Draft Version D:

Similar documents
Patrick Iglesias-Zemmour

Dimension in diffeology

A homotopy theory of diffeological spaces

Dimension in diffeology

DIFFERENTIAL FORMS ON CORNERS

2 Lecture 2: Logical statements and proof by contradiction Lecture 10: More on Permutations, Group Homomorphisms 31

Lecture on Equivariant Cohomology

Noncommutative geometry and quantum field theory

Algebraic Geometry. Andreas Gathmann. Class Notes TU Kaiserslautern 2014

3. The Sheaf of Regular Functions

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ).

Mini-Course on Moduli Spaces

1. Classifying Spaces. Classifying Spaces

HYPERBOLIC DYNAMICAL SYSTEMS AND THE NONCOMMUTATIVE INTEGRATION THEORY OF CONNES ABSTRACT

2. Prime and Maximal Ideals

LECTURE 5: SOME BASIC CONSTRUCTIONS IN SYMPLECTIC TOPOLOGY

NOTES ON FINITE FIELDS

Subgroups of Lie groups. Definition 0.7. A Lie subgroup of a Lie group G is a subgroup which is also a submanifold.

2. Intersection Multiplicities

1 Categorical Background

CW-complexes. Stephen A. Mitchell. November 1997

Three Descriptions of the Cohomology of Bun G (X) (Lecture 4)

Groupoids and Orbifold Cohomology, Part 2

Topological K-theory, Lecture 3

1 Differentiable manifolds and smooth maps

10. The subgroup subalgebra correspondence. Homogeneous spaces.

The Hurewicz Theorem

Stable complex and Spin c -structures

AFFINE PUSHFORWARD AND SMOOTH PULLBACK FOR PERVERSE SHEAVES

ORBIFOLDS AND ORBIFOLD COHOMOLOGY

Holomorphic line bundles

B 1 = {B(x, r) x = (x 1, x 2 ) H, 0 < r < x 2 }. (a) Show that B = B 1 B 2 is a basis for a topology on X.

THE REPRESENTATION THEORY, GEOMETRY, AND COMBINATORICS OF BRANCHED COVERS

MA554 Assessment 1 Cosets and Lagrange s theorem

GEOMETRIC QUANTIZATION

Math 249B. Nilpotence of connected solvable groups

Introduction to Arithmetic Geometry Fall 2013 Lecture #24 12/03/2013

Math 210B. Profinite group cohomology

Cosets and Lagrange s theorem

The Fundamental Group and Covering Spaces

FILTERED RINGS AND MODULES. GRADINGS AND COMPLETIONS.

p,q H (X), H (Y ) ), where the index p has the same meaning as the

The d-orbifold programme. Lecture 5 of 5: D-orbifold homology and cohomology, and virtual cycles

L E C T U R E N O T E S O N H O M O T O P Y T H E O R Y A N D A P P L I C AT I O N S

Algebraic Geometry. Question: What regular polygons can be inscribed in an ellipse?

Lemma 1.3. The element [X, X] is nonzero.

GROUPS AND THEIR REPRESENTATIONS. 1. introduction

Characteristic classes in the Chow ring

ALGEBRA II: RINGS AND MODULES OVER LITTLE RINGS.

Math 210C. The representation ring

We then have an analogous theorem. Theorem 1.2.

0. Introduction 1 0. INTRODUCTION

Definitions. Notations. Injective, Surjective and Bijective. Divides. Cartesian Product. Relations. Equivalence Relations

Algebraic Topology Homework 4 Solutions

7. Homotopy and the Fundamental Group

121B: ALGEBRAIC TOPOLOGY. Contents. 6. Poincaré Duality

The Moment Maps in Diffeology

INTRODUCTION TO SEMIGROUPS AND MONOIDS

NOTES ON FIBER BUNDLES

An Introduction to the Stolz-Teichner Program

Math 676. A compactness theorem for the idele group. and by the product formula it lies in the kernel (A K )1 of the continuous idelic norm

1. Foundations of Numerics from Advanced Mathematics. Mathematical Essentials and Notation

Action-angle coordinates and geometric quantization. Eva Miranda. Barcelona (EPSEB,UPC) STS Integrable Systems

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory

Math 210B. Artin Rees and completions

ALGEBRAIC GROUPS. Disclaimer: There are millions of errors in these notes!

LECTURE 16: LIE GROUPS AND THEIR LIE ALGEBRAS. 1. Lie groups

Universal Algebra for Logics

First Draft, Version of / 09:02

MTH 428/528. Introduction to Topology II. Elements of Algebraic Topology. Bernard Badzioch

INTERSECTION THEORY CLASS 6

Classification of definable groupoids and Zariski geometries

STRONGLY CONNECTED SPACES

Topological properties

Math 231b Lecture 16. G. Quick

QUANTIZATION VIA DIFFERENTIAL OPERATORS ON STACKS

FOUNDATIONS OF ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY CLASS 24

The Steenrod algebra

Algebraic Curves and Riemann Surfaces

LECTURE 6: J-HOLOMORPHIC CURVES AND APPLICATIONS

NOTES ON DIFFERENTIAL FORMS. PART 5: DE RHAM COHOMOLOGY

Raynaud on F -vector schemes and prolongation

FUNDAMENTAL GROUPS AND THE VAN KAMPEN S THEOREM

A QUICK NOTE ON ÉTALE STACKS

PICARD GROUPS OF MODULI PROBLEMS II

Lecture 4 Super Lie groups

2 Metric Spaces Definitions Exotic Examples... 3

CDM. Finite Fields. Klaus Sutner Carnegie Mellon University. Fall 2018

DIFFEOLOGICAL VECTOR SPACES

An Outline of Homology Theory

THE STEENROD ALGEBRA. The goal of these notes is to show how to use the Steenrod algebra and the Serre spectral sequence to calculate things.

