Where is quantum theory headed?

Similar documents
The Measurement Problem

The Foundations of Quantum Mechanics and The Limitations of Human Being

Evidence and Theory in Physics. Tim Maudlin, NYU Evidence in the Natural Sciences, May 30, 2014

Quantum Mechanics: Interpretation and Philosophy

Master Projects (EPFL) Philosophical perspectives on the exact sciences and their history

Cosmology Lecture 2 Mr. Kiledjian

Relational Causality and Classical Probability: Grounding Quantum Phenomenology in a Superclassical Theory

Identical Particles in Quantum Mechanics

From Bohmian Mechanics to Bohmian Quantum Gravity. Antonio Vassallo Instytut Filozofii UW Section de Philosophie UNIL

09a. Collapse. Recall: There are two ways a quantum state can change: 1. In absence of measurement, states change via Schrödinger dynamics:

The subquantum arrow of time

Bell s Theorem. Ben Dribus. June 8, Louisiana State University

Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox and Bell s inequalities

David Bohm s Hidden Variables

Quantum Entanglement. Chapter Introduction. 8.2 Entangled Two-Particle States

Outline. What does Quantum Mechanics Tell us about Time? Classical Mechanics in a Nutshell. Classical Mechanics in a Nutshell

Closing the Debates on Quantum Locality and Reality: EPR Theorem, Bell's Theorem, and Quantum Information from the Brown-Twiss Vantage

Hiding a collapse mechanism inside the standard model

Double slit questions

On the origin of probability in quantum mechanics

1.1.1 Bell Inequality - Spin correlation

EPR Paradox and Bell s Inequality

Statistical Mechanics

What does Quantum Mechanics Tell us about Time?

Hugh Everett III s Many Worlds

Why we need quantum gravity and why we don t have it

arxiv: v4 [quant-ph] 26 Oct 2017

Review of the Formalism of Quantum Mechanics

Is quantum linear superposition exact on all energy scales? A unique case study with flavour oscillating systems

A very efficient two-density approach to atomistic simulations and a proof of principle for small atoms and molecules

Problems with/failures of QM

The Measurement Problem of Quantum Mechanics Click to edit Master title style. Wells Wulsin SASS 24 September 2008

GRW Theory (Ghirardi, Rimini, Weber Model of Quantum Mechanics)

arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 30 Oct 2012

Experiments testing macroscopic quantum superpositions must be slow

The hybrid-epistemic model of quantum mechanics and the solution to the measurement problem

Advanced Quantum Mechanics, Notes based on online course given by Leonard Susskind - Lecture 8

Quantum mechanics in one hour

228 My God - He Plays Dice! Schrödinger s Cat. Chapter 28. This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/problems/scrodingerscat

The nature of Reality: Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument in QM

226 My God, He Plays Dice! Entanglement. Chapter This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/problems/entanglement

Coins and Counterfactuals

On the Present Status of Quantum Mechanics

Models of spontaneous wave function collapse: what they are, and how they can be tested.

QFT. Unit 1: Relativistic Quantum Mechanics

Stochastic Histories. Chapter Introduction

EPR Paradox and Bell Inequalities

INTRODUCTORY NOTES ON QUANTUM COMPUTATION

Walking on quantum foundations

Logical difficulty from combining counterfactuals in the GHZ-Bell theorems

The Postulates of Quantum Mechanics Common operators in QM: Potential Energy. Often depends on position operator: Kinetic Energy 1-D case: 3-D case

Finite Ring Geometries and Role of Coupling in Molecular Dynamics and Chemistry

G : Quantum Mechanics II

1 Introduction. 1.1 Stuff we associate with quantum mechanics Schrödinger s Equation

3 Bananaworld. 3.1 Einstein Podolsky Rosen bananas

Measurement: still a problem in standard quantum theory

HSSP Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics 08/07/11 Lecture Notes

Modern Physics notes Spring 2007 Paul Fendley Lecture 27

Extending the 4 4 Darbyshire Operator Using n-dimensional Dirac Matrices

No Fine theorem for macroscopic realism

2.1 Half-Silvered Mirror Experiment 1

Honors 225 Physics Study Guide/Chapter Summaries for Final Exam; Roots Chapters 15-18

Introduction to Quantum Computing

3. Quantum Mechanics in 3D

Time in Bohmian Mechanics

Modern Physics for Frommies V Gravitation Lecture 8

QUANTUM MECHANICS. Franz Schwabl. Translated by Ronald Kates. ff Springer

1 1D Schrödinger equation: Particle in an infinite box

Gedankenexperimente werden Wirklichkeit The strange features of quantum mechanics in the light of modern experiments

