals Ali Nesin 1 July 2001

Part II Logic and Set Theory

Section 31 Algebraic extensions

Short notes on Axioms of set theory, Well orderings and Ordinal Numbers

NOTES ON WELL ORDERING AND ORDINAL NUMBERS. 1. Logic and Notation Any formula in Mathematics can be stated using the symbols

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

Section V.3.Appendix. The Fundamental Theorem of Algebra

Products, Relations and Functions

ON THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SETS AND GROUPS

X = { X f X i A i : (œx, y 0 X)[x /= y œi[ x i /= y i ]]}.

Notes on ordinals and cardinals

D-MATH Algebra I HS18 Prof. Rahul Pandharipande. Solution 1. Arithmetic, Zorn s Lemma.

INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS

Dr. Bob s Axiom of Choice Centennial Lecture Fall A Century Ago

Ordinals. Mustafa Elsheikh elsheimm at mcmaster dot ca. Wed 18 Nov 2008

Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G. Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21

Fields and Galois Theory. Below are some results dealing with fields, up to and including the fundamental theorem of Galois theory.

Extension theorems for homomorphisms

The Axiom of Choice and Zorn s Lemma

Chapter 3. Topology of the Real Numbers.

MATH 220 (all sections) Homework #12 not to be turned in posted Friday, November 24, 2017

MATH 51H Section 4. October 16, Recall what it means for a function between metric spaces to be continuous:

MATH 3300 Test 1. Name: Student Id:

IV.3. Zeros of an Analytic Function

Department of Computer Science University at Albany, State University of New York Solutions to Sample Discrete Mathematics Examination I (Spring 2008)

DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET

NOTES ON DIOPHANTINE APPROXIMATION

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9

VII.5. The Weierstrass Factorization Theorem

Essential Background for Real Analysis I (MATH 5210)

0.2 Vector spaces. J.A.Beachy 1

Report 1 The Axiom of Choice

Math Introduction to Modern Algebra

Notes on graduate algebra. Robert Harron

MINIMAL GENERATING SETS OF GROUPS, RINGS, AND FIELDS

Course 311: Michaelmas Term 2005 Part III: Topics in Commutative Algebra

6 CARDINALITY OF SETS

Section V.2. The Fundamental Theorem (of Galois Theory)

Initial Ordinals. Proposition 57 For every ordinal α there is an initial ordinal κ such that κ α and α κ.

Fields and Galois Theory

Bulletin of the Iranian Mathematical Society

THE CANTOR GAME: WINNING STRATEGIES AND DETERMINACY. by arxiv: v1 [math.ca] 29 Jan 2017 MAGNUS D. LADUE

Problems - Section 17-2, 4, 6c, 9, 10, 13, 14; Section 18-1, 3, 4, 6, 8, 10; Section 19-1, 3, 5, 7, 8, 9;

Section 31. The Separation Axioms

Homework #5 Solutions

Chapter 8. P-adic numbers. 8.1 Absolute values

Section III.6. Factorization in Polynomial Rings

Part VI. Extension Fields

Section 33 Finite fields

Problem Set 2: Solutions Math 201A: Fall 2016

Sets, Models and Proofs. I. Moerdijk and J. van Oosten Department of Mathematics Utrecht University

Math 762 Spring h Y (Z 1 ) (1) h X (Z 2 ) h X (Z 1 ) Φ Z 1. h Y (Z 2 )

Math General Topology Fall 2012 Homework 6 Solutions

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO ZFC. Contents. 1. Motivation and Russel s Paradox

Tensor Product of modules. MA499 Project II

Theorem 5.3. Let E/F, E = F (u), be a simple field extension. Then u is algebraic if and only if E/F is finite. In this case, [E : F ] = deg f u.

On Transfinite Cardinal Numbers

1 Topology Definition of a topology Basis (Base) of a topology The subspace topology & the product topology on X Y 3

The Axiom of Choice and Some Equivalences:

The category of linear modular lattices

Algebra: Groups. Group Theory a. Examples of Groups. groups. The inverse of a is simply a, which exists.

