Favoring Consensus and Penalizing Disagreement in Group Decision Making

Similar documents
A DISTANCE-BASED EXTENSION OF THE MAJORITY JUDGEMENT VOTING SYSTEM

Using quasiarithmetic means in a sequential decision procedure

Weighting Expert Opinions in Group Decision Making for the Influential Effects between Variables in a Bayesian Network Model

An Analysis on Consensus Measures in Group Decision Making

The dual decomposition of aggregation functions and its application in welfare economics

A general class of simple majority decision rules based on linguistic opinions

A model of elitist qualification

Group Decision-Making with Incomplete Fuzzy Linguistic Preference Relations

Additive Consistency of Fuzzy Preference Relations: Characterization and Construction. Extended Abstract

Collective transitivity in majorities based on difference in support

Preservation of graded properties of fuzzy relations by aggregation functions

Metrizable ordinal proximity measures and their aggregation

Non Additive Measures for Group Multi Attribute Decision Models

Some Characterizations based on Double Aggregation Operators*

A new consensus ranking approach for correlated ordinal information based on Mahalanobis distance

Triple-acyclicity in majorities based on difference in support

could not model some situations as e.g. the Ellsberg Paradox, see [13]. For the non-additive set function (measure) m defined on a ff-algebra ± of sub

Ordinal aggregation and ranking

Preservation of t-norm and t-conorm based properties of fuzzy relations during aggregation process

Preference aggregation and DEA: An analysis of the methods proposed to discriminate efficient candidates

On (Weighted) k-order Fuzzy Connectives

Information Sciences

Strategic Manipulation and Regular Decomposition of Fuzzy Preference Relations

A unifying model to measure consensus solutions in a society

POSET-VALUED PREFERENCE RELATIONS

Aggregation and Non-Contradiction

The problem of distributivity between binary operations in bifuzzy set theory

Research Article A Study of SUOWA Operators in Two Dimensions

Similarity-based Classification with Dominance-based Decision Rules

Multiattribute decision making models and methods using intuitionistic fuzzy sets

Group Decision Making Using Comparative Linguistic Expression Based on Hesitant Intuitionistic Fuzzy Sets

Directional Monotonicity of Fuzzy Implications

Classifying inputs and outputs in data envelopment analysis

AGGREGATION OPERATORS FOR MULTICRITERIA DECISION AID. Jean-Luc Marichal University of Liège

Arrow's theorem and max-star transitivity. National University of Ireland, Galway

Social Dichotomy Functions (extended abstract)

Compenzational Vagueness

Copulas with given diagonal section: some new results

Fusing Interval Preferences

On tolerant or intolerant character of interacting criteria in aggregation by the Choquet integral

Kybernetika. Margarita Mas; Miquel Monserrat; Joan Torrens QL-implications versus D-implications. Terms of use:

Multicriteria Decision Making Based on Fuzzy Relations

A Model of Consensus. in Group Decision Making. under Linguistic Assessments. F. Herrera, E. Herrera-Viedma, J.L. Verdegay

An axiomatic approach of the discrete Sugeno integral as a tool to aggregate interacting criteria in a qualitative framework

A Consistency Based Procedure to Estimate Missing Pairwise Preference Values

Survey of Voting Procedures and Paradoxes

Construction of Interval-valued Fuzzy Preference Relations from Ignorance Functions and Fuzzy Preference Relations. Application to Decision Making

Ensemble determination using the TOPSIS decision support system in multi-objective evolutionary neural network classifiers

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

Computing a Transitive Opening of a Reflexive and Symmetric Fuzzy Relation

A Cooperative Approach to Queue Allocation of Indivisible Objects

Social Choice Theory. Felix Munoz-Garcia School of Economic Sciences Washington State University. EconS Advanced Microeconomics II

Aggregation on bipolar scales

Comparison of two versions of the Ferrers property of fuzzy interval orders

Geometry of distance-rationalization

A characterization of the 2-additive Choquet integral

Copyright Author(s) ISSN

A DEA- COMPROMISE PROGRAMMING MODEL FOR COMPREHENSIVE RANKING

Reference-based Preferences Aggregation Procedures in Multicriteria Decision Making

Valued relations aggregation with the Borda method.