Models in condensed matter physics

1 1D Schrödinger equation: Particle in an infinite box

Droplets and atoms. Benjamin Schumacher Department of Physics Kenyon College. Bright Horizons 35 (July, 2018)

General Physical Chemistry II

When I hear of Schrödinger s cat, I reach for my gun. --Stephen W. Hawking. Lecture 21, p 1

Does Quantum Measurement Violate the Conservation of Angular Momentum? A Paradox Resolved Rick Bradford, 6/12/16

Brownian Motion and The Atomic Theory

Comment on a Proposed Super-Kamiokande Test for Quantum Gravity Induced Decoherence Effects

Attempts at relativistic QM

Lecture 21: Lasers, Schrödinger s Cat, Atoms, Molecules, Solids, etc. Review and Examples. Lecture 21, p 1

3/10/11. Which interpreta/on sounds most reasonable to you? PH300 Modern Physics SP11

Introduction to Bell s theorem: the theory that solidified quantum mechanics

arxiv: v1 [gr-qc] 17 Jan 2019

Quantum Mechanics C (130C) Winter 2014 Final exam

For the seminar: Ausgewählte Probleme der Quantenmechanik Faculty of Physics, University of Vienna, WS 2011/2012 Christian Knobloch a

Finite Automata, Random Fields, Quantum Fluctuations, and Bell Inequalities

De-coherence and transition from Quantum to Classical

Writing-Intensive Quantum Mechanics

The Search for a Fundamental Theory of the Universe

Brownian Motion and Langevin Equations

The Klein Gordon Equation

Quantum Mechanics: Stranger than we can imagine?

Physics 115A: Statistical Physics

Angular momentum and spin

Stern-Gerlach Experiment and Spin

Lecture 4. QUANTUM MECHANICS FOR MULTIPLE QUBIT SYSTEMS

No Fine Theorem for Macrorealism

The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics (Handout Eight) between the microphysical and the macrophysical. The macrophysical world could be understood

What is spin? Thomas Pope and Werner Hofer. School of Chemistry Newcastle University. Web: wernerhofer.eu

What is wrong with the standard formulation of quantum theory?

CURRICULUM COURSE OUTLINE

Transcription:

Where is quantum theory headed? Stephen L. Adler January 5, 2014 arxiv

Abstract Public talk at the EmQM13 conference opening event on The Future of Quantum Mechanics The organizers have asked me to state my views on the direction of the future development of quantum mechanics. Will it evolve within the standard framework, without the addition of new foundational physics? Or will the foundations require modification in an, at least in principle, experimentally detectable way? First, let s discuss the current status of quantum theory. Quantum mechanics is our most successful physical theory. It underlies our detailed understanding of atomic physics, chemistry, and nuclear physics, and the many technologies based on this knowledge. Additionally, relativistic quantum mechanics is the basis for the very successful standard model of elementary particles. However, from its beginnings there have been conceptual problems associated with the nature of measurement in quantum mechanics. These can be simply illustrated with the famous Stern-Gerlach experiment (Fig. 1). Stern-Gerlach Experiment Figure 1: Schematic representation of the Stern-Gerlach experiment Silver atoms boiled off from a furnace are sent through a non-uniform magnetic field, and impinge on a photographic plate. Instead of a continuous distribution of spots, one sees two spots, corresponding to spin up and spin down relative to the magnetic field axis. Each atom goes up OR down, but

one cannot predict which in any given run - the results of the experiment are probabilistic. There is a 50% chance of an atom going up, and a 50% chance that it will go down. From the point of view of the Schrödinger equation of quantum theory, this result has no explanation. In quantum theory, the state of the particle is described by its wave function, and the Schrödinger equation says that at a post-measurement final time T f, the wave function is related to that at a pre-measurement initial time T i, by a deterministic relation Ψ(T f ) = U(T f, T i )Ψ(T i ) U(T f, T i ) = e ih(t f T i ) with the transition operator U completely specified by the Hamiltonian H. To explain what is observed, the Schrödinger equation must be supplemented by the reduction postulate and the Born rule. These state that the wave function only gives a description of probabilities when a measurement is made, with the probabilities for an up outcome and a down outcome given by the squares of the coefficients of the corresponding components in the initial wave function Ψ(T i ), Born Rule for Probabilities Ψ(T i ) = C up Ψ up + C down Ψ down prob up = C up 2 prob down = C down 2 C up 2 + C down 2 = 1 with the sum of the up and down probabilities equal to one. The reduction postulate and Born rule are an add-on to the Schrödinger equation. According to the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics, the Schrödinger equation applies when a microscopic system, the silver atom, is time-evolving in isolation. But when the atom interacts with a macroscopic measuring apparatus, as in the Stern-Gerlach setup, you have to use the reduction postulate and Born rule. This situation leads to puzzles that have been debated for over eighty years. If quantum mechanics describes the whole universe, then why can t one use the Schrödinger equation to describe the system consisting of the silver atom 2

