On monadic MV -algebras

Similar documents
Monadic GMV -algebras

The logic of perfect MV-algebras

Embedding logics into product logic. Abstract. We construct a faithful interpretation of Lukasiewicz's logic in the product logic (both

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

A note on fuzzy predicate logic. Petr H jek 1. Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic

MV-algebras and fuzzy topologies: Stone duality extended

The prime spectrum of MV-algebras based on a joint work with A. Di Nola and P. Belluce

MV -ALGEBRAS ARE CATEGORICALLY EQUIVALENT TO A CLASS OF DRl 1(i) -SEMIGROUPS. (Received August 27, 1997)

Implicational classes ofde Morgan Boolean algebras

Distributive Lattices with Quantifier: Topological Representation

RINGS IN POST ALGEBRAS. 1. Introduction

Monadic MV-algebras I: a study of subvarieties

Morita-equivalences for MV-algebras

SUBALGEBRAS AND HOMOMORPHIC IMAGES OF THE RIEGER-NISHIMURA LATTICE

Andrzej Walendziak, Magdalena Wojciechowska-Rysiawa BIPARTITE PSEUDO-BL ALGEBRAS

De Jongh s characterization of intuitionistic propositional calculus

The Blok-Ferreirim theorem for normal GBL-algebras and its application

A simple propositional calculus for compact Hausdor spaces

The Morita-equivalence between MV-algebras and abelian l-groups with strong unit

Given a lattice L we will note the set of atoms of L by At (L), and with CoAt (L) the set of co-atoms of L.

Congruence Boolean Lifting Property

Independence of Boolean algebras and forcing

Minimal enumerations of subsets of a nite set and the middle level problem

Geometric aspects of MV-algebras. Luca Spada Università di Salerno

The nite submodel property and ω-categorical expansions of pregeometries

INTRODUCING MV-ALGEBRAS. Daniele Mundici

Omitting Types in Fuzzy Predicate Logics

On some properties of elementary derivations in dimension six

Forcing in Lukasiewicz logic

Fleas and fuzzy logic a survey

Stabilization as a CW approximation

ON THE LOGIC OF CLOSURE ALGEBRA

Scattered toposes. Received 1 April 1999; received in revised form 1 July 1999 Communicated by I. Moerdijk

PROJECTIVE MONOIDAL RESIDUATED ALGEBRAS

1. Algebra H-B-M-S- <A, 0, 1,,,,,, >

AN AXIOMATIC FORMATION THAT IS NOT A VARIETY

Chapter 5. Modular arithmetic. 5.1 The modular ring

The primitive root theorem

Mathematica Slovaca. Ján Jakubík On the α-completeness of pseudo MV-algebras. Terms of use: Persistent URL:

Duality and Automata Theory

Some remarks on hyper MV -algebras

Universal Algebra for Logics

The average dimension of the hull of cyclic codes

Foundations of Mathematics MATH 220 FALL 2017 Lecture Notes

On the Complexity of the Reflected Logic of Proofs

A shrinking lemma for random forbidding context languages

Finite homogeneous and lattice ordered effect algebras

Duality in Logic. Duality in Logic. Lecture 2. Mai Gehrke. Université Paris 7 and CNRS. {ε} A ((ab) (ba) ) (ab) + (ba) +

Some consequences of compactness in Lukasiewicz Predicate Logic

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. The universal modality, the center of a Heyting algebra, and the Blok Esakia theorem

On the Structure of Rough Approximations

A CHARACTERIZATION OF LOCALLY FINITE VARIETIES THAT SATISFY A NONTRIVIAL CONGRUENCE IDENTITY

Part II Logic and Set Theory

55 Separable Extensions

Basic Algebraic Logic

ORTHOPOSETS WITH QUANTIFIERS

Some properties of residuated lattices

Summary of the PhD Thesis MV-algebras with products: connecting the Pierce-Birkhoff conjecture with Lukasiewicz logic Serafina Lapenta

UNITARY UNIFICATION OF S5 MODAL LOGIC AND ITS EXTENSIONS

Notes on Ordered Sets

Varieties of Heyting algebras and superintuitionistic logics

Herbrand s Theorem, Skolemization, and Proof Systems for First-Order Łukasiewicz Logic

Lifting to non-integral idempotents

Algebra and probability in Lukasiewicz logic

DUAL BCK-ALGEBRA AND MV-ALGEBRA. Kyung Ho Kim and Yong Ho Yon. Received March 23, 2007

On the normal completion of a Boolean algebra

A NEW VERSION OF AN OLD MODAL INCOMPLETENESS THEOREM

Vector Space Basics. 1 Abstract Vector Spaces. 1. (commutativity of vector addition) u + v = v + u. 2. (associativity of vector addition)

arxiv: v1 [math.ra] 1 Apr 2015

8. Distributive Lattices. Every dog must have his day.

Note On Parikh slender context-free languages

SUBLATTICES OF LATTICES OF ORDER-CONVEX SETS, III. THE CASE OF TOTALLY ORDERED SETS

On the variety generated by planar modular lattices

Logics above S4 and the Lebesgue measure algebra

Finite Simple Abelian Algebras are Strictly Simple

F -inverse covers of E-unitary inverse monoids

ON THE RESIDUALITY A FINITE p-group OF HN N-EXTENSIONS

Mathematica Bohemica

On non-tabular m-pre-complete classes of formulas in the propositional provability logic

4.4 Noetherian Rings

Semilattice Modes II: the amalgamation property

Localizations as idempotent approximations to completions

Finite pseudocomplemented lattices: The spectra and the Glivenko congruence

The lattice of varieties generated by small residuated lattices

294 Meinolf Geck In 1992, Lusztig [16] addressed this problem in the framework of his theory of character sheaves and its application to Kawanaka's th

Recursive definitions on surreal numbers

On Urquhart s C Logic

THE LARGEST INTERSECTION LATTICE OF A CHRISTOS A. ATHANASIADIS. Abstract. We prove a conjecture of Bayer and Brandt [J. Alg. Combin.

