TILING PROOFS OF SOME FIBONACCI-LUCAS RELATIONS. Mark Shattuck Department of Mathematics, University of Tennessee, Knoxville, TN , USA

Similar documents
TILING PROOFS OF SOME FORMULAS FOR THE PELL NUMBERS OF ODD INDEX

RECOUNTING DETERMINANTS FOR A CLASS OF HESSENBERG MATRICES. Arthur T. Benjamin Department of Mathematics, Harvey Mudd College, Claremont, CA 91711

Counting on Continued Fractions

Tiling Proofs of Recent Sum Identities Involving Pell Numbers

In Search of Combinatorial Fibonacci Identities

arxiv: v1 [math.co] 11 Aug 2015

COMPLEMENTARY FAMILIES OF THE FIBONACCI-LUCAS RELATIONS. Ivica Martinjak Faculty of Science, University of Zagreb, Zagreb, Croatia

Counting on Chebyshev Polynomials

Two Identities Involving Generalized Fibonacci Numbers

Combinatorial proofs of Honsberger-type identities

The Negs and Regs of Continued Fractions

Georgia Tech HSMC 2010

Phased Tilings and Generalized Fibonacci Identities

The Fibonacci Numbers -- Exposed More Discretely

arxiv: v2 [math.co] 29 Jun 2016

CATALAN DETERMINANTS A COMBINATORIAL APPROACH

A Tiling Approach to Chebyshev Polynomials

Transforming Inductive Proofs to Bijective Proofs

Enumerating Distinct Chessboard Tilings and Generalized Lucas Sequences Part I

Counting permutations by cyclic peaks and valleys

#A91 INTEGERS 18 (2018) A GENERALIZED BINET FORMULA THAT COUNTS THE TILINGS OF A (2 N)-BOARD

BIJECTIVE PROOFS FOR FIBONACCI IDENTITIES RELATED TO ZECKENDORF S THEOREM

Fibonacci Numbers. Justin Stevens. Lecture 5. Justin Stevens Fibonacci Numbers (Lecture 5) 1 / 10

SELF-AVOIDING WALKS AND FIBONACCI NUMBERS. Arthur T. Benjamin Dept. of Mathematics, Harvey Mudd College, Claremont, CA

arxiv: v3 [math.co] 6 Aug 2016

Math 324 Summer 2012 Elementary Number Theory Notes on Mathematical Induction

Fibonacci numbers. Chapter The Fibonacci sequence. The Fibonacci numbers F n are defined recursively by

The Combinatorialization of Linear Recurrences

F. T. HOWARD AND CURTIS COOPER

q-counting hypercubes in Lucas cubes

Generalized Lucas Sequences Part II

The solutions to the two examples above are the same.

MATH 324 Summer 2011 Elementary Number Theory. Notes on Mathematical Induction. Recall the following axiom for the set of integers.

LINEAR RECURRENCES THROUGH TILINGS AND MARKOV CHAINS ARTHUR T. BENJAMIN, CHRISTOPHER R. H. HANUSA, AND FRANCIS EDWARD SU

Bijective proofs for Fibonacci identities related to Zeckendorf s Theorem

Lecture 8 : Structural Induction DRAFT

Combinatorial Proofs and Algebraic Proofs I

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Fall 2013 Vazirani Note 1

Counting Palindromic Binary Strings Without r-runs of Ones

1. Introduction Definition 1.1. Let r 1 be an integer. The r-generalized Fibonacci sequence {G n } is defined as

Mathematical Induction. Section 5.1

Math 120. x x 4 x. . In this problem, we are combining fractions. To do this, we must have

Math 46 Final Exam Review Packet

A Probabilistic View of Certain Weighted Fibonacci Sums

Lecture 7 Feb 4, 14. Sections 1.7 and 1.8 Some problems from Sec 1.8

17 Advancement Operator Equations

THE OFFICIAL JOURNAL OF THE FIBONACCI ASSOCIATION

FIFTH ROOTS OF FIBONACCI FRACTIONS. Christopher P. French Grinnell College, Grinnell, IA (Submitted June 2004-Final Revision September 2004)

C) x m A) 260 sq. m B) 26 sq. m C) 40 sq. m D) 364 sq. m. 7) x x - (6x + 24) = -4 A) 0 B) all real numbers C) 4 D) no solution

Math 378 Spring 2011 Assignment 4 Solutions

Integer Sequences Related to Compositions without 2 s

Homework #2 Solutions Due: September 5, for all n N n 3 = n2 (n + 1) 2 4

ON SUMS OF SQUARES OF PELL-LUCAS NUMBERS. Gian Mario Gianella University of Torino, Torino, Italy, Europe.