Lecture 7: Etale Fundamental Group - Examples

Introduction to type theory and homotopy theory

1 / A bird s-eye view of type theory. 2 A bird s-eye view of homotopy theory. 3 Path spaces and identity types. 4 Homotopy type theory

Metric spaces and metrizability

Math 300 Introduction to Mathematical Reasoning Autumn 2017 Inverse Functions

A Crash Course in Topological Groups

Formal power series rings, inverse limits, and I-adic completions of rings

Algebraic Geometry. Andreas Gathmann. Notes for a class. taught at the University of Kaiserslautern 2002/2003

3-manifolds and their groups

Transcription:

AN INTRODUCTION TO DIFFEOLOGY PATRICK IGLESIAS-ZEMMOUR Draft Version D:20180209183947+01 00 Abstract. This text presents the basics of Difffeology and the main domains: Homotopy, Fiber Bundles, Quotients, Singularities, Cartan-de Rham Calculus which form the core of diffferential geometry from the point of view of this theory. We show what makes difffeology special and relevant in regard to these traditional subjects. Introduction Since its inception, in the early 80s, Difffeology has become a totalizing alternative to traditional Diffferential Geometry 1. With its developments in Higher Homotopy Theory, Fiber Bundles, Cartan-de Rham Calculus, Moment Maps and the new Symplectic Program 2... Difffeology covers a large spectrum of traditional fiields and deploys them from singular quotients to infiinite dimensional spaces and mixing the two treating mathematical objects that are or not strictly speaking manifolds, and other constructions, on an equal footing in a common framework. We shall see some of its achievements through a series of examples, chosen because they are not covered by the geometry of manifolds, either because they involve infiinite dimensional spaces or singular quotients or both of them. The relative success of Difffeology comes from the conjunction of two strong properties of the theory: (1) First of all, the category {Difffeology} is stable under all set-theoretic constructions: sums, products, subsets and quotients. It is then a complete and co-complete category. It is also Cartesian closed, the space of smooth maps in difffeology has itself a natural functional diffeology. Date: February 9, 2018. Text of the talk given at the Conference New Spaces in Mathematics & Physics, September 28 October 2, 2015 Institut Henri Poincaré Paris, France. 1 An alternative to diffferential geometry which is totalizing, in the sense that difffeology is a theory which has the ambition to totalize (synthetize, include) the whole set of mathematical constructions generated by diffferential geometry inside of a same axiomatic corpus. 2 About the question: what does mean exactly to be symplectic in difffeology. This question is approached in [PIZ10, PIZ16, PIZ17]. 1

2 PATRICK IGLESIAS-ZEMMOUR (2) Second of all, quotient spaces, that are trivial under almost all other generalizations of diffferential calculus 3, get naturally a meaningful difffeology. That is in particular the case of irrational tori, quotients of the real line by strict subgroups. They own, as we shall see, a non trivial difffeology, capturing faithfully the intrication of the subgroup into its ambient space. This crucial property will be the raison d être of many new constructions, or wide generalizations of classical constructions, that cannot exist in almost all the other extensions of Diffferential Geometry 3. The treatment of singularities, maybe more than the inclusion of infiinite dimensional spaces, reveals how Difffeology changes the way we understand smoothness, and discriminates this theory among its various competitors, see for example the use of dimension in difffeology [PIZ07] which diffferentiates the various quotients R n /O(n). The diagram (Fig. 1) tries to show the inclusivity of Difffeology, with respect to diffferential constructions, in comparison with the classical theory. Connecting A Few Dots The story begins in the early 80s, when Jean-Marie Souriau introduces his diffféologies in a paper titled Groupes Diffférentiels [Sou80]. It is defiined as a formal but light structure on groups 4, designed a priori for dealing easily with infiinite dimensional groups of difffeomorphisms, like the group of automorphisms of a symplectic manifold. He named the groups equipped with such a structure groupes diffférentiels 5 6, and that was the title of his paper. The defiinition was made of fiive axioms that we can decompose today into a fiirst group of three which gave later the notion of difffeology on arbitrary sets, and the last two ones which were related to the compatibility of the group multiplication. But it took three years from 1980 to 1983 to separate the fiirst three axioms from the last two ones, and extract the general structure of espace diffférentiel. Souriau s work was profoundly group-oriented, especially when it came to quantization. That was the ongoing work of Paul Donato on the covering of homogeneous spaces of diffferential groups, for one part, and mostly our joint work with Paul on the irrational torus, which made urgent a formal separation between Groups and Spaces in the domain of Souriau s differential structures, as it gave a new spin at the theory. Actually, the fiirst occurrence of the wording espace diffférentiel (for differential space), between quotes appears in the paper Exemple de groupes diffférentiels : flots irrationnels sur le 3 I am referring here to the various generalizations of C diffferential geometry à la Sikorski or Frölicher [KriMic97]... I am not considering the various algebraic generalizations that do not play on the same level of intuition and generality, and do not concern exactly the same sets/objects, lattices instead of quotients for example etc. 4 Compared to functional analysis heavy structures. 5 That translates in English as Diffferential or Diffferentiable Groups. 6 Actually, diffféologies are built on the model of K.-T. Chen Differentiable Spaces [Che77], for which the structure is defiined over convex Euclidean subsets instead of open Euclidean domains. That makes difffeology more suitable to extend diffferential geometry than Chen s diffferentiable spaces, which focuses more on homology and cohomology theories.

AN INTRODUCTION TO DIFFEOLOGY 3 Figure 1 The Scope of Difffeology. tore, published as a preprint in July 1983 [DonIgl83, p.112 l.18]. We used this expression informally, for the purposes of the case, without giving a precise defiinition. The formal defiinition was published a couple of months later by Souriau in his paper Groupes diffférentiels et physique mathématique, as a preprint in October 1983 [Sou83]. As we were working intensively at this time on the foundation of this theory, it developed in a couple of years to some level in a few diffferent directions, with Souriau on generating quantum structures [Sou84], with Paul Donato doctoral dissertation on covering of homogeneous spaces, defended in 1984 [Don84], and with my own doctoral dissertation on higher homotopy theory and difffeological fiiber bundles 7, defended in 1985 [Igl85]. What follows now is an attempt to introduce the main constructions and results in Difffeology, through several meaningful examples. More details on the theory will be found in the textbook Diffeology [PIZ13]. 7 It s in this work that the wording difffeological space has been introduced, in replacement of diffferential space which would have been confused with other structures.

4 PATRICK IGLESIAS-ZEMMOUR Thanks I am grateful to the organizers of the Conference New Spaces in Mathematics and Physics, Gabriel Catren and Mathieu Anel, who gave me the opportunity to present the today state of Difffeology.

