Making Sense. Tom Carter. tom/sfi-csss. April 2, 2009

Similar documents
CHAPTER 1. Introduction

PROOF-THEORETIC REDUCTION AS A PHILOSOPHER S TOOL

Big Bang, Black Holes, No Math

Astronomy H161 An Introduction to Solar System Astronomy Winter Quarter 2009 Prof. Gaudi Homework #4. Due Monday, February 9 in class

Physics 107 Ideas of Modern Physics. Goals of the course. How is this done? What will we cover? Where s the math?

Lecture 4: Constructing the Integers, Rationals and Reals

Last few slides from last time

Q25: Record the wavelength of each colored line according to the scale given.

Discrete Structures Proofwriting Checklist

Introduction to Logic and Axiomatic Set Theory

Direct Proofs. the product of two consecutive integers plus the larger of the two integers

Error Correcting Codes Prof. Dr. P. Vijay Kumar Department of Electrical Communication Engineering Indian Institute of Science, Bangalore

Introduction to Metalogic

How we do science? The scientific method. A duck s head. The problem is that it is pretty clear that there is not a single method that scientists use.

Russell s logicism. Jeff Speaks. September 26, 2007

Things to do today. Terminal, Astronomy is Fun. Lecture 24 The Science of Astronomy. Scientific Thinking. After this lecture, please pick up:

Physics 107 Ideas of Modern Physics (uw.physics.wisc.edu/~rzchowski/phy107) Goals of the course. What will we cover? How do we do this?

Math 300: Foundations of Higher Mathematics Northwestern University, Lecture Notes

Introduction to Algebra: The First Week

PTOLEMY DAY 6 THE SEXAGESIMAL SYSTEM AND THE NEED FOR A TABLE OF CHORDS AND ARCS

Superposition - World of Color and Hardness

MATH2206 Prob Stat/20.Jan Weekly Review 1-2

Introduction to Basic Proof Techniques Mathew A. Johnson

Gravity Well Demo - 1 of 9. Gravity Well Demo

Section 3- The history and future of space exploration

Discrete Mathematics for CS Fall 2003 Wagner Lecture 3. Strong induction

D. A system of assumptions and principles applicable to a wide range of phenomena that has been repeatedly verified

2.1 Definition. Let n be a positive integer. An n-dimensional vector is an ordered list of n real numbers.

This is a brief overview of some of the very basic and classic laws of physics and how magnetic energy theory fits into those laws.

Projects in Geometry for High School Students

The paradox of knowability, the knower, and the believer

If Earth had no tilt, what else would happen?

MA554 Assessment 1 Cosets and Lagrange s theorem

PHYS 340 ( From Atoms to the Universe ): SECTION A

Big Bang, Black Holes, No Math

Final Exam Comments. UVa - cs302: Theory of Computation Spring < Total

Chapter 4. The Origin Of Modern Astronomy. Is okay to change your phone? From ios to Android From Android to ios

Is there life outside of Earth? Activity 2: Moving Stars and Their Planets

Cosets and Lagrange s theorem

Primary KS1 1 VotesForSchools2018

DIFFERENTIAL EQUATIONS

Introducing Proof 1. hsn.uk.net. Contents

Quadratic Equations Part I

The Scientific Method

Modern Algebra Prof. Manindra Agrawal Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur

Quantum Entanglement. Chapter Introduction. 8.2 Entangled Two-Particle States

Section 1.2: Propositional Logic

Learning Objectives. one night? Over the course of several nights? How do true motion and retrograde motion differ?

, (1) e i = ˆσ 1 h ii. c 2016, Jeffrey S. Simonoff 1

Lesson Plan: Star Gazing By: Darby Feldwinn

The Physics of Boomerangs By Darren Tan

Three objects; 2+1 problem

Earth/matriX SCIENCE TODAY. The Sun Earth Moon Relation: Polar/Mean/Equatorial Diameters and Circumferences

Galileo Educator Network

Section 29: What s an Inverse?

e π i 1 = 0 Proofs and Mathematical Induction Carlos Moreno uwaterloo.ca EIT-4103 e x2 log k a+b a + b

Most of the time during full and new phases, the Moon lies above or below the Sun in the sky.

