From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Similar documents
Category Theory (UMV/TK/07)

MATH 101B: ALGEBRA II PART A: HOMOLOGICAL ALGEBRA

CATEGORY THEORY. Cats have been around for 70 years. Eilenberg + Mac Lane =. Cats are about building bridges between different parts of maths.

Category Theory. Categories. Definition.

A GLIMPSE OF ALGEBRAIC K-THEORY: Eric M. Friedlander

Algebraic Geometry

Cartesian Closed Topological Categories and Tensor Products

PART I. Abstract algebraic categories

Categories and functors

THE CANTOR-SCHROEDER-BERNSTEIN PROPERTY IN CATEGORIES

An introduction to locally finitely presentable categories

MATH 101: ALGEBRA I WORKSHEET, DAY #1. We review the prerequisites for the course in set theory and beginning a first pass on group. 1.

MATH 101B: ALGEBRA II PART A: HOMOLOGICAL ALGEBRA 23

Category theory for computer science. Overall idea

1 Categorical Background

LECTURE 3: RELATIVE SINGULAR HOMOLOGY

sset(x, Y ) n = sset(x [n], Y ).

arxiv: v2 [math.ct] 27 Dec 2014

Representable presheaves

Category Theory. Travis Dirle. December 12, 2017

III A Functional Approach to General Topology

Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem

Algebra Qualifying Exam Solutions January 18, 2008 Nick Gurski 0 A B C 0

FOUNDATIONS OF ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY CLASS 2

TCC Homological Algebra: Assignment #3 (Solutions)

FILTERED RINGS AND MODULES. GRADINGS AND COMPLETIONS.

A brief Introduction to Category Theory

EXAMPLES AND EXERCISES IN BASIC CATEGORY THEORY

Solutions to some of the exercises from Tennison s Sheaf Theory

Commutative Algebra Lecture 3: Lattices and Categories (Sept. 13, 2013)

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

B 1 = {B(x, r) x = (x 1, x 2 ) H, 0 < r < x 2 }. (a) Show that B = B 1 B 2 is a basis for a topology on X.

MORITA EQUIVALENCE OF MANY-SORTED ALGEBRAIC THEORIES

Spectrum (functional analysis) - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

MATH 101A: ALGEBRA I PART C: TENSOR PRODUCT AND MULTILINEAR ALGEBRA. This is the title page for the notes on tensor products and multilinear algebra.

Topos Theory. Lectures 21 and 22: Classifying toposes. Olivia Caramello. Topos Theory. Olivia Caramello. The notion of classifying topos

Enriched Categories. Stephen Fitz

A TALE OF TWO FUNCTORS. Marc Culler. 1. Hom and Tensor

1 First Theme: Sums of Squares

arxiv: v1 [math.ct] 28 Oct 2017

MTH 428/528. Introduction to Topology II. Elements of Algebraic Topology. Bernard Badzioch

A Functorial Approach to Group C -Algebras

De Rham Cohomology. Smooth singular cochains. (Hatcher, 2.1)

GALOIS CATEGORIES MELISSA LYNN

Etale cohomology of fields by Johan M. Commelin, December 5, 2013

0.1 Spec of a monoid

A note on separation and compactness in categories of convergence spaces

ABSOLUTELY PURE REPRESENTATIONS OF QUIVERS

Formal power series rings, inverse limits, and I-adic completions of rings

HSP SUBCATEGORIES OF EILENBERG-MOORE ALGEBRAS

SOME EXERCISES. This is not an assignment, though some exercises on this list might become part of an assignment. Class 2

A COURSE IN HOMOLOGICAL ALGEBRA CHAPTER 11: Auslander s Proof of Roiter s Theorem E. L. Lady (April 29, 1998)

COMMUTATIVE ALGEBRA LECTURE 1: SOME CATEGORY THEORY

7. Homotopy and the Fundamental Group

Review of category theory

CATEGORICAL GROTHENDIECK RINGS AND PICARD GROUPS. Contents. 1. The ring K(R) and the group Pic(R)

An introduction to toposes. Richard Pettigrew Department of Philosophy University of Bristol

LECTURE: KOBORDISMENTHEORIE, WINTER TERM 2011/12; SUMMARY AND LITERATURE

Groupoid Representation Theory

Injective Envelopes and Projective Covers of Quivers

Algebraic Geometry Spring 2009

Takeuchi s Free Hopf Algebra Construction Revisited

HOMOLOGY THEORIES INGRID STARKEY

EXT, TOR AND THE UCT

Algebraic Geometry Spring 2009

Lectures on Homological Algebra. Weizhe Zheng

Math 210B. Profinite group cohomology

Lecture 6: Etale Fundamental Group

A Grothendieck site is a small category C equipped with a Grothendieck topology T. A Grothendieck topology T consists of a collection of subfunctors

