Midterm #1 EconS 527 Wednesday, February 21st, 2018

Similar documents
Preferences and Utility

Solution Homework 1 - EconS 501

Microeconomic Theory-I Washington State University Midterm Exam #1 - Answer key. Fall 2016

Utility Maximization Problem

Solution Homework 1 - EconS 501

Recitation 2-09/01/2017 (Solution)

Recitation #2 (August 31st, 2018)

Structural Properties of Utility Functions Walrasian Demand

Utility Maximization Problem. Advanced Microeconomic Theory 2

EconS 501 Final Exam - December 10th, 2018

Hicksian Demand and Expenditure Function Duality, Slutsky Equation

Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Chapter 2: Demand Theory

The Ohio State University Department of Economics. Homework Set Questions and Answers

Last Revised: :19: (Fri, 12 Jan 2007)(Revision:

Econ 101A Midterm 1 Th 29 September 2004.

Week 9: Topics in Consumer Theory (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 2)

Chapter 1 - Preference and choice

Week 7: The Consumer (Malinvaud, Chapter 2 and 4) / Consumer November Theory 1, 2015 (Jehle and 1 / Reny, 32

Revealed Preferences and Utility Functions

GARP and Afriat s Theorem Production

Preferences and Utility

i) This is simply an application of Berge s Maximum Theorem, but it is actually not too difficult to prove the result directly.

ECON501 - Vector Di erentiation Simon Grant

Notes on Consumer Theory

Economics 101. Lecture 2 - The Walrasian Model and Consumer Choice

Microeconomics II Lecture 4. Marshallian and Hicksian demands for goods with an endowment (Labour supply)

= 2 = 1.5. Figure 4.1: WARP violated

Week 6: Consumer Theory Part 1 (Jehle and Reny, Chapter 1)

PhD Qualifier Examination

Consumer theory Topics in consumer theory. Microeconomics. Joana Pais. Fall Joana Pais

Microeconomics, Block I Part 1

GS/ECON 5010 section B Answers to Assignment 1 September Q1. Are the preferences described below transitive? Strictly monotonic? Convex?

First Welfare Theorem

Advanced Microeconomics Fall Lecture Note 1 Choice-Based Approach: Price e ects, Wealth e ects and the WARP

EconS Microeconomic Theory II Homework #9 - Answer key

Problem set 2 solutions Prof. Justin Marion Econ 100M Winter 2012

Notes I Classical Demand Theory: Review of Important Concepts

Microeconomic Analysis

x 1 1 and p 1 1 Two points if you just talk about monotonicity (u (c) > 0).

Advanced Microeconomics

Introduction to General Equilibrium: Framework.

Chapter 1 Consumer Theory Part II

Economics 121b: Intermediate Microeconomics Midterm Suggested Solutions 2/8/ (a) The equation of the indifference curve is given by,

Midterm Exam, Econ 210A, Fall 2008

Advanced Microeconomics

Consumer Theory. Ichiro Obara. October 8, 2012 UCLA. Obara (UCLA) Consumer Theory October 8, / 51

The Fundamental Welfare Theorems

DEPARTMENT OF MANAGEMENT AND ECONOMICS Royal Military College of Canada. ECE Modelling in Economics Instructor: Lenin Arango-Castillo

Rice University. Answer Key to Mid-Semester Examination Fall ECON 501: Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Part A

Microeconomic Theory -1- Introduction

Introduction to General Equilibrium

Applications I: consumer theory

Problem Set 5: Expenditure Minimization, Duality, and Welfare 1. Suppose you were given the following expenditure function: β (α

Social Choice Theory. Felix Munoz-Garcia School of Economic Sciences Washington State University. EconS Advanced Microeconomics II

Lecture 3 - Axioms of Consumer Preference and the Theory of Choice

Final Examination with Answers: Economics 210A

ECON 304 MIDTERM EXAM ANSWERS

CHAPTER 4: HIGHER ORDER DERIVATIVES. Likewise, we may define the higher order derivatives. f(x, y, z) = xy 2 + e zx. y = 2xy.