On fuzzy preordered sets and monotone Galois connections

Principles of Pattern Recognition. C. A. Murthy Machine Intelligence Unit Indian Statistical Institute Kolkata

Paretian evaluation of infinite utility streams: an egalitarian criterion

The Axiomatic Method in Social Choice Theory:

Dra. Aïda Valls Universitat Rovira i Virgili, Tarragona (Catalonia)

Mathematical Approach to Vagueness

Modeling Influence In Group Decision Making

Ranking Multicriteria Alternatives: the method ZAPROS III. Institute for Systems Analysis, 9, pr. 60 let Octjabrja, Moscow, , Russia.

Continuous R-implications

Reasoning in a Hierarchical System with Missing Group Size Information

Great Expectations. Part I: On the Customizability of Generalized Expected Utility*

A NOTE ON L-FUZZY BAGS AND THEIR EXPECTED VALUES. 1. Introduction

Multiple Equilibria in the Citizen-Candidate Model of Representative Democracy.

Fitting Aggregation Functions to Data: Part II Idempotization

Borda count versus approval voting: A fuzzy approach

Left-continuous t-norms in Fuzzy Logic: an Overview

Roberta Parreiras * and Petr Ekel

Intuitionistic Fuzzy Sets: Spherical Representation and Distances

Inequality of Representation

A Borda Count for Collective Sentiment Analysis

Evaluation of Fuzzy Linear Regression Models by Parametric Distance

ORDERING OBJECTS ON THE BASIS OF POTENTIAL FUZZY RELATION FOR GROUP EXPERT EVALUATION

Preferences and Consistency Issues in Group Decision Making

The possible and the necessary for multiple criteria group decision

Understanding (dis)similarity measures

Efficient Algorithms for Hard Problems on Structured Electorates

Approval Voting for Committees: Threshold Approaches

On some ways of determining membership and non-membership functions characterizing intuitionistic fuzzy sets

Fuzzified weighted OWA (FWOWA) operator

A preference aggregation method through the estimation of utility intervals

Variations of non-additive measures

PYTHAGOREAN FUZZY INDUCED GENERALIZED OWA OPERATOR AND ITS APPLICATION TO MULTI-ATTRIBUTE GROUP DECISION MAKING

Social Choice and Networks

Multi-argument distances

Incomplete Pairwise Comparison Matrices and Weighting Methods

A risk attitudinal ranking method for interval-valued intuitionistic fuzzy numbers based on novel attitudinal expected score and accuracy functions

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups

Drawing Conclusions from Data The Rough Set Way

Social choice theory, Arrow s impossibility theorem and majority judgment

Volume 31, Issue 1. Manipulation of the Borda rule by introduction of a similar candidate. Jérôme Serais CREM UMR 6211 University of Caen

Transcription:

Favoring Consensus and Penalizing Disagreement in Group Decision Making Paper: jc*-**-**-**** Favoring Consensus and Penalizing Disagreement in Group Decision Making José Luis García-Lapresta PRESAD Research Group, Dep. of Applied Economics, University of Valladolid Avda. Valle de Esgueva 6, 47011 Valladolid, Spain E-mail: lapresta@eco.uva.es [Received 00/00/00; accepted 00/00/00] Abstract. In this paper we introduce a multi-stage decision making procedure where decision makers opinions are weighted by their contribution to the agreement after they sort alternatives into a fixed finite scale given by linguistic categories, each one having an associated numerical score. We add scores obtained for each alternative using an aggregation operator. Based on distances among vectors of individual and collective scores, we assign an index to decision makers showing their contributions to the agreement. Opinions of negative contributors are excluded and the process is reinitiated until all decision makers contribute positively to the agreement. To obtain the final collective weak order on the set of alternatives, we weigh the scores that decision makers assign to alternatives by indices corresponding to their contribution to the agreement. Keywords: group decision making, consensus, aggregation operators, metrics 1. Introduction Some decision problems require a group of decision makers to rank a set of alternatives to generate a collective decision. This outcome is usually obtained by applying a given decision procedure that aggregates individual opinions. If the number of alternatives is high, decision makers may find it difficult to rank feasible alternatives. According to Dummett [5], If there are, say, twenty possible outcomes, the task of deciding the precise order of preference in which he ranks them may induce a kind of psychological paralysis in the voter. To help decision makers arrange the alternatives, we propose that they sort alternatives within a given finite scale in which each term is identified with a linguistic category e.g., very good, good, regular, bad, very bad. We assign a score to each linguistic category, then associate a collective score with each alternative by using an aggregation operator that works on individual scores. Alternatives are thus ordered based on collective scores. After this first stage, we introduce a distance between the collective weak order obtained and each individual weak order. Through these distances, we propose an index for measuring the overall contribution of each decision maker to the agreement. Opinions of decision makers with not positive indices are excluded, then we reinitiate the process with only the opinions of individuals contributing positively to the agreement. We repeat this procedure by recalculating new collective orders and overall indices until we obtain a final subset of decision makers who all contribute positively to the agreement, then weigh the scores that decision makers indirectly assign to alternatives by their overall contribution to the agreement indices, to obtain the final collective ranking of alternatives. When all individual assessments have the same importance, the collective decision could be distorted by extravagant or spiteful opinions. Some individuals, in fact, could have reasons to conceal sincere opinions to favor or penalize certain alternatives. Consensus, however, implies some effort for moving individual opinions toward a majority position. It thus makes sense to weigh individual assessments in order of their contribution to the agreement. Weighting individual opinions with the above indices, then decision makers have an incentive not to declare opinions very divergent from the majority opinion to avoid being penalized by reducing their influence over the collective ranking or being expelled from the group. 2. Preliminaries Let V = {v 1,...,v m } a set of decision makers (or voters) who show their preferences on the pairs of a set of alternatives X = {x 1,...,x n }, with m,n 3. P(V ) denotes the power set of V (I P(V ) I V ). Linear orders are complete, antisymmetric and transitive binary relations, and weak orders (or complete preorders) are complete and transitive binary relations. With I, we denote the cardinal of any set I. We consider that each decision maker classifies alternatives within a fixed finite scale given by a set of linguistic categories L = {l 1,...,l p }, with p 2, equipped with a linear order l 1 > > l p. Under this assumption decision makers are not totally free for declaring their preferences. However, the common language they use enables us to aggregate their opinions robustly (see Balinski and Laraki [1]). Vol.0 No.0, 200x Journal of Advanced Computational Intelligence 1