MATH 326: RINGS AND MODULES STEFAN GILLE

MINKOWSKI THEORY AND THE CLASS NUMBER

School of Mathematics and Statistics. MT5836 Galois Theory. Handout 0: Course Information

Lecture 6: Finite Fields

Part IX. Factorization

NOTES ON FINITE FIELDS

Outline Inverse of a Relation Properties of Relations. Relations. Alice E. Fischer. April, 2018

Infinite constructions in set theory

VARIATIONS FOR SEPARATING CLUB GUESSING PRINCIPLES

Elliptic Curves Spring 2013 Lecture #14 04/02/2013

Math 418 Algebraic Geometry Notes

Transcription:

Supplement: Algebraic Closure of a Field 1 Supplement. Algebraic Closure of a Field Note. In this supplement, we give some background material which is used in the proof of Fraleigh s Theorem 31.17/31.22 (Every field has an algebraic closure). All proofs require some set theoretic background. Definition 31.1. An extension field E of field F is an algebraic extension of F if every element in E is algebraic over F. Note. The following result is a big deal and should probably be part of Fraleigh s basic goal. This result simply claims the existence of an algebraic closure of a field but, as we ll see, neither the result nor its proof give insight as to how to construct the algebraic closure of a field. Theorem 31.17/31.22. Every field F has an algebraic closure; that is, an algebraic extension F that is algebraically closed. Note. We now introduce the ideas necessary to prove that every field has an algebraic closure (Theorem 31.17/31.22). We need some ideas from set theory.

Supplement: Algebraic Closure of a Field 2 Definition 31.19. A partial ordering of a set S is given by a relation denoted defined for certain ordered pairs of elements of S such that the following are satisfied: 1. a a for all a S (Reflexive Law). 2. If a b and b a then a = b (Antisymmetric Law). 3. If a b and b c then a c (Transitive Law). If for a,b S we have either a b or b a then a and b are comparable. A subset T S is a chain if every two elements a and b in T are comparable. An element u S is an upper bound for subset A of S if a u for all a A. An element m of S is maximal if there is no s S such that m s. Example. Consider the sets A =, B = {1}, C = {2}, D = {3}, E = {1,2}, F = {1,3}, and G = {2,3}. Define S = {A,B,C,D,E,F,G}. For sets X and Y in S, define X Y if X Y. Then A X for all X S. Also, B E, B F, C E, C G, D F and D G. The remaining pairs of sets are not comparable. Set S has no upper bound. Set {A,B,C,E} has E as an upper bound. for set S, maximal elements are E, F, and G. Set T = {A,B,F } is a chain in S. Lemma 31.21. Zorn s Lemma. If S is a partially ordered set such that every chain in S has an upper bound in S, then S has at least one maximal element.

Supplement: Algebraic Closure of a Field 3 Note. Zorn s Lemma is equivalent to the famous Axiom of Choice, which has some surprising consequences in measure theory (to drop some verbiage, a non- Lebesgue-measurable set and the Banach-Tarski Paradox ). Zorn s Lemma can be used to show that every vector space has a basis (notice that the definition of vector space did not require the existence of a basis). We need Zorn s Lemma for the proof of Theorem 31.17/31.22. Note. Russell s Paradox from set theory implies that there can be no largest set nor a set of all sets. Russell s Paradox results from the 19th century approach to sets which did not have a clear way of constructing new sets from old ( sets were still viewed informally). The fallout of Russell s Paradox was to inspire an axiomatic development of set theory (lead by Russell and Whitehead s Principia Mathematica of circa 1910). For more details on Russell s Paradox, see my notes on Analysis 1 (MATH 4217/5217): http://faculty.etsu.edu/gardnerr/4217/notes/1-1.pdf. Note. Georg Cantor (1845 1918) introduced the concept of the cardinality of an infinite set. We denote the cardinality of set A as A. Cantor s Theorem states that for any set A, the cardinality of the power set of set A, denoted P(A), is strictly greater than the cardinality of set A: P(A) > A. For details, see my notes from Analysis 1 (MATH 4217/5217): http://faculty.etsu.edu/gardnerr/4217/notes/1-3.pdf