Economics th April 2011

General Equilibrium and Welfare

Microeconomics II. MOSEC, LUISS Guido Carli Problem Set n 3

Positive Theory of Equilibrium: Existence, Uniqueness, and Stability

Duality. for The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd ed. Lawrence E. Blume

Microeconomic Theory I Midterm

Advanced Microeconomic Theory. Chapter 6: Partial and General Equilibrium

The Kuhn-Tucker Problem

Homework 3 Suggested Answers

Intro to Economic analysis

Advanced Microeconomic Analysis, Lecture 6

Economics 501B Final Exam Fall 2017 Solutions

Problem Set 1 Welfare Economics

3/1/2016. Intermediate Microeconomics W3211. Lecture 3: Preferences and Choice. Today s Aims. The Story So Far. A Short Diversion: Proofs

Lecture 1. History of general equilibrium theory

Demand Theory. Lecture IX and X Utility Maximization (Varian Ch. 7) Federico Trionfetti

Intermediate Microeconomics (UTS 23567) * Preliminary and incomplete Available at

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program May 2012

Monotone comparative statics Finite Data and GARP

Sometimes the domains X and Z will be the same, so this might be written:

Econ Review Set 2 - Answers

The B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics

The Consumer, the Firm, and an Economy

Department of Economics ECO 204 Microeconomic Theory for Commerce (Ajaz) Test 1 Solutions

Microeconomics I Fall 2007 Prof. I. Hafalir

Introductory Microeconomics

Choice Theory. Matthieu de Lapparent

Ph.D. Preliminary Examination MICROECONOMIC THEORY Applied Economics Graduate Program June 2016

Mathematical Foundations -1- Constrained Optimization. Constrained Optimization. An intuitive approach 2. First Order Conditions (FOC) 7

ECON5110: Microeconomics

Existence, Computation, and Applications of Equilibrium

Adv. Micro Theory, ECON

Lecture 8: Basic convex analysis

1 + x 1/2. b) For what values of k is g a quasi-concave function? For what values of k is g a concave function? Explain your answers.

Econ 5150: Applied Econometrics Empirical Demand Analysis. Sung Y. Park CUHK

U b (x b ) = xb 1x b 2 x a 1. means the consumption of good i by an h-type person.

3. THE EXCHANGE ECONOMY

Answer Key: Problem Set 1

Econ 121b: Intermediate Microeconomics

1 General Equilibrium

EC487 Advanced Microeconomics, Part I: Lecture 2

Revealed Preference 2011

Transcription:

NAME: Midterm #1 EconS 527 Wednesday, February 21st, 2018 Instructions. Show all your work clearly and make sure you justify all your answers. 1. Question 1 [10 Points]. Discuss and provide examples of three different sources of intransitivity. Sources of intransitivity: a. Indistinguishable alternatives: When two alternatives are extremely similar we are often unable to state which of them we prefer. Consider the following example. Take the set of alternatives X to be the real numbers, e.g., a share of pie. b. Framing eff ects: In certain cases intransitivity might be violated because of the way in which alternatives are presented to the individual decision-maker, also referred as framing effects. Let us consider an example where the following holiday packages are shown to Masters students, asking each student: Which holiday package do you prefer? a. A weekend in Paris for $574 at a four star hotel. b. A weekend in Paris at the four star hotel for $574. c. A weekend in Rome at the five star hotel for $612. Alternatives a and b are, of course, the same. This was indeed detected by most of the students since they stated to be indifferent between alternatives a and b. Moreover, they strictly preferred alternative b to c. By transitivity, hence, we should expect that students who gave the previous responses should then strictly prefer alternative a to c when asked to compare these two options. However, this did not happen. Indeed, more than 50% of the students responded that they strictly preferred alternative c to a, showing an intransitive preference relation, merely induced by the way in which the options were presented to them c. Aggregation of criteria: In some cases several individual preferences must be aggregated into only one. In these situations we might find that the resulting preference relation violates transitivity. Let us consider the following example. The set of possible alternatives X contains three universities where you were admitted. A similar argument can be used for the aggregation of individual preferences in group decision-making, where every person in the group has a different (transitive) preference relation but the group preferences (aggregated from these individual preferences in order to have a ranking of alternatives) are not necessarily transitive. This is the so-called Condorcet paradox, extensively studied in social choice problems. d. Change in preferences: Changes in the underlying preferences are common in the analysis of goods that create a strong dependency or that become addictive. For instance, when an individual starts smoking, his preferences over cigarettes might be: One cigarette No smoking Smoking heavily. Hence, according to transitivity, he should prefer one cigarette to smoking heavily. However, once this individual has been smoking for several years, his preferences over cigarettes could have changed to: Smoking heavily One cigarette No smoking. According to this new preference relation, and using transitivity, we can conclude that now this individual prefers to smoke heavily versus having only one cigarette. But this conclusion contradicts his past preferences when he started to smoke. 2. Question 2 [15 Points]. Formally define Convexity and Monotonicity and provide the intuition behind these concepts. How does monotonicity affect the indifference curve? Finally, discuss whether the following function is monotone or strongly monotone. u (x 1, x 2 ) = min {x 1, x 2 }

