DIVIDING AND WEAK QUASI-DIMENSIONS IN ARBITRARY THEORIES

Similar documents
HINDMAN S THEOREM AND IDEMPOTENT TYPES. 1. Introduction

Representing Scott Sets in Algebraic Settings

Representing Scott Sets in Algebraic Settings

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007)

Stable embeddedness and N IP

VAUGHT S THEOREM: THE FINITE SPECTRUM OF COMPLETE THEORIES IN ℵ 0. Contents

EXISTENTIALLY CLOSED II 1 FACTORS. 1. Introduction

ISAAC GOLDBRING AND THOMAS SINCLAIR

Scott Sentences in Uncountable Structures

ISAAC GOLDBRING AND BRADD HART

Properly forking formulas in Urysohn spaces

A New Spectrum of Recursive Models Using An Amalgamation Construction

TRANSFERING SATURATION, THE FINITE COVER PROPERTY, AND STABILITY

Partial Collapses of the Σ 1 Complexity Hierarchy in Models for Fragments of Bounded Arithmetic

SPECTRA OF ATOMIC THEORIES

Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory

Hrushovski s Fusion. A. Baudisch, A. Martin-Pizarro, M. Ziegler March 4, 2007

AN APPROXIMATE LOGIC FOR MEASURES

Weight and measure in NIP theories

Disjoint n-amalgamation

The constructible universe

LINDSTRÖM S THEOREM SALMAN SIDDIQI

EXCURSIONS IN MODEL THEORY

A generalization of modal definability

Introduction to Model Theory

HOW DO ULTRAFILTERS ACT ON THEORIES? THE CUT SPECTRUM AND TREETOPS

Qualifying Exam Logic August 2005

SEPARABLE MODELS OF RANDOMIZATIONS

arxiv:math.lo/ v1 28 Nov 2004

DISJOINT-UNION PARTIAL ALGEBRAS

Limit computable integer parts

Stable embeddedness and N IP

Definable henselian valuation rings

Model theory of algebraically closed fields

AN INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC STABILITY THEORY

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

An uncountably categorical theory whose only computably presentable model is saturated

The nite submodel property and ω-categorical expansions of pregeometries

Mathematics 114L Spring 2018 D.A. Martin. Mathematical Logic

A NEW LINDELOF SPACE WITH POINTS G δ

PETER A. CHOLAK, PETER GERDES, AND KAREN LANGE

Strong theories, burden, and weight

tp(c/a) tp(c/ab) T h(m M ) is assumed in the background.

This is logically equivalent to the conjunction of the positive assertion Minimal Arithmetic and Representability

A Hanf number for saturation and omission: the superstable case

A SIMPLE PROOF OF THE MARKER-STEINHORN THEOREM FOR EXPANSIONS OF ORDERED ABELIAN GROUPS

Imaginaries in Boolean algebras.

Forcing and Group Theory

INTERPRETING HASSON S EXAMPLE

Forking and Dividing in Random Graphs

AMS regional meeting Bloomington, IN April 1, 2017

Lecture 2: Syntax. January 24, 2018

VC-DENSITY FOR TREES

Annals of Pure and Applied Logic

ω-stable Theories: Introduction

Introduction. Itaï Ben-Yaacov C. Ward Henson. September American Institute of Mathematics Workshop. Continuous logic Continuous model theory

MATHEMATICS: CONCEPTS, AND FOUNDATIONS Vol. II - Model Theory - H. Jerome Keisler

PRESERVATION THEOREMS IN LUKASIEWICZ MODEL THEORY

HIGH DENSITY PIECEWISE SYNDETICITY OF PRODUCT SETS IN AMENABLE GROUPS

A Note on Graded Modal Logic

More Model Theory Notes

CONVEXLY ORDERABLE GROUPS AND VALUED FIELDS

arxiv: v1 [math.oa] 18 Oct 2013

ULTRAPRODUCTS AND MODEL THEORY

Axioms for Set Theory

PETER A. CHOLAK, PETER GERDES, AND KAREN LANGE

A MODEL-THEORETIC PROOF OF HILBERT S NULLSTELLENSATZ

Generic cuts in models of Peano arithmetic

Introduction to Model theory Zoé Chatzidakis CNRS (Paris 7) Notes for Luminy, November 2001

