"PRINCIPLES OF PHYLOGENETICS: ECOLOGY AND EVOLUTION" Integrative Biology 200B Spring 2011 University of California, Berkeley

Similar documents
Integrative Biology 200A "PRINCIPLES OF PHYLOGENETICS" Spring 2012 University of California, Berkeley

The Origin of Species

UON, CAS, DBSC, General Biology II (BIOL102) Dr. Mustafa. A. Mansi. The Origin of Species

SPECIATION. REPRODUCTIVE BARRIERS PREZYGOTIC: Barriers that prevent fertilization. Habitat isolation Populations can t get together

Speciation. Today s OUTLINE: Mechanisms of Speciation. Mechanisms of Speciation. Geographic Models of speciation. (1) Mechanisms of Speciation

Bio 1B Lecture Outline (please print and bring along) Fall, 2008

Speciation. Today s OUTLINE: Mechanisms of Speciation. Mechanisms of Speciation. Geographic Models of speciation. (1) Mechanisms of Speciation

Unfortunately, there are many definitions Biological Species: species defined by Morphological Species (Morphospecies): characterizes species by

Speciation. Today s OUTLINE: Mechanisms of Speciation. Mechanisms of Speciation. Geographic Models of speciation. (1) Mechanisms of Speciation

GENETICS - CLUTCH CH.22 EVOLUTIONARY GENETICS.

The Origin of Species

Conceptually, we define species as evolutionary units :

5/31/17. Week 10; Monday MEMORIAL DAY NO CLASS. Page 88

ESS 345 Ichthyology. Systematic Ichthyology Part II Not in Book

How Biological Diversity Evolves

Chapter 17A. Table of Contents. Section 1 Categories of Biological Classification. Section 2 How Biologists Classify Organisms

Microevolutionary changes show us how populations change over time. When do we know that distinctly new species have evolved?

The Origin of Species

--Therefore, congruence among all postulated homologies provides a test of any single character in question [the central epistemological advance].

The Origin of Species

Chapter 27: Evolutionary Genetics

Chapter 14 The Origin of Species

The Origin of Species

EVOLUTION Unit 1 Part 9 (Chapter 24) Activity #13

NOTES CH 24: The Origin of Species

Outline. Classification of Living Things

4/4/2017. Extrinsic Isolating Barriers. 1. Biological species concept: 2. Phylogenetic species concept:

Speciation Plant Sciences, 2001Updated: June 1, 2012 Gale Document Number: GALE CV

Using Trees for Classifications. Introduction

Speciation and Patterns of Evolution

"PRINCIPLES OF PHYLOGENETICS: ECOLOGY AND EVOLUTION" Integrative Biology 200B Spring 2011 University of California, Berkeley

Lecture V Phylogeny and Systematics Dr. Kopeny

Biology 211 (2) Week 1 KEY!

Economic Evolutionary Domain (Macroevolution)

Wake Acceleration Academy - Biology Note Guide Unit 6: Evolution & The Diversity of Life

The Origin of Species

Phylogeny and systematics. Why are these disciplines important in evolutionary biology and how are they related to each other?

The Origin of Species

Species Are Not Uniquely Real Biological Entities

Historical Biogeography. Historical Biogeography. Systematics

These next few slides correspond with 23.4 in your book. Specifically follow along on page Use your book and it will help you!

In R. Wilson (ed.), Species: New Interdisciplinary Essays, pp MIT Press Getting Rid of Species? Brent D. Mishler

The Origin of Species

8/23/2014. Phylogeny and the Tree of Life

Evolutionary Patterns, Rates, and Trends

The units of phylogenetic analysis. Species and speciation

Biology Eighth Edition Neil Campbell and Jane Reece

1/30/2012. Review. Speciation and macroevolution - Chapter

Processes of Evolution

Integrative Biology 200A "PRINCIPLES OF PHYLOGENETICS" Spring 2012 University of California, Berkeley

Announcements: 1. Labs meet this week 2. Lab manuals have been ordered 3. Some slides from each lecture will be on the web 4. Study questions will be

Classification and Phylogeny

The Nature of Species. The Origin of Species. The Nature of Species. The Nature of Species. The Biological Species Concept

Chapter 26: Phylogeny and the Tree of Life Phylogenies Show Evolutionary Relationships

Classification, Phylogeny yand Evolutionary History

EVOLUTION. Evolution - changes in allele frequency in populations over generations.