Several restrictions reminiscent of Hilbert's connection and order axioms were imposed. The modular core of a convexity lattice was interpreted as the

Embedding theorems for normal divisible residuated lattices

Probability Measures in Gödel Logic

Contents. Introduction

Characters and triangle generation of the simple Mathieu group M 11

FREE STEINER LOOPS. Smile Markovski, Ana Sokolova Faculty of Sciences and Mathematics, Republic of Macedonia

Christopher J. TAYLOR

case of I? 1 (over P A? ) was essentially treated in [11], where the authors show that 2 consequences of that theory are contained in EA, cf also [6].

MATH 326: RINGS AND MODULES STEFAN GILLE

Handbook of Logic and Proof Techniques for Computer Science

Congruence Coherent Symmetric Extended de Morgan Algebras

Transcription:

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 128 (2004) 125 139 www.elsevier.com/locate/apal On monadic MV -algebras Antonio Di Nola a;, Revaz Grigolia b a Department of Mathematics and Informatics, University of Salerno, Via S. Allende Baronissi (Salerno) 84081, Italy b Department of Mathematical Logic, Institute of Cybernetics of Georgian Academy of Sciences, Italy Received 1 September 2001; received in revised form 13 July 2003; accepted 28 November 2003 Communicated by S.N. Artemov Abstract We dene and study monadic MV -algebras as pairs of MV -algebras one of which is a special case of relatively complete subalgebra named m-relatively complete. An m-relatively complete subalgebra determines a unique monadic operator. A necessary and sucient condition is given for a subalgebra to be m-relatively complete. A description of the free cyclic monadic MV -algebra is also given. c 2003 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved. MSC: 03G25; 08B05 Keywords: MV -algebra; Monadic algebra; Relatively complete algebra; Free algebra 1. Introduction The nitely valued propositional calculi, which have been described by Lukasiewicz and Tarski in [12], are extended to the corresponding predicate calculi. The predicate Lukasiewicz (innitely valued) logic QL is dened in the following standard way. For some universe and some complete MV -algebra (or Chang algebra by Rutledge s terminology), which in most cases is a chain particularly it is the real unit interval, it is dened existential (universal) quantier as supremum (inmum). Then the predicate calculus is dened as all formulas having value 1 for any assignment. The functional description of the predicate calculus is given by Rutledge in [16]. Scarpellini in [17] has proved that the set of valid formulas is not recursively enumerable. We also refer a reader to the papers [18,19,7] concerning to the Lukasiewicz predicate calculus. Corresponding author. Tel.: +39-081-7903211. E-mail addresses: adinola@unisa.it (A. Di Nola), grigolia@yahoo.com (R. Grigolia). 0168-0072/$ - see front matter c 2003 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved. doi:10.1016/j.apal.2003.11.031

126 A. Di Nola, R. Grigolia / Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 128 (2004) 125 139 Monadic MV -algebras (monadic Chang algebras by Rutledge s terminology) were introduced and studied by Rutledge in [16] as an algebraic model for the predicate calculus ql of Lukasiewicz innite-valued logic, in which only a single individual variable occurs. Rutledge followed P.R. Halmos study of monadic Boolean algebras. In view of the incompleteness of the predicate calculus the result of Rutledge in [16], showing the completeness of the monadic predicate calculus, has been a great interest. Adapting for the propositional case the axiomatization of monadic MV -algebras given by Rutledge in [16], we can dene modal Lukasiewicz propositional calculus MLPC as a logic which contains Lukasiewicz propositional calculus Luk, the formulas as the axioms schemes: M1., M2. ( ), M3. ( ), M4. ( + ) +, M5. ( + ) +, M6. ( ) and closed under modus ponens and necessitation (=, where = ). Let L denote a rst-order language based on ; +; ; ; and L m denotes monadic propositional language based on ; +; ; ;, and Form(L) and Form(L m ) the set of all formulas of L and L m, respectively. We x a variable x in L, associate with each propositional letter p in L m a unique monadic predicate p (x) in L and dene by induction a translation : Form(L m ) Form(L) by putting: (p)=p (x) ifp is propositional variable, ( )= () (), where = ; +;, ( )= x (). Through this translation, we can identify the formulas of L m with monadic formulas of L containing the variable x. Moreover, it is routine to check that (MLPC) QL. For a detailed consideration of Lukasiewicz predicate calculus we refer to [11,16,2,3]. 2. Monadic MV-algebras The denition and investigation of monadic MV -algebras (monadic Chang algebras in other terminology) is given by Rutledge in [16]. MV -algebras were introduced by Chang in [5] as an algebraic model for innitely valued Lukasiewicz logic. An MV -algebra is an algebra A =(A; ; ; ; 0; 1) where (A; ; 0) is an abelian monoid, and the following identities hold for all x; y A : x 1=1; x = x; 0 =1; x x =1; (x y) y =(x y ) x; x y =(x y ).