Isomorphisms of Non-Standard Fields and Ash s Conjecture

ARTEM CHERNIKOV AND SERGEI STARCHENKO

Pseudo-finite model theory

VC-MINIMALITY: EXAMPLES AND OBSERVATIONS

March 3, The large and small in model theory: What are the amalgamation spectra of. infinitary classes? John T. Baldwin

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

ON VC-MINIMAL THEORIES AND VARIANTS. 1. Introduction

Model theory, algebraic dynamics and local fields

There are infinitely many set variables, X 0, X 1,..., each of which is

Algebras with finite descriptions

Characterizing First Order Logic

FINITE MODEL THEORY (MATH 285D, UCLA, WINTER 2017) LECTURE NOTES IN PROGRESS

Foundations of Mathematics

arxiv: v2 [math.lo] 3 Nov 2011

EXTERNAL AUTOMORPHISMS OF ULTRAPRODUCTS OF FINITE MODELS

A LOCAL CHARACTERIZATION OF VC-MINIMALITY

Stat 451: Solutions to Assignment #1

Model theory for metric structures

Model theory of bounded arithmetic with applications to independence results. Morteza Moniri

Lecture 11: Minimal types

Applications of model theory in extremal graph combinatorics

Model Theory MARIA MANZANO. University of Salamanca, Spain. Translated by RUY J. G. B. DE QUEIROZ

Handout: Proof of the completeness theorem

Mathematical Logic II

Math 225A Model Theory. Speirs, Martin

Local Homogeneity. June 17, 2004

3. Only sequences that were formed by using finitely many applications of rules 1 and 2, are propositional formulas.

Tame definable topological dynamics

Proof Theory and Subsystems of Second-Order Arithmetic

Meta-logic derivation rules

. Final submission March 21, 2010 compiled: March 21, 2010 ON THE n-back-and-forth TYPES OF BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS

Transcription:

DIVIDING AND WEAK QUASI-DIMENSIONS IN ARBITRARY THEORIES ISAAC GODBRING AND HENRY TOWSNER Abstract. We show that any countable model of a model complete theory has an elementary extension with a pseudofinite-like quasidimension that detects dividing. 1. Introduction In a pseudofinite structure, every set S has a size S, a nonstandard cardinality. It is reasonable to say that S and T are similar in size if log S log T is bounded (by a natural number). This gives the notion of fine pseudofinite dimension [3, 2], the quotient of log S by a suitable convex set. García shows [1] that the fine pseudofinite dimension detects dividing: roughly speaking, if φ(x, b) divides over ψ(x, a) then there is a b with tp(b /a) = tp(b/a) so that the dimension of φ(x, b ) is strictly stronger than the dimension of ψ(x, a). We give a limited extension of this to model complete theories in relational languages (and, via Morleyization, to any theory): any countable model whose theory is model complete embeds elementarily in a large fragment of a pseudofinite structure in such a way that the notion of dimension pulls back to the original model; moreover, if φ(x, b) divides over ψ(x, a) then there is a b in an elementary extension with tp(b /a) = tp(b/a) so that the dimension of φ(x, b ) is strictly stronger than the dimension of ψ(x, a). There is a straightforward way to embed a countable structure in a pseudofinite structure, namely embed M in an ultraproduct of its finite restrictions. That being said, this embedding need not be elementary. It is also easy to obtain a dimension-like function that detects dividing by linearizing the partial order on definable sets given by dividing. The dimension here, however, is an abelian group, and even a quotient of R. We would like to thank Dario García for useful comments on an earlier draft of this note. 2. Construction et be a countable first-order relational signature and let T be a complete, model complete theory in. Set := {V α : α < ω + ω}, where the V α are fresh unary relation symbols. For the sake of readability, if M is Goldbring s work was partially supported by NSF CAREER grant DMS-1349399. 1