AN INTRODUCTION TO DIFFEOLOGY 5 The Unexpected Example: The Irrational Torus Let us begin with the irrational torus T α. At this time, in the early 80s, physicists were interested in quantizing 1-dimensional systems with a quasi periodic potential. That is, a function u from R to R which is the pullback of a smooth function U on a torus T 2 = R 2 /Z 2 along a line of slope α, with α R Q. If you prefer, u(x) = U(e 2iπx, e 2iπαx ), where U C (T 2,R). That problem has drawn the attention of physicists and some mathematicians to the question about the statute of the quotient space T α = T 2 / α, where α T 2 is a 1-parameter subgroup, projection from R 2 of the line y = αx, that is, α = {(e 2iπx, e 2iπαx )} x R. As a topological space T α is trivial, because α is irrational and α fiills the torus, that is, its closure is T 2. And a trivial topological space is of no help. The various diffferentiable approaches 8 lead also to dead ends, the only smooth maps from T α to R are constant maps, because the composition with the projection π : T 2 T α should be smooth. For these reasons, the irrational torus was regarded by everyone as an extremely singular space. But when we think a little bit, the irrational torus T α is a group, moreover an Abelian group, and there is nothing more regular and homogeneous than a group. And that was the point that made us 9, eager to explore T α through the approach of Diffeologies. But, difffeologies were invented to study infiinite dimensional groups, like groups of symplectomorphisms, and it was not clear that they could be of any help for the study of such singular spaces like T α. Except that, because a difffeology on a set is defiined by its smooth parametrizations, and because smooth parametrizations on T α are just (locally) the composites of smooth parametrizations into T 2 by the projection π : T 2 T α, it was already clear that the difffeology of T α was not the trivial diffeology made of all parametrizations, neither the discrete diffeology made only of locally constant parametrizations. Indeed, considering two smooth parametrizations 10 P and P in T 2 and there is a great chance that π P and π P are diffferent. And because P and P are not any parametrizations but smooth ones, that makes T α neither trivial, nor discrete. That was already a big diffference with the traditional topological or diffferential approches we mentioned above that makes T α coarse. But how to measure this non-triviality? To what ends did this new approach lead? That was the true question. We gave some answers in the paper Exemple de groupes différentiels : flots irrationnels sur le tore [DonIgl83]. Thanks to what Paul Donato had already developed at this time on the covering of homogeneous differential spaces, 8 Sikorski, Frölicher, ringed spaces etc. 9 Paul Donato and myself 10 A parametrization in a set X is just any map P defiined on some open subset U of some numerical space R n into X.

6 PATRICK IGLESIAS-ZEMMOUR and which made the core of his doctoral dissertation [Don84], we could compute the fundamental group of T α and its universal covering T α. We found that π 1 (T α ) = Z Z and Tα = R, with π 1 (T α ) included in R as Z + αz. That was a fiirst insightful result showing the capability of difffeology concerning these spaces regarded ordinarily as (highly) singular. Needless to say that since then they became completely admissible. In the second half of the seventies, the quantum mechanics of quasi-periodic potentials hit the fiield of theoretical physics. 11. And the question of the structure of the space of leaves of the linear foliation of the 2-torus sparked a new level of interest. In particular, French theoretical physicists used the techniques of Noncommutative Geometry developed by Alain Connes. So, the comparison between the two theories became a natural question. The notion of fundamental group or universal covering was missing at that time in noncommutative geometry 12, then it was not with these invariants that we could compare the two approaches. That came eventually from the following result: Theorem 1 (Donato-Iglesias, 1983). Two irrational tori T α and T β are diffeomorphic if and only if α and β are conjugate modulo GL(2,Z). That is, if there exists a matrix a b M = GL(2,Z) such that β = aα + b c d cα + d. That result had its correspondence in Connes theory, due to Marc Riefffel [Rie81], the C -algebras associated with α and β are Morita-equivalent if and only if α and β are conjugate modulo GL(2, Z). At this moment it was clear that difffeology was a serious alternative to noncommutative geometry. The advantage of difffeology was to stay close to the special intuition and concepts developed by geometers along centuries, if not millenia. Actually, because of irrationality of α and β, we showed that a difffeomorphism ϕ: T α T β could be fully lifted at the level of the covering R 2 of T 2 into an afffiine difffeomorphism Φ(Z) = AZ + B, where A preserves the lattice Z 2 R 2, that is, A GL(2,Z), and B R 2. The fact that these natural isomorphisms are preserved a minima in difffeology was of course an encouragement to continue the exploration of this example, and to push the test of difffeology even further. And that is not all what could be said, and has been said, on irrational tori. Indeed, the category {Difffeology} has many nice properties, in particular, as we shall see in the following, it is Cartesian closed. That means in particular that the set of smooth maps between difffeological spaces has a natural difffeology. We call it the functional diffeology. Thus any set of smooth maps bewteen difffeological spaces has a fundamental group, in 11 The most famous paper on the question was certainly from Dinaburg and Sinai, on The onedimensional Schrödinger equation with a quasiperiodic potential" [DS75]. 12 And are still missing today, except for a few attempts to fiill the holes [IZL16].

AN INTRODUCTION TO DIFFEOLOGY 7 Figure 2 A difffeomorphism from T α to T β. particular the group Diff(T α ) of difffeomorphisms of T α. And its computation reserves us another surprise: Theorem 2 (Donato-Iglesias, 1983). The connected component of Diff(T α ) is T α, acting by multiplication on itself. Its group of connected components is {±1} Z if α is quadratic, π 0 (Diff(T α )) = {±1} otherwise. We recall that a number is quadratic if it is solution of a quadratic polynomial with integer coefffiicients. That result was indeed discriminating, since it did not appear in any other theory pretending to extend ordinary diffferential geometry. That clearly showed that difffeology, even for such a twisted example, was subtle enough to distinguish between numbers, quadratic or not. This property was not without reminding us about the periodicity of the continued fraction of real numbers. This computation has been generalized on the π 0 (Diff(T H )) [IglLac90], where H R n is a totally irrational hyperplane and T H = T n /H.

8 PATRICK IGLESIAS-ZEMMOUR Theorem 3 (Iglesias-Lachaud, 1990). Let H R n be a totally irrational hyperplane, that is, H Z n = {0}. Let T H = T n /pr(h), where pr is the projection from R n to T n. Let w = (1, w 2,..., w n ) be the normalized 1-form such that H = ker(w). The coefficients w i are independent on Q. Let E w = Q + w 2 Q + + w n Q R be the Q-vector subspace of R generated by the w i. The subset K w = {λ R λe w E w } is an algebraic number field, a finite extension of Q. Then, π 0 (Diff(T H )) is the group of the units of an order of K w. Thanks to the Dirichlet theorem, π 0 (Diff(T H )) {±1} Z r +s 1, where r and s are the number of real and complex places of K w. Now, since we have seen what difffeology is capable of, we may have got your attention and it s time to give some details on what exactly a diffeology on an arbitrary set is. And then we shall see other applications of difffeology and examples, some of them famous. What is a Diffeology? It is maybe time to give a precise meaning to what we claimed on the irrational torus. As a preamble, let us say that, contrarily to many constructions in diffferential geometry, difffeologies are defiined just on sets, dry sets, without any pre-existing structure, neither topology nor anything else. That is important enough to be underlined and that is what also makes the diffference with the other approaches. A difffeology on a set X consists in declaring what parametrizations are smooth. Let us fiirst introduce formally a fundamental word of this theory. 1. Parametrization We call parametrization in a set X, any map P: U X such that U is some open subset of an Euclidean space. If we want to be specifiic we say that P is a n-parametrization when U is an open subset of R n. The set of all parametrizations in X is denoted by Params(X). Note that, there is no condition of injectivity on P, neither any topology precondition on X a priori. And also: we shall say Euclidean domain for open subset of an Euclidean space. Now, 2. Definition of a Diffeology A diffeology on X is any subset of Params(X) that satisfiies the following axioms. (1) Covering : contains the constant parametrizations. (2) Locality : Let P be a parametrization in X. If for all r dom(p) there is an open neighbourhood V of r such that P V, then P. (3) Smooth compatibility : For all P, for all F C (V,dom(P)), where V is a Euclidean domain, P F.