Linear Equations & Inequalities Definitions

1. INTRODUCTION. Figure 1: An ellipse with b < 0. are the image of the n th roots of unity under the mapping. n,j ) + (a n + b n ) (2) j=0

3 - Induction and Recursion

Counting Peaks and Valleys in a Partition of a Set

1 Sequences and Summation

On Some Combinations of Non-Consecutive Terms of a Recurrence Sequence

Properties of Radicals

Extended Binet s formula for the class of generalized Fibonacci sequences

From Simplest Recursion to the Recursion of Generalizations of Cross Polytope Numbers

Four Basic Sets. Divisors

ASSIGNMENT 12 PROBLEM 4

Great Theoretical Ideas in Computer Science

Day 2: Let The Good Roll

Sum of Squares. Defining Functions. Closed-Form Expression for SQ(n)

The Fibonacci Quilt Sequence

Parity Theorems for Statistics on Domino Arrangements

Primary classes of compositions of numbers

Climbing an Infinite Ladder

DISTRIBUTION OF FIBONACCI AND LUCAS NUMBERS MODULO 3 k

Fibonacci Number of the Tadpole Graph

RUSSELL JAY HENDEL. F i+1.

Induction and Recursion

Discrete Mathematics and Probability Theory Spring 2014 Anant Sahai Note 3

A bijective proof of Shapiro s Catalan convolution

Some Review Problems for Exam 3: Solutions

Mathematical Induction

At the start of the term, we saw the following formula for computing the sum of the first n integers:

Direct Proof Universal Statements

AND OCCUPANCY PROBLEMS

Compositions of n with no occurrence of k. Phyllis Chinn, Humboldt State University Silvia Heubach, California State University Los Angeles

Great Theoretical Ideas in Computer Science

College Algebra Final, 7/2/10

Several Generating Functions for Second-Order Recurrence Sequences

SEQUENCES, MATHEMATICAL INDUCTION, AND RECURSION

n F(n) 2n F(2n) Here are some values of the series in comparison to Fibonacci number:

12 Sequences and Recurrences

On the possible quantities of Fibonacci numbers that occur in some type of intervals

ON THE POSSIBLE QUANTITIES OF FIBONACCI NUMBERS THAT OCCUR IN SOME TYPES OF INTERVALS

Module 2: Reflecting on One s Problems

Chapter 4 ARITHMETIC AND GEOMETRIC PROGRESSIONS 2, 5, 8, 11, 14,..., 101

THE DIVISION THEOREM IN Z AND R[T ]

Congruence successions in compositions

#A87 INTEGERS 18 (2018) A NOTE ON FIBONACCI NUMBERS OF EVEN INDEX

One Pile Nim with Arbitrary Move Function

SERIES


ENUMERATING DISTINCT CHESSBOARD TILINGS

Transcription:

INTEGERS: ELECTRONIC JOURNAL OF COMBINATORIAL NUMBER THEORY 8 (008), #A18 TILING PROOFS OF SOME FIBONACCI-LUCAS RELATIONS Mark Shattuck Department of Mathematics, University of Tennessee, Knoxville, TN 37996-1300, USA shattuck@math.utk.edu Received: 3/6/07, Revised: 1/7/08, Accepted: 4/18/08, Published: 5/8/08 Abstract We provide tiling proofs for some relations between Fibonacci Lucas numbers, as requested by Benjamin Quinn in their text, Proofs that Really Count. Extending our arguments yields Gibonacci generalizations of these identities. 1. Introduction Let F n L n denote the Fibonacci Lucas numbers defined, respectively, by F 0 = 0, F 1 = 1 with F n = F n 1 + F n if n by L 0 =, L 1 = 1 with L n = L n 1 + L n if n. The following four relations can be shown using the Binet formulas for F n L n occur as (V85) (V88) in Vajda [: F (k+3)t = F t [( 1) (k+1)t + F (k+)t = F t ( 1) it L (k+ i)t, (1.1) ( 1) it L (k+1 i)t, (1.) L (k+3)t = L t [( 1) (k+1)(t+1) + F (k+)t = L t ( 1) i(t+1) L (k+ i)t, (1.3) ( 1) i(t+1) F (k+1 i)t, (1.4) where k t are nonnegative integers. Benjamin Quinn request combinatorial proofs of (1.1) (1.4) on page 145 of their text, Proofs that Really Count [1. In this note, we provide tiling proofs for (1.1) (1.4) as well as for a couple of closely related identities. The arguments

INTEGERS: ELECTRONIC JOURNAL OF COMBINATORIAL NUMBER THEORY 8 (008), #A18 can be extended to yield generalizations involving Gibonacci numbers. The tiling proofs we give will also supply a combinatorial insight into the various divisibility relations implicit in (1.1) (1.4) within/between the Fibonacci Lucas sequences. The Fibonacci number F n+1 counts tilings of a board of length n with cells labeled 1,,..., n using squares dominos (termed n-tilings). The Lucas number L n is given by the simple relation L n = F n+1 + F n 1, n. (1.5) From (1.5), we see that L n counts n-tilings in which one may circle a domino covering cells n 1 n, which we ll term Lucas n-tilings. (There are F n 1 Lucas n-tilings which end in a circled domino F n+1 Lucas n-tilings which do not.) We ll say that a tiling is breakable at m (as in [1, p. 3) if cell m is covered by a square or by a second segment of a domino. The 5-tiling below is breakable at 0 (vacuously), 1, 3, 5. For m 0, let F m L m denote the sets consisting of m-tilings of Lucas m-tilings, respectively.. Tiling Proofs We first provide a combinatorial interpretation for (1.) when t is even. By (1.5), we re to show ( ) F (k+)t = Ft F (k+1 i)t+1 + F t F (k+1 i)t 1. (.1) Given i, 0 i k, let F i F (k+)t 1 comprise those tilings starting with it consecutive dominos, but not with (i + 1)t consecutive dominos. There are clearly F t F (k+1 i)t 1 members of F i that are not breakable at (i + 1)t, as such tilings can be decomposed as d it δ 1 dδ, where δ 1 δ are tilings of length t 1 (k + 1 i)t, respectively. So we need to show that there are F t F (k+1 i)t+1 members of F i that are breakable at (i + 1)t. Suppose λ F i is breakable at (i + 1)t. Let α be the t-tiling obtained by taking all the pieces in λ covering cells it + 1 through (i + 1)t β be the [(k + 1 i)t 1-tiling obtained by taking all the pieces in λ past cell (i + 1)t. We place α above β, offsetting the tilings by shifting β to the right by one cell. (Tiling α covers cells 1 through t β covers cells through (k + 1 i)t.) Look for the first fault line passing through α β. (A fault line occurs at cell j if both α β are breakable at cell j.) Exchange all the pieces in α past the first fault line with all the pieces in β past it (i.e., swap tails as shown) to obtain (A, B) F (k+1 i)t F t 1.