Supplement: Algebraic Closure of a Field 4 Note. Fraleigh gives a proof on pages 290 and 291. You can find an alternate proof in Hungerford s Algebra in Section V.3, but the proof requires a number of other results in Hungerford (some of them deep, set theoretic results). Another proof is given in Dummit and Foote s Abstract Algebra, 3rd Edition, John Wiley and Sons (2004), Section 13.4. This proof uses results concerning ideals and maximal ideals, but otherwise is pretty much independent of other results in the book. An additional interesting source is given by Hanspeter Fischer of Ball State University. His proof is given as a supplement to his notes and is posted online (see http://www.cs.bsu.edu/homepages/fischer/math412/closure.pdf). Note. The proof of Theorem 31.17/21.22 is unlike much of the rest of the content of this class because the proof is largely set-theoretic, instead of algebraic (though some of the details are algebraic which must be verified in order to apply the st theoretic approach). We break the proof into three parts. FIRST, in order to apply Zorn s Lemma we need to insure that all of the extension fields of field F we deal with are in the same set, Ω. SECOND, for any chain of fields, we construct an upper bound for the chain. THIRD, we show that the upper bound is a maximal element of the set of algebraic extension fields of F and that it is (with a proof by contradiction) algebraically closed. This maximal element approach will not necessarily guarantee uniqueness of the algebraic closure of field F. Theorem 31.17/31.22. Every field F has an algebraic closure; that is, an algebraic extension F that is algebraically closed.

Supplement: Algebraic Closure of a Field 5 Proof. I. Construction of a set Ω large enough to contain all algebraic extensions of field F. For a given field F, form a set A which has an element for every possible zero of a polynomial in F[x]: A = {ω f,i f(x) F[x],i = 1,2,...,(degree of f)}. The idea here is that for any polynomial f(x) = a 0 +a 1 x+a 2 x 2 + +a n x n F[x], there are at most n zeros, one for such ω f,1,ω f,2,...,ω f,n. So for every zero of every polynomial in F[x] (and hence for every element of E an algebraic extension of F, see Definition 31.1) there is an element of S. The elements of a field are simply elements of a set. In the following arguments, we ll deal with fields consisting of elements of F and another set we need not concern ourselves with what the elements of the other set are, simply that a field exists consisting of these elements. Consider the power set P(A). By Cantor s Theorem (see above), P(A) > A. Now, for each a F, we have a as a zero of f a (x) = x a and so there is ω fa,1 A and hence {ω fa,1} P(A). Define set Ω as Ω = (P(A) \ a F {ω fa,1}) {a a F }. That is, replace each {ω fa,1} P(A) with a F. Then F Ω. Now consider all possible fields that can be defined on the elements of Ω that are algebraic extensions of F. Denote the set of all such fields as E. Since E P(Ω), then set E actually exists.

Supplement: Algebraic Closure of a Field 6 Recall from Russell s Paradox that we can t simply define a set in an arbitrary way, such as the set of all sets or the set of all algebraic extensions of F, and that s why we take this approach of defining set A and considering power sets A and Ω. Also, F E, so E is nonempty. Let E be an algebraic extension field of F with γ E a zero of f(x) F[x] and γ / F. Say deg(γ,f) = n. Then every element of F(γ) is of the form a 0 + a 1 γ + a 2 γ 2 + + a n 1 γ n 1 by Theorem 29.18. Now pick ω Ω, ω / F, and rename γ as ω. Also rename the element a 0 +a 1 γ +a 2 γ 2 + +a n 1 γ n 1 of F(γ) by distinct elements of Ω as the a i range over F. For any infinite set, the set of all finite-tuples from the set has the same cardinality as the original set (though I need a reference for this result!). So set Ω is large enough to do this renaming with distinct elements of F. The renamed F(γ) (now named F(ω)) is an algebraic extension field of F where F(ω) Ω and f(ω) = 0. For all algebraic extension fields E j of F, with E j Ω (after the renaming above), form a set S = {E j j J}. Set S is partially ordered by subfield inclusion. F S, so S is nonempty. II. Showing that every chain in S has an upper bound in S. Let T = {E jk k K} be a chain in S, and let W = k K E jk. We will (a) make W into a field, (b) show that W is an algebraic extension of F, and (c) show that W is an upper bound for T.