José Luis García-Lapresta The individual assignment of decision maker v i is a mapping C i : X L that assigns a linguistic category C i (x u ) L to each alternative x u X. Associated with C i, we consider the weak order R i defined by x u R i x v if C i (x u ) C i (x v ). A profile is a vector C = (C 1,...,C m ) of individual assignments. We use C to denote the set of profiles. We assume that every linguistic category l k L has an associated score s k [0, ) in such a way that s 1 s 2 s p and s 1 > s p = 0. For the decision maker v i, let S i : X [0, ) be the scoring mapping that assigns the score to each alternative: S i (x u ) = s k C i (x u ) = l k. The scoring vector of v i is (S i (x 1 ),...,S i (x n )). An aggregation operator 1 is a mapping F : [0, ) m [0, ) that satisfies the following two conditions: 1 Idempotency: F(a,...,a) = a. 2 Monotonicity: if a i b i for every i {1,...,m}, then F(a 1,...,a m ) F(b 1,...,b m ). Note that from monotonicity, idempotency is equivalent to compensativeness: min{a 1,...,a m } F(a 1,...,a m ) max{a 1,...,a m }. Interesting examples of aggregation operators belong to the very general class of OWA (Ordered Weighted Averaging) operators introduced by Yager [8], e.g., average, median and olympic aggregators the average of intermediate values after excluding highest and lowest values (see also Yager and Kacprzyk [9], Fodor and Roubens [7, 5.8], and Calvo, Kolesárova, Komorníková and Mesiar [3, 4.2]). Given an aggregation operator F, we assign a collective score to each alternative by means of the scoring mapping S F : X [0, ) defined by S F (x u ) = F (S 1 (x u ),...,S m (x u )), for every alternative x u X. For each alternative x u X, we associate a collective scoring vector (S F (x u ),...,S F (x u )). The collective weak order on X, R F, is given by x u R F x v if S F (x u ) S F (x v ). 3. Agreement measures Once decision makers show their opinions on alternatives and we generate a collective weak order by using an aggregation operator, it is interesting to know the distance of each decision maker to the collective opinion. After this, we introduce an agreement measure that shows us what is the agreement in each subset of decision makers. 1. Aggregation operators are usually defined in the unit interval. See Fodor and Roubens [7, Chapter 5], and Calvo, Kolesárova, Komorníková and Mesiar [3, 4.2]. Definition 1. An agreement measure 2 is a mapping M : C P(V ) [0,1] that assigns a number in the unit interval to each profile and each subset of decision makers, and satisfies the following conditions: 1 Unanimity: M (C,V ) = 1 C 1 = = C m. 2 Anonymity: For every permutation π on {1,...,m} and (C,I) C P(V ) it holds M (C,I) = M (C π,i π ), where C π = ( ) C π(1),...,c π(m) and vi I π if and only if v π(i) I, i.e., I π = { v π(i) v i I }. 3 Neutrality: For every permutation σ on {1,...,n} and (C,I) C P(V ) it holds M (C,I) = M (C σ,i), where C σ = ( C1 σ m),...,cσ is the profile obtained from C by relabeling the alternatives according to σ, i.e., Ci σ ( ) xσ(u) =Ci (x u ) for all i {1,...,m} and u {1,...,n}. Unanimity means that the maximum agreement in the set of all decision makers is only achieved when all opinions are the same. Anonymity requires symmetry with respect to decision makers, and neutrality means symmetry with respect to alternatives. Given a metric d : [0, ) n [0, ) n [0, ) and S, S individual or collective scoring mappings, we denote d(s,s ) = d ( (S(x 1 ),...,S(x n )),(S (x 1 ),...,S (x n )) ). Definition 2. Given a metric d and an aggregation operator F, the mapping Md F : C P(V ) [0,1] defined by d ( S i,s F) Md F (C,I) = v 1 i I, if I /0, I 0, if I = /0, where = d((s 1,...,s 1 ),(0,...,0)), is the overall agreement measure based on d and F. Note that is the maximum distance among scoring vectors. Consequently, Md F (C,I) [0,1] for every (C,I) C P(V ). It is easy to see that Md F satisfies the properties required to be an agreement measure. We now introduce indices that measure the overall contribution to the agreement of each decision maker. Using these indices, we modify the initial group decision procedure for prioritizing consensus 3. 2. This notion was widely explored by Bosch [2] for linear orders. 3. Consensus has different meanings, one of which is related to an interactive and sequential procedure where some decision makers must change their preferences to improve agreement. Usually, a moderator advises decision makers to modify opinions. See, for instance, Eklund, Rusinowska and de Swart [6]. 2 Journal of Advanced Computational Intelligence Vol.0 No.0, 200x