2 ISAAC GODBRING AND HENRY TOWSNER an -structure and α < ω+ω, we let V α (M) denote the interpretation of the symbol V α in M. Occasionally we might abuse notation and write a formula in the form x V α ( ) to mean x( i V α(x i ) ). All -structures considered will have the property that the interpretations of the V α s will form a chain: if α < β < ω + ω, then V α (M) V β (M). By a partitioned -formula we mean a triple (ϕ, x, y), where ϕ is a - formula, x and y are disjoint finite tuples of variables (taken from some fixed countably infinite list of variables), and the free variables of ϕ are amongs those appearing in x and y. We follow traditional model-theoretic notation by writing ϕ( x; y) for the partitioned formula (ϕ, x, y). We let F denote the set of partitioned quantifier-free -formulae. et (σ i : i < ω) denote an enumeration of F (ω + ω). For i < ω, we write σ i = (ϕ i, α i ) and sometimes refer to α i by α(σ i ). We say that an -structure M strongly satisfies σ i if, whenever a V αi (M) is such that there is N M with N = T and b N such that N = ϕ i ( a; b), then there is c V αi +1(M) such that M = ϕ i ( a; c). For each n ω, we define an -structure M n = T with the property that if i < n, M n strongly satisfies σ i. et M 0 denote a one-element substructure of a model of T whose unique element satisfies each V α. Suppose we have constructed M n 1. Consider the first n pairs σ 0,..., σ n 1 and fix a permutation σ r0,..., σ rn 1 so that i j implies that α(σ ri ) α(σ rj ). We construct -structures Mn i = T, for i = 0,..., n, by recursion on i in such a way that Mn i strongly satisfies σ r0,..., σ ri 1. We will then set M n := Mn n. et Mn 0 = M n 1. Suppose that Mn i has been constructed and set α := α(σ ri ) and let ϕ( x; y) be the formula in σ ri. Enumerate the tuples of length x in V α (Mn) i as a 1,..., a k. models Mn i,j ; we begin with Mn i,0 We now recursively construct a sequence of = Mn. i Given Mn i,j, we proceed as follows: If there is a b V α+1 (Mn i,j ) such that Mn i,j M i,j+1 n := M i,j n, = φ( a j ; b), then set Otherwise, if there is an extension M of Mn i,j and a tuple b from M such that M = φ( a j ; b), then set Mn i,j+1 := Mn i,j { b} and declare that any element of b which is not in V α+1 (Mn i,j ) belongs to V α+1 (Mn i,j+1 ) \ V α (Mn i,j+1 ). If neither of the first two cases apply, set Mn i,j+1 = Mn i,j. Set Mn i+1 := Mn i,k+1. Since V α (Mn i+1 ) = V α (Mn), i we see that Mn i+1 still strongly satisfies σ r0,..., σ ri 1; moreover, by design, Mn i+1 also strongly satisfies σ ri, thus finishing the recursive construction. Fix a nonprincipal ultrafilter U on ω and set M := U M n. By definition, V α (M) = {x M : M V α (x)}. We also set V <ω (M) := n<ω V n(m) and V (M) := α<ω+ω V α(m), both considered as -structures in the obvious way.

