Can Everettian Interpretation Survive Continuous Spectrum?

Similar documents
On the origin of probability in quantum mechanics

Measurement: still a problem in standard quantum theory

arxiv:gr-qc/ v1 15 Apr 1997

arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 16 Oct 2018

PHY305: Notes on Entanglement and the Density Matrix

Delayed Choice Paradox

2. As we shall see, we choose to write in terms of σ x because ( X ) 2 = σ 2 x.

MATH 3300 Test 1. Name: Student Id:

Quantum Systems Measurement through Product Hamiltonians

Master Projects (EPFL) Philosophical perspectives on the exact sciences and their history

Spekkens Toy Model, Finite Field Quantum Mechanics, and the Role of Linearity arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 15 Mar 2019

Deriving quantum mechanics from statistical assumptions

Mathematics 220 Workshop Cardinality. Some harder problems on cardinality.

Economics 204 Fall 2011 Problem Set 1 Suggested Solutions

EPR Paradox and Bell s Inequality

RVs and their probability distributions

SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS

Hardy s Paradox. Chapter Introduction

Pure Quantum States Are Fundamental, Mixtures (Composite States) Are Mathematical Constructions: An Argument Using Algorithmic Information Theory

1 Mathematical preliminaries

Chem 3502/4502 Physical Chemistry II (Quantum Mechanics) 3 Credits Spring Semester 2006 Christopher J. Cramer. Lecture 7, February 1, 2006

The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics (Handout Eight) between the microphysical and the macrophysical. The macrophysical world could be understood

Consistent Histories. Chapter Chain Operators and Weights

INFINITESIMALS ARE TOO SMALL FOR COUNTABLY INFINITE FAIR LOTTERIES

Lecture 4 (Sep. 18, 2017)

THE OBJECTIVE PAST OF

arxiv:quant-ph/ v3 18 May 2004

Throwing Darts, Time, and the Infinite

Quantum decoherence. Éric Oliver Paquette (U. Montréal) -Traces Worshop [Ottawa]- April 29 th, Quantum decoherence p. 1/2

Topic 2: The mathematical formalism and the standard way of thin

When Worlds Collide: Quantum Probability From Observer Selection?

Instant Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics

Continuous quantum states, Particle on a line and Uncertainty relations

Statistical Interpretation

Seminaar Abstrakte Wiskunde Seminar in Abstract Mathematics Lecture notes in progress (27 March 2010)

Discrete Mathematics 2007: Lecture 5 Infinite sets

Cardinality and ordinal numbers

Review of Quantum Mechanics, cont.

08a. Operators on Hilbert spaces. 1. Boundedness, continuity, operator norms

CONSTRUCTION OF THE REAL NUMBERS.

So far we have limited the discussion to state spaces of finite dimensions, but it turns out that, in

MATH 13 FINAL EXAM SOLUTIONS

P3317 HW from Lecture and Recitation 10

REU 2007 Transfinite Combinatorics Lecture 9

Section 7.5: Cardinality

What does it feel like to be in a quantum superposition?

Incompatibility Paradoxes

The Two Faces of Infinity Dr. Bob Gardner Great Ideas in Science (BIOL 3018)

Math 4603: Advanced Calculus I, Summer 2016 University of Minnesota Notes on Cardinality of Sets

Problem 1: Compactness (12 points, 2 points each)

4 Choice axioms and Baire category theorem

The Schrodinger Equation and Postulates Common operators in QM: Potential Energy. Often depends on position operator: Kinetic Energy 1-D case:

Page 684. Lecture 40: Coordinate Transformations: Time Transformations Date Revised: 2009/02/02 Date Given: 2009/02/02

When Worlds Collide: Quantum Probability From Observer Selection?

Singlet State Correlations

Some Basic Notations Of Set Theory

Stochastic Processes

The Born rule and its interpretation

HOW TO CREATE A PROOF. Writing proofs is typically not a straightforward, algorithmic process such as calculating

Stat 451: Solutions to Assignment #1

Ultraproducts of Finite Groups

2. Signal Space Concepts

Metainduction in Operational Set Theory

Time-Independent Perturbation Theory

COPENHAGEN INTERPRETATION:

HOW DO ULTRAFILTERS ACT ON THEORIES? THE CUT SPECTRUM AND TREETOPS

A variant of Namba Forcing

Stochastic Histories. Chapter Introduction

ABOUT THE CLASS AND NOTES ON SET THEORY

TOWARD AN OBJECTIVE PRINCIPLE FOR

Lecture 4: Completion of a Metric Space

Let us first solve the midterm problem 4 before we bring up the related issues.