Favoring Consensus and Penalizing Disagreement in Group Decision Making Definition 3. Given an agreement measure M, we define the overall contribution to the agreement of the decision maker v i as w i (C) = I V ( M (C,I) M ( C,I \ {v i } )), for every profile C C. Clearly, if v i / I, then M (C,I) M ( C,I \ {v i } ) = 0. If w i (C) > 0, we say that decision maker v i contributes positively to the agreement; and if w i (C) < 0, we say that decision maker v i contributes negatively to the agreement. We now introduce a new collective preference by weighting scores that decision makers assign indirectly to alternatives with the corresponding overall contribution to the agreement indices. Definition 4. Given an aggregation operator F, the collective weak order associated with the weighting vector w = (w 1,...,w m ), R w, is defined by where x u R w x v S w (x u ) S w (x v ), S w (x u ) = F (w 1 S 1 (x u ),...,w m S m (x u )). Note that if we use the vector of the corresponding overall contribution to the agreement indices, we prioritize decision makers in order of their contribution to the agreement, as suggested by Cook, Kress and Seiford [4]. 4. The multi-stage group decision procedure Given an aggregation operator F and an agreement measure M, we propose the following multi-stage decision making procedure. 1 Decision makers V = {v 1,...,v m } sort alternatives of X = {x 1,...,x n } based on the linguistic categories of L = {l 1,...,l p }. So, we have individual weak orders R 1,...,R m which rank alternatives within the fixed set of linguistic categories. 2 Taking into account scores s 1,...,s p associated with l 1,...,l p, a score is assigned to each alternative for every decision maker: S i (x u ), for i = 1,...,m and u = 1,...,n. 3 A collective score is obtained for each alternative: S F (x u ) = F (S 1 (x u ),...,S m (x u )) and we rank alternatives through the collective weak order R F : x u R F x v S F (x u ) S F (x v ). 4 We calculate overall contributions to the agreement (Definition 3) for all decision makers: w 1 (C),...,w m (C). a If w i (C) 0 for every i {1,...,m}, then we obtain new collective scores by: S w (x u ) = F (w 1 (C) S 1 (x u ),...,w m (C) S m (x u )), for u = 1,...,n, and rank alternatives by using the collective weak order R w : x u R w x v S w (x u ) S w (x v ). This process is equivalent to that for with normalized overall contributions to the agreement: w i(c) = w i (C) w 1 (C) + + w m (C), i = 1,...,m. Notice that now w 1 (C) + + w m(c) = 1. b Otherwise, we exclude opinions of decision makers whose overall contributions to the agreement are negative and initiate the decision procedure for remaining decision makers V = {v i V w i (C) 0}. The process continues until all decision makers contribute positively to the agreement. At this stage, we apply the previous procedure (4a) to obtain the final ranking on the set of alternatives. 4.1. An illustrative example Consider five decision makers who sort alternatives of X = {x 1,,...,x 7 } based on the set of linguistic categories L = {l 1,...,l 6 } and associated scores given in Table 1. Table 2 shows assessments of decision makers and corresponding weak orders. Table 1. Linguistic categories. L Meaning Score l 1 Excellent s 1 = 10 l 2 Very good s 2 = 7 l 3 Good s 3 = 4 l 4 Regular s 4 = 2 l 5 Bad s 5 = 1 l 6 Very bad s 6 = 0 Table 3 gives individual scores and two collective scores: S A for the average and S O for the olympic aggregator. Table 4 shows collective weak orders provided by the average R A and the olympic aggregator R O. Case 1. First we use the average as an aggregation operator, the Euclidean (or L 2 ) metric, d ((a 1,...,a n ),(b 1,...,b n )) = n (a i b i ) 2, i=1 and its associated agreement measure. Taking into account distance between individual and collective scores, we obtain the following overall contributions to the agreement: Vol.0 No.0, 200x Journal of Advanced Computational Intelligence 3