AMALGAMATIONS OF CATEGORIES

SECTION 2: THE COMPACT-OPEN TOPOLOGY AND LOOP SPACES

Notes on p-divisible Groups

ne varieties (continued)

3. Categories and Functors We recall the definition of a category: Definition 3.1. A category C is the data of two collections. The first collection

Reflexive cum Coreflexive Subcategories in Topology*

LOCALIZATIONS, COLOCALIZATIONS AND NON ADDITIVE -OBJECTS

are additive in each variable. Explicitly, the condition on composition means that given a diagram

Algebraic Theories of Quasivarieties

Direct Limits. Mathematics 683, Fall 2013

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

Homework 3: Relative homology and excision

1 Introduction. 2 Categories. Mitchell Faulk June 22, 2014 Equivalence of Categories for Affine Varieties

C2.7: CATEGORY THEORY

Relative Left Derived Functors of Tensor Product Functors. Junfu Wang and Zhaoyong Huang

P.S. Gevorgyan and S.D. Iliadis. 1. Introduction

Algebraic varieties. Chapter A ne varieties

Galois theory of fields

ALGEBRAIC GROUPS J. WARNER

Algebraic Topology Final

Elementary (ha-ha) Aspects of Topos Theory

Topos Theory. Lectures 17-20: The interpretation of logic in categories. Olivia Caramello. Topos Theory. Olivia Caramello.

An Algebraic View of the Relation between Largest Common Subtrees and Smallest Common Supertrees

An Axiomatic Description of a Duality for Modules

THE FUNDAMENTAL GROUP AND BROUWER S FIXED POINT THEOREM AMANDA BOWER

Exact Categories in Functional Analysis

CONTINUITY. 1. Continuity 1.1. Preserving limits and colimits. Suppose that F : J C and R: C D are functors. Consider the limit diagrams.

h M (T ). The natural isomorphism η : M h M determines an element U = η 1

Isogeny invariance of the BSD conjecture

Exercises on chapter 0

Profinite Groups. Hendrik Lenstra. 1. Introduction

Transcription:

Monomorphism - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/monomorphism 1 of 3 24/11/2012 02:01 Monomorphism From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia In the context of abstract algebra or universal algebra, a monomorphism is an injective homomorphism. A monomorphism from X to Y is often denoted with the notation. In the more general setting of category theory, a monomorphism (also called a monic morphism or a mono) is a left-cancellative morphism, that is, an arrow f : X Y such that, for all morphisms g 1, g 2 : Z X, Monomorphisms are a categorical generalization of injective functions (also called "one-to-one functions"); in some categories the notions coincide, but monomorphisms are more general, as in the examples below. The categorical dual of a monomorphism is an epimorphism, i.e. a monomorphism in a category C is an epimorphism in the dual category C op. Every section is a monomorphism, and every retraction is an epimorphism. Contents 1 Relation to invertibility 2 Examples 3 Properties 4 Related concepts 5 Terminology 6 See also 7 References Relation to invertibility Left invertible morphisms are necessarily monic: if l is a left inverse for f (meaning l is a morphism and ), then f is monic, as A left invertible morphism is called a split mono. However, a monomorphism need not be left-invertible. For example, in the category Group of all groups and group morphisms among them, if H is a subgroup of G then the inclusion f : H G is always a monomorphism; but f has a left inverse in the category if and only if H has a normal complement in G. A morphism f : X Y is monic if and only if the induced map f : Hom(Z, X) Hom(Z, Y), defined by for all morphisms h : Z X, is injective for all Z. Examples Every morphism in a concrete category whose underlying function is injective is a monomorphism; in other