Section 11: Review. µ1 x < 0

Introduction to Group Theory

Quantum Theory and the Many- Worlds Interpretation. David Wallace (Balliol College, Oxford) LSE, October 2014

Approximating the infinite - a model theoretic look at quantum physics

Stochastic Quantum Dynamics I. Born Rule

arxiv: v4 [quant-ph] 26 Oct 2017

Writing proofs for MATH 51H Section 2: Set theory, proofs of existential statements, proofs of uniqueness statements, proof by cases

A derivation of the time-energy uncertainty relation

Introduction to Bell s theorem: the theory that solidified quantum mechanics


Lecture Notes 2: Review of Quantum Mechanics

Lattices, closure operators, and Galois connections.

Einselection of Pointer Observables: The New H-Theorem?

Introduction to Bases in Banach Spaces

Math 105A HW 1 Solutions

CSCI3390-Lecture 6: An Undecidable Problem

Extended Essay - Mathematics

Algorithms: Lecture 2

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ).

arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 15 Mar 2016

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Spring 2014 Anant Sahai Note 20. To Infinity And Beyond: Countability and Computability

Thus, X is connected by Problem 4. Case 3: X = (a, b]. This case is analogous to Case 2. Case 4: X = (a, b). Choose ε < b a

The Different Sizes of Infinity

ADVANCED CALCULUS - MTH433 LECTURE 4 - FINITE AND INFINITE SETS

6 Cosets & Factor Groups

A Re-Evaluation of Schrodinger s Cat Paradox

is any vector v that is a sum of scalar multiples of those vectors, i.e. any v expressible as v = c 1 v n ... c n v 2 = 0 c 1 = c 2

Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur. Lecture 1 Real Numbers

Transcription:

Can Everettian Interpretation Survive Continuous Spectrum? Bryce M. Kim 2016/02/21 Abstract This paper raises a simple continuous spectrum issue in many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics, or Everettian interpretation. I will assume that Everettian interpretation refers to many-worlds understanding based on quantum decoherence. The fact that some operators in quantum mechanics have continuous spectrum is used to propose a simple thought experiment based on probability theory. Then the paper concludes it is untenable to think of each possibility that wavefunction Ψ gives probability as actual universe. While the argument that continuous spectrum leads to inconsistency in the cardinality of universes can be made, this paper proposes a different argument not relating to theoretical math that actually has practical problems. 1 Introduction It is assumed that the Everettian interpretation of quantum mechanics refers to understanding based on quantum decoherence, first pursued by Everett (1957) [2] and later by the papers such as Zurek (1981) [4]. To say simply, in this interpretation, wavefunction Ψ = k a k k with k a k 2 = 1 interacts with environment and reduced density matrix that recovers classical probability in terms of Born s rule is recovered when tracing over environment from original pure density matrix. By this, one can interpret each k as being possible universe, with probability of being in the world k given by a k 2, Born s rule. In this paper, a universe would refer to a single possible world allowed by the Everettian interpretation. Thus a universe does not refer to the set of worlds. The interpretation has clear advantage of not having to think about how our world becomes chosen by probability mechanism, as one can simply say that wavefunction, or decohered wavefunction represents the state of entire universes. But is this advantage really tenable? When spectra of operators are all countable, this seems to be reasonable, as countable additivity of probability theory is there - this will be discussed further in the later section. However, whenever 1