CS 124 Math Review Section January 29, 2018

Introduction To Modern Astronomy I

Hestenes lectures, Part 5. Summer 1997 at ASU to 50 teachers in their 3 rd Modeling Workshop

Announcements. Topics To Be Covered in this Lecture

35 Chapter CHAPTER 4: Mathematical Proof

Calculational Problems

Name: Earth 110 Exploration of the Solar System Assignment 1: Celestial Motions and Forces Due on Tuesday, Jan. 19, 2016

Models of the Solar System, Gravitation and the motion of the Planets A.K.A DEAD WHITE GUYS WEEK! 1/28/14

COPENHAGEN INTERPRETATION:

Today. Review. Momentum and Force Consider the rate of change of momentum. What is Momentum?

Deep Algebra Projects: Algebra 1 / Algebra 2 Go with the Flow

1 Propositional Logic

Teaching the Geocentric Model Dr. David H Bradstreet Distributed by Spitz, Inc

INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC

11 Newton s Law of Universal Gravitation

THE GREAT SUN-EARTH-MOON LINE-UP

PHILOSOPHY OF PHYSICS (Spring 2002) 1 Substantivalism vs. relationism. Lecture 17: Substantivalism vs. relationism

Chapter 6. Net or Unbalanced Forces. Copyright 2011 NSTA. All rights reserved. For more information, go to

CHAPTER 2 Strand 1: Structure and Motion within the Solar System

Supplementary Logic Notes CSE 321 Winter 2009

BROCK UNIVERSITY. 1. The observation that the intervals of time between two successive quarter phases of the Moon are very nearly equal implies that

How Astronomers Learnt that The Heavens Are Not Perfect

Science. Is this course science? A. Yes B. No

Philosophy of Mathematics Structuralism

Eigenvectors and Hermitian Operators

= v = 2πr. = mv2 r. = v2 r. F g. a c. F c. Text: Chapter 12 Chapter 13. Chapter 13. Think and Explain: Think and Solve:

Uncertainty. Michael Peters December 27, 2013

Direct Proof and Counterexample I:Introduction

PHY1033C/HIS3931/IDH 3931 : Discovering Physics: The Universe and Humanity s Place in It Fall Prof. Peter Hirschfeld, Physics

1.1 The Language of Mathematics Expressions versus Sentences

Newton s Law of Motion

Critical Notice: Bas van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective Oxford University Press, 2008, xiv pages

Direct Proof and Counterexample I:Introduction. Copyright Cengage Learning. All rights reserved.

Observing the Solar System 20-1

MAT Mathematics in Today's World

BROCK UNIVERSITY. 1. The observation that the intervals of time between two successive quarter phases of the Moon are very nearly equal implies that

Lecture 6: Finite Fields

How the Greeks Used Geometry to Understand the Stars

An experiment to test the hypothesis that the Earth is flat. (Spoiler alert. It s not.)

INTRODUCING NEWTON TO SECONDARY SCHOOL STUDENTS

Lecture 17 Ptolemy on the Motion of the Earth


Today in class Review: The Sky and Celestial Motion The Science and History of Planetary Motion

Transcription:

Making Sense Tom Carter http://astarte.csustan.edu/ tom/sfi-csss April 2, 2009 1

Making Sense Introduction / theme / structure 3 Language and meaning 6 Language and meaning (ex)............... 7 Theories, models and simulation 8 Theories, models and simulation (ex).......... 28 References 29 2

Introduction / theme / structure This is a brief introduction to some thoughts about making sense of the world. We all make sense of the world in many ways all the time, but we don t always do it consciously, nor do we necessarily have rigorous / structured approaches to the project... My goal here is to talk some about how I go about building theories, models and simulations that I can use to make the world make more sense to me and also that I can use as parts of explanations to help others see the world in potentially more useful ways. As a teacher/researcher, I m always looking for more illumination, and better ways to reveal that illumination. 3

One important point for me is that in general in these sorts of projects, I am much more interested in epistemology than in ontology. Just briefly, what are ontology and epistemology? I tend to think about them this way: Ontology: What is there? (i.e., questions of being ) Epistemology: How do we know? (i.e., questions of knowledge ) In many respects, I see these as two of the main (or the main two) branches of philosophy, and especially of philosophy of science. They tend to have convergences and divergences, but they drive much philosphizing (and much argumentation over angels and heads of pins... :-) 4