Monomorphism - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/monomorphism 2 of 3 24/11/2012 02:01 words, if morphisms are actually functions between sets, then any morphism which is a one-to-one function will necessarily be a monomorphism in the categorical sense. In the category of sets the converse also holds, so the monomorphisms are exactly the injective morphisms. The converse also holds in most naturally occurring categories of algebras because of the existence of a free object on one generator. In particular, it is true in the categories of all groups, of all rings, and in any abelian category. It is not true in general, however, that all monomorphisms must be injective in other categories; that is, there are settings in which the morphisms are functions between sets, but one can have a function that is not injective and yet is a monomorphism in the categorical sense. For example, in the category Div of divisible (abelian) groups and group homomorphisms between them there are monomorphisms that are not injective: consider, for example, the quotient map q : Q Q/Z, where Q is the rationals under addition, Z the integers (also considered a group under addition), and Q/Z is the corresponding quotient group. This is not an injective map, as for example every integer is mapped to 0. Nevertheless, it is a monomorphism in this category. This will follows from the implication q h = 0 h = 0, which we now prove. If h : G Q, where G is some divisible group, and q o h = 0, then h(x) Z, x G. Now fix some x G. Without loss of generality, we may assume that h(x) 0 (otherwise, choose x instead). Then, letting n=h(x)+1, since G is a divisible group, there exists some y G such that x = ny, so h(x) = n h(y). From this, and 0 h(x) < h(x) + 1=n, it follows that Since h(y) Z, it follows that h(y) = 0, and thus h(x) = 0 = h( x), x G. This says that h = 0, as desired. To go from that implication to the fact that q is an epimorphism, assume that q o f = q o g for some morphisms f, g : G Q, where G is some divisible group. Then q o (f g) = 0, where (f g) : x f(x) g(x). (Since (f g)(0) = 0, and (f - g)(x + y) = (f - g)(x) + (f - g)(y), it follows that (f - g) Hom(G, Q)). From the implication just proved, q o (f g) = 0 f g = 0 x G, f(x) = g(x) f = g. Hence q is a monomorphism, as claimed. Properties In a topos, every monic is an equalizer, and any map that is both monic and epic is an isomorphism. Every isomorphism is monic. Related concepts There are also useful concepts of regular monomorphism, strong monomorphism, and extremal monomorphism. A regular monomorphism equalizes some parallel pair of morphisms. An extremal monomorphism is a monomorphism that cannot be nontrivially factored through an epimorphism: Precisely, if m=g e with e an epimorphism, then e is an isomorphism. A strong monomorphism satisfies a certain lifting property with respect to commutative squares involving an epimorphism. Terminology The companion terms monomorphism and epimorphism were originally introduced by Nicolas Bourbaki; Bourbaki uses monomorphism as shorthand for an injective function. Early category theorists believed that the correct generalization of injectivity to the context of categories was the cancellation property given above. While this is not exactly true for monic maps, it is very close, so this has caused little trouble, unlike the case of epimorphisms. Saunders Mac Lane attempted to make a distinction between what he called monomorphisms, which were maps in a concrete category whose underlying maps of sets were injective, and

Monomorphism - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/monomorphism 3 of 3 24/11/2012 02:01 monic maps, which are monomorphisms in the categorical sense of the word. This distinction never came into general use. Another name for monomorphism is extension, although this has other uses too. See also embedding isomorphism subobject References Francis Borceux (1994), Handbook of Categorical Algebra 1, Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-44178-1. George Bergman (1998), An Invitation to General Algebra and Universal Constructions (http://math.berkeley.edu/~gbergman/245/index.html), Henry Helson Publisher, Berkeley. ISBN 0-9655211-4-1. Jaap van Oosten, Basic Category Theory (http://www.math.uu.nl/people/jvoosten/syllabi /catsmoeder.pdf) Retrieved from "http://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=monomorphism&oldid=514268488" Categories: Morphisms This page was last modified on 24 September 2012 at 05:13. Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License; additional terms may apply. See Terms of Use for details. Wikipedia is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.

1 of 4 24/11/2012 02:02 Epimorphism From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia In category theory, an epimorphism (also called an epic morphism or, colloquially, an epi) is a morphism f : X Y which is right-cancellative in the sense that, for all morphisms g 1, g 2 : Y Z, Epimorphisms are analogues of surjective functions, but they are not exactly the same. The dual of an epimorphism is a monomorphism (i.e. an epimorphism in a category C is a monomorphism in the dual category C op ). Many authors in abstract algebra and universal algebra define an epimorphism simply as an onto or surjective homomorphism. Every epimorphism in this algebraic sense is an epimorphism in the sense of category theory, but the converse is not true in all categories. In this article, the term "epimorphism" will be used in the sense of category theory given above. For more on this, see the section on Terminology below. Contents 1 Examples 2 Properties 3 Related concepts 4 Terminology 5 See also 6 References Examples Every morphism in a concrete category whose underlying function is surjective is an epimorphism. In many concrete categories of interest the converse is also true. For example, in the following categories, the epimorphisms are exactly those morphisms which are surjective on the underlying sets: Set, sets and functions. To prove that every epimorphism f: X Y in Set is surjective, we compose it with both the characteristic function g 1 : Y {0,1} of the image f(x) and the map g 2 : Y {0,1} that is constant 1. Rel, sets with binary relations and relation preserving functions. Here we can use the same proof as for Set, equipping {0,1} with the full relation {0,1} {0,1}. Pos, partially ordered sets and monotone functions. If f : (X, ) (Y, ) is not surjective, pick y 0 in Y \ f(x) and let g 1 : Y {0,1} be the characteristic function of {y y 0 y} and g 2 : Y {0,1} the characteristic function of {y y 0 < y}. These maps are monotone if {0,1} is given the standard ordering 0 < 1. Grp, groups and group homomorphisms. The result that every epimorphism in Grp is surjective is due to Otto Schreier (he actually proved more, showing that every subgroup is an equalizer using the free product with one amalgamated subgroup); an elementary proof can be found in (Linderholm 1970). FinGrp, finite groups and group homomorphisms. Also due to Schreier; the proof given in (Linderholm 1970) establishes this case as well. Ab, abelian groups and group homomorphisms. K-Vect, vector spaces over a field K and K-linear transformations.

