Voting and Experimentation with Correlated Types

Similar documents
Voting and Experimentation

Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lecture 10. Information, Beliefs and Politics

Game Theory Fall 2003

Definitions and Proofs

On Inducing Agents with Term Limits to Take Appropriate Risk

Game Theory Lecture 10+11: Knowledge

EC3224 Autumn Lecture #04 Mixed-Strategy Equilibrium

Distributional stability and equilibrium selection Evolutionary dynamics under payoff heterogeneity (II) Dai Zusai

First Prev Next Last Go Back Full Screen Close Quit. Game Theory. Giorgio Fagiolo

Mechanism Design: Basic Concepts

Political Economy of Institutions and Development: Problem Set 1. Due Date: Thursday, February 23, in class.

Online Appendix for. Breakthroughs, Deadlines, and Self-Reported Progress: Contracting for Multistage Projects. American Economic Review, forthcoming

On-Line Appendix. B.1 General Setup

Persuading Skeptics and Reaffirming Believers

Robert Wilson (1977), A Bidding Model of Perfect Competition, Review of Economic

6.207/14.15: Networks Lecture 24: Decisions in Groups

Introduction to Game Theory Lecture Note 2: Strategic-Form Games and Nash Equilibrium (2)

Theory Field Examination Game Theory (209A) Jan Question 1 (duopoly games with imperfect information)

SPATIAL VOTING (MULTIPLE DIMENSIONS)

Multiple Equilibria in the Citizen-Candidate Model of Representative Democracy.

Dynamic Pricing in the Presence of Social Learning

A Nonspeculation Theorem with an Application to Committee Design

Bounded Rationality Lecture 4

Ex Post Cheap Talk : Value of Information and Value of Signals

SPATIAL VOTING (MULTIPLE DIMENSIONS)

Interdependent Value Auctions with an Insider Bidder 1

Repeated Downsian Electoral Competition

Opting Out in a War of Attrition. Abstract

Bayes Correlated Equilibrium and Comparing Information Structures

A Nonspeculation Theorem with an Application to Committee Design

Signaling and Learning in Collective Bargaining 1

Learning from Others Outcomes

On Reputation with Imperfect Monitoring

Government 2005: Formal Political Theory I

Static Information Design

EC3224 Autumn Lecture #03 Applications of Nash Equilibrium

The Condorcet Jur(ies) Theorem

INFORMATIONAL ROBUSTNESS AND SOLUTION CONCEPTS. Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris. December 2014 COWLES FOUNDATION DISCUSSION PAPER NO.

Guilt in Games. P. Battigalli and M. Dufwenberg (AER, 2007) Presented by Luca Ferocino. March 21 st,2014

Bargaining with Periodic Participation Costs

Pre-Bayesian Games. Krzysztof R. Apt. CWI, Amsterdam, the Netherlands, University of Amsterdam. (so not Krzystof and definitely not Krystof)

July Framing Game Theory. Hitoshi Matsushima. University of Tokyo. February 2018

Auctions. data better than the typical data set in industrial organization. auction game is relatively simple, well-specified rules.

Players as Serial or Parallel Random Access Machines. Timothy Van Zandt. INSEAD (France)

Weak Robust (Virtual) Implementation

Using Cheap Talk to Polarize or Unify a Group of Decision Makers

Costly Social Learning and Rational Inattention

A Model of Farsighted Voting

An Example of Conflicts of Interest as Pandering Disincentives

The ambiguous impact of contracts on competition in the electricity market Yves Smeers

Models of Wage Dynamics

Correlated Equilibrium in Games with Incomplete Information

Expected Utility Framework

Political Economy of Institutions and Development. Lectures 2 and 3: Introduction to Dynamic Voting and Constitutions

Deceptive Advertising with Rational Buyers

Notes on Coursera s Game Theory

Information Design. Dirk Bergemann and Stephen Morris. Johns Hopkins University April 2017