Can Everettian Interpretation Survive Continuous Spectrum? 2 we allow spectra of operators to be uncountable, thinking of k as a different universe is highly problematic. Unless one assumes that there are some worlds privileged, the probability theory thought experiment demonstrates that the Everettian interpretation cannot match with what quantum mechanics predicts. 2 Continuous spectrum It is known that integral must be used when trying to express Ψ in terms of position state vectors: Ψ = k a kk dk. The fact that any rigged Hilbert space that describes a quantum system is a subspace of some countable Hilbert space is therefore maintained, as one can always resort to a good basis. But when one wishes to think wavefunction in terms of universes realized, different possible positions should mean different universes - there is no intuitive reason why a good basis is preferred basis for describing different realities. This immediately raises the question of cardinality, since we have 2 ℵ0 possible universes when described in possible positions, or ℵ 0 universes when described in terms of a good basis. In such a case, it is certainly possible to say that we instead have 2 ℵ0 universes, that share some property of the world. (If this is consistent understanding, then this proves that there needs to be at least 2 ℵ0 universes in the Everettian interpretation.) But as one will see, this understand has a fundamental problem. Another possible solution would be to say that only countably many positions of all possible positions are realized as universes by picking the set of computable reals (for simplicity, I assume that position is one-dimensional). But the real line is selected arbitrarily, and function x x + k with x, k R with k being some arbitrary constant should not affect qualitative results. It is certainly possible to adjust k so that previously a non-computable real x is a computable real x + k. The remaining possibility is to say that countably many universes are picked randomly - but then the Everettian interpretation no longer holds advantage over traditional interpretations of quantum mechanics. 3 Probability to a set of universes There are also issues related to how one may assign probability to a set of universes. The question mainly is, since each branch/ universe is equal, should not we assign equal probability to every outcome, barring the fact that uniform distribution over a real line does not exist, necessitating the need to use an improper prior, in case of continuous possible outcomes? One may easily go around this by allowing several universes to share same outcome, but the question of assigning probability, and in particular how Born s rule is realized, remains. For a small subset of papers available, Deutsch (1999) [1] provides informationtheoretical argument for assigning probability, Zurek (2005) [5] discusses envariance and derives Born s rule by quantum decoherence arguments. Sebens et

Can Everettian Interpretation Survive Continuous Spectrum? 3 al. (2014) [3] discusses self-locating uncertainty and also derives Born s rule. 4 Does infinite cardinality matter in physics? Discussions in previous sections mentioned uncountable and countable cardinality. But in physics, it may be the case that as long as cardinality is infinite, different cardinalities do not matter. Rigorously, one does say that some countable basis spans a quantum system, but sans rigor one may say that position state vectors do span the system, albeit with use of integral. This can be true for traditional interpretations such as Copenhagen - though what Copenhagen interpretation actually means has been different from a physicist to a different physicist. However, I will show in the next section that for the Everettian interpretation, uncountable cardinality matters. 5 Probability thought experiment Assume that wavefunction Ψ for a particle satisfies Ψ(x, 0) 2 = 1 for 0 < x < 1 and Ψ(x, 0) = 0 for rest. A wavefunction that satisfies above can be developed by Fourier analysis - I will drop the discussion here. I will ignore time, as this is not important to the analysis below. Let X be random variable for one-dimensional position x of the particle. Let y = f(x) = x 2, with Y being random variable for position squared. The probability density function (pdf) for X is: p(x) = 1 with support (0, 1). x = f 1 (y) = y, with dx/dy = 1/(2 y). The pdf for Y is: g(y) = 1/(2 y). Notice that g(y) p(x). Let us now take the following thought experiment: Following the Everettian interpreation, each possible outcome is now an individual world. But because of probability necessity, there will be other worlds that share the same outcome (thus avoiding criticism that every world is equally likely). Each world is associated with particle position x. Now x 2 is calculated inside the world. But subsets of universes were assigned probability in the Everettian interpretation. Since the universes that share some position x must have equal chance of occurring compared to the universes sharing a different position x, it must be the case that just applying function f should not change this probability, because one is only dealing with/transforming the value! We only replaced associated x with associated x 2, and f is bijective.

