Let us first solve the midterm problem 4 before we bring up the related issues.

Similar documents
1.4 Cardinality. Tom Lewis. Fall Term Tom Lewis () 1.4 Cardinality Fall Term / 9

MATH 3300 Test 1. Name: Student Id:

Math 4603: Advanced Calculus I, Summer 2016 University of Minnesota Notes on Cardinality of Sets

Cardinality and ordinal numbers

1 Partitions and Equivalence Relations

Notes on ordinals and cardinals

5 Set Operations, Functions, and Counting

DO FIVE OUT OF SIX ON EACH SET PROBLEM SET

Section 7.5: Cardinality

Math 455 Some notes on Cardinality and Transfinite Induction

Exercises for Unit VI (Infinite constructions in set theory)

Basic set-theoretic techniques in logic Part III, Transfinite recursion and induction


Axioms for Set Theory

Date: October 24, 2008, Friday Time: 10:40-12:30. Math 123 Abstract Mathematics I Midterm Exam I Solutions TOTAL

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers

MATH FINAL EXAM REVIEW HINTS

S15 MA 274: Exam 3 Study Questions

In N we can do addition, but in order to do subtraction we need to extend N to the integers

Chapter 1. Sets and Mappings

ADVANCED CALCULUS - MTH433 LECTURE 4 - FINITE AND INFINITE SETS

Chapter 6 Cardinal Numbers and Cardinal Arithmetic

20 Ordinals. Definition A set α is an ordinal iff: (i) α is transitive; and. (ii) α is linearly ordered by. Example 20.2.

Extended Essay - Mathematics

ON A QUESTION OF SIERPIŃSKI

MATH 13 SAMPLE FINAL EXAM SOLUTIONS

Finite and Infinite Sets

6 CARDINALITY OF SETS

Mathematics Course 111: Algebra I Part I: Algebraic Structures, Sets and Permutations

Axioms of separation

Sets, Models and Proofs. I. Moerdijk and J. van Oosten Department of Mathematics Utrecht University

Initial Ordinals. Proposition 57 For every ordinal α there is an initial ordinal κ such that κ α and α κ.

INDEPENDENCE OF THE CONTINUUM HYPOTHESIS

REVIEW FOR THIRD 3200 MIDTERM

Math 4606, Summer 2004: Inductive sets, N, the Peano Axioms, Recursive Sequences Page 1 of 10

S. Mrówka introduced a topological space ψ whose underlying set is the. natural numbers together with an infinite maximal almost disjoint family(madf)

Functions and cardinality (solutions) sections A and F TA: Clive Newstead 6 th May 2014

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals

MORE ABOUT SPACES WITH A SMALL DIAGONAL

X = { X f X i A i : (œx, y 0 X)[x /= y œi[ x i /= y i ]]}.

(1) Which of the following are propositions? If it is a proposition, determine its truth value: A propositional function, but not a proposition.

1.3. The Completeness Axiom.

MAT115A-21 COMPLETE LECTURE NOTES

Thus, X is connected by Problem 4. Case 3: X = (a, b]. This case is analogous to Case 2. Case 4: X = (a, b). Choose ε < b a

Class Notes on Poset Theory Johan G. Belinfante Revised 1995 May 21

Outside ZF - Set Cardinality, the Axiom of Choice, and the Continuum Hypothesis

Introduction to Proofs in Analysis. updated December 5, By Edoh Y. Amiran Following the outline of notes by Donald Chalice INTRODUCTION

Week Some Warm-up Questions

Introduction to Proofs

MATH31011/MATH41011/MATH61011: FOURIER ANALYSIS AND LEBESGUE INTEGRATION. Chapter 2: Countability and Cantor Sets

CSE 20 DISCRETE MATH. Fall

Solution. 1 Solutions of Homework 1. 2 Homework 2. Sangchul Lee. February 19, Problem 1.2

Countability. 1 Motivation. 2 Counting

Topology. Xiaolong Han. Department of Mathematics, California State University, Northridge, CA 91330, USA address:

SOME TRANSFINITE INDUCTION DEDUCTIONS

Chapter One. The Real Number System

Abstract Measure Theory

MATH 220 (all sections) Homework #12 not to be turned in posted Friday, November 24, 2017

INTRODUCTION TO CARDINAL NUMBERS

Essential Background for Real Analysis I (MATH 5210)

Mathematics 220 Workshop Cardinality. Some harder problems on cardinality.