José Luis García-Lapresta Table 2. Individual assessments. R 1 R 2 R 3 R 4 R 5 l 1 x 2 x 1 x 5 x 6 x 3 x 5 l 2 x 1 x 3 x 2 x 2 x 3 x 7 x 4 l 3 x 5 x 1 x 3 x 4 x 5 x 1 x 3 x 1 x 2 l 4 x 4 x 6 x 5 x 7 x 6 x 2 l 5 x 7 x 6 x 7 x 6 l 6 x 4 x 4 x 7 Table 4. Collective orders. R A R O x 3 x 2 x 3 x 5 x 2 x 5 x 1 x 1 x 4 x 6 x 6 x 4 x 7 x 7 Table 3. Individual and collective scores. S 1 S 2 S 3 S 4 S 5 S A S O x 1 7 4 10 4 4 5.8 5 x 2 10 7 7 2 4 6 6 x 3 7 4 7 4 10 6.4 6 x 4 2 0 4 0 7 2.6 2 x 5 4 2 4 10 10 6 6 x 6 2 1 2 10 1 3.2 1.666 x 7 1 2 1 7 0 2.2 1.333 w 1 (C) = 0.735548827 w 2 (C) = 0.414899002 w 3 (C) = 1.132602066 w 4 (C) = 0.225015149 w 5 (C) = 0.511082118 Then, w 3 (C) > w 1 (C) > w 2 (C) > 0 > w 4 (C) > w 5 (C). Since decision makers v 4 and v 5 contribute negatively to the agreement, they are expelled from the group and we reinitiate the process with the first three decision makers. The new collective scores are: S A (x 1 ) = 7, S A (x 2 ) = 8, S A (x 3 ) = 6, S A (x 4 ) = 2, S A (x 5 ) = 3.333, S A (x 6 ) = 1.666, S A (x 7 ) = 1.333, quite different of those obtained in the first iteration (Table 3). The new overall contributions to the agreement are: w 1 (C) = 1.0043468 w 2 (C) = 0.7587926 w 3 (C) = 0.82545947 Now all decision makers contribute positively to the agreement, but now the first decision maker contributes more to the agreement than the third one, just the opposite of that in the initial stage where opinions of all decision makers were taken into account. We now obtain the following normalized indices: w 1 w 2 w 3 (C) = 0.38798858 (C) = 0.29312869 (C) = 0.31888273 Taking into account these normalized indices, we generate the collective scores S w (x u ), for u = 1,...,n, by using w 1 (C) S 1(x u ) + w 2 (C) S 2(x u ) + w 3 (C) S 3(x u ). 3 Multiplying these collective scores by 3, yields normalized collective scores within the interval of original scores associated with linguistic categories, [0, 10]. We thus obtain the normalized collective scores in Table 5. Table 5. Normalized collective scores. x 1 7.07726211 x 2 8.16396573 x 3 6.12061392 x 4 2.05150807 x 5 3.41374261 x 6 1.70687131 x 7 1.29312869 After this normalization, if we take into account scores associated with linguistic categories, we obtain both a ranking and a classification of the alternatives. In this sense, x 1 and x 2 are located between very good and excellent, x 3 between good and very good, x 4 and x 5 between regular and good, and x 6 and x 7 between bad and regular. Table 6 shows initial and final orders. Note that the final outcome differs from the initial one due to the exclusion of decision makers v 4 and v 5 and by weights we apply to scores given by the first three decision makers. Table 6. Case 1. Collective orders. Initial (weak) order Final (linear) order x 3 x 2 x 2 x 5 x 1 x 1 x 3 x 6 x 5 x 4 x 4 x 7 x 6 x 7 Case 2. We now use the olympic aggregation operator, 4 Journal of Advanced Computational Intelligence Vol.0 No.0, 200x

Favoring Consensus and Penalizing Disagreement in Group Decision Making the Manhattan (or L 1 ) metric, d ((a 1,...,a n ),(b 1,...,b n )) = n i=1 a i b i, and its associated agreement measure. Taking into account distances between individual and collective scores, we obtain the following overall contributions to the agreement: w 1 (C) = 1.40666667 w 2 (C) = 1.22809524 w 3 (C) = 1.19238095 w 4 (C) = 0.45047619 w 5 (C) = 1.1115873 Then, w 1 (C) > w 2 (C) > w 3 (C) > 0 > w 4 (C) > w 5 (C), quite different from Case 1. As in Case 1, v 4 and v 5 contribute negatively to the agreement, so they are expelled of the group, and we reinitiate the process with the first three decision makers. The new collective scores are: S O (x 1 ) = 7, S O (x 2 ) = 7, S O (x 3 ) = 7, S O (x 4 ) = 2, S O (x 5 ) = 4, S 0 (x 6 ) = 2, S O (x 7 ) = 1. New overall contributions to the agreement are: w 1 (C) = 1.06190476 w 2 (C) = 0.67619048 w 3 (C) = 0.97619048 All decision makers now contribute positively to the agreement, yielding the following normalized indices w 1 w 2 w 3 (C) = 0.39122807 (C) = 0.24912281 (C) = 0.35964912 We now weight individual scores by using these indices and obtain the outcome given by the olympic aggregator, multiplied by 3 for normalization, as in the previous case. Table 7 shows normalized collective scores. Table 7. Normalized collective scores. x 1 7.33157895 x 2 8.17368421 x 3 6.25263158 x 4 2.22105263 x 5 3.50175439 x 6 1.75087719 x 7 1.24912281 As in Case 1, x 1 and x 2 are located between very good and excellent, x 3 between good and very good, x 4 and x 5 between regular and good, and x 6 and x 7 between bad and regular Table 8 shows initial and final orders. Note that the final order is the same in Cases 1 and 2. The final and initial outcomes thus differ. Again, this is due to the exclusion of decision makers v 4 and v 5, and by the weights we apply to scores given by the first three decision makers. Table 8. Case 2. Collective orders. Initial (weak) order Final (linear) order x 2 x 3 x 5 x 2 x 1 x 1 x 4 x 3 x 6 x 5 x 7 x 4 x 6 x 7 Note that in Cases 1 and 2 we have used different metrics and aggregation operators, yet in both cases, decision makers v 4 and v 5 are expelled from the group in the first iteration, and the final linear order and classification of alternatives coincide in analyzed cases. This may not, however, necessarily hold for every metric and aggregation operator. 5. Conclusions To facilitate decision makers the task of ranking a high number of alternatives, we have proposed that decision makers sort alternatives through a small set of linguistic categories. We associate a score with each linguistic category, then decision makers indirectly assign a score to each alternative. Given an aggregation operator, we obtain a collective score for each alternative and then a collective weak order on the set of alternatives. Given a metric, we calculate distances between individual and collective weak orders, using these distances to assign an index to decision makers that measures their overall contribution to the agreement. Decision makers who contribute negatively to the agreement are expelled from the group and we iterate the decision procedure until all decision makers contribute positively to the agreement. Taking into account the indices we obtain in the final step, we weight individual scores and obtain final collective ranking of alternatives. After normalization, we sort the alternatives by using the linguistic categories that individuals use in their assessments. The final collective ranking we obtain after implementing the proposed multi-stage decision procedure yields valuable information about alternatives. Note the following regarding our multi-stage decision making procedure: The procedure is flexible: different linguistic categories with different associated scores can be used. We can also consider different aggregation operators and metrics, and agreement measures different from that in Definition 2 can be also used. Vol.0 No.0, 200x Journal of Advanced Computational Intelligence 5