2 of 4 24/11/2012 02:02 Mod-R, right modules over a ring R and module homomorphisms. This generalizes the two previous examples; to prove that every epimorphism f: X Y in Mod-R is surjective, we compose it with both the canonical quotient map g 1 : Y Y/f(X) and the zero map g 2 : Y Y/f(X). Top, topological spaces and continuous functions. To prove that every epimorphism in Top is surjective, we proceed exactly as in Set, giving {0,1} the indiscrete topology which ensures that all considered maps are continuous. HComp, compact Hausdorff spaces and continuous functions. If f: X Y is not surjective, let y in Y-fX. Since fx is closed, by Urysohn's Lemma there is a continuous function g 1 :Y [0,1] such that g 1 is 0 on fx and 1 on y. We compose f with both g 1 and the zero function g 2 : Y [0,1]. However there are also many concrete categories of interest where epimorphisms fail to be surjective. A few examples are: In the category of monoids, Mon, the inclusion map N Z is a non-surjective epimorphism. To see this, suppose that g 1 and g 2 are two distinct maps from Z to some monoid M. Then for some n in Z, g 1 (n) g 2 (n), so g 1 (-n) g 2 (-n). Either n or -n is in N, so the restrictions of g 1 and g 2 to N are unequal. In the category of algebras over commutative ring R, take R[N] R[Z], where R[G] is the group ring of the group G and the morphism is induced by the inclusion N Z as in the previous example. This follows from the observation that 1 generates the algebra R[Z] (note that the unit in R[Z] is given by 0 of Z), and the inverse of the element represented by n in Z is just the element represented by -n. Thus any homomorphism from R[Z] is uniquely determined by its value on the element represented by 1 of Z. In the category of rings, Ring, the inclusion map Z Q is a non-surjective epimorphism; to see this, note that any ring homomorphism on Q is determined entirely by its action on Z, similar to the previous example. A similar argument shows that the natural ring homomorphism from any commutative ring R to any one of its localizations is an epimorphism. In the category of commutative rings, a finitely generated homomorphism of rings f : R S is an epimorphism if and only if for all prime ideals P of R, the ideal Q generated by f(p) is either S or is prime, and if Q is not S, the induced map Frac(R/P) Frac(S/Q) is an isomorphism (EGA IV 17.2.6). In the category of Hausdorff spaces, Haus, the epimorphisms are precisely the continuous functions with dense images. For example, the inclusion map Q R, is a non-surjective epimorphism. The above differs from the case of monomorphisms where it is more frequently true that monomorphisms are precisely those whose underlying functions are injective. As to examples of epimorphisms in non-concrete categories: If a monoid or ring is considered as a category with a single object (composition of morphisms given by multiplication), then the epimorphisms are precisely the right-cancellable elements. If a directed graph is considered as a category (objects are the vertices, morphisms are the paths, composition of morphisms is the concatenation of paths), then every morphism is an epimorphism. Properties Every isomorphism is an epimorphism; indeed only a right-sided inverse is needed: if there exists a morphism j : Y X such that fj = id Y, then f is easily seen to be an epimorphism. A map with such a right-sided inverse is called a split epi. In a topos, a map that is both a monic morphism and an epimorphism is an isomorphism. The composition of two epimorphisms is again an epimorphism. If the composition fg of two morphisms is an epimorphism, then f must be an epimorphism. As some of the above examples show, the property of being an epimorphism is not determined by the morphism alone, but also by the category of context. If D is a subcategory of C, then every morphism in D