A. Di Nola, R. Grigolia / Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 128 (2004) 125 139 127 The present denition, given by Mangani in [13], is equivalent to Chang s original denition given in [5]. The real interval [0; 1] is an MV -algebra with respect to the operations x y = min(1;x+ y); x y = max(0;x+ y 1); x =1 x. We dene x y = x y; x y = x (x y); x y = x (x y). Then (A; ; ; 0; 1) is a bounded distributive lattice [5]. Recall that the category of MV -algebras is equivalent to the category of -group with strong unit [15], and in any -group the following identities hold (see [4]): (1) a + x = (a + x ), (2) a + x = (a + x ), (3) 1 x = (1 x ), i.e. in MV -algebras we have (3 )( x )? = x?, (4) a x = (a x ), (5) a x = (a x ). For MV -algebras from(1), (2) and (3 ) we can deduce (1 ) a x = (a x ), (2 ) a x = (a x ). An algebra A =(A; ; ; ; ; 0; 1) is said to be monadic MV-algebra (for short MMV -algebra) if (A; ; ; ; 0; 1) is an MV -algebra and in addition satises the following identities: E1. x6 x, E2. (x y)= x y, E3. ( x) =( x), E4. ( x y)= x y, E5. (x x)= x x, E6. (x x)= x x. This denition belongs to Rutledge (see [16]). Sometimes we shall denote a monadic MV -algebra A =(A; ; ; ; ; 0; 1) by (A; ), for brevity. We can dene a unary operation x =( x ) corresponding to the universal quanti- er. Then in any monadic MV -algebra hold the identities which are dual to E1 E6: A1. x x, A2. (x y)= x y, A3. ( x) =( x), A4. ( x y)= x y, A5. (x x)= x x, A6. (x x)= x x. Let A 1 and A 2 be any MMV -algebras. A mapping h : A 1 A 2 is MMV -homomorphism if h is MV -homomorphism and for every x A 1 h( x)= h(x). Denote by MMV the variety and the category of MMV -algebras and MMV-homomorphisms.

128 A. Di Nola, R. Grigolia / Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 128 (2004) 125 139 Lemma 1 (Rutledge [16]). In every monadic MV -algebra A the following identities hold: 1. 1=1, 2. 0=0, 3. x = x, 4. ( x y)= x y, 5. x6 y x6 y, 6. x6y x6 y, 7. (x y)6 x y, 8. (x y)6 x y, 9. ( x) y6 (x y). Let A = {x A : x = x}. Then it holds Lemma 2. Let (A; ; ; ; ; 0; 1) be a monadic MV -algebra. Then ( A; ; ; ; 0; 1) is an MV -subalgebra of the MV -algebra (A; ; ; ; 0; 1). Proof. The proof immediately follows from E1 E6 and Lemma 1. 3. m-relatively complete MV-algebras A subalgebra A 0 of an MV -algebra A is said to be relatively complete i for every a A the set {b A 0 : a6b} has the least element, which is denoted by inf {b A 0 : a 6 b} or a6b A 0 b: Proposition 3 (Rutledge [16]). Let (A; ; ; ; ; 0; 1) be a monadic MV -algebra. Then the MV -algebra A is a relatively complete subalgebra of the MV -algebra (A; ; ; ; 0; 1), and a = inf{b A : a6b}. Let us consider a function h : A 0 A. The function h : A A 0 is called left adjoint to h, if h (b)6a b6h(a) for any a A 0 and b A. If in addition h (x x)= h (x) h (x); h (x x)= h (x) h (x), then h is called left m-adjoint. A subalgebra A 0 of an MV -algebra A is said to be m-relatively complete, ifa 0 is relatively complete and two additional conditions hold: (#) ( a A)( x A 0 )( v A 0 )(x a a v a & v v6x), (##) ( a A)( x A 0 )( v A 0 )(x a a v a & v v6x). Let us remark that not every relatively complete subalgebra A 0 of an MV -algebra A denes a monadic operator converting A into a monadic MV -algebra. For illustration let us consider the MV -algebra ([01]; ; ; ; 0; 1) and its relatively complete subalgebra ({0; 1}; ; ; ; 0; 1), which is the two-element Boolean algebra. We can