Convexity. A preference relation satisfies convexity if, for any two bundles x, y X, x y implies that αx + (1 α)y y for all α (0, 1). Intuitively, the convex combination of bundles x and y is weakly preferred to bundle y alone. First Interpretation: Convexity can be interpreted as a taste for diversification. An individual with convex preferences prefers the convex combination of bundles x and y, than either of those bundles alone. Second Interpretation: convexity can be understood as a diminishing marginal rate of substitution (MRS) between the two goods, where MRS = u dx 1 u. Since the MRS describes the additional amount of good 1 that dx 2 the consumer Monotonicity. A preference relation satisfies monotonicity if, for any two bundles x, y X, (where x y), x k y k for all k, implies x y, and x k > y k for all k, implies x y That is, increasing the amounts of some commodities (without reducing the amount of any other commodity) cannot hurt, x y; and increasing the amounts of all commodities is strictly preferred, x y. Under strongly monotonic preference if we increase the amount of only one commodity, the individual is made better off. Note that this is not necessarily true if this individual s preferences satisfy monotonicity. Strong monotonicity (and monotonicity) implies that indiff erence curves must be negatively sloped. Hence, to maintain utility level unaffected along all the points on a given indifference curve, an increase in the amount of one good must be accompanied by a reduction in the amounts of other goods. The function u (x 1, x 2 ) = min {x 1, x 2 } The preference relation represented by this utility function satisfies monotonicity since, if we increase all arguments by a common factor δ > 0, we obtain min{x 1 + δ, x 2 + δ}, which is larger than min {x 1, x 2 } for any positive δ. However, it does not satisfy strong monotonicity since, if we increase one argument alone (for instance, the amount of good 1 consumed), we obtain min {x 1 + δ, x 2 }, which is not necessarily larger than min {x 1, x 2 }. 3. Question 3 [20 Points]. Let us consider the case of two goods, L = 2. Then, an individual prefers a bundle x = (x 1, x 2 ) to another bundle y = (y 1, y 2 ) if and only if it contains more units of both goods than bundle y, i.e. x 1 y 1 and x 2 y 2. Informally, he prefers more of everything. Check if this preference relation satisfies: (1) completeness, (2) transitivity and (3) strong monotonicity. Assume a bundle equal to (4, 2) and use a graph to support your answer. Completeness: First, the upper contour set (UCS) describes the region of bundles that the consumer prefers to bundle (4, 2). The UCS of bundle (4, 2) thus contains those bundles (x 1, x 2 ) with weakly more than two units of good 1 and weakly more than one unit of good 1, that is UCS(4, 2) = {(x 1, x 2 ) (4, 2) x 1 4 and x 2 2} as depicted in the shaded region of figure 1 labeled UCS, which lies to the northeast (4, 2). 2x Region A UCS 2 (4,2) LCS 4 Region B 1x Figure 1

In contrast, the bundles in the lower contour set of bundle (4, 2), whereby the consumer is better off with bundle (4, 2), contain fewer units of both goods, that is, LCS(4, 2) = {(4, 2) (x 1, x 2 ) x 1 4 and x 2 2 The lower contour set (LCS) is therefore illustrated by those points to the southwest of (4, 2); as depicted in figure 1. Finally, the indifference set, IND (4, 2), which comprises those bundles (x 1, x 2 ) for which the consumer is indifferent between (4, 2) and (x 1, x 2 ), is empty, since there are no regions for which the upper contour set and the lower contour set overlap. Hence, it is not complete, since completeness requires for every pair x and y, either x y or y x (or both). Transitivity: It is transitive, since transitivity requires that, for any three bundles x, y and z, if x y and y z then x z. Now x y and y z means that x y and y z. In vector notation, this means that bundle x is weakly larger than y in every component. Similarly, bundle y is weakly larger than bundle z in every component. Hence, x y and y z, which implies that x 1 y 1 and y 1 z 1 for every good l. Strong monotonicity: It is strongly monotone. The property of strong monotonicity requires that if we increase one of the goods in a given bundle, then the newly created bundle must be strictly preferred to the original bundle. More compactly, for a given bundle y, if bundle x satisfies x y and x y then x y In words, bundle x being weakly larger than y in all components (but being strictly larger in at least one component, since they cannot completely coincide) implies that bundle x is weakly preferred to y, and it can never be that bundle y is weakly preferred to bundle x. We can therefore conclude that x is strictly preferred to y, x y, as required. 4. Question 4 [20 Points]. Consider a consumer with CES utility function: where coeffi cient satisfy 0 and 1. u (x 1, x 2 ) = [x 1 + x 2 ] 1 (a) Find the Walrasian demands of this consumer. The Lagragian in this individual s UMP is Taking first order conditions yields L(x 1, x 2 ; λ) = [x 1 + x 2 ] 1 + λ [w x 1 p 2 x 2 ] x 1 = [x 1 + x 2 ] 1 x 2 = [x 1 + x 2 ] 1 λ = w x 1 p 2 x 2 = 0 Rearranging the first two equalities, we obtain ( ) 1 x 2 = x 1. x 1 λ = 0 x 2 λp 2 = 0 Plugging this result into the budget constraint, we obtain [ ( ) 1 ] x 1 p 2 x 1 = w