Chapter 14 The Origin of Species

Fig. 26.7a. Biodiversity. 1. Course Outline Outcomes Instructors Text Grading. 2. Course Syllabus. Fig. 26.7b Table

Classification and Phylogeny

Saturday, August 24, Speciation

Northwestern Garter Snake (Thamnophis. ordinoides)

Ch. 24 The Origin of Species

AP Biology Notes Outline Enduring Understanding 1.C. Big Idea 1: The process of evolution drives the diversity and unity of life.

How Species Form. 4.3 How Species Form. Reproductive Isolation

Adaptation. Adaptation describes any trait that enhances an organisms fitness or increases its chance of survival.

Branches in the lines of descent: Charles Darwin and the evolution of the species concept

Chapter 22: Descent with Modification 1. BRIEFLY summarize the main points that Darwin made in The Origin of Species.

Charles Darwin ( ) Sailed around the world

Life Sciences For NET & SLET Exams Of UGC-CSIR. Section B and C. Volume-16. Contents A. PRINCIPLES AND METHODS OF TAXONOMY 1

Lecture 11 Friday, October 21, 2011

Part 1: Types of Speciation

BIO 1130FF. An introduction to Organismal biology Midterm examination Worth either 15% or 20% of your final grade. Saturday, October 3, 2015

Lecture #4 evening (4pm) 1/25/02 Dr. Kopeny

Name 14 The Origin of Species Test Date Study Guide You must know: The difference between microevolution and macroevolution. The biological concept

5/31/2012. Speciation and macroevolution - Chapter

Phylogenetic Analysis

Phylogenetic Analysis

Phylogenetic Analysis

Integrative Biology 200A "PRINCIPLES OF PHYLOGENETICS" Spring 2012 University of California, Berkeley

Chapter 10. Classification and Phylogeny of Animals. Order in Diversity. Hierarchy of taxa. Table Linnaeus introduced binomial nomenclature

The practice of naming and classifying organisms is called taxonomy.

SPECIATION. SPECIATION The process by which once species splits into two or more species

MODELS OF SPECIATION. Sympatric Speciation: MODEL OF SYMPATRIC SPECIATION. Speciation without restriction to gene flow.

Integrative Biology 200 "PRINCIPLES OF PHYLOGENETICS" Spring 2018 University of California, Berkeley

The theory of evolution continues to be refined as scientists learn new information.

Name: Class: Date: ID: A

The Life System and Environmental & Evolutionary Biology II

Need for systematics. Applications of systematics. Linnaeus plus Darwin. Approaches in systematics. Principles of cladistics

Big Idea #1: The process of evolution drives the diversity and unity of life

Biologists use a system of classification to organize information about the diversity of living things.

Chapters Objectives

Biology 2. Lecture Material. For. Macroevolution. Systematics

Anthro 101: Human Biological Evolution. Lecture 6: Macroevolution & Speciation. Prof. Kenneth Feldmeier feldmekj.weebly.com

Major questions of evolutionary genetics. Experimental tools of evolutionary genetics. Theoretical population genetics.

Chapter 26. Phylogeny and the Tree of Life. Lecture Presentations by Nicole Tunbridge and Kathleen Fitzpatrick Pearson Education, Inc.

9.3 Classification. Lesson Objectives. Vocabulary. Introduction. Linnaean Classification

Reproduction and Evolution Practice Exam

Chapter 5 Evolution of Biodiversity. Sunday, October 1, 17

Classification Systems. - Taxonomy

Unit 9: Evolution Guided Reading Questions (80 pts total)

Transcription:

"PRINCIPLES OF PHYLOGENETICS: ECOLOGY AND EVOLUTION" Integrative Biology 200B Spring 2011 University of California, Berkeley B.D. Mishler March 29, 2011. "Speciation" (diversification) and related issues: species revisited I. Species A. Different approaches: a. typological or essentialist approach (i.e., systematics through Linnaeus) b. phenetic, morphological, or "natural" approach - older botanists (Gray, Bentham, Hooker) plus many recent botanists (Cronquist, Levin, Sokal & Crovello) - some recent cladists (!) (Nelson & Platnick, Cracraft, Nixon & Wheeler) c. "biological" species concept: interbreeding groups - classic isolation approach (most zoologists, e.g., Mayr, Dobzhansky) - newer recognition approach (some zoologists, see Paterson) d. "evolutionary" species concept: lineages (Simpson, Wiley, De Quieroz) e. "ecological" species concept: niches (Van Valen) f. "species as individual": integrated, cohesive units with spatio-temporal boundaries (Ghiselin, Hull) g. "phylogenetic" species concept: basal monophyletic groups (more below) B. Reason for the existence of a species problem: a. most of the above concepts and criteria conflict in most real cases -- different concepts (and processes) "pick out" different groups in each particular case, thus the implied correspondence between different criteria relied on by the BSC (and phenetic concepts) is abundantly falsified. b. operationality -- how to apply various concepts in a practical sense. c. what causes integration/cohesion of species? -- concerns: - breeding relationships are often clinal and/or non-transitive (what does "potential" interbreeding mean?) - gene flow is often very limited or lacking (what causes the evident distinctness of many asexual species?) - what is a niche? - developmental constraints (phylogenetic inertia)? C. A Phylogenetic Solution: Recognize that there is no species problem per se in systematics. Rather, there is a taxon problem. Once one has decided what taxon names are to represent in general, then species taxa should be the same kind of things -- just the least inclusive. There is an element of arbitrariness to the formal Linnaean nomenclatorial system. Evolution is real, as are organisms (physiological units), lineages (phylogenetic units), and demes (interbreeding units) for example. On the other hand, our classification systems are obviously human constructs, meant to serve certain purposes of our own: communication, data storage and retrieval, predictivity. These purposes are best served by classification systems that reflect our best understanding of natural processes of evolution, and the field of systematics in general has settled on restricting the use of formal taxonomic names to represent phylogenetically natural, monophyletic groups.

Grouping vs. ranking. There are two necessary parts to any species definition. The criteria by which organisms are grouped into taxa must be specified, as well as the criteria by which a taxon is ranked as a species rather than some other hierarchical level. Following the arguments given previously supporting a Hennigian phylogenetic system of classification, the grouping criterion that should be used is monophyly. Under this view, apomorphies are considered to be the necessary empirical evidence for unambiguous phylogenetic species, as for phylogenetic taxa at all levels. There are difficulties applying the concept of monophyly at this level. As you consider less inclusive levels in the genealogical hierarchy there is an increasing probability that reticulating ("hybridizing") events will occur, rather than the diverging phylogenetic relationships assumed by the cladistic approach. However, the problem of reticulation is not specific to the species level; indeed reticulation can occur throughout the hierarchy of life, and so is one of more general difficulty, and one that is receiving a lot of attention in the professional literature. It is becoming clear that while a certain amount of reticulation does not preclude cladistic reconstructions of phylogeny, extensive reticulation can cause major problems (more next lecture). Note in passing that reproductive criteria cannot be used to group organisms into phylogenetic species. The fundamental inappropriateness of using breeding compatibility in cladistic analysis is because the ability to interbreed (potential or actual), is a plesiomorphy by definition, thus not a phylogenetically valid grouping criterion. The ranking decision should involve practical criteria such as the amount of character support for a group and may also involve biological criteria in better known organisms, including reproductive criteria, e.g., the origin of a distinctive mating system at a particular node or the acquisition of exclusivity (a condition in which each allele in a lineage is more closely related to another allele in the lineage than it is to an allele outside the lineage). This ranking decision is forced because systematists have legislatively constrained themselves to use a ranked Linnaean hierarchy. A larger issue are recent calls for reforming the Linnaean system to remove the concept of ranks. This move would keep the hierarchy of named phylogenetic groups, but remove the ranks (including species) associated with the names (more below). This move would decrease the arbitrariness of ranking decisions at the "species level," but at the moment we assume that the current Linnaean system of ranked classifications is to remain in place. To summarize, assuming the current codes of nomenclature, a phylogenetic species concept can be defined. First, organisms should be grouped into species on the basis of evidence for monophyly, as at all taxonomic levels; breeding criteria in particular have no business being used for grouping purposes. Second, ranking criteria used to assign species rank to certain monophyletic groups must vary among different organisms, but might well include ecological criteria or presence of breeding barriers in particular cases (Mishler & Brandon 1987). The Phylogenetic Species Concept: A species is the least inclusive taxon recognized in a formal phylogenetic classification. As with all hierarchical levels of taxa in such a classification, organisms are grouped into species because of evidence of monophyly. Taxa are ranked as species rather than at some higher level because they are the smallest monophyletic groups deemed worthy of formal recognition, because of the amount of support for their monophyly and/or their importance in biological processes operating on the lineage in question.