A. Di Nola, R. Grigolia / Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 128 (2004) 125 139 129 dene a = inf{x {0; 1} : x a}. Then a =1, if a 0, and a =0, if a = 0. But this operation does not satisfy E6 : for any 0 a61=2 a a = 1, and (a a)= 0=0. The subalgebra ({0; 1}; ; ; ; 0; 1) is not m-relatively complete. Indeed, let a =1=2 and x = 0. Then x x a a. But the only element v {0; 1} such that v a is 1, and v v x x. Theorem 4. Let (A; ; ; ; ; 0; 1) be a monadic MV-algebra. Then the MV-subalgebra A of MV -algebra (A; ; ; ; 0; 1) is m-relatively complete. Proof. According to Proposition 3 the algebra A is relatively complete. Now it suces to check the validity of conditions (#) and (##). Let a and x be any elements of A and A, respectively. Let us suppose that x a a (x a a). Then x = x (a a)= a a (x = x (a a)= a a). Hence in the case when v = a the condition (#) ((##)) is satised. Theorem 5. There exists a one-to-one correspondence between. (1) monadic MV -algebras (A; ); (2) the pairs (A; A 0 ), where A 0 is m-relatively complete subalgebra of A; (3) the pairs (A; A 0 ), where A 0 is a subalgebra of A and the canonical embedding h : A 0, A has left m-adjoint function. Proof. Let us prove that (1) implies (2). Indeed, for a given A MMV let us put A 0 = { a : a A} = A which is uniquely dened by the operator. Then, according to Theorem 4, A 0 is m-relatively complete MV -subalgebra of A. Vice versa, for a given pair (A; A 0 ), where A 0 is an m-relatively complete MV -subalgebra of A, let us dene on A, the operator, by putting a = Inf{b A 0 : b a} = a6b A 0 b: And this operator is dened uniquely. From(1), (2), (3) we get (6) a x = (a x ), (7) a x = (a x ). From conditions (1) (5) it immediately follows that E1 E4 hold. Now, let us show E5. Indeed, a a = x y = (x y): a6y A 0 a6y A 0 a6x A 0 a6x A 0 According to (#), if x y a 2, then there exists v A 0 such that v a (and, hence, v 2 a 2 ) and v 2 6x y. Therefore, (x y) = (v v) = (v v) = (v v): a6x A 0 a6y A 0 a6v A 0 a6v A 0 a6v A 0 a 2 6v 2 A 0

130 A. Di Nola, R. Grigolia / Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 128 (2004) 125 139 Now let t be an arbitrary element of A 0 such that t a 2. Then, according to (#), there exists v A 0 such that v a and v 2 6t. Therefore, (v v) = t = (a a): a 2 6v 2 A 0 a6x A 0 a 2 6t A 0 Now we show E6. Indeed, a a = x y = a6y A 0 a6x A 0 a6y A 0 (x y): Since x a and y a, x y a a. According to (##) for x y a a there exist v a and x y v v. So (x y) = (x y) = (v v): a6y A 0 2a6x y A 0 2a6v v A 0 a6x A 0 According to (##) (as in the previous case for E5) (v v)= u = (a a): 2a6v v A 0 2a6u A 0 Hence, it is proved that (1) and (2) are equivalent. Let us prove that (3) implies (2). Indeed, for a given pair (A; A 0 ), where A 0 is a subalgebra of A and the canonical embedding h : A 0, A has left m-adjoint function h, let us dene a = h h (a) for every a A. It is easy to check that left m-adjoint function is order preserving, i.e. if x6y, then h (x)6 h (y). Let x be any element of A 0 and x a 2, where a A. Let v = h (a). Then, v a; h (x)=x h (a 2 )= h (a) h (a)=v 2. Now let x 2a. Then v = h (a) satises the conditions v a; h (x) h (2a)= h (a) h (a)=v v. It means that A 0 is m-relatively complete. Conversely, for a given pair (A; A 0 ), where A 0 is m-relatively complete MV - subalgebra of A, let us dene h (a)=inf{b A 0 : b a}. It is obvious that this function is the left m-adjoint to the canonical embedding h : A 0, A. Then (2) is equivalent to (3). The proof is now complete. Denote by MV 2 the category whose objects are pairs (A; A 0 )ofmv -algebras, where injective MV -algebra homomorphism h : A 0, A has left m-adjoint function h, and whose morphisms are pairs of functions (f;f 0 ):(A; A 0 ) (A ;A 0 ) such that the following conditions are satised: (1) f : A A is MV -algebra homomorphism; (2) f h = h f 0 ; (3) f 0 h = h f, where h : A 0, A is injective MV -algebra homomorphism which has left m-adjoint function h. (1) and (2) imply that f 0 is also an MV -algebra homomorphism.

A. Di Nola, R. Grigolia / Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 128 (2004) 125 139 131 Theorem 6. The category MMV is equivalent to the category MV 2. Proof. Dene the functors : MMV MV 2 and : MV 2 MMV by assuming (A) =(A; A 0 ), where A 0 = { a : a A} and (f)=(f;f A0 ), and ((A; A 0 ))=(A; ), where = h h and ((f;f 0 )) = f. It is easy to check that for every A MMV and (A; A 0 ) MV 2 ((A)) = A and ( ((A; A 0 ))) = (A; A 0 ); ((f)) = f and ( ((f; f 0 )))=(f;f 0 ). 4. Subdirect representation In this section we investigate the properties of monadic MV -algebras. In particular, we characterize congruences of a given monadic MV -algebra and prove that MMV is congruence distributive and has congruence extension property. We characterize subdirectly irreducible monadic MV -algebras and prove a monadic analogous of Chang s representation theoremfor MV -algebras. An ideal M of an algebra (A; ) MMV is called monadic ideal (see [16]), if M is an ideal of MV -algebra A (i.e. A M and for every x; y A (a) x y M; (b) x y; x M y M) and for every a A we have a M a M. For any set X A, let (X ] denote the ideal generated by X. It is easy to check that (X ]={a A : a6x 1 x n ;x 1 ;:::x n X }. Note that if X is closed under, then (X ]={a A : a6x for some x X }. Lemma 7. If =({a} M], where a A 0 (= A) and M is a monadic ideal, then is also a monadic ideal. Proof. If p, then there exists b M such that p6a b. Hence, p6 (a b)6 a b = a b and since b M, weget p. Theorem 8 (see also Rutledge [16]). An ideal M A is monadic if and only if M = (M A 0 ], and there exists a lattice isomorphism between the lattice of all monadic ideals of A and the lattice of all ideals of A 0. Proof. Let (A; ) be a monadic MV -algebra and M A is a monadic ideal. Let a M. Then a M and a M A 0. Therefore, since a6 a; a (M A 0 ]. Conversely, if a (M A 0 ], then a6x for some x M A 0. Therefore, since a6 x = x and a6x; a6 a; a M. Let us note that A 0 is an MV -algebra. The correspondence M (M] maps any ideal M of A 0 to the monadic ideal (M] of(a; ), since M is closed under. It is clear that M =(M] A 0. On the other hand, let J be a monadic ideal of A. Then J =(J A 0 ]. Since J A 0 is an ideal of A 0, we have shown the required 1 1 correspondence between the set of monadic ideals of A and the set of MV -ideals of A 0. Finally, it easy to check that M 1 M 2 (M 1 ] (M 2 ] and J 1 J 2 J 1 A 0 J 2 A 0. This completes the proof of the theorem. The result expressed in the next theoremis also obtained by Rutledge in [16].