José Luis García-Lapresta Due to the overall contribution to the agreement indices, which multiply individual scores, are usually irrational numbers, so when the number of decision makers is high, it is unlikely that the decision procedure provides ties among alternatives. Our proposal requires only a single judgment for each individual about alternatives. Since the proposed decision procedure penalizes individuals who are far from majority positions, this provides incentives for decision makers to moderate their opinions which, otherwise, may be excluded or underestimated. All decision makers use a common language, which avoids problems arising when purely ordinal methods are used (see Balinski and Laraki [1]). It is easy to implement computer programs for generating the final ranking on the set of alternatives. Acknowledgements This paper was supported in part by the Spanish Ministerio de Educación y Ciencia (Project SEJ2006-04267/ECON) and ERDF. References: [1] Balinski, M., Laraki R. (2007), A theory of measuring, electing and ranking, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 104, pp. 8720-8725. [2] Bosch, R. (2006), Characterizations of Voting Rules and Consensus Measures, Ph. D. Dissertation, Tilburg University. [3] Calvo, T., Kolesárova, A., Komorníková, M., Mesiar, R. (2002), Aggregation operators: Properties, classes and construction methods. In T. Calvo, G. Mayor and R. Mesiar, R. (eds.), Aggregation Operators: New Trends and Applications, Physica-Verlag, Heidelberg, pp. 3-104. [4] Cook, W.D., Kress, M., Seiford, L.M. (1996), A general framework for distance-based consensus in ordinal ranking models, European Journal of Operational Research 96, pp. 392-397. [5] Dummett, M. (1984), Voting Procedures, Clarendon Press, Oxford. [6] Eklund, P., Rusinowska, A., de Swart, H. (2007), Consensus reaching in committees, European Journal of Operational Research 178, pp. 185-193. [7] Fodor, J., Roubens, M. (1994), Fuzzy Preference Modelling and Multicriteria Decision Support, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht. [8] Yager, R.R. (1988), Ordered weighted averaging operators in multicriteria decision making, IEEE Transactions on Systems, Man and Cybernetics 8, pp. 183-190. [9] Yager, R.R., Kacprzyk, J. (1997), The Ordered Weighted Averaging Operators: Theory and Applications, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Norwell. 6 Journal of Advanced Computational Intelligence Vol.0 No.0, 200x