Some elaboration of the term monophyly from this definition is needed. Monophyly is here defined synchronically to be: all and only descendants of a common ancestor, existing in any one slice in time. This ancestor was not an ancestral species, but rather a less inclusive entity such as an organism, kin group or population. The synchronic approach is necessary to avoid the time paradoxes that arise when classifying ancestors with descendants [i.e., questions like: Was your grandmother your grandmother before your parents were born?]. The evidence required for a hypothesis of monophyly is primarily corroborated patterns of synapomorphy (but possibly also including other factors, such as geography). II. Wave of the future: phylogenetic taxonomy A number of recent calls have been made for the reformation of the Linnaean hierarchy (e.g., De Queiroz & Gauthier, 1992). These authors have emphasized that the existing system is based in a non-evolutionary world-view; the roots of the Linnaean hierarchy are a speciallycreated world-view. Perhaps the idea of fixed ranks made some sense under that view, but under an evolutionary world view they don't make sense. Most aspects of the current code, including priority, revolve around the ranks, which leads to instability of usage. For example, when a change in relationships is discovered, several names often need to be changed to adjust, including those of groups whose circumscription has not changed. Frivolous changes in names often occur when authors merely change the rank of a group without any change in postulated relationships. While practicing systematists know that groups given the same rank across biology are not comparable in any way (i.e., in age, size, amount of divergence, diversity within, etc.), many users do not know this. For example, ecologists and macroevolutionists often count numbers of taxa at a particular rank as an erroneous measure of "biodiversity." The nonequivalence of ranks means that at best (to those who are knowledgeable) they are a meaningless formality and perhaps not more than a hindrance. At worst, in the hands of a user of classifications who naively assumes groups at the same rank are comparable in some way, formal ranks lead to bad science. It is not completely clear at this point how exactly a new code of nomenclature should be written (see draft at: http://www.ohiou.edu/phylocode/index.html), but the basics are clear. Such a new code should maintain the principle of priority (the first name for a lineage should be followed) and other aspects of the current code that promote effective communication of new names to the community. However, the major change would be that the Linnaean ranks should be abandoned, for efficient and accurate representation of phylogenetic relationships. Instead, names of clades should be hierarchically nested uninomials regarded as proper names. A clade

would retain its name regardless of where new knowledge might change its phylogenetic position, thus increasing nomenclatorial stability. Furthermore, since clade names would be presented to the community without attached ranks, users would be encouraged to look at the actual attributes of the clades they compare, thus improving research in comparative biology. What about the species rank? The most controversial level of all, but the above arguments can be applied to the species rank just as well as to higher levels. In my opinion, this rank need to be eliminated as well. Below is how it could be done in practice; we will keep returning to this subject later in the semester, in terms of its implications. How could rank-free classification be applied to terminal taxa? Names of clades (including the terminal level), should be hierarchically nested uninomials regarded as proper names (current usage should be followed as much as possible to retain links to the literature). As at all taxonomic levels, use node-based names with two or more internal type specimens. All the higher clades to which a taxon belongs should be regarded as part of its complete name. Therefore each clade has a uninomial given name, but also a set of more and more inclusive family names. Homonyms can thus be told apart by higher level clade names. Recommendations: Don't use taxonomic ranks, including species, for comparative purposes or ecological/evolutionary inferences. Do use trees, branching events (represented by monophyletic taxa), and branch lengths for comparative purposes and ecological/evolutionary inferences. III. Diversification As discussed previously (3/15), there are two fundamental kinds of things in evolutionary theory (Hull, Dawkins). Both of these form nested hierarchies. replicator = things of which copies are made -- a succession of replicators forms a lineage interactor = things that interact in a common environment such that replication is differential Four things can happen to lineages: 1. Origin 2. Extinction 3. Divergence 4. Reticulation