132 A. Di Nola, R. Grigolia / Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 128 (2004) 125 139 Lemma 9. If M is a monadic ideal of a monadic MV -algebra (A; ), then the relation R on A dened by xry if and only if (x? y) (x y? ) M is a congruence relation. Proof. Since M is an MV -ideal, then the relation R preserves the operations ; ;? [5]. Let xry, i.e. (x? y) (x y? ) M. Then (x? y); (x y? ) M and (x? y); (x y? ) M. Consequently ( x ( y)? ); (( x)? y)) M by Lemma 1.9. Hence ( x ( y)? ) (( x)? y)) M. Fromhere we conclude that xr y. FromTheorem8 and Lemma 9 we get Corollary 10. For every monadic MV -algebra (A; ), there exists a lattice isomorphism between the lattice of all monadic ideals and the lattice of all congruence relations of (A; ). Corollary 11. (a) There exists a lattice isomorphism between the lattice of congruence relations of (A; ) and the lattice of all congruence relations of A 0 (= A). (b) The variety MMV is congruence distributive. (c) The variety MMV has the congruence extension property. Proof. (a) directly follows fromtheorem8, Corollary 10 and the fact that the lattice of all ideals of A 0 is isomorphic to the lattice of all congruence relations of A 0. (b) and (c) directly follow from(a) and the fact that the variety of all MV -algebras is congruence distributive and has the congruence-extension property. An ideal M of a monadic MV -algebra (A; ) is called prime provided that M A and a b M implies a M or b M. Proposition 12 (Rutledge [16]). Any monadic MV -algebra (A; ) is isomorphic to a subdirect product of monadic MV -algebras (A i ; ) such that A i is totally ordered. Proof. Let S be the family of all prime ideals of A such that S = {0}, which exists according to Chang s theoremabout representation of any MV -algebra as a subdirect product of totally ordered MV -algebras [5]. Then S = {0}, where S = {(P]:P S} is the family of the monadic ideals of A. Lemma 13. If A 0 is m-relatively complete totally ordered an MV -subalgebra of an MV -algebra A, then A 0 is a maximal totally ordered subalgebra of A. Proof. Let us suppose that A 0 is an m-relatively complete totally ordered MV -subalgebra of an MV -algebra A and there exists a A\A 0 such that the subalgebra A 0 generated by a and A 0 is totally ordered. Let us suppose also that a = a? a. Then a a a.

A. Di Nola, R. Grigolia / Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 128 (2004) 125 139 133 Let us note that the identity x y = x y is true in [0; 1] MV-algebra. Therefore, the identity ( x y) = x y is derived from the axioms E1 E6. Since A 0 is totally ordered, ( a)? a 1, and since (( a)? a)=( a)? a =1, ( a)? a = A 0. Denote ( a)? a by d. Then we have d d d = 1. Let us suppose d 2 d. Then 1 = d 2 6 d 1, a contradiction. If d 2 d, then 2d? 6 d?. Since d d d, we obtain ( d)? d? ( d)?. Therefore (d? d? )6 d?. Fromhere, since d? 1; (d? d? ) d? d?. Corollary 14. If (A; ) is a totally ordered monadic MV -algebra, then A = A(=A 0 ). Proposition 15 (Rutledge [16, TheoremIII.2.1.3]). Let (A; ) be a monadic MV - algebra with totally ordered A 0 (= A): Then (A; ) can be represented (as MV - algebra) as a subdirect product of a family {A i } i I of totally ordered MV -algebras, with canonical projections i : A A i, such that A 0 = i (A 0 ) A i. Theorem 16. If (A; ) is a nite monadic MV -algebra with totally ordered A, then MV -algebra A is isomorphic to a product of totally ordered MV -algebras A i ; i I; A i = A and A is isomorphic to the diagonal subalgebra of the product. Proof. According to Chang s representation theorema nite MV -algebra A is isomorphic to a direct product of totally ordered MV -algebras A i : A, A i. A 0 is m-relatively complete subalgebra of A, which is totally ordered by the condition of the theorem. Therefore, according to Theorem15, A 0 = i (A 0 ) A i, where i is a canonical projection (i I). Suppose i (A 0 )isnotm-relatively complete in i (A). It means that for some a i i (A);x i i (A 0 ) and for every v i i (A 0 ) conditions (#) and/or (##) do not hold in i (A). In other words, for some a i i (A); x i i (A 0 ) we have (i) x i a i a i &(v i a i v i v i x i ) and/or (ii) x i a i a i &(v i a i v i v i x i ): Suppose, that (i) ((ii)) holds. Then, since A is nite, there exist a A and x A 0 such that x a 2 (x 2a); i (a)=a i ; i (x)=x i. But for a A and x A 0 there exists v A such that the condition (#) ((##)) holds in A. Then for i (a)=a i ; i (x)=x i there exists i (v)=v i such that the condition (#) ((##)) holds, which contradicts the assumption. Then the theoremfollows fromcorollary 14. 5. Free cyclic MMV-algebra Let U be some class of algebras. By V(U) we denote the variety generated by the class U.