plus the measuring apparatus? But we never see a superposition state of the atom plus apparatus. This is Schrödinger s famous cat paradox. Arrange the experiment so that an up outcome triggers a mechanism that kills the cat, while a down outcome keeps the cat alive. Of course we don t do this, but if we were to do it, we would always see a live cat OR a dead one, never a superposition of the two (Fig. 2). Stern-Gerlach Experiment Figure 2: The Stern-Gerlach experiment with a Schrödinger cat as the outcome registration So we have the problem of definite outcomes: where does the either - or dichotomy arise? A related question is where do the probabilities come from? Quantum mechanics has probabilities without a sample space! An example of a sample space is a population of people, 40% blonde and 60% brunette. If you pick a person at random from the population, there is a probability prob blonde = 0.4 that you will have a blonde, and prob brunette = 0.6 that you will have a brunette. But the population (the sample space) is composed of individuals, with definite hair coloring - the probabilities only reflect our ignorance of details if we make a random pick without looking. Another example of a sample space, closer to our Stern-Gerlach experiment, is a coin toss. Consider 1000 coin tosses. If the coin is tossed without bias, you will find close to 500 heads and 500 tails, corresponding to prob heads = 0.5 and prob tails = 0.5. Here the sample space consists of the 1000 detailed trajectories of the toss, 3

which your eye cannot follow, but which if analyzed by a very fast computer could predict which toss would give a head and which a tail (Fig. 3). Sample Space Figure 3: Some sample spaces: (a) Populations of individuals with blonde/brunette hair coloring (b) Trajectories in a coin toss Again, the probabilities are just reflections of our ignorance of the details, but the details are there. So we have the questions - are there hidden details underlying the probabilities in quantum mechanics? Is there a hidden sample space? Now we come to the question with which I began - where is future work to deal with these problems headed? Two routes proceed within quantum theory: (i) The first route within quantum theory is to try to change the interpretational rules. Examples are the so-called many worlds interpretation (all possibilities are there, we just only see one), and the so-called histories program, which sets up an observer-free generalization of the Copenhagen rules. (ii) The second route within quantum theory is to say there is a sample space, but we don?t see it. One example is the proposal of Bohmian trajectories as the sample space underlying the Born rule. Another example comprises 4

various statistical interpretations, which attribute the probabilistic outcomes to different internal states of the apparatus and or its environment, with the aim of deriving the Born rule. None of these routes within orthodox quantum theory has gained general acceptance. Also, none makes experimental predictions at odds with standard theory, so experimentally they are not distinguishable. The other possibility is to modify the foundations of quantum theory. Specifically, one gets a sample space by postulating additional degrees of freedom - so called hidden variables. There are two possibilities for hidden variables? they can be local, or nonlocal. Local variables have the property that variables V (x 1, t 1 ) and W (x 2, t 2 ), with x 1, x 2 the spatial points and t 1, t 2 the times of occurrence, cannot influence one another if the distance between them x 1 x 2 is greater than the distance c t 1 t 2 that light can travel, at velocity c, in the time interval from t 1 to t 2. Such local variables are called causally separated. In quantum theory, causally separated variables have a commutative multiplication law V (x 1, t 1 ) W (x 2, t 2 ) = W (x 2, t 2 ) V (x 1, t 1 ) Ordinary numbers obey such a commutative law of multiplication, for example AB = BA for A = 7 and B = 11, whereas in non-commutative multiplication, one would have AB BA. John Bell s theorem asserts that local hidden variables plus the usual rules for probabilities imply certain inequalities that are not satisfied by quantum mechanical systems - and experiment sees that these inequalities are in fact violated. There is much discussion of possible loopholes, but I believe the result is robust, and that local hidden variables are excluded. The other possibility is that the hidden variables are non-local: the hidden variables can act faster than the speed of light to establish correlations (as long as no faster than light signaling is possible). The hidden variables can also obey a non-commutative multiplication law. For the rest of the talk I ll focus on the possibility of non-local hidden variables - this is where my research interests lie. At a phenomenological level, there are very interesting models for the emergence of probabilities within the 5