AN INTRODUCTION TO DIFFEOLOGY 9 A space equipped with a difffeology is called a diffeological space. The elements of the difffeology of a difffeological space are called the plots of (or in) the space 13. The fiirst and foremost examples of difffeological spaces are the Euclidean domains, equipped with their smooth diffeology, that is, the ordinary smooth parametrizations. Pick for example the smooth R 2, we have a difffeology on T 2 = R 2 /Z 2 by lifting locally the parametrizations in R 2. That is, a plot of T 2 will be a parametrization P: r (z r, z r ) such that, for every point in the domain of P, there exist two smooth parametrizations θ and θ, in R, defiined in the neighbourhood of this point, with (z r, z r ) = (e2iπθ(r ), e 2iπθ (r ) ). That is the usual difffeology which makes T 2 the manifold we know. But that procedure can be extended naturally to T α. Indeed, a parametrization P: r τ r in T α is a plot if there exists locally, in the neighbourhood of every point in the domain of P, a parametrization ζ: r (z r, z r ), such that τ r = π(ζ(r )). That construction is summarized by the sequence of arrows: R 2 pr T 2 π T α That is exactly the difffeology we consider when we talk about the irrational torus. But this construction of difffeologies by pushforward is actually one of the fundamental constructions of the theory. However to go there we need previously to precise an important property of difffeologies. 3. Comparing Diffeologies Inclusion defiines a partial oder in difffeology. If and are two difffeologies on a set X, one says that is fiiner than if, or is coarser than. Moreover, difffeologies are stable by intersection, that gives the following property: Proposition. This partial order, called fineness, makes the set of diffeologies on a set X, a lattice. That is, every set of diffeologies has an infimum and a supremum. As usual, the infimum of a family is obtained by intersection of the elements of the family. And the supremum is obtained by intersecting the diffeologies coarser than any element of the family. The infiimum of every difffeology, the fiinest difffeology, is called the discrete diffeology. It consists of locally constant parametrizations. The supremum of every difffeology, the coarsest difffeology, is called the coarse or trivial diffeology, it is made of all the parametrizations. As we shall see these bounds will be useful to defiine difffeologies defiined by properties (boolean functions). Now, we can write the construction by pushforward: 4. Pushing Forward Diffeologies Let f : X X be a map, let X be a difffeological space, with difffeology. Then, there exists a fiinest difffeology on X such that f 13 There is a discussion about difffeology as a sheaf theory in [Igl87, Annex]. But we do not develop this formal point of view in general, because the purpose of difffeology is to minimise the technical tools in favour of a direct, more geometrical, intuition.

10 PATRICK IGLESIAS-ZEMMOUR is smooth. It is called the pushforward of the difffeology of X. We denote it by f ( ). If f is surjective, its plots are the parametrizations P in X that can be written Sup i f P i, where the P i are plots of X such that the f P i are compatible, that is, coincide on the intersection of their domains, and Sup denotes the smallest common extension of the family {f P i } i. In particular, the difffeology of T 2 is the pushforward of the smooth difffeology of R 2 by pr, and the difffeology on T α is the pushforward of the difffeology of T 2 by π. Or, what is equivalent, the pushforward of the smooth difffeology of R 2 by the projection π pr. Note 1. Let π : X X be a map between difffeological spaces. We say that π is a subduction if it is surjective and if the pushforward of the difffeology of X coincides with the difffeology of X. In particular pr: R 2 T 2 and π : T 2 T α are two subductions. Subductions made a subcategory, since the composite of two subductions is again a subduction. Note 2. Let X be a difffeological space and be an equivalence relation on X. Let Q = X/ be the quotient set 14, that is, Q = {class(x) x X} and class(x) = {x x x}. The pushforward on Q of the difffeology of X by the projection class is called the quotient diffeology. Equipped with the quotient difffeology, Q is called the quotient space of X by. This is the fiirst important property of the category {Difffeology}, it is closed by quotient. Then, after having equipped the irrational tori with a difffeology (actually the quotient difffeology), we would compare diffferent irrational tori with respect to difffeomorphisms. For that we need a precise defiintion. 5. Smooth Maps Let X and X be two difffeological spaces. A map f : X X is smooth if for any plot P in X, f P is a plot in X. The set of smooth maps from X to X is denoted, as usual, by C (X,X ). Note 1. The composition of smooth maps is smooth. Difffeological spaces, together with smooth maps, make a category which we denote by {Difffeology}. Note 2. The isomorphisms of the category {Difffeology} are the bijective maps, smooth as well as their inverses. They are called diffeomorphisms. 6. What about Manifolds? The time has come now to make a comment on manifolds. Every manifold is naturally a difffeological space, its plots are the smooth parametrizations in the usual sense. That makes the category {Manifolds} a full and faithfull subcategory of {Difffeology}. But we should insist on that difffeology must not be understood as a generalization of the theory of manifolds. It happens that, between many other things, difffeology extends the theory of manifolds, but its true nature is to 14 I regard always a quotient set as a subset of the set of all subsets of a set.