134 A. Di Nola, R. Grigolia / Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 128 (2004) 125 139 Fromthe variety MMV select the subvariety K n for 16n!, which is dened by the following equation: (K n )x n = x n+1 ; that is K n = MMV+(K n ). Fromthe variety K n we select the subvariety MMV n which is dened in the following way: MMV n = K n +(S n ); where (S n )={n(x j (x? (x j 1 )? )=1: 1 j n and j does not divide n}. Let us note, that if A K n, then A MV m for some m6n, where MV m is the subvariety of the variety of all MV -algebras studied in [9]. More precisely MV m = MV + (K m )+(S m ): MV m is generated by the linearly ordered simple MV -algebra S m =(S m ; ; ;?;0; 1), which in turn is the subalgebra of MV -algebra of the real unit interval [0; 1], where S m = {0; 1=m;:::;m 1=m; 1} (0 m!). Note that we have an increasing sequence of subvarieties: K 1 K 2 K 3 MMV. Theorem 17. ( ) ( ) MMV = V MMV n = V K n : n! n! Proof. The theoremimmediately follows fromcorollary of TheoremII.4.1 in [16], rephrasing the one in algebraic terms. Let D(k; n)={{x 1 ;:::;x k } :(x 1 ;:::;x k ) Sn k ; [{x 1 ;:::;x k }]=S n }, where [{x 1 ;:::;x k }] is the subalgebra of S n generated by the set {x 1 ;:::;x k }. One can dene a unique monadic operator on Sn k, which corresponds to m-relatively complete linearly ordered MV -subalgebra, converting the algebra Sn k into a simple monadic MV -algebra. This subalgebra coincides with the greatest diagonal subalgebra, i.e. (Sn k )={(x;:::;x) Sn k : x S n }. Denote this monadic MV -algebra by (Sn k ; ). In this case the monadic operator is dened as follows: (x 1 ;:::;x k )=(x j ;:::;x j ), where x j = max(x 1 ;:::;x k ). Operator is dened dually: (x 1 ;:::;x k )=(x i ;:::;x i ), where x i = min(x 1 ;:::;x k ). Theorem 18. The algebra (F n ; n )= n m+1 m=1 k=1 {x 1;:::; x k } D(k;m) (S {x1;:::; x k} m ; ) is the free cyclic algebra over the variety K n with free generator g(n)=((x 1 ;:::; x k )) (k {1;:::; m+1};{x1;:::; x k } D(k; m)), where {x 1 ;:::;x k } is the cardinal number of the set {x 1 ;:::;x k }, where 16n!. Proof. In order to prove the theoremwe need some auxiliary assertions.

A. Di Nola, R. Grigolia / Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 128 (2004) 125 139 135 First note that when k =1, n (S m x ; ) m=1 {x} D(1;m) is the free cyclic MV -algebra over the subvariety of the variety of all MV -algebras generated by S 1 S n, which is described in [10,6]. According to Corollary 14, here we identify (S m ; ) with S m. Claim 19. Monadic MV -algebra (S {x1;:::; x k} m ; ) is generated by (x 1 ;:::;x k ) S {x1;:::; x k} m, where x 1 x k, for any k {1;:::;m+1}. Proof. Since {x 1 ;:::;x k } generates S m, either there exists x i {x 1 ;:::;x k } such that g:c:d:(num(x i );m)=1(g:c:d: = the greatest common divisor, num(x) = numerator of x), or there exist x i ;x j {x 1 ;:::;x k } such that g:c:d:(num(x i ); num(x j );m) = 1. According to McNaughton criterion [14], in the rst case there exists an MV -polynomial q such that q(x i )=1=m, and in the second case there exists a polynomial p such that p(x i ;x j )=1=m. Consider both cases. In the rst case q((x 1 ;:::;x k ))=(y 1 ;:::;y i 1 ; 1=m; y i+1 ;:::;y k )=a for some y 1 ;:::; y i 1 ;y i+1 ;:::;y k ) S m. Then ( (m 1)a = (m 1)y 1 ;:::;m 1 ) m ;:::;(m 1)y k ; (m 1)a ((m 1)a)? = (:::; 1m ) ;::: = b: Since any component of b is equal to either 0 or 1=m; b =(1=m;:::;1=m;:::;1=m). Hence, by means of the operation we can get every element of S {x1;:::; x k} m. Further, u( b) (x 1 ;:::;x k )) m, for u =1;:::;m, give us the elements (0; 1;:::;1);:::; (0;:::;0; 1; 1), (0;:::;0; 1). Applying on these elements the operations?; ; we get the elements (1; 0;:::;0), (0; 1; 0;:::;0);:::;(0;:::;1; 0); (0;:::;0; 1). Therefore from such elements, by means of MV -polynomials, we obtain every element of S {x1;:::; x k} m. In the second case consider the element ((x 1 ;:::;x k ) (x 1 ;:::;x k ) )=(x i ;:::;x i ). Then, since {x 1 ;:::;x k } generates S m, there exists an x j such that g:c:d:(num(x i ); num(x j );m) = 1, and according to McNaughton criterion, there exists a polynomial p such that p(x i ;x j )=1=m. Consequently, one has p((x 1 ;:::;x j ;:::;x k ); (x i ;:::;x i )) = (y 1 ;:::;y i 1 ; 1=m; y i+1 ;:::;y k ) for some y 1 ;:::;y i 1 ;y i+1 ;:::;y k S m. After that we act similarly to the rst case. Claim 20. If k m +1, then (S k m; ) is not generated by one generator. Proof. First observe that when k = m+1, then the generator of (S m+1 m ; ) is(0; 1=m;:::; m 1=m; 1). Let us suppose that k m+ 1 and (x 1 ;:::;x k ) S k m generates (S k m; ). Then at least two components, say x i and x j (i j), of the generator are equal. Therefore,