Benefits from non-competing persuaders

Intrinsic and Extrinsic Motivation

NTU IO (I) : Auction Theory and Mechanism Design II Groves Mechanism and AGV Mechansim. u i (x, t i, θ i ) = V i (x, θ i ) + t i,

Dynamic Information Acquisition from Multiple Sources

Loss Aversion and the Dynamics of Political Commitment

Introduction to Bayesian Inference

arxiv: v1 [physics.soc-ph] 3 Nov 2008

Recap Social Choice Functions Fun Game Mechanism Design. Mechanism Design. Lecture 13. Mechanism Design Lecture 13, Slide 1

When to Ask for an Update: Timing in Strategic Communication. National University of Singapore June 5, 2018

Organizational Barriers to Technology Adoption: Evidence from Soccer-Ball Producers in Pakistan

Strategic Information Transmission under Reputation Concerns

When to Ask for an Update: Timing in Strategic Communication

Essays on Information and Political Economy

Dynamic Information Acquisition from Multiple Sources

Strategic Experimentation Lecture 1: Poisson Bandits

Discussion of "Persuasion in Global Games with an Application to Stress Testing" by Nicolas Inostroza and Alessandro Pavan

The Impact of Advertising on Media Bias. Web Appendix

Recap Social Choice Fun Game Voting Paradoxes Properties. Social Choice. Lecture 11. Social Choice Lecture 11, Slide 1

Economics 209B Behavioral / Experimental Game Theory (Spring 2008) Lecture 3: Equilibrium refinements and selection

Political Economy of Transparency

Higher Order Beliefs in Dynamic Environments

Reputational Herding

Reputation with a Bounded Memory Receiver

Game Theory. Wolfgang Frimmel. Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium

Why Master s Programs in Top Schools Thrive

Fault Tolerant Implementation

UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND Department of Economics Economics 754 Topics in Political Economy Fall 2005 Allan Drazen. Exercise Set I

NASH IMPLEMENTATION USING SIMPLE MECHANISMS WITHOUT UNDESIRABLE MIXED-STRATEGY EQUILIBRIA

האוניברסיטה העברית בירושלים

Game Theory. Greg Plaxton Theory in Programming Practice, Spring 2004 Department of Computer Science University of Texas at Austin

Review of topics since what was covered in the midterm: Topics that we covered before the midterm (also may be included in final):

On the Unique D1 Equilibrium in the Stackelberg Model with Asymmetric Information Janssen, M.C.W.; Maasland, E.

Endogenous Information Choice

A technical appendix for multihoming and compatibility

Theory of Auctions. Carlos Hurtado. Jun 23th, Department of Economics University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign

Strategic Voting in Sequential Committees

Robustness of Equilibria in Anonymous Local Games

Strategic Abuse and Accuser Credibility

Confronting Theory with Experimental Data and vice versa. European University Institute. May-Jun Lectures 7-8: Equilibrium

Known Unknowns: Power Shifts, Uncertainty, and War.

EC319 Economic Theory and Its Applications, Part II: Lecture 7

The obvious way to play repeated Battle-of-the-Sexes games: Theory and evidence.

Dynamic Mechanisms without Money

Transcription:

Voting and Experimentation with Correlated Types Bruno Strulovici Northwestern University March 24, 2010 Abstract This note extends Strulovici (2010) to the case where voter types are correlated and/or ex ante heterogeneous. There are two voters and the risky action is taken according to the unanimity rule. Increasing correlation between the types of the two voters reduces the negative payoff externality that voters have on each other, thereby increases experimentation and efficiency. Moreover, it allows voters to learn from each other and, therefore, increases the speed of experimentation.