AN INTRODUCTION TO DIFFEOLOGY 11 extend the diffferential calculus on domains in Euclidean spaces, and it is the way it should be regarded. Let us continue to explore our example of the irrational torus T α. We still have to describe its fundamental group and its universal covering. Actually, the way it was treated in the founding paper [DonIgl83] used special defiinitions adapted only to groups and homogeneous spaces. Because at this time difffeology was only about groups. It was clear at this moment that considering difffeology only on groups was insufffiicient, and that we missed a real independent theory of fiiber bundles and homotopy in difffeology. That was the content of the doctoral dissertation Fibrations Difféologiques et Homotopie [Igl85]. Let us begin with the covering thing. A covering is a special kind of fiiber bundle with a discrete fiiber. But all these terms must be understood in the sense of difffeology, especially the word discrete. Let me give an example: 7. Proposition The rational numbers Q are discrete in R. This is completely natural for everyone, except that this is false as far as topology is concerned. But we are talking difffeology: if we equip Q with the difffeology induced by R, it is not difffiicult to prove 15 that Q is discrete, that is, its difffeology is discrete. And that is the meaning we want to give to be a discrete subset of a difffeological space. Well, we still have to elaborate a little bit about induced diffeology. 8. Pulling Back Diffeologies Let f : X X be a map, let X be a difffeological space, with difffeology. Then, there exists a coarsest difffeology on X such that f is smooth. It is called the pullback of the difffeology of X. We denote it by f ( ). Its plots are the parametrizations P in X such that f P is a plot of X. In particular that gives to any subset A X, where X is a difffeological space, a subset diffeology, that is, j ( ), where j : A X is the inclusion and is the difffeology of X. A subset equipped with the subset difffeology is called a diffeological subspace. Now, it is clear what does mean a discrete subset of a difffeological space, it is a subset such that its induced difffeology is discrete. Note. Let j : X X be a map between difffeological spaces. We say that j is an induction if j is injective and if the pullback of the difffeology of X coincides with the difffeology of X. For example, in the case of the irrational torus, the injection t (e 2iπt, e 2iπαt ) from R to T 2 is an induction. That means precisely that if r (z r, z r ) is smooth in T2 but takes its values in α, then there exists a smooth parametrization r t r in R such that z r = e 2iπt r and z r = e 2iπαt r. Then, with this construction, the category {Difffeology} which was closed by quotient is also closed by inclusion. 15 A nice application of the intermediate value theorem.

12 PATRICK IGLESIAS-ZEMMOUR Now, continuing with our example, there are two reasons we need a good concept of fiiber bundle in difffeology. (a) Coverings of difffeological spaces should be defiined as fiiber bundles with discrete fiiber. (We shall see then that we are even able to build a universal covering, unique up to isomorphism, for every difffeological space.) (b) If we look closely at the projection π : T 2 T α, we observe that this looks like a fiiber bundle with fiiber α R. Thus, if the long homotopy sequence could apply to difffeological fiiber bundles, we should get immediately π 1 (T α ) = π 1 (T 2 ) = Z 2, since the fiiber R is contractible. Fiber Bundles Of course, the classical defiinition of locally trivial bundle is helpless here since T α has a trivial topology. The situation is more subtle, we are looking for a defiinition 16 that satisfiies the following two conditions: (1) The quotient of a difffeological group by any subgroup is a difffeological fiibration, whatever the subgroup is. (2) For difffeological fiibrations, the long exact homotopy sequence applies. And since we refer to difffeological groups, we have to clarify their defiinition. 9. Diffeological Group A difffeological group is a group G which is also a difffeological space such that the multiplication m : (g, g ) g g, and the inversion inv: g g 1, are smooth. That needs a comment on the product of difffeological spaces, since we refer to the multiplication in a difffeological group G which is defiined on the product G G. 10. Product of Diffeological Spaces Let {X i } i be any family of difffeological spaces. There exists on the product X = i X i a coarsest difffeology such that every projection π i : X X i is smooth. It is called the product diffeology. A plot in X is just a parametrization r (x i,r ) i such that each r x i,r is a plot of X i. Note. The category {Difffeology} is then closed by products. There are two equivalent defiinitions of difffeological bundles, this one is the pedestrian version. 11. Diffeological Fiber Bundles Let π : Y X be a map with X and Y two difffeological spaces. We say that π is a fiibration, with fiiber F, if, for every plot P: U X, the pullback pr 1 : P (Y) U with P (Y) = {(r, y) U Y P(r ) = π(y)}, 16 The defiinition of fiiber bundles in difffeology their two equivalent versions has been introduced in Fibrés Diffféologiques et Homotopie [Igl85, Thesis].

AN INTRODUCTION TO DIFFEOLOGY 13 is locally trivial with fiiber F. That is, every point in U has an open neighbourhood V such that there exists a difffeomorphism φ : V F pr 1 1 (V) P (Y), with pr 1 φ = pr 1. φ V F P pr (Y) V 2 Y pr 1 V pr 1 P V This defiinition extends the usual defiinition of smooth fiiber bundles in diffferential geometry. But it contains more: Proposition. The projection π : G G/H, where G is a diffeological group and H G is any subgroup, is a diffeological fibration. We have now the formal framework where π : T 2 T α is a legitimate fiiber bundle. This defiinition of fiiber bundle satisfiies also the long sequence of homotopy, we shall come back on the subject later. Since we have a defiinition of fiiber bundles, we inherit naturally the notion of a difffeological covering: Definition of Coverings. A covering of a diffeological space X is a diffeological fibration π : ˆX X with a discrete fiber. Note. The projection π : R R/(Z + αz) is a connected, simply connected covering, since R is a difffeological group and Z + αz a subgroup. The fact that R/(Z + αz) is difffeomorphic to T α is an exercise left to the reader. There is an alternative to the defiinition of fiiber bundles involving a groupoid of diffeomorphisms. This alternate defiinition is maybe less intuitive, but more internal to difffeology. It is based on the existence of a natural difffeology on the set of smooth maps between difffeological spaces. 12. The Functional Diffeology Let X and X be two difffeological spaces. There exists on C (X,X ) a coarsest difffeology such that the evaluation map ev: C (X,X ) X X defiined by ev(f, x) = f (x), is smooth. Thus difffeology is called the functional diffeology. Note 1. A parametrization r f r is a plot for the functional difffeology if the map (r, x) f r (x) is smooth. Note 2. There exists a natural difffeomorphism between C (X,C (X,X )) and C (X X,X ). That makes the category {Difffeology} Cartesian closed. Which is a pretty nice property. 13. Fiber Bundles: The Groupoid Approach Let π : Y X be a map with X and Y two difffeological spaces. Consider the groupoid K whose objects are the points X π