136 A. Di Nola, R. Grigolia / Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 128 (2004) 125 139 for any MMV -polynomial pp((x 1 ;:::;x k )) will have equal elements on ith and jth positions. It means that (S k m; ) is not generated by (x 1 ;:::;x k ) S k m. Claim 21. Let {x 1 ;:::;x k }; {y 1 ;:::;y k } D(k; m) and {x 1 ;:::;x k } {y 1 ;:::;y k }. Then there is no isomorphism :(S {x1;:::; x k} m ; ) (S {y1;:::; y k} m ; ) such that ((x 1 ;:::;x k )) = (y 1 ;:::;y k ). Proof. Observe that (S r m; ) is simple (r!). Therefore, any automorphism of the algebra is generated by a permutation of factors of the direct product. Then the claim follows fromthe fact that {x 1 ;:::;x k } {y 1 ;:::;y k }. Claim 22. The monadic MV -algebra algebra n m+1 m=1 k=1 {x 1;:::;x k } D(k;m) (S {x1;:::;x k} m ; ) is cyclic. The element g(n)=((x 1 ;:::;x k )) (k {1;:::; m+1};{x1;:::; x k } D(k; m)) is the generator of the algebra. Proof. Let us generate a subalgebra A of the algebra F n by the element ((x 1 ;:::; x k )) (k {1;:::; m+1};{x1;:::; x k } D(k; m)). Since (x 1 ;:::;x k ) S {x1;:::; x k} m generates S {x1;:::; x k} m, A is the subdirect product of the algebras S {x1;:::; x k} m. Since S {x1;:::; x k} m is simple, the canonical projections correspond to maximal ideals of the algebra A, say J 1 ;:::;J r. Then J 1 J r = {0}. On the other hand, according to Corollary 11(b), (J 1 J i 1 ) Ji = A, where i =2;:::;r. Therefore, according to [4], A is isomorphic to the direct product of the algebras S {x1;:::; x k} m. Lemma 23. Any cyclic subdirectly irreducible K n -algebra is a homomorphic image of the algebra (F n ; n ). Proof. The proof immediately follows from Claims 19 22 and the construction of the algebra (F n ; n ). Now, we are in a position to prove Theorem 18. Indeed, it is sucient to show that if the polynomial identity p = q on one variable does not hold in the variety K n, then p = q does not hold in F n. Let us suppose that p = q does not hold in K n. Then p = q does not hold in some nite subdirectly irreducible MMV -algebra A on some element a, where a generates A. Then, according to Lemma 23, A is a homomorphic image of (F n ; n ). Denote this homomorphism by, and set (g(n)) = a. Hence p = q does not hold in (F n ; n ). According to Theorem 18 we have (F 1 ; 1 )=(S 1 ; ) 2 (S 2 1; );