usual wave function formulation of nonrelativistic quantum theory, pioneered by Ghirardi, Rimini, and Weber in Trieste and by also by Pearle at Hamilton College in the U. S., and worked on by many others. These models postulate that space is filled with a very low level noise with a coupling to matter proportional to the imaginary unit i, rather than with a real-valued coupling (more technically, they couple through an anti-hermitian Hamiltonian term). For example, there could be a small, rapidly fluctuating contribution to the gravitational potential or g 00 metric component proportional to the imaginary unit i. If such a theory obeys two general properties, (1) the total probability of a particle being present remains one for all times (that is, the wave function normalization is preserved), and (2) there is no faster than light signaling, then the extra terms in the Schrödinger equation equation must have a special structure. This special structure allows one to prove definite outcomes obeying the Born rule! In these models, for each repetition of the Stern?Gerlach experiment, the noise variable takes different values. For a large apparatus, these have a measurable effect, whereas for an atom not interacting with an apparatus, the effect is not measurable. The noise leads to different outcomes for different runs, with probabilities given by the Born rule. The different noises for different runs of the experiment are analogous, in the coin toss example I gave earlier, to different details of the tumbling coin trajectories for the different coin tosses (Fig. 4). Figure 4: Different noise histories, in objective reduction models, can explain up and down registrations in the Stern?Gerlach experiment 6

I ve worked on phenomenological reduction models, but my main long term interest has been at the foundational level. I am trying to make an analogy between quantum mechanics emerging from a possible pre-quantum theory, and the known fact that thermodynamics emerges from the laws of statistical mechanics. Thermodynamics - the science of heat and work (Fig. 5) - reflects averaged properties of huge numbers of atoms. Figure 5: (a) Thermodynamics: the science of heat and work (b) Brownian motion of a pollen grain being bombarded by molecules in the liquid in which it is suspended It is a complete, consistent system by itself, and remarkably was discovered in the 19th century before the existence of atoms was established. But from statistical mechanics - the laws of motion of large systems of atoms, one can deduce the laws of thermodynamics, together with details of fluctuation corrections to thermodynamics, so called Brownian motion corrections. (The figure shows the random walk trajectory of a pollen grain being bombarded by molecules in thermal motion.) My suggestion, in articles with collaborators and a small book that I wrote 7

in 2004 [1], is a theory that I call trace dynamics. It is a classical-like system of non-commutating variables - even distant systems in the universe are interacting instantaneously with us. One can make sense of the mathematics of non-commuting variables by using the cyclic property of a mathematical operation called the Trace: Trace ABCD..F G = Trace GABCD..F = Trace F GABCD.. This is a very powerful tool. One can use it to set up a system of equations analogous to classical mechanics, and to do statistical averaging. Getting a little technical now, for those in the audience familiar with quantum theory and statistical physics, what distinguishes trace dynamics from ordinary classical mechanics is the existence of a generic conserved quantity in addition to the energy and momentum. This quantity is operator-valued, and has the form Conserved operator in trace dynamics = [q boson p boson p boson q boson ] bosons [q fermion p fermion + p fermion q fermion ] fermions with the qs he canonical coordinates and the ps the canonical momenta. This is reminiscent in structure to the canonical commutation and anticommutation relations of quantum theory. Just as energy in statistical mechanics is equally partitioned between the various degrees of freedom, one might expect this conserved operator, in a statistical mechanical treatment of trace dynamics, to also be equi-partitioned, giving the starting point for quantum theory. My conjectures thus are: statistical averages in trace dynamics give the Schrödinger equation and operator algebra of quantum theory, while Brownian motion corrections give the low level noise on which phenomenological reduction models are based. I talked about this program in my keynote address at the Vienna conference two years ago. Currently I am working on incorporating gravity into trace dynamics [2], and that is what I will talk about tomorrow. My approach to an emergent quantum theory is still a work in progress - there is much yet to be done! Acknowledgments I wish to thank Gerhard Grössing for organizing the conference EmQM13 on Emergent Quantum Mechanics, the Fetzer Franklin fund for its financial support, and Susan Higgins for redrawing my figure sketches for publication. 8

References [1 ] S.L. Adler Quantum Theory as an Emergent Phenomenon: The Statistical Mechanics of Matrix Models as the Precursor of Quantum Field Theory, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2004). [2 ] S. L. Adler, Incorporating gravity into trace dynamics: the induced gravitational action, arxiv:1306.0482, Class. Quantum Grav. 30 (2013) 195015 and Class. Quantum Grav. 30 (2013) 239501 (Erratum); S. L. Adler and F. R. Ramazanoǧlu, Spherically symmetric vacuum solutions arising from trace dynamics modifications to gravitation, arxiv:1308.1448. 9