14 PATRICK IGLESIAS-ZEMMOUR of X and the arrows from x to x are the difffeomorphisms from Y x to Y x, where the preimages Y x = π 1 (x) are equipped with the subset difffeology. There is a functional diffeology on K that makes it a diffeological groupoid. The set Obj(K) = X is obviously equipped with its own difffeology. Next, a parametrization r φ r in Mor(K), defiined on a domain U, will be a plot if (1) r (src(φ r ),trg(φ r )) is a plot of X X. (2) The maps ev: U src Y and ev: U trg Y, defiined by ev(r, y) = φ r (y) and ev(r, y) = φr 1 (y), on U src = {(r, y) U Y y def(φ r )} and U trg = {(r, y) U Y y def(φr 1 )}, are smooth, where these two sets are equipped with the subset difffeology of the product U Y. We have then the following theorem [Igl85] : Theorem. The map π is a fibration if and only if the characteristic map is a subduction. χ : Mor(K) X X, defined by χ(f ) = (src(f ),trg(f )), Thanks to this approach we can construct, for every difffeological fiiber bundle, a principal fiiber bundle by spliting the groupoid with which the fiiber bundle is associated. It is possible then to refiine this construction and defiine fiiber bundles with structures (linear etc.). The next step about fiiber bundles will be the establishment of the long homotopy sequence, but that requires a preliminary preparation, beginning by the defiinition of the homotopy groups. Homotopy Theory The basis of homotopy begins by understanding what does mean to be homotopic, that is, being in the same place or component. 14. Homotopy and Connexity Let X be a difffeological space, we denote by Paths(X) the space of (smooth) paths in X, that is, C (R,X). The ends of a path γ are denoted by ˆ0(γ) = γ(0), ˆ1(γ) = γ(1) and ends(γ) = (γ(0), γ(1)). We say that two points x and x are connected or homotopic if there exists a path γ such that x = ˆ0(γ) and x = ˆ1(γ). To be connected defiines an equivalence relation whose equivalence classes are called connected components, or simply components. The set of components is denoted by π 0 (X).

AN INTRODUCTION TO DIFFEOLOGY 15 Proposition. The space X is the sum of its connected components, that is, X = X i. X i π 0 (X) Moreover, the partition in connected components is the finest partition of X that makes X the sum of its parts. It is time to give the precise defiinition of the sum of difffeological spaces that founds the previous proposition. 15. Sum of Diffeological Spaces Let {X i } i be a familly of difffeological spaces. There exists a fiinest difffeology on the sum X = X i X i such that each injection j i = x (i, x), from X i to X, is smooth. We call it the sum diffeology. The plots of X are the parametrization r (i r, x r ) such that r i r is locally constant. With that defiinition we close, by the way, one of the most interesting aspects of the category {Difffeology}. This category is stable by all the set theoretic constructions: sum, product, part, quotient. It is a complete and co-complete category, every direct or inverse limit of difffeological spaces have their natural difffeology. Moreover, the category is Cartesian closed. That is by itself very interesting, as a generalization of the smooth category of Euclidean domains. But there are a few other generalizations that have these same properties (diffferential spaces for example). What makes really the diffference is that, these nice properties apply to a category that includes non trivially extremely singular spaces, as we have seen with the irrational tori. And that is what makes {Difffeology} so unique. Let us now come back to the Homotopy Theory. 16. The Fundamental Group and Coverings Let X be a connected difffeological space, that is, π 0 (X) = {X}. Let x X be some point. We denote by Loops(X, x) Paths(X) the subspaces of loops in X, based at x. As a difffeological space, with its functional difffeology, this space has a set of components. We defiine the fundamental group 17 of X, at the point x as π 1 (X, x) = π 0 (Loops(X, x), ˆx), where ˆx is the constant loop t x. The group multiplication on π 1 (X, x) is defiined as usual, by concatenation: τ τ l(2t) if t 1/2 = class t l, (2t 1) if t > 1/2 where τ = class(l) and τ = class(l ). The inverse is given by τ 1 = class[t l(1 t)]. Actually, we work with stationary paths for the concatenation to be smooth. A stationary 17 Formally speaking, the homotopy groups are objects of the category {Pointed Sets}. In particular π 0 (X, x) = (π 0 (X), x).

16 PATRICK IGLESIAS-ZEMMOUR path is a path that is constant on a small interval around 0 and also around 1. We have now a few main results. Proposition. The groups π 1 (X, x) are conjugate to each other when x runs over X. We denote π 1 (X) their type. We say that X is simply connected if its fundamental group is trivial, π 1 (X) = {0}. Now we have the following results. Theorem [Universal Covering]. Every connected diffeological space X has a unique up to isomorphism simply connected covering π : X X. It is a principal fiber bundle with group π 1 (X). It is called the universal covering: every other connected covering is a quotient of X by a subgroup of π 1 (X). Actually the universal covering is the half of the Poincaré Groupoid, quotient of the space Paths(X) by fiixed-end homotopy relation [PIZ13, 5.15]. This is the second meaningful construction of groupoid in the development of difffeology. Monodromy Theorem. Let f : Y X be a smooth map, where Y is a simply connected diffeological space. With the notations above, there exists a unique lifting f : Y X once we fix f (y) = x, with x = f (y) and x π 1 (x). These are the more relevant constructions and results, familiar to the diffferential geometer, concerning the fundamental group on difffeological spaces. 17. Two Examples of Coverings Let us now come back to our irrational torus T α = T 2 / α = [R 2 /Z 2 ]/ α, that is, T α = R 2 /[Z 2 {(x,αx)} x R ] = [R 2 /{(x,αx)} x R ]/Z 2. The quotient R 2 /{(x,αx)} x R can be realized by R with the projection (x, y) y αx. Then, the action of Z 2 on R 2 induces the action on Z 2 on R by (n, m)(x, y) = (x + n, y +m) y +m α(x +n) = y αx +(m αn). That is, (n, m): t t +m αn. Therefore, T α R/Z + αz. Since R is simply connected, thanks to the theorem on existence and unicity of the universal covering, T α = R and the π 1 (T α ) injects in R as Z + αz. Of course there is no need all this gear of sophisticated tools to get this result, as we have seen in [DonIgl83]. But this shows how the pedestrian computation integrates seamlessly the general theory. Another example 18 of this theory, this one in infiinite dimension: the universal covering of Diff(S 1 ). The group is equipped with its functional difffeology. Let f be a difffeomorphism of S 1 = R/Z, assume that f fiixes 1. Let π : t e 2iπt, from R to S 1, be the universal covering. The composite f π is a plot. Thanks to the monodromy theorem, since R is simply connected, f π has a unique smooth lifting f : R R, such that 18 It was fiirst elaborated by Paul Donato in his dissertation [Don84]. We just reinterpret it with our tools.