A. Di Nola, R. Grigolia / Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 128 (2004) 125 139 137 which is a free monadic Boolean algebra (see also [1]), with and g(1)=(1; 0; (1; 0)) 1 (g(1)) = (1; 0; (1; 1)); (F 2 ; 2 )=(F 1 ; 1 ) (S 2 ; ) (S 2 2; ) 2 (S 3 2; ); g(2)=(g(1); 1=2; (0; 1=2); (1; 1=2); (0; 1=2; 1)); 2 (g(2)) = ( 1 (g(1)); 1=2; (1=2; 1=2); (1; 1); (1; 1; 1)); (F 3 ; 3 )=(F 2 ; 2 ) (S 3 ; ) 2 (S 2 3; ) 5 (S 3 3; ) 4 (S 4 3; ); g(3)=(g(1);g(2); (1; 2=3); (1; 1=3); (1=3; 2=3); (2=3; 0); (1=3; 0); (1; 2=3; 0); (1; 1=3; 0); (1=3; 2=3; 0); (1=3; 2=3; 1)); 3 (g(3)) = ( 1 (g(1)); 2 (g(2)); (1; 1); (1; 1); (2=3; 2=3); (2=3; 2=3); (1=3; 1=3); (1; 1; 1); (1; 1; 1); (2=3; 2=3; 2=3); (1; 1; 1)): By an inverse system in a category C we mean a family {B i ; ij } i I of objects, indexed by a directed poset I, together with a family of morphisms ij : B j B i, for each i6j, satisfying the following conditions: (i) kj = ki ij for all k6i6j; (ii) ii =1 Bi for every i I. For brevity we say that {B i ; ij } is an inverse systemin C. We will not specify in which category we take an inverse systemwhen it is evident fromthe context. The inverse limit of an inverse systemis an object B of C together with a family i : B B i of morphisms (which is often denoted by {B; i }) satisfying the condition: ij j = i for i6j, and having the following universal property: for any object D of C together with a family of morphisms i : D B i,if ij j = i for i6j, then there exists a morphism : D B such that i = i for any i I. The inverse limit of the above systemis denoted by lim{b i ; ij } I, and its elements by (b i ) i I, with b i B i.if ij is understood, we may simply write lim{b i } I. Recall fromgratzer [8] that the inverse limits of families of algebras are constructed in the following way: Suppose {B i } i I is an inverse family of algebras. Consider their product i I B i. Call (b i ) i I i I B i a tread, if ij (b j )=b i for j i. Let B be the subset of i I B i consisting of all treads. Hence { B = (b i ) i I } B i : ij (b j )=b i ; j i : i I

138 A. Di Nola, R. Grigolia / Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 128 (2004) 125 139 It is known from[8] that B is a subalgebra of i I B i, and that B is isomorphic to lim {B i } I. Let us consider the inverse limit (F ; ) = lim {(F i ; i ); ij }! of the inverse system {(F i ; i ); ij }!, with onto homomorphisms ij :(F j ; j ) (F i ; i ) for i6j, and its subalgebra (F; ), generated by g =(g(1); g(2);:::), where g(i) is the free generator of (F i ; i ): (F 1 ; 1 ) (F 2 ; 2 ) (F ; ) - (F; ): Theorem 24. The monadic MV -algebra (F; ) is the free cyclic algebra over the variety MMV with the free generator g. Proof. It is well known that because of the fact that MMV is generated by n! K n we only need to show that every mapping g a to an algebra A with generator a belonging to some K n can be extended to a homomorphism from F to that algebra A. But if A K n, then there is a homomorphism h : F n A such that h(g(n)) = a, and h n F : F A is the needed homomorphism extending the mappings g a, where n is the canonical projection. Acknowledgements Authors are grateful to L.P. Belluce for reading the manuscript and useful advices. We also express our gratitude to the referee for her/his suggestions to improve the readability of this paper. References [1] H. Bass, Finite monadic algebras, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. (1958) 258 268. [2] L.P. Belluce, Further results on innite valued predicate logic, J. Symbolic Logic 29 (1964) 69 78. [3] L.P. Belluce, C.C. Chang, A weak completeness theorem for innite valued rst-order logic, J. Symbolic Logic 28 (1963) 43 50. [4] G. Birkho, Lattice Theory, Providence, Rhode Island, 1967. [5] C.C. Chang, Algebraic analysis of many-valued logics, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 88 (1958) 467 490. [6] A. Di Nola, R. Grigolia, G. Panti, Finitely generated free MV -algebras and their automorphism groups, Stud. Logica 61 (1998) 65 78. [7] G. Georgescu, A. Iurgulescu, I. Leustean, Monadic and Closure MV-Algebras, Multi. Val. Logic 3 (1998) 235 257. [8] G. Gratzer, Universal Algebra, 2nd ed., Springer, New York, 1978. [9] R. Grigolia, Algebraic analysis of Lukasiewicz Tarski n-valued logical systems, Selected Papers on Lukasiewicz Sentential Calculi, Wroclaw, 1977, pp. 81 91. [10] R. Grigolia, Free Algebras of Non-Classical Logics, Metsniereba Press, Tbilisi, 1987. [11] L.S. Hay, An axiomatization of the innitely many-valued calculus, M.S. Thesis, Cornell University, 1958. [12] J. Lukasiewicz, A. Tarski, Unntersuchungen uber den Aussagenkalkul, Comptes Rendus des seances de la Societe des Sciences et des Lettres de Varsovie 23 (cl iii) (1930) 30 50. [13] P. Mangani, On certain algebras related to many-valued logics, Boll. Un. Mat. Ital. 4 (1973) 68 78. [14] R. McNaughton, A theoremabout innite-valued sentential logics, J. Symbolic Logic 16 (1951) 1 13.

A. Di Nola, R. Grigolia / Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 128 (2004) 125 139 139 [15] D. Mundici, Interpretation of AF C -algebras in Lukasiewicz sentential calculus, J. Funct. Anal. 65 (1986) 15 63. [16] J.D. Rutledge, A preliminary investigation of the innitely many-valued predicate calculus, Ph.D. Thesis, Cornell University, 1959. [17] B. Scarpellini, Die Nichtaxiomatisierbarkeit des unendlichwertigen Pradikaten-kalkulus von Lukasiewicz, J. Symbolic Logic 27 (1962) 159 170. [18] D. Schwartz, Theorie der polyadischen MV-Algebren endlicher Ordnung, Math. Nachr. 78 (1977) 131 138. [19] D. Schwartz, Polyadic MV-algebras, Zeit. f. math. Logik und Grundlagen d. Math. 26 (1980) 561 564.