INTEGERS: ELECTRONIC JOURNAL OF COMBINATORIAL NUMBER THEORY 8 (008), #A18 3 Figure 1: Swapping tails past cell 8 converts (α, β) into (A, B). Note that λ F i implies that tails can always be swapped as it cannot be the case that α consists of β starts with t dominos. (If i = k, there is a single case in which tails of length zero are swapped.) Since t 1 is odd, there is always at least one square in a tiling of length t 1. Thus, the inverse on F (k+1 i)t F t 1 can always be defined, which completes the even case. Now suppose t 1 is odd. With the F i as above, let F i > := k j=i+1 F j, 0 i k ; (.) note that F i > = F (k i)t, as members of F i > must start with at least (i + 1)t consecutive dominos. There are F t F (k+1 i)t 1 members of F (k+)t 1 starting with it dominos that aren t breakable at (i + 1)t. These tilings consist of the F (k i)t members of F i > (they aren t breakable at (i+1)t since t is odd) as well as the members of F i that aren t breakable at (i + 1)t. Upon subtraction, there are then F t F (k+1 i)t 1 F (k i)t members of F i that aren t breakable at (i + 1)t. If λ F i is breakable at (i + 1)t, then use the correspondence above with F (k+1 i)t F t 1, noting that now the F (k i)t ordered pairs whose first component starts with t+1 dominos whose second component consists of t 1 dominos are missed. Thus, there are F t F (k+1 i)t+1 F (k i)t members of F i that are breakable at (i + 1)t. Upon adding the F t F (k+1 i)t 1 F (k i)t members of F i that aren t breakable at (i + 1)t, we see that there are (F t F (k+1 i)t+1 F (k i)t ) + (F t F (k+1 i)t 1 F (k i)t ) = F t L (k+1 i)t F (k i)t members of F i altogether, which implies F i + F i > = F t L (k+1 i)t. Therefore, F t ( 1) i L (k+1 i)t = ( 1) [ i F i + F i > = F i = F (k+)t 1 = F (k+)t,

INTEGERS: ELECTRONIC JOURNAL OF COMBINATORIAL NUMBER THEORY 8 (008), #A18 4 where the second equality follows from a simple characteristic function argument: If 0 j k λ F j, then both the second third sums count λ one time, the second j 1 since ( 1) j + ( 1) i = 1. This completes the odd case the proof of (1.). A slight modification of the preceding argument gives (1.1) as well. We now turn to identity (1.3), first assuming t 1 is odd. A similar proof will apply to (1.4). By (1.5), we re to show L (k+3)t = L t + (F t+1 + F t 1 ) L (k+ i)t. (.3) Given i, 0 i k + 1, let L i L (k+3)t comprise those tilings starting with it consecutive dominos, but not with (i + 1)t consecutive dominos. Clearly, L k+1 = L t. If 0 i k, then there are F t+1 L (k+ i)t members of L i that are breakable at (i + 1)t as well, since such tilings can be decomposed as d it δ 1 δ, where δ 1 is a regular tiling of length t δ is a Lucas tiling of length (k + i)t. So we need to show that there are F t 1 L (k+ i)t members of L i that are not breakable at (i + 1)t. Suppose λ L i is not breakable at (i + 1)t. Let α be the (t 1)-tiling obtained by taking all the pieces in λ covering cells it + 1 through (i + 1)t 1 β be the Lucas [(k + i)t 1-tiling obtained by taking all the pieces in λ past cell (i + 1)t + 1. Set α above β, shifting β to the right by one cell, exchange pieces past the first fault line to obtain (A, B) L (k+ i)t F t. Note that this operation can always be performed since λ L i can always be reversed since t is odd. If t is even, then let L i > := k+1 j=i+1 L j, 0 i k, (.4) where the L i are as above. Note that L i > = L (k+1 i)t, since members of L i > must start with at least (i + 1)t consecutive dominos. If 0 i k, then there are F t+1 L (k+ i)t members of L (k+3)t which start with it consecutive dominos are breakable at (i + 1)t. Since t is even, there are among these the L (k+1 i)t members of L i >. By subtraction, we get F t+1 L (k+ i)t L (k+1 i)t members of L i that are breakable at (i + 1)t if 0 i k. If λ L i is not breakable at (i+1)t, then use the correspondence above with L (k+ i)t F t, noting that now the ordered pairs whose second component consists of t 1 dominos whose first component starts with t dominos are missed. Thus, there are F t 1L (k+ i)t L (k+1 i)t members of L i that aren t breakable at (i+1)t (F t+1 L (k+ i)t L (k+1 i)t )+ (F t 1 L (k+ i)t L (k+1 i)t ) = L t L (k+ i)t L (k+1 i)t members of L i in all. The rest of the proof goes much like the odd case of (1.) above. Two further identities can also be obtained from the arguments above. On page 146 of their text, Benjamin Quinn request combinatorial proofs for Identities V93 V94,