AN INTRODUCTION TO DIFFEOLOGY 17 f (0) = 0. π R f R π S 1 S 1 f Then, π f = f π implies that f (t + 1) = f (t) + k, k Z, but f cannot be injective unless k = ±1. Next, f being a difffeomorphism implies that f is a difffeomorphism of R, that is a strictly increasing or decreasing function. Assume that f is increasing, then f (t + 1) = f (t) + 1. Thus, the positive diffeomorphisms of S 1 are the quotient of the increasing difffeomorphisms of R satisfying that condition. Now, let f s (t) = f (t) + s(t f (t)), with s [0,1]. We still have f s (t + 1) = f s (t) + 1 and f s (t) = s + (1 s) f (t), which still is positive. Thus, since f 0 (t) = f (t) and f 1 (t) = t, the group Diff+ (S 1 ) = { f Diff + (R) f (t + 1) = f (t) + 1} is contractible, hence simply connected. It is the universal covering of Diff + (S 1 ), the group of the positive difffeomorphisms of S 1. The monodromy theorem indicates that there is only Z diffferent liftings f of a given difffeomorphism f. Hence, π 1 (Diff + (S 1 )) = Z. 18. Higher Homotopy Groups Let X be a difffeological space and x X. Since Loops(X, x) is a difffeological space that contains ˆx : t x, there is no obstruction to defiine the higher homotopy groups by recursion: π n (X, x) = π n 1 (Loops(X, x), ˆx), n 1. One can also defiine the recursion of difffeological spaces: X 0 = X, x 0 = x X 0 ; X 1 = Loops(X 0, x 0 ), x 1 = [t x 0 ] X 1 ;...... ; X n = Loops(X n 1, x n 1 ), x n = [t x n 1 ] X n ;... Thus, π n (X, x) = π n 1 (Loops(X, x), ˆx), that is, π n (X, x) = π n 1 (X 1, x 1 ) = = π 1 (X n 1, x n 1 ) = π 0 (X n, x n ). Since π n (X, x) is the fundamental group of a difffeological space, it is a group. And that is the formal defiinition of the n-th homotopy group 19 of X at the point x. We can feel in particular here, the benefiits of considering all these spaces: X, Paths(X), Loops(X), etc., on an equal footing. Being all difffeological spaces, the recursion does not need any supplementary construction than the ones already defiined. 19. The Homotopy Sequence of a Fiber Bundle One of the most important property of difffeological fiiber bundles is their long homotopy sequence. Let π : Y X be 19 It is abelian for n = 2.

18 PATRICK IGLESIAS-ZEMMOUR a fiiber bundle with fiiber F. Then, there is a long exact sequence of group homomorphisms [Igl85], π n (F) π n (Y) π n (X) π n 1 (F) π 0 (F) π 0 (Y) π 0 (X) 0. As usual in these cases, if the fiiber is homotopy trivial then the base space has the homotopy of the total space. And that is what happens for the irrational torus π k (T α ) = π k (T 2 ), k N. Let us consider another example, in infiinite dimension this time. Let S be the infinite dimensional sphere in the Hilbert space = l 2 (C). We equip fiirst with the fiine difffeology of vector space [PIZ13, 3.7]. Then, we prove that S, equipped with the subset difffeology, is contractible [PIZ13, 4.10]. Then we consider the infinite projective space CP = S /S 1, where S 1 acts on the l 2 sequences by multiplication. The projection π : S CP is then a difffeological principal fiibration with fiiber S 1. The homotopy exact sequence gives then π 2 (CP ) = Z and π k (CP ) = 0 if k 2, what is what we expected. That would prove if necessary that we can work on singular constructions or infiinite dimensional spaces using the same tools and the same intuition than when we deal with ordinary diffferential geometry. 20. Connections on Fiber Bundles and Homotopy Invariance Let π : Y X be a principal fiiber bundle with group G. That fabricates a new principal fiibration π : Paths(Y) Paths(X) with structure group Paths(G). Roughly speaking, a connection on π is a reduction of this paths fiber bundle to the subgroup G Paths(G), consisting of constant paths [PIZ13, 8.32]. We require for this reduction to satisfy a few axioms: locallity (sheaf condition on the interval of R), compatibility with concatenation etc. The main point is that once we have a path γ in X and a point y over x = γ(t), then there exists a unique lift γ of γ such that γ(t) = y, it is called the horizontal lift. Moreover, if y = g Y (y), the lift γ of γ passing at y at the time t is the shifted γ = g Y γ. That property is exactly what we call a reduction of π to G. An important consequence of the existence of a connection on a principal fiiber bundle is the homotopy invariance of pullbacks. Proposition. Let π : Y X be a principal fiber bundle with group G, equipped with a connection. Let t f t be a smooth path in C (X,X), where X is any diffeological space. Then, the pullbacks pr 0 : f0 (Y) X and pr 1 : f1 (Y) X are equivalent. Corollary. Any diffeological fiber bundle equipped with a connection over a contractible space is trivial. We know that this is always true in ordinary diffferential geometry, because every principal bundle over a manifold can be equipped with a connection. 21. The Group of Flows of a Space Connections are usually defiined in ordinary diffferential geometry by a diffferential form with values in some Lie algebra. As we have

AN INTRODUCTION TO DIFFEOLOGY 19 seen above, that is not the way chosen in difffeology. There are a few good reasons for that. First of all, for such important property like the homotopy invariance of pullbacks, a broad defiinition of connection is enough. Moreover, we have no indisputable concept of Lie algebra in difffeology 20, and choosing one defiinition rather than another would link a universal concept, like parallel transport, to an arbitrary choice. And there is also a new difffeological construction where the diffference between generalconnections versus form-valued-connections is meaningful enough to justify a posteriori our choice. That is the computation of the group of flows over the irrational torus [PIZ13, 8.39]. Let us begin by a defiinition: Definition. We shall call flow over a diffeological space X, any (R,+)-principal bundle over X. There is an additive operation on the set Flows(X) of (equivalence classes of) flows. Let a = class(π : Y X) and a = class(π : Y X) be two classes of flows. Consider the pullback π (Y ) = {(y, y ) Y Y π(y) = π (y )}. It is a (R 2,+) principal bundle over X by (y, y ) π(y) = π (y ). Let Y be the quotient of π (Y ) by the antidiagonal action of R, that is, t(y, y ) = (t Y (y), t Y (y )). And let π : Y X be the projection π (class(y, y )) = π(y) = π (y ). We defiine then a + a = a with a = class(π : Y X). The set Flows(X), equipped with this addition, is an abelian group. The neutral element is the class of the trivial bundle, the inverse of a flow is the same bundle but with the inverse action of R. Note that this is a kind of Picard Group on a difffeological space but with R instead of S 1. And if this group doesn t appear in ordinary diffferential geometry, it is because every principal bundle with fiiber R over a manifold is trivial. But that is not the case in difffeology, and we know one such non trivial bundle, the irrational torus π : T 2 T α. Let π : Y T α be a flow. Consider the pullback pr 1 : pr (Y) R, where pr: R T α is the universal covering. It is an R-principal fiiber bundle over R, then it is trivial. Let φ : R R pr (Y) be an isomorphism. Thus Y R R/pr 2 φ. But pr 2 φ is any lifting on the second factor of R R, of the action of Z αz on the fiirst one. φ R R pr pr (Y) 2 Y pr 1 pr 1 R pr π T α 20 Even for the moment map in symplectic difffeology we do not need the defiinition of a Lie algebra, as we shall see later on.