Supplement: Algebraic Closure of a Field 7 (a) The same elements of set W can form different fields under different binary operation + and, so we need to define + and on W in a uniform way. Let α,β W. Then α E j1 and β = E j2 for some E j1,e j2 S. Since T is a chain under subfield inclusion, one of these is a subfield of the other. Say, WLOG, E j1 E j2. Then α,β E j2. So define (in W) the sum α + W β as the sum α + j2 β E j2. Similarly define the product α W β as α j2 β E j2. We simply denote these elements of W as α + β and αβ. Notice that these definitions of + and in W are welldefined. If αβ E j3 then, since T is a chain, then either E j2 E j3 or E j3 E j2. In either case, the sum and product of α and β are the same fields and so + and in W is unambiguously defined. Now we verify that W is a field. We address this using the definition of a field as a commutative division ring (Definition 18.16). Since + and in W is defined using fields in chain T, then commutivity and associativity is inherited from the fields in T. For any α W, we have 0,1,α E jk for some E jk T, and so 0 + α = α + 0 = α and 1 α = α 1 = α since E jk is a field. Also, if α 0, then there is α,α 1 E jk such that α + ( α) = ( α) + α = 0 and αα 1 = α 1 α = 1. For α,β,γ W, since T is a chain, there is some E jk S such that α,β,γ E jk. then α(β + γ) = αβ + αγ since E jk is a field, and do left distribution (and hence right distribution) holds in W. So W is a field. (b) For any α W, we have α E jk for some E jk T. Since E jk is an algebraic extension of F, then α is algebraic over F. So W is an algebraic extension field of field F. Therefore, W S.

Supplement: Algebraic Closure of a Field 8 (c) By construction, E jk W for all E jk T, so W S is an upper bound for chain T. III. Showing that a maximal element of S is an algebraic closure of F. Since for arbitrary chain T in S there is an upper bound W of T with W S, then the hypotheses of Zorn s Lemma are satisfied. Therefore, Zorn s Lemma implies that there is a maximal element F of S. We now show that F is algebraically closed. Let f(x) F[x] where f(x) is a nonconstant polynomial (i.e., f(x) / F). ASSUME that f(x) has no zero in F. Then take ω Ω, where ω / F and ω is a zero of f(x), and form the field F(ω) Ω, as in Part I of the proof. Let β F(ω). Then by Theorem 30.23, β is a zero of a polynomial g(x) = α 0 + α 1 x + α 2 x 2 + + α n x n in F[x] where α i F. Since F S (the set of all algebraic extensions of F) then F is an algebraic extension of F and so each α i is algebraic over F. By Theorem 31.11 the field F(α 0,α 1,...,α n ), we also see that F(α 0,α 1,...,α n,β) is a finite extension over F(α 0,α 1,...,α n ) (again, by Theorem 31.11). In fact, by Theorem 31.4, [F(α 0, α 1,..., α n, β) : F] = [F(α 0, α 1,..., α n, β) : F(α 0, α 1,..., α n )][F(α 0, α 1,..., α n ) : F] and so F(α 0,α 1,...,α n,β) is a finite extension of F. By Theorem 31.3, F(α 0,α 1,..., α n,β) is therefore an algebraic extension of F and so β is algebraic over F. Since β F(ω) is arbitrary, then F(ω) is an algebraic extension of F and so F(ω) S. But then F < F(ω) where F(ω) S, contradicting the choice of F as a maximal element of S. Therefore, the assumption that f(x) has no zero in F[x] is false. Since f(x) F[x] is arbitrary, then we have shown that every nonconstant polynomial has a zero in F. That is, F is algebraically closed. Since F F, then F has an algebraic closure F (that is, F is an algebraically closed extension field of F).

Supplement: Algebraic Closure of a Field 9 Note. In Section 49 we will see that the algebraic closure of a field is unique in the following sense: Corollary 49.5. Let F and F be two algebraic closures of F. Then F is isomorphic to F under an isomorphism leaving each element of F fixed. Revised: 2/16/2014