and solving for x 1, we find the Walrasian demand for good 1, x 1 (p, w) = w 1 p1 + For compactness, this demand can be expressed as x 1 (p, w) = w pr 1 1 p r 1 +pr 2 where r. We can finally plug x 1 (p, w) into x 2 = x 1 ( ) r in order to find the Walrasian demand of good 2, x 2 (p, w) = w pr 1 2 p r 1 + pr 2 (b) What is the Walrasian demand of any good i = {1, 2} when parameter 0? When 0 (the consumer s preferences can be represented with a Cobb-Douglas utility function) parameter r also approaches zero. In this setting, his Walrasian demand for good i, x i (p, w) = w pr 1 i p, becomes r i +pr j lim x i(p, w) = w p 1 i 0 1 + 1 = w 2 which exactly coincides with the Walrasian demand of a consumer with Cobb-Douglas utility function u(x 1, x 2 ) = x α 1 x α 2 for any α > 0. 5. Question 5 [20 Points]. Luis has a monthly income of $80. He spends his money sending text messages (measured in minutes) at a price p x and on other composite good y, whose price has been normalized to one, i.e., p y = $1. His mobile phone company offers him two plans: Plan A, in which he pays no monthly fee and sends text messages for $0.25 per minute; or Plan B, in which he pays a $40 monthly fee and benefits from cheaper text messages at $0.10 per minute. 2. a. Depict Luis s budget constraint under each of the two plans, with the number of phone calls (good x) in the horizontal axis and the composite good (good y) in the vertical axis. Let x denote the number of texts, and y denote spending on other goods. The expression of the budget line under Plan A, BL A is 0.25x + y = 80, or y = 80 0.25x, as depicted in the solid line of figure that originates at y = 80 and which crosses the horizontal axis at x = 320. Under Plan B, Luis budget line, BL B, is 0.1x+y = 40, or y = 40 0.1x, as illustrated in figure 2.11 by the dashed line that originates at y = 40 and crosses the horizontal axis at x = 400. These two budget lines intersect each other at 0.25x+(40 0.1x) = 80, i.e., x = 266.67. Hence, y = 40 0.1x = 40 (0.1 266.67) = 13.33 Therefore, BL A and BL B intersect at bundle (266.67, 13.33). 400

Figure 2.11. Checking WARP 3. b. If Luis mentions that Plan A is better for him, what is the set of baskets he may purchase if his behavior is consistent with the WARP? According to WARP, if the consumption bundle under new prices and wealth was affordable under the original prices and wealth, p x(p, w ) w, then the bundle selected under the old prices and wealth cannot be affordable under the new prices and wealth, i.e., p x(p, w) w. In this context, where the consumer moves from facing budget line BL B to BL A, WARP states that, if the consumption bundle under BL B, x(p, w ), is affordable under BL A, it must lie on segment KJ in figure 2.11, i.e., this is equivalent to the premise of WARP, p x(p, w ) w. Hence, the bundle selected when facing budget line BL A, x(p, w), must be unaffordable under BL B ; that is, x(p, w) must lie on segment LJ of budget line BL A. Notice that bundles in segment JM are instead affordable under BL B, thus violating WARP. 6. Question 6 [15 Points]. An individual can choose among N different goods. Using Shepard s lemma show that for any two goods: milk (m) and cereals (c), the price elasticity of the individual s Hicksian demands ε hm,p c h m(p, u) p m p m h m (p, u) must satisfy ε hm,p m ε hc,p c ε hm,p c ε hc,p m. From Shepard s lemma Differentiating both sides with respect to e(p, u) = h i (p, u) 2 e(p, u) = h i(p, u) must be positive semi- Since the expenditure function is convex in prices, the Hessian matrix 2 e(p,u) definite. That is, its determinant is weakly positive. which can be expressed as follows Finally, multiplying by h i (p, u) which can be rewritten as h i(p,u) and = 2 e(p, u) 2 e(p, u) 2 e(p, u) 2 e(p, u) 0 h i (p, u) h i(p, u) h j(p,u) h i (p, u) h j(p, u) in both sides h i(p, u) ε hm,p m ε hc,p c ε hm,p c ε hc,p m GOOD LUCK! h i (p, u) h j(p, u)