1 Introduction In a dynamic voting model where voters gradually learn about their preferences between a risky and a safe action, Strulovici (2010) identifies two effects, winner frustration and loser trap, which reduce voters incentive to experiment with the risky action, thereby causing experimentation to be inefficiently brief. In most of that paper, 1 preferences are independently distributed across voters. This note shows, for the case of two voters and where the risky action requires unanimity, that increased correlation across voter types alleviates winner frustration and improves efficiency. Thus, it reduces the negative payoff externality that voters have on each other. Moreover, increased correlation creates a positive informational externality, as voters can learn about their type by observing each other s payoffs. Ex ante heterogeneity of types also results in more experimentation: the more pessimistic voter prefers, other things equal, the other voter to have a higher probability of being a winner, as this reduces the risk of winner frustration. In the limit, if a voter is a sure winner (i.e., the risky action is surely optimal for him), the other voter behaves as a single decision maker. 2 The intuition for this result is more general: with more ex ante type heterogeneity, the voter who is pivotal today is more likely to be pivotal in the future as well (because it is less likely that voter preferences will cross one another) and, therefore, is less subject to winner frustration and loser trap effects. Therefore, provided that heterogeneity is persistent, more heterogeneity today should result in more experimentation. 2 Correlation and Heterogeneity The setting is the same as the benchmark setting of Strulovici (2010), with the following modifications. There are two voters, 1 and 2, who share a common belief about the initial joint distribution of their types, although this distribution may be asymmetric and exhibit type correlation across voters. Let θ i denote Voter i s type, and let p ϑ 1ϑ 2 = Pr[(θ 1,θ 2 ) = (ϑ 1,ϑ 2 ), 1 Section 5 allows for correlation and arbitrary news arrival processes, but does not specifically study the impact of increased correlation on equilibrium and efficiency. 2 This case implies zero correlation since one voter has a known type. 2

where ϑ i {g,b} describes the possible types (good or bad) of each voter. Also let for i {1,2}, and p i = Prob[θ i = g] α = pgg p 1 p 2. α is a measure of the correlation between voter types. The standard correlation measure and α have a one-to-one relationship for any given p 1 and p 2. If α = 1, types are uncorrelated. In general, α takes values in R +, although not all values of R + are achievable for given p 1,p 2. For example, p 1 = 1 implies that α = 1, since in that case Voter 1 s type is deterministic hence uncorrelated with Voter 2 s type. Let denote the set of pairs (p 2,α) that are achievable as elementary probabilities vary over the four-dimensional simplex, i.e., ( = p gg + p bg p gg ), (p gg + p gb )(p gg + p bg : p ϑ 1ϑ 2 = 1,p ϑ 1ϑ 2 0 ). ϑ 1,ϑ 2 The following proposition is a simple exercise of Bayesian updating, whose proof is easy and omitted. Proposition 1 (State Dynamics) Beliefs are governed by the following dynamics equations. When no lump-sum is observed, dpgg = λp gg (2 p 1 p 2 ) dpbb = λp bb (p 1 + p 2 ) dpgb = λp gb (1 p 1 p 2 ), dpbg = λp bg (1 p 1 p 2 ) dα = λα(1 α)(p1 + p 2 ) When Voter 1 receives a lump-sum, p bb + = 0, p gb + = pgb p, p bg 1 + = 0, pbb + = pbb p 1 α + = 1, p 1 + = 1, p2 + = αp2 where the subscript + denotes values immediately after the lump-sum is observed, and its absence denotes values immediately before the lump-sum. Symmetric formulas obtain if instead Voter 2 receives a lump sum. 3

Suppose that R requires unanimity. We assume that the voter who is the less likely of being a winner is in control: if that voter wants to play the risky action, so should the player with a higher expected type. This assumption is consistent with the elimination of weakly dominated strategies. A unanimity equilibrium (UE) is defined as follows: at any time t, if p i p j, then j votes for R whenever i does. Theorem 1 There exists a unique UE. This equilibrium determined by a cut-off function δ : [0,1] such that C(p 1,p 2,α) = R if and only if p 1 > δ(p 2,α) whenever p 1 p 2, with the reverse relation if p 1 > p 2. Proof. First suppose that p 2 = 1. Then, Voter 1 has full control over the collective decision. He therefore imposes his optimal policy, which