For today, will focus on divergence, which leads to diversification of lineages. The total number of lineages in a clade is diversity. Constraints: Why is morphospace not filled in completely? Adaptive landscapes vs developmental landscapes GENERAL CLASSES OF CAUSAL FACTORS ADVANCED TO EXPLAIN COHESION/INTEGRATION OF "SPECIES": 1) GENE FLOW 2) STABILIZING SELECTION -- ECOLOGICAL CONSTRAINTS 3) DEVELOPMENTAL CONSTRAINTS THE NULL HYPOTHESIS: RANDOM WALK; ACCIDENTS OF HISTORY Reproductive isolation: 1. Prezygotic: 1) habitat isolation, 2) temporal isolation, 3) behavioral isolation, 4) mechanical isolation, 5) gametic incompatibility Anything that prevents mating and fertilization is a prezygotic mechanism. Prezygotic mechanisms fall into two broad categories. Habitat isolation, that is, preferring different habitats, is likely to have evolved because of natural selection. In this case, reproductive isolation is a byproduct of changes occurring for other reasons. In other cases, characters associated with mating also are isolating mechanisms. Differences between lineages could evolve in order to prevent hybridization. In some cases, such as the time of mating, it is difficult to tell. Lineages could be active at different times of the day or breed at slightly different times of the year, because of food preferences or because selection favored reduced hybridization. 2. Postzygotic: 1) hybrid inviability, 2) hybrid sterility, 3) hybrid breakdown Postzygotic barriers prevent the hybrid zygote from developing into a viable, fertile adult. Reduced viability or fertility of hybrid offspring all are known to be postzygotic isolating mechanisms. Lack of ability to survive in intermediate habits is an ecological barrier. Often differences in chromosome number or arrangement of genes on chromosomes result in genetic barriers. Geographic modes of diversification: 1. Allopatric: Diversification by geographically separated populations. Either a barrier can form, separating a single lineage into two isolated ones, or a lineage can colonize a new area. In both cases, gene flow is highly reduced. The formation of a barrier is sometimes called a vicariant event. How large a barrier has to be depends on dispersal capacity. A river may be a barrier for a snake but not a bird. There are two important subtypes of allopatic diversification: I. Initial population divided into two large halves (the "dumbbell" model) II. Initial population divided into one large half an one small, marginal half (the peripheral isolate model) 2. Sympatric: Diversification between lineages with overlapping geographic ranges

In plants polyploidy can lead to immediate reproductive isolation. Chromosomal mutations in self-fertile plants can lead to instant speciation. The genus Clarkia provides several examples of allopolyploid and autopolyploid species. Many domesticated plants are polyploid, including oats, wheat, barley, potatoes, bananas, tobacco. It is likely that polyploid individuals were used early in the domestication of plants, both because they had unusual properties and because they were reproductively isolated from their wild relatives. Implications for studies of "speciation": The study of speciation involves an interplay between empirical research and concepts of species (the units of speciation). As emphasized before, the converse is true in that an understanding of processes impacting on species can influence species concepts for a group. Studies of pattern (i.e., phylogenetic reconstructions) and process (underlying causal mechanisms) are related to each other in a reciprocal manner (Hull 1988). We must ask not just what species are and how they are to be defined, but also how they came into being and how they are maintained. General evolutionary theories about species, their origin and nature, can (and should) be examined in such a manner. The process of studying divergence should always start with a cladogram down to as fine a level as is possible to resolve. The next step is to examine the characters changing on the branches (morphological, functional, geographic, reproductive, etc.), looking for common denominators (possible causes/constraints). How do we study adaptive radiations in a rank-free world view? A sampling problem: how many "basal" lineages are there? IV. Further reading B.D. Mishler and M.J. Donoghue. 1982. Species concepts: a case for pluralism. Systematic Zoology 31: 491-503. B.D. Mishler and R.N. Brandon. 1987. Individuality, pluralism, and the phylogenetic species concept. Biology and Philosophy 2: 397-414. B.D. Mishler and A.F. Budd. 1990. Species and evolution in clonal organisms--introduction. Systematic Botany 15: 79-85. [symposium on species in several asexual groups of organisms] B.D. Mishler. 1999. Getting rid of species? In R. Wilson (ed.), Species: New Interdisciplinary Essays, pp. 307-315. MIT Press. B.D. Mishler and E. Theriot. 2000. The phylogenetic species concept sensu Mishler and Theriot: monophyly, apomorphy, and phylogenetic species concepts. Three chapters in Q.D. Wheeler & R. Meier (eds.), Species Concepts and Phylogenetic Theory: A Debate. Columbia U. Press. B.D. Mishler. 2010. Species are not uniquely real biological entities. In F. Ayala and R. Arp (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Biology, pp. 110-122. Wiley-Blackwell.