DIVIDING AND WEAK QUASI-DIMENSIONS IN ARBITRARY THEORIES 3 Since T is model-complete, it has a set of -axioms. Suppose that x yϕ( x; y) is such an axiom. Fix α < ω + ω and take i such that σ i = (ϕ( x; y), α). Fix n > i and consider N = T such that M n N. Since N = T and M n strongly satisfies σ i, we have M n = x V α y V α+1 ϕ( x; y). It follows that M = x V α y V α+1 ϕ( x; y). This proves: Proposition 2.1. V <ω (M) and V (M) are both models of T. There is no guarantee that V ω (M) nor M are models of T. Note that V (M) is existentially closed in M. Indeed, M = T and every model of T is an existentially closed model of T (by model-completeness of T ). emma 2.2. Suppose that p( x) is a countable set of existential -formulae with parameters from V α (M) that is finitely satisfiable in V (M) (equivalently, in M). Then there is c V α+1 (M) such that V (M) = p( c). Proof. et p ( x) := p( x) {V α+1 ( x)}. Since M is countably saturated, it suffices to show that p ( x) is finitely satisfiable in M. Indeed, we then get c V α+1 (M) such that M = p( c); since V (M) is existentially closed in M (as remarked above), we have that V (M) = p( c). In addition, since the formulae in p are existential and, to show that M = x V α+1 zφ( x, z, a) it clearly suffices to show M = x V α+1 z V α+1 φ( x, z, a), it suffices to assume that the formulae in p are actually quantifier-free. We are left with showing the following: if ϕ( x, a) is a quantifier-free formula with parameters from V α (M) such that V (M) = xϕ( x, a), then V (M) = x V α+1 ϕ( x, a). Since M = xϕ( x, a), we get M n = xϕ( x, a n ) for U-almost all n, where ( a n ) is a representative sequence for a. Fix i such that σ i = (ϕ( x, y), α). Since M n strongly satisfies σ i for n > i, it follows that, for U-almost all n, we can find c n V α+1 (M n ) such that M n = ϕ( c n, a n ). emma 2.3. Suppose N is a model of T and A N is countable. Then there is A V <ω (M) such that tp N (M) (A) = tpv (A ). Proof. Enumerate A = {a 0, a 1,...} and construct A M inductively: given a 0,..., a n V n+1 (M) with tp N (a 0,..., a n ) = tp V (M) (a 0,..., a n), by the previous lemma and the model-completeness of T (so every type is determined by its existential formulae), there is an a n+1 V n+2(m) with tp N (a n+1/a 0,..., a n ) = tp V (M) (a n+1 /a 0,..., a n). We now fix a countable model N of T and take A = N in the above lemma, yielding an elementary embedding a a : N V <ω (M) with image N. Definition 2.4. For an -formula ϕ( x), we let ϕ ω ( x) := ϕ( x) V ω ( x). emma 2.5. Suppose that ϕ( x, y) and ψ( x, z) are existential -formulae. If N = x(ϕ( x, a) ψ( x, b)), then M = x(ϕ ω ( x, a ) ψ ω ( x, b )). Proof. Since a a is elementary, we get V <ω (M) = x(ϕ( x, a ) ψ( x, b )). Since V <ω (M) V (M) (by model-completeness of T ), the same equivalence

4 ISAAC GODBRING AND HENRY TOWSNER holds in V (M). Finally, if c V ω (M), then M = ϕ ω ( c, a ) if and only if V (M) = ϕ ω ( c, a ) and likewise with ψ ω. We recall the notion of pseudofinite dimension, especially as considered in [3, 2]. Since M is an ultraproduct of finite sets, any definable set D has a nonstandard cardinality D in R (the ultrapower of the reals). We let C be the convex hull of Z in R. Then for any definable set X, we can define δ M (X) = log X /C, the image of log X in R /C { } (where log X = if X = 0). This is the fine pseudofinite dimension. The fine pseudofinite dimension satisfies the quasi-dimension axioms: δ M ( ) = and δ M (X) > implies δ M (X) 0, δ M (X Y ) = max{δ M (X), δ M (Y )}, For any definable function f : X Z and every α R /C { }, if δ M (f 1 (z)) α for all z Z then δ M (X) α + δ M (Z). One of the features of fine pseudofinite dimension is that if we fix any definable set X, we may define a measure µ X (Y ) on definable Y by µ X (Y ) = st( Y X ) so that δ M(Y ) = δ M (X) if and only if µ X (Y ) (0, ). In light of the lemma above, the following definition makes sense. Definition 2.6. Suppose X N k is definable. Without loss of generality, we may suppose that X is defined by ϕ( x, a), where ϕ( x, y) is quantifierfree. We then define δ N (X) = δ M (ϕ ω ( x, a )), where the latter dimension is computed in the pseudofinite structure M. emma 2.7. δ N (X Y ) = δ N (X) + δ N (Y ) Proof. Suppose X and Y are defined by ϕ( x, a) and ψ( y, b) respectively. Then X Y is defined by ρ( x, y, a, b) = ϕ( x, a) ψ( y, b). Then δ N (X Y ) = δ M (ρ ω ( x, y, a, b)) = δ M (ϕ ω ( x, a))+δ M (ψ ω ( y, b)) = δ N (X)+δ N (Y ). using the pseudofinite axioms for δ M. δ N need not satisfy the final quasi-dimension axiom, however it is possible that there are many values z Z ω so that δ(f 1 (z)) is large and so δ M (X ω ) is large as well, but that none of these are in the image of M, so δ N (X) is large even though δ N (f 1 (z)) is small for all z Z. Nonetheless, there is a connection between δ N and dividing, essentially the one shown by García in [1] for pseudofinite dimension. Proposition 2.8. Suppose that ψ(x, a) and ϕ(x, b) are existential -formulae with parameters from V ω (M) such that ϕ(x, b) implies ψ(x, a) and ϕ(x, b) divides over a. Then there is b # V ω (M) with b #,a b and δ M (ϕ(x, b # )) < δ M (ψ(x, a)).