Ontological questions tend to litter the fields of science: What are the fundamental elements? Are there just four of them? What is the Fifth Element? Is it the quintessence, or just a so-so sci-fi movie? Does caloric exist? Does phlogiston exist? Are there atoms, or not? Do electrons exist? Does the force of gravity exist? What is a gene? What is a species? What is life? Does Truth exist? For the most part, I think these questions are largely irrelevant. In many respects, I think they are very often the wrong kinds of questions for scientists to ask... Epistemological questions also abound: What can we know? How can we best go a trying to learn (gain knowledge) about the world? What role does evidence play in understanding systems? How meaningful is deduction within axiomatic contexts? 5

Language and meaning Hmmm... This is a placeholder for some things I want to write about, but haven t yet. Reference and Platonism Use and Wittgenstein What is meaning, and how does it happen? 6

Language and meaning - exercises 1. Explain why meaning is use is meaningful. 7

Theories, models and simulation What is a theory? This turns out (at least in a socio-cultural sense) to be a rather difficult question. One fairly traditional notion is to use ideas from mathematics. In this form, a theory is a collection of axioms, definitions, rules of inference, symbols, objects, relations, etc. (e.g., the theory of Euclidean Geometry). One can (in theory :-) derive results within the theory, and engage in a general hypothetico-deductive cycle. One makes a hypothesis within the framework of the theory, and then checks to see if the hypothesis is derivable within the theory. A fundamental question one can ask at this stage is whether the theory is consistent i.e., whether the collection of axioms, etc., is logically consistent. 8

A straightforward example of this is the mathematical theory of Groups. A group is a quadruple (G,, 1, e), where G is a set (of group elements), : G G G is a binary operation, 1 : G G is a unary operation (the inverse in G), and e G is a distinguished element of G (the identity element) satisfying the axioms, for g, g 1, g 2, g 3 G: 0. g 1 g 2 G and g 1 G (closure under and 1 ) 1. (g 1 g 2 ) g 3 = g 1 (g 2 g 3 ) (associativity) 2. e g = g e = g (identity element) 3. g g 1 = g 1 g = e (inverses) 9

(Note that we don t really need axiom 0, since we require that and 1 be a binary and unary operation (respectively) on G, but it is traditional to emphasize the closure property(s)). Given these axioms, we can prove various things. For example, the identity element e is unique: If a g = g for all g G, then a = a e = e (axiom 2, and then the property of a). Similarly, inverses are unique: if g a = a g = e, then a = a e = a (g g 1 ) = (a g) g 1 = e g 1 = g 1. The next step, then, would be to try to construct an interpretation of the theory (what might also be called a model). In general, this would be a mapping from object 10

and relation (etc.) symbols in the theory to specific objects, relations, etc., external to the theory. This process can sometimes be relatively straightforward, and other times remarkably problematic... For example, it is easy to check that the integers form a group under addition (i.e., the quadruple (Z, +,, 0) satisfies the group axioms). We then have the nice property that any theorem we have proven using the group axioms is automatically satisfied by the integers. Similarly we can develop notions of symmetry groups and crystallographic groups, with a variety of interesting applications... 11

An observation we can make here is that the existence of a model of a given theory assures us that the theory is consistent. But a somewhat more subtle question is the Truth question. Does it make sense to ask whether Group Theory is True? I have to say, I can t really make sense of that question. It certainly is the case that Group Theory is consistent (it has models), and it is certainly very useful in many contexts, but True? I don t know... 12

Perhaps more interesting are attempts to construct interpretations to real-world objects and phenomena. Unfortunately, this can be quite subtle in particular, difficulty typically arises in confirming that the axioms actually hold in the interpretation. We can now enter into another level of hypothetico-deductive cycle. We make observations in the realm external to the theory, then turn the crank to get predictions, make more observations, and see if the results match (e.g., we do experiments ). At this point, we are likely to have to make some sense of what we have seen, and decide what to do next. 13

Perhaps it would be worth going through a specific example, to see some of the issues. Imagine for a moment that it is around 1300 C.E., and you work for the Grand Vizier. He (and the King) believe that the planets affect one s life, and they demand that you cast the King s horoscope. In other words, you are to describe (in some detail) what the sky would look like at a particular time and place (perhaps some 35 years prior). Your first observation is that most of the points of light (stars) in the night sky are fixed. Of course, even this much requires a significant degree of abstraction if you hold your gaze fixed with respect to the ground you stand on, the stars will move they will rotate during the night. The stars are fixed with respect to each other. Notice that there is also a (covert) assumption that the 14