20 PATRICK IGLESIAS-ZEMMOUR A lifting of a subgroup Γ R on the second factor of R R, where Γ acts by translation on the fiirst factor is given, for all k Γ and (x, τ) R R, by k : (x, t) (x + k, t + τ(k)(x)), where τ : Γ C (R) is a cocycle satisfying τ(k + k )(x) = τ(k)(x + k ) + τ(k )(x). Two cocycles τ and τ defiine the same flow if they difffer from a coboundary δσ: In other words, τ (k)(x) = τ(k)(x) + σ(x + k) σ(x), with σ C (R). Flows(R/Γ) = H 1 (Γ,C (R)). Applied to Γ = Z + αz, that gives Flows(T α ) equivalent to the group of real 1-periodic functions f, after some normalization, modulo the relation: f f if f (x) = f (x) + g(x + α) g(x). This relation is known as the small divisors Arnold s cohomology relation. The solution depends on the arithmetic of α: if α is a diophantine or a Liouville number, Flows(T α ) is 1-dimensional or -dimensional 21. Moreover, every flow π : Y T = R/Γ defiined by a cocycle τ, can be naturally equipped with the connection associated with the covering pr: R T [PIZ13, 8.36]. However, not all these bundles support a connection form [PIZ13, 8.37], only those whose cocycle τ defiining π is equivalent to a homomorphism from Γ to R, see [PIZ13, Exercise 139]. In other words, if the cocycle τ is not cohomologous to a homomorphism, then there is no connection which can be defiined by a connection form. In particular, for T α, the only flow equipped with connections defiined by a connection form is the Kronecker flow (with arbitrary speeds). Modeling Diffeology Now we have seen a few constructions in difffeology and applications to unusual situations: singular quotients, infiinite dimension spaces. It will be interesting to revisit some constructions of diffferential geometry, and see what difffeology can do with them. 22. Manifolds Every manifold owns a natural difffeology, for which the plots are the smooths parametrizations. There is a defiinition internal to the category difffeology 22 : Definition. An n-manifold is a diffeological space locally diffeomorphic to R n at each point. With this defiinition, as difffeological spaces, {Manifolds} form a full subcategory of the category {Difffeology}. 21 As H 1 (Γ,C (R)), the group Flows(R/Γ) is obviously a real vector space. 22 We could use too the concept of generating families, see [PIZ13, 1.66].

AN INTRODUCTION TO DIFFEOLOGY 21 Of course, this defiinition needs to precise the use of the wording locally diffeomorphic. 23. Local smooth maps, D-topology &c. Very soon after the initial works in difffeology, it was clear that we needed to enrich the theory with local considerations, which were missing until then. To respect the spirit of difffeology we defiined directly the concept of local smoothness [Igl85], as follows. Definition. Let X and X be two diffeological spaces. Let f be a map from a subset A X into X. We say that f is local smooth if for each plot P in X, f P is a plot of X. Note that f P is defiined on P 1 (A), and a fiirst condition for f P to be a plot of X is that P 1 (A) is open. That leads to the second defiinition. Definition. We say that a subset A X is D-open if P 1 (A) is open for all plots P in X. The D-open subsets in X define a topology on X called the D-Topology. We have then the following proposition linking these two defiinitions: Proposition. A map f defined on a subset A X to X is local smooth if and only if: A is D-open and f : A X is smooth when A is equipped with the subset diffeology. To avoid misunderstanding and signify that f is local smooth not just smooth for the subset difffeology we note f : X A X. Next, since we have local smooth maps, we have local diffeomorphisms too. Definition. We say that f : X A X is a local difffeomorphism if f is injective, local smooth, and if its inverse f 1 : X f (A) X is local smooth. We say that f is a local diffeomorphism at x X if there is a superset A of x such that f A: X A X is a local diffeomorphism. In particular, these defiinitions give a precise meaning to the sentence the space X is locally diffeomorphic to X at each/some point. 24. Orbifold as Diffeologies. The word orbifold was coined by Thurston [Thu78] in 1978 as a replacement for V-manifold, a structure invented by Ishiro Satake in 1956 [Sat56]. These new objects have been introduced to describe the smooth structure of spaces that look like manifolds, except around a few points, where they look like quotients of Euclidean domains by fiinite linear groups. Satake captured the smooth structure around the singularities by a family of compatible local uniformizing systems defiining the orbifold 23. The Figure 3 gives an idea about what would be an uniformizing system for the Teardrop with one conic singularity. The main problem with Satake s defiinition is that it does not lead to a satisfactory notion of smooth maps between orbifolds, and therefore prevents the conception of a category of orbifolds. Indeed, in [Sat57, page 469], Satake writes this footnote: 23 We will not discuss this construction here. The original description by Satake is found in [Sat56], and a discussion on this defiinition in [IKZ10].

22 PATRICK IGLESIAS-ZEMMOUR Figure 3 The Teardrop as Satake s Orbifold. The notion of C -map thus defined is inconvenient in the point that a composite of two C -maps defined in a different choice of defining families is not always a C map. And, for a mathematician, that is very annoying. Considering orbifolds as diffeologies solved the problem. Indeed, in [IKZ10] we defined a diffeological orbifold by a modeling process in the same spirit than for smooth manifolds Definition. An orbifold is a diffeological space which is localy diffeomorphic, at each point, to some quotient space Rn /Γ, for some finite subgroup Γ of the linear group GL(n, R), depending possibly on the point. The Figure 4 gives an idea about what is a diffeological orbifold: the Teardrop as some diffeology on the sphere S2. C Figure 4 The Teardrop as Diffeology. Once this definition given, we could prove op. cit. that, according to this definition, every Satake defining family of local uniformizing system was associated with a diffeology of