DIVIDING AND WEAK QUASI-DIMENSIONS IN ARBITRARY THEORIES 5 Proof. Assume that no b # exists as in the conclusion. We then use that to get K N such that K ϕ ω (x, b # ) ψ ω (x, a) for all b # V ω (M) with b #,a b. In fact, by saturation again, there is χ(x, a) tp M (b/a) such that K ϕ ω (x, b # ) ψ ω (x, a) for all b # = χ ω (x, a). Fix sufficiently large (depending only on k and K) and take (b i ) i< from V <ω (M) satisfying χ ω (x, a) and such that {ϕ(x, b i ) : i < } is k- inconsistent. In particular, we have K ϕ ω (x, b i ) ψ ω (x, a) for all i <. As in [1], if is sufficiently large, we get i 1 <... < i k < such that k j=1 µ ψ ω (ϕ ω (x, b ij )) > 0. In particular, there is c V ω (M) such that M = ϕ ω (c, b ij ) for all j = 1,..., k. It follows that V (M) = ϕ(c, b ij ) for j = 1,..., k, a contradiction. In the previous result, if we have ψ(x, a) and ϕ(x, b) formulae with parameters from N such that ϕ(x, b) implies ψ(x, a) and ϕ(x, b) forks over a, then we can apply the previous result with ψ(x, a ) and ϕ(x, b ). It should not be too surprising that, even in this situation, we need to look in V (M) for the desired witness to dimension drop as N is usually not saturated enough to see this dimension drop. Combining Proposition 2.8 with the remarks made in the previous paragraph yields the main result of this note: Theorem 2.9. Suppose that ψ(x, a) and φ(x, b) are existential -formulae with parameters from N such that φ(x, b) implies ψ(x, a) and φ(x, b) divides over a. Then there is an elementary extension N # of N, an extension of δ N to a quasidimension δ N # on N #, and b # N # with b #,a b and δ N #(φ(x, b # )) < δ N #(ψ(x, a)) = δ N (ψ(x, a)). Remark 2.10. Note that a similar argument applies to an arbitrary relational language by taking 0 and an 0 -structure N and letting T be the theory of the Morleyization of N. Remark 2.11. Note that the same construction applies, with only the obvious changes, to theories in continuous logic. References [1] Dario García. A note on pseudofinite dimensions and forking. ArXiv e-prints, February 2014. [2] Ehud Hrushovski. Stable group theory and approximate subgroups. J. Amer. Math. Soc., 25(1):189 243, 2012. [3] Ehud Hrushovski. On pseudo-finite dimensions. Notre Dame J. Form. og., 54(3-4):463 495, 2013. University of Illinois at Chicago, Department of Mathematics, Statistics, and Computer Science, Science and Engineering Offices (M/C 249), 851 S. Morgan St., Chicago, I 60607-7045, USA E-mail address: isaac@math.uic.edu UR: www.math.uic.edu/~isaac

6 ISAAC GODBRING AND HENRY TOWSNER University of Pennsylvania, Department of Mathematics, 209 S. 33rd Street, Philadelphia, PA 19104-6395 E-mail address: htowsner@math.upenn.edu UR: www.sas.upenn.edu/~htowsner