INTEGERS: ELECTRONIC JOURNAL OF COMBINATORIAL NUMBER THEORY 8 (008), #A18 5 which may be written as k+1 F (k+3)t = ( 1) (k+1)t F t [(k + 3) + 5 ( 1) it Fit i=1 (.5) k+1 F (k+3)t = ( 1) (k+1)t F t [ (k + 1) + ( 1) it L it. (.6) Replacing i by k + 1 i in (1.1) gives i=1 substituting k+1 F (k+3)t = ( 1) (k+1)t F t [1 + ( 1) it L it, (.7) i=1 L it = 5F it + ( 1) it (.8) L it = L it ( 1) it (.9) into (.7) yields (.5) (.6), respectively. The preceding argument for (1.1) hence (.7) can then be easily combined with the arguments for (.8) (.9), which are known involve tailswapping (see, e.g., Identities 36, 45, 53 of [1), to obtain combinatorial interpretations for (.5) (.6), as desired. 3. Generalizations Let (G n ) n 0 be the sequence given by G n = G n 1 + G n if n, where G 0 G 1 are nonnegative integers (termed Gibonacci numbers [1, p. 17 as shorth for generalized Fibonacci numbers). The G n are seen to enumerate n-tilings in which a terminal square is assigned one of G 1 possible phases a terminal domino is assigned one of G 0 possible phases (termed phased n-tilings). Note that G n reduces to F n+1 when G 0 = G 1 = 1 to L n when G 0 =, G 1 = 1. Reasoning as in the prior section with phased tilings instead of regular tilings yields the following (reindexed) generalizations of (1.1) (1.4): G (k+3)t 1 = ( 1) kt [ ( 1) t G t 1 + F t ( 1) it (G (i+)t + G (i+)t ), (3.1)

INTEGERS: ELECTRONIC JOURNAL OF COMBINATORIAL NUMBER THEORY 8 (008), #A18 6 G (k+)t 1 = ( 1) kt [ ( 1) t (G 1 G 0 ) + F t G (k+3)t = ( 1) k(t+1) [ G (k+)t 1 = ( 1) k(t+1) [ ( 1) it (G (i+1)t + G (i+1)t ), (3.) ( 1) t+1 G t + L t ( 1) i(t+1) G (i+)t, (3.3) ( 1) t+1 (G 1 G 0 ) + L t ( 1) i(t+1) G (i+1)t 1. (3.4) Identities (3.1), (3.), (3.4) reduce to (1.1), (1.), (1.4), respectively, when G n = F n+1, (3.3) reduces to (1.3) when G n = L n. We outline the proof of (3.), leave the others as exercises for the interested reader. We adjust the argument above for (1.), first assuming t is even. Let G m denote the set consisting of phased tilings of length m let G i G (k+)t 1 comprise those tilings starting with it consecutive dominos, but not with (i+1)t consecutive dominos, 0 i k. There are then F t G (i+1)t members of G k i that are not breakable at (k i + 1)t if 0 i k, upon tailswapping as above, F t G (i+1)t members of G k i that are breakable at (k i + 1)t if 0 < i k. If i = 0, we omit the G 1 cases in which λ G k ends in a phased square preceded by t 1 dominos, since here tailswapping doesn t actually move any tiles (i.e., the first only fault occurs directly after cell t) hence the phased square ending λ fails to be moved. Similarly, we must omit from consideration the G 0 members of G t F t 1 whose first coordinate is a phased tiling which contains no squares whose second coordinate is a regular tiling which contains only a single square occurring at the end. Thus, there are F t G t + (G 1 G 0 ) members of G k that are breakable at (k + 1)t. Adding together all of the cases gives (3.) when t is even. Similar adjustments apply when t is odd. References [1 A. Benjamin J. Quinn, Proofs that Really Count: The Art of Combinatorial Proof, The Dolciani Mathematical Expositions, 7, Mathematical Association of America, 003. [ S. Vajda, Fibonacci & Lucas Numbers, the Golden Section: Theory Applications, John Wiley & Sons, Inc., 1989.