Can Everettian Interpretation Survive Continuous Spectrum? 4 Thus Y must still have uniform distribution. We know that this cannot be consistent with quantum mechanics results. (Observable for position can be referred as ˆX, with observable for position squared being Ŷ = ˆX 2, which follows matrix multiplication/exponentiation. Ŷ and ˆX obviously commute.) It is then clear that the problem with the Everettian universe is the use of uncountably many distinct universes. Continuum of real numbers cannot be captured back into ordinals - here, universes. 5.1 Additional mathematical observations To repeat what was said above, the Everettian interpretation requires assigning probability on universes, that can be mapped to probability derived by wavefunctions. If universes are all equally likely, then this fact should remain so when labels change from x to x 2. Everettians may, however, argue that all universes being equally likely is obviously true, since each universe has zero probability, in case of continuous x. Thus, one must discuss probability of universes being in the interval (a, b) for label x or in the interval (a 2, b 2 ) for x 2, say hypothetical Everettians. I will argue that this observation misses the below mathematical point. First of all, intuition that all universes being equally likely lead to uniform distribution (when location is localized to (0, 1)) is not really wrong. To see why Y does not exhibit uniform distribution and why the paradox results from the Everettian interpretation, the below formula is helpful: y 2 = (x 2 ) 2 = (x + k) 2 = x 2 + 2kx + k 2 = y + 2kx + k 2 Assume that k is some real number. For any real x 2 x = k, however small it is, one can find that y 2 y = 2kx+k 2. 2kx factor is dependent on x, implying that x increases, 2kx factor increases. Thus, when universes that were distinguished by position x change label to x 2, they actually have some universes missing according to Y, and these missing universes affect probability proportional to x each y maps to. Thus, the intuition that all universes equally likely should map to uniform distribution is a correct one - and that changing labels of universes by a bijective function should not affect probability of universes. 5.2 Density argument Everettians may say that at position x, there are not really separate universes but a continuum of utilities given by density. Does this argument the Everettian interpretation? Recall that all arguments explored in this paper so far against the Everettian universe do not rely on distinct universes existing at position x. Rather, these arguments required that different x should have some representative universe

REFERENCES 5 that is assigned some probability. And in order for the Everettian interpretation to work, probability on the set of representative universes still must be considered, that is shown to reduce to probability deduced from Ψ. Thus density argument still fails. 5.3 Can infinitesimals then save the Everettian interpretation? Recall y 2 = (x 2 ) 2 = (x + k) 2 = x 2 + 2kx + k 2 = y + 2kx + k 2. If k being real caused the problem, what if one allows infinitesimals? That is, assume that some universe at x = x 1 + dx is not at x = x 1. Then what was explored in the subsection Additional mathematical observations does not seem to work, and the Everettian interpretation seems to be saved. But by symmetry then, it is natural to allow infinitesimals for probability too. Why should positions only be allowed infinitesimals? When allowing infinitesimals for probability, P (A) = P (B) where A is one universe and B is some universe can be discussed in a clean way. This allows an easy way to prove that when universes are all equally likely, this should remain so regardless of any label. 6 Conclusion The remaining concern is that for some pdf p(x), countable points may differ from p(x) without really affecting probability of events. This, however, does not apply for difference between the p(x) and g(y) discussed in this paper. Thus this concern can be ignored safely. From the thought experiment, the reasonable conclusion I derive is that Everettian interpretation needs to develop probability of events (for example, probability of position of a particle being in 0.5 < x < 0.7) independently of universes. That is, the Everettian universe must somehow dispose of the concept of distinct universes. But if this is required, then it must be asked whether there are really advantages in adopting the Everettian interpretation. The main advantage of the interpretation comes from its ability to treat possible outcomes as universes. This half-equivalence does naturally imply necessity to assign probability to the set of universes. Alternatives may be developed, and the author hopes to see the progress in light of this thought experiment. References [1] Deutsch, D. (1999). Quantum Theory of Probability and Decisions. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London A455, pp. 31293137 [2] Everett, H. (1957). Relative State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics. Reviews of Modern Physics Vol. 29, pp. 454-462

REFERENCES 6 [3] Sebens, C. and Caroll, S. (2014). Self-Locating Uncertainty and the Origin of Probability in Everettian Quantum Mechanics. [Preprint] [4] Zurek, W. (1981). Pointer Basis of Quantum Apparatus: Into what Mixture does the Wave Packet Collapse? Physical Review D, 24, pp. 1516-1525 [5] Zurek, W. (2005). Probabilities from entanglement, Born s rule from envariance. Phys. Rev. A71, 052105