Some Basic Notations Of Set Theory

NAME: Mathematics 205A, Fall 2008, Final Examination. Answer Key

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO ZFC. Contents. 1. Motivation and Russel s Paradox

Math 3361-Modern Algebra Lecture 08 9/26/ Cardinality

Math 105A HW 1 Solutions

Theorems. Theorem 1.11: Greatest-Lower-Bound Property. Theorem 1.20: The Archimedean property of. Theorem 1.21: -th Root of Real Numbers

Sets and Infinity. James Emery. Edited: 2/25/ Cardinal Numbers 1. 2 Ordinal Numbers 6. 3 The Peano Postulates for the Natural Numbers 7

CHAPTER 8: EXPLORING R

Clearly C B, for every C Q. Suppose that we may find v 1, v 2,..., v n

Real Analysis Math 131AH Rudin, Chapter #1. Dominique Abdi

Introduction to Set Theory

Unsolvable problems, the Continuum Hypothesis, and the nature of infinity

PRACTICE PROBLEMS: SET 1

HOMEWORK ASSIGNMENT 6

CORES OF ALEXANDROFF SPACES

MATH 102 INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL ANALYSIS. 1. Some Fundamentals

Economics 204 Summer/Fall 2011 Lecture 2 Tuesday July 26, 2011 N Now, on the main diagonal, change all the 0s to 1s and vice versa:

Cardinality of Sets. P. Danziger

On Transfinite Cardinal Numbers

Functions. Definition 1 Let A and B be sets. A relation between A and B is any subset of A B.

VI I : The Axiom of Choice and related properties

One-to-one functions and onto functions

MATH 13 FINAL EXAM SOLUTIONS

Economics 204 Fall 2011 Problem Set 1 Suggested Solutions

Extension of continuous functions in digital spaces with the Khalimsky topology

Chapter 2 Metric Spaces

MATH 201 Solutions: TEST 3-A (in class)

Discrete Mathematics. W. Ethan Duckworth. Fall 2017, Loyola University Maryland

Solutions to Tutorial 8 (Week 9)

CHAPTER 7. Connectedness

Well Ordered Sets (continued)

The Two Faces of Infinity Dr. Bob Gardner Great Ideas in Science (BIOL 3018)

Section 0.7. The Axiom of Choice, Order, and Zorn s Lemma

Infinite constructions in set theory

ON THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SETS AND GROUPS

Lecture Notes on Discrete Mathematics. October 15, 2018 DRAFT

WHY ISN T THE CONTINUUM PROBLEM ON THE MILLENNIUM ($1,000,000) PRIZE LIST?

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ).

A SYSTEM OF AXIOMATIC SET THEORY PART VI 62

Transcription:

Math 310 Class Notes 6: Countability Let us first solve the midterm problem 4 before we bring up the related issues. Theorem 1. Let I n := {k N : k n}. Let f : I n N be a one-toone function and let Im(f) be the image (range) of f in N. Then there is a one-to-one function g : I n Im(f) such that g is order-preserving in the sense that g(x) < g(y) if x < y. Proof. Let us do induction on n. For n = 1, there is nothing to prove. Suppose the statement is true for n. Let f : I n N be one-to-one. Let l I n be such that w := f(l) is the least element of Im(f) whose existence is quaranteed by the well-ordering principle. Define a function h : I n Im(f)\{w} given by h(z) = f(z) for z < l and h(z) = f(z+1) for z l. Then h is one-to-one and onto (why?), so that by the induction hypothesis there is an order-preserving function k : I n Im(f) \ {w}. Now define the function g : I n Im(f) such that g(1) = w and g(z) = k(z 1) for z 2. It is readily checked that g is one-to-one and onto and order-preserving (why?). Corollary 2. If f : I m I n is one-to-one, then m n. In particular, if f is one-to-one and onto, then m = n. Proof. By Theorem 1, there is a one-to-one and onto function g : I m Im(f) such that g is order-preserving. We claim that g(x) x for all x I m. Suppose this is not the case. Then there is a least element k in I m such that g(k) < k. It is clear that k > 1 as g(1) 1 always holds. Now g(k 1) k 1, and so by the fact that g is order-preserving we have g(k) > g(k 1) k 1, so that g(k) k. This is a contradiction. Thus g(x) x for all x I m. But then as g(m) I n we see n g(m) m. This settles the first statement. When f is one-to-one and onto, f 1, the inverse function to f, is also one-to-one. Hence we also have n m for f 1 in addition to m n for f. So m = n. Definition 3. A set S is said to be a finite set if there is a bijective (one-to-one and onto) function f : I m S for some m N. m is called the cardinality of S. Otherwise, S is said to be an infinite set. 1