3 of 4 24/11/2012 02:02 which is an epimorphism when considered as a morphism in C is also an epimorphism in D; the converse, however, need not hold; the smaller category can (and often will) have more epimorphisms. As for most concepts in category theory, epimorphisms are preserved under equivalences of categories: given an equivalence F : C D, then a morphism f is an epimorphism in the category C if and only if F(f) is an epimorphism in D. A duality between two categories turns epimorphisms into monomorphisms, and vice versa. The definition of epimorphism may be reformulated to state that f : X Y is an epimorphism if and only if the induced maps are injective for every choice of Z. This in turn is equivalent to the induced natural transformation being a monomorphism in the functor category Set C. Every coequalizer is an epimorphism, a consequence of the uniqueness requirement in the definition of coequalizers. It follows in particular that every cokernel is an epimorphism. The converse, namely that every epimorphism be a coequalizer, is not true in all categories. In many categories it is possible to write every morphism as the composition of a monomorphism followed by an epimorphism. For instance, given a group homomorphism f : G H, we can define the group K = im(f) = f(g) and then write f as the composition of the surjective homomorphism G K which is defined like f, followed by the injective homomorphism K H which sends each element to itself. Such a factorization of an arbitrary morphism into an epimorphism followed by a monomorphism can be carried out in all abelian categories and also in all the concrete categories mentioned above in the Examples section (though not in all concrete categories). Related concepts Among other useful concepts are regular epimorphism, extremal epimorphism, strong epimorphism, and split epimorphism. A regular epimorphism coequalizes some parallel pair of morphisms. An extremal epimorphism is an epimorphism that has no monomorphism as a second factor, unless that monomorphism is an isomorphism. A strong epimorphism satisfies a certain lifting property with respect to commutative squares involving a monomorphism. A split epimorphism is a morphism which has a right-sided inverse. A morphism that is both a monomorphism and an epimorphism is called a bimorphism. Every isomorphism is a bimorphism but the converse is not true in general. For example, the map from the half-open interval [0,1) to the unit circle S 1 (thought of as a subspace of the complex plane) which sends x to exp(2πix) (see Euler's formula) is continuous and bijective but not a homeomorphism since the inverse map is not continuous at 1, so it is an instance of a bimorphism that is not an isomorphism in the category Top. Another example is the embedding Q R in the category Haus; as noted above, it is a bimorphism, but it is not bijective and therefore not an isomorphism. Similarly, in the category of rings, the maps Z Q and Q R are bimorphisms but not isomorphisms. Epimorphisms are used to define abstract quotient objects in general categories: two epimorphisms f 1 : X Y 1 and f 2 : X Y 2 are said to be equivalent if there exists an isomorphism j : Y 1 Y 2 with j f 1 = f 2. This is an equivalence relation, and the equivalence classes are defined to be the quotient objects of X.

4 of 4 24/11/2012 02:02 Terminology The companion terms epimorphism and monomorphism were first introduced by Bourbaki. Bourbaki uses epimorphism as shorthand for a surjective function. Early category theorists believed that epimorphisms were the correct analogue of surjections in an arbitrary category, similar to how monomorphisms are very nearly an exact analogue of injections. Unfortunately this is incorrect; strong or regular epimorphisms behave much more closely to surjections than ordinary epimorphisms. Saunders Mac Lane attempted to create a distinction between epimorphisms, which were maps in a concrete category whose underlying set maps were surjective, and epic morphisms, which are epimorphisms in the modern sense. However, this distinction never caught on. It is a common mistake to believe that epimorphisms are either identical to surjections or that they are a better concept. Unfortunately this is rarely the case; epimorphisms can be very mysterious and have unexpected behavior. It is very difficult, for example, to classify all the epimorphisms of rings. In general, epimorphisms are their own unique concept, related to surjections but fundamentally different. See also List of category theory topics References Adámek, Jiří, Herrlich, Horst, & Strecker, George E. (1990). Abstract and Concrete Categories (http://katmat.math.uni-bremen.de/acc/acc.pdf) (4.2MB PDF). Originally publ. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 0-471-60922-6. (now free on-line edition) Bergman, George M. (1998), An Invitation to General Algebra and Universal Constructions, Harry Helson Publisher, Berkeley. ISBN 0-9655211-4-1. Linderholm, Carl (1970). A Group Epimorphism is Surjective. American Mathematical Monthly 77, pp. 176 177. Proof summarized by Arturo Magidin in [1] (http://groups.google.com/group/sci.math /msg/6d4023d93a2b4300). Lawvere & Rosebrugh: Sets for Mathematics, Cambridge university press, 2003. ISBN 0-521-80444-2. Retrieved from "http://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=epimorphism&oldid=520188681" Categories: Morphisms This page was last modified on 28 October 2012 at 00:21. Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License; additional terms may apply. See Terms of Use for details. Wikipedia is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.