stars I see tonight are the same stars I saw last night. I can have my graduate students (apprentices :-) draw maps of the (relative) positions of the stars on successive nights, noting the strong similarities between the maps, I can then make the (simplifying) assumption that they are the same stars. Part of what I am pointing out here is that in building a theory there are innumerable background (often unspoken) assumptions necessarily underlying the theory. It is probably worth noting that if the theory doesn t work, it may be (is?) a nontrivial exercise to figure out which of the explicit and/or implicit assumptions might be changed to get the theory to work... We can now observe (with various caveats... ) that the planets move with respect to the fixed stars. Making various assumptions about regularity, continuity, and 15

simplicity in general, we want to build a model (an orrery?) of the (relative) motions of the planets. What are the constraints within which we will build our model? A first major constraint is that the planets, being celestial objects, will move in perfect ways, and since the circle is the most perfect of shapes, they will move along circular paths. Thus we start building our theory. Our theory: The fixed stars are on an encompassing immense sphere. The planets move on circular paths within the sphere. The planets move continuously, smoothly, and at a constant rate along their paths. Each (circular) path has a fixed center and a fixed radius. We now build a specific model. For each planet, we choose (determine) a specific center, radius, and rate of travel. Without much thought, the circles are all coplanar. 16

Here is a first picture: 17

Or, perhaps a better way to think about it: Here the observer (us) looks at the world through the theory/model (from within a perhaps unacknowledged paradigm). The theory/model becomes a lens through 18

which the world is viewed. This lens serves to select/emphasize certain aspects of the world. Notice that the prediction of the model does not exactly match the world... Now what do we do? Given that the prediction of our model does not exactly match the world, we have several choices. First, we could declare the match good enough, take the money from the Grand Vizier, and go on our way. Second, we could modify our model, by changing various parameters (radii, centers, rate of motion, etc.). We could then check each of these revised models to see if one was good enough. 19

We might notice that some particular aspects of the phenomena are not consistent with the model. For example, we might notice that the motion of Mars is sometimes retrograde: If none of the revised models was good enough, we might replace our theory with a different one. In this case (remaining in the same paradigm ) we might allow our planets to move in circles upon circles (i.e., epicycles), so that sometimes the planet would move backward. 20

Here s the next: We now have lots of parameters we can adjust. We could also add epicycles upon epicycles upon... (and, by Fourier, make things match pretty much as well as we want... ). 21

On the other hand, we could even go so far as to step to a new paradigm, and allow our theory to include the earth as one of the moving bodies (no longer distinguishing between celestial and terrestrial), and even allow the paths to be other conic sections, such as ellipses. We might make an orrery like this, with an actual physical crank we can turn: 22

Hmmm. Are we done now? What do we want a theory/model to do for us? It seems to me in various contexts we would like it to 1. Give us a good description of the system 2. Allow us to predict behavior of the system 3. Give us an explanation of the system 4. Allow us to control the system A nice heliocentric theory/model (Keplerian, say) can do a very good job of describing the solar system, and can allow us to make good predictions (or retrodictions) of the behavior, but it doesn t give us much in the way of an explanation of the system. In the next step, things get very interesting. 23

Enter Isaac Newton. In the new paradigm, we allow new entities to exist in our theory/model forces. In particular, gravitational force. The picture looks very similar to what we had before: 24

Note, though, that the new entity gravitational force, shown as an arrow in the model, does not correspond with any observed entity in the world... No one has ever observed the gravitational force (i.e., the force itself). People have observed things falling, and drawn the conclusion that there must be a force that causes the things to fall, but the force is not anything anyone has observed it is an entity in the model. The supposed existence of the force in the world is a conclusion drawn from the model, not through direct observation. Within the paradigm of forces and differential equations, etc., it is easy to imagine that we are seeing the effects of forces, but it is worth remembering that we are always already looking at the world through the lenses of our models, and it is all to easy to mistake aspects of the lens for real phenomena in the world... 25

One more, to clarify the last observation. In general relativity, an object follows a geodesic within a curved spacetime, with curvature determined by local masses. Note that there is no force of gravity in this model... 26

On building models: My general policy when building a model is to start with the absolute minimum to get the model off the ground. In order to do this, I have to observe / think about the system long and hard, thinking about what might possibly be irrelevant to the aspects of the system s behavior in which I am interested. (See, for example, my economics models... ) There must be more to come, but I ll stop writing here for now, and talk instead :-) 27

Theories, models and simulation - exercises 1. What sorts of relations can there be between models and reality? 28

References [1] Fox Keller, Evelyn, Making Sense of Life, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 2002. To top 29