2 Note that the cardinality of a finite set is well-defined. This is because if f : I n S and g : I m S are both bijective, then g 1 f : I n I m is bijective, so that m = n by Corollary 2. Theorem 4. Any subset of I m is a finite set. More generally, any subset of a finite set is a finite set; in particular, if A is an infinite subset of B, then B is infinite. Proof. It suffices to prove the first statement, for which we use induction on n. The statement is automatically true for n = 1. Suppose it is true for n. Let S be a subset of I n. If S I n, then the induction hypothesis implies that S is a finite set; the induction is complete. Otherwise n S. The set S 1 = S \ {n } is a subset of I n, so that by the induction hypothesis there is a bijective function f : I m S 1, with m n by Corollary 2. The function g : I m S defined by g(z) = f(z) for z I m and g(m ) = n is bijective, proving that S is a finite set. The induction is done. Definition 5. A set S is said to be countable if there is a bijective function f : N S. Theorem 6. N is an infinite set. Proof. Suppose N is finite. Let f : I m N be a bijective function for some m N. By Theorem 1 we know there is a bijective function g : I m Im(f) that is also order-preserving. But then all the elements of Im(f) will be no greater than g(m), and since Im(f) = N by the assumption that f is an onto map, we are forced to have that all natural numbers will be no greater than g(m). This is absurd as g(m) + 1 > g(m). Hence N is infinite. Corollary 7. Any countable set is an infinite set. Proof. Otherwise, there would be a bijective function f : I m S for some m N. However, there is a bijective function g : N S. Hence, the bijective composite function g 1 f : I m N, where g 1 denotes the function inverse to g, would make N a finite set, which is absurd. Before proving the next theorem, let us look at a generalized recursion theorem. Theorem 8. Let V be a set and let f : V V be a function. Let c be a fixed element in V. Then there is a unique function g : N V such that g(1) = c and g(x ) = f(g(x)).

Proof. It goes verbatim with the proof of the recursion theorem in Class Notes 5. The only change is that we must consider the set N V when coming up with the function g, as its range lies in V. Theorem 9. Let S be an infinite subset of N. Then S is countable. Proof. Let V be the power set of N; the elements of V are all subsets of N. Consider the function f : V V defined by f : A N A \ {the least element of A} if A, and defined by f( ) =. Let c = S in V. Then by Theorem 8, there is a function g : N V such that g(1) = S and g(x ) = f(g(x)). To illustrate, g(1) = S, g(2) = S \ {the least element of S} := S 1, g(3) = S 1 \ {the least element of S 1 } := S 2, etc. We first claim that when x < y, then the least element of g(x) does not belong to g(y), so long as g(x). We fix x and do induction on k N with y = x + k. For k = 1 we have y = x. Since g(x ) = g(x) \ {the least element of g(x)}, the statement is certainly true. Assume the statement is true for k with y = x + k. That is, we have now x < y and the least element of g(x) does not belong to g(y). Then g(y ) = g(y) \ {the least element of g(y)} and so certainly the least element of g(x) does not belong to g(y ) with y = x + k. So the statement holds for k. The induction is completed and the claim proven. We claim next that g(x) for all x N. Suppose the contrary. Then there is an x N for which g(x) =. By the well-ordering principle, there is a least m N such that g(m) =. Note that m > 1 as g(1) = S since S is infinite. It follows that for all natural numbers k < m, we have g(k). Consider the function H : I m 1 S N defined by H : k the least element of g(k) for 1 k m 1. We show H is one-to-one. This is because we have verified four paragraphs above that if 1 k < l m 1 then the least element of g(k) does not belong to g(l), whereas H(k) = H(l) would force the least element of g(k) to belong to g(l), which is impossible. We show H is onto. Suppose the contrary. Then there is an element z S such that z is not the least element of any g(k), 1 k m 1. We claim that z g(y) for all 1 y m 1. This is true for y = 1 because g(1) = S and z S. Suppose the claim is not true; let k, 2 k m 1, be the least natural number such that z / g(k). Since now z g(k 1), the fact that g(k) = g(k 1) \ {the least element of g(k 3

4 1)}, z g(k 1) and z is not the least element of g(k 1) imply that z g(k). This is a contradiction. Therefore, z g(y) for all 1 y m 1; in particular z g(m 1). But then, exactly the same argument establishes that z g(m) =, which is absurd. So, H is onto. That H is one-to-one and onto means that S is a finite set, which contradicts the infinitude of S. The contradiction verifies the validity of the claim that g(x) for all x N. Define now the function K : N S given by K : x the least element of g(x). An easy induction argument warrants that K is order-preserving, that is, K(x) < K(y) if x < y (why?). It follows from another easy induction argument that K(x) x for all x N (why?). The same argument for the function H ensures that K is one-to-one. We show K is onto. Suppose K is not onto; let z S \Im(K). Then an induction argument similar to that for H gives that z g(x) for all x N, which forces that z > the least element of g(x) = K(x) x for all x N. This is absurd. Hence K is onto. In conclusion, S is countable. Corollary 10. Let f : N S be an onto function. If S is an infinite set, then S is a countable set. Proof. Since f is an onto map, we know for each y S, there is an x N such that f(x) = y. Let T y be the subset of N consisting of natural numbers m such that f(m) = y. Then T y is not empty as x is in it. Hence the well-ordering principle implies that T y has the least element; call it n y. Consider the function h : S N, where h(y) = n y. (Why is h a function?) Observe h is one-to-one (why?) so that it follows that Im(h) is an infinite subset of N (why?). Therefore, Im(h) is countable by Theorem 9. Hence S is also countable (why?). Corollary 11. Let S be a countable set and let f : S T be an onto function. If T is infinite, then T is countable. Proof. Why? Corollary 12. Let A and B be two countable sets. Then A B is countable.

Proof. Let f : N A and g : N B be two one-to-one and onto functions identifying N with A and B, respectively. Consider the set C := {(n, z n ) : n N, z n A B, z n = f(k) if n = 2k, and z n = g(k) if n = 2k+1} C is countable via the function n (n, z n ). Now consider the onto map π : C A B defined by π : (n, z n ) z n. Since A is countable and hence infinite by Corollary 7, we see A B is also infinite by Theorem 4. Then the ontoness of π and Corollary 11 applied to π assert that A B is countable. Theorem 13. N N is countable. More generally, if A and B are countable sets, then A B is countable. Proof. For any (p, q) N N with p + q = n + 1 we define the function F : (p, q) N N q + (n 1)n/2 N. Check F is one-to-one and onto. (Why is this true?) Corollary 14. Q is countable. Proof. By Corollary 12, it suffices to show that Q +, the set of positive rational numbers is countable. Consider the map f : N N Q + given by f : (m, n) n/m. Now Q is an infinite set as it contains N. Corollary 11 and Theorem 13 then finish the proof. Definition 15. A set S is said to be uncountable if it is neither finite nor countable. Theorem 16. The power set 2 N of N is uncountable. Proof. 2 N is the set whose elements are all subsets of N. Suppose 2 N is countable and let f : N 2 N be a one-to-one and onto function. Consider the set S := {x N : x / f(x)}. Since S 2 N and since f is onto, we see there is a y N such that f(y) = S. If y f(y) = S, then y / f(y) by the definition of S; this is a contradiction. So, y / f(y). But then y S = f(y) by the definition of S. This is again a contradiction. Therefore, f does not exist. That is, 2 N is uncountable.. 5

6 Remark 17. More generally, the method in Theorem 16 shows that there are no onto functions from any set A to its power set 2 A, though there is a one-to-one function from A to 2 A that sends a A to {a} 2 A. Definition 18. We say set A and set B have the same cardinality, denoted card(a)=card(b), if there is a one-to-one and onto function between them. Theorem 19. card(r) = card(2 N ). The proof will be given in class. Definition 20. We say set A is dominated by set B, denoted card(a) card(b), if there is a one-to-one function f : A B. We say set A is strictly dominated by set B, denoted card(a) < card(b), if A is dominated by B and there are no functions g that map A one-to-one and onto B. Intuitively, A is strictly dominated by B if the size of A is smaller than the size of B. A set is thus strictly dominated by its power set by Remark 17. In particular, card(n) < card(r) by Theorem 19. Cantor s Continuum Hypothesis. There are no sets A satisfying card(n) < card(a) < card(r). Through Kurt Gödel and Paul Cohen s deep works, we know the Continuum Hypothesis is independent of the axioms of set theory! A Final Remark About The Axiom Of Choice We know N is well-ordered with respect to the standard < we have defined. The question naturally arises as to whether every set can be well-ordered. Definition 21. A relation < on a set S is said be an order if for any elements x, y S, one and only one of the following holds: (1) x = y; (2) x < y; (3) y < x. A set S with an order < is said to be well-ordered by < if every nonempty subset of S has the least element. For a well-ordered set we have the following induction theorem Theorem 22. (Transfinite induction) Let X be well-ordered by <. Suppose a subset S of X has the property: Then we conclude S = X. ( ) x S if {y X : y < x} S.

Proof. Suppose S X. Let x 0 be the samllest element of X \ S. Then every y < x 0 lies in S, since x 0 is the smallest element not in S. So by (*) we assert x 0 S, a contradiction. Hence S = X. Note that if y X is the least element, then y S automatically. This is because the set {z X : z < y} = S. Therefore, y S by (*). Of course, when X = N with the usual <, the transfinite induction is just the mathematical induction. Theorem 23. (The Well-ordering Principle) Every set can be wellordered if and only if the axiom of choice holds. For a proof of this theorem, see Naive Set Theory by Paul Halmos. The idea is to utilize the concept of ordinal numbers. Therefore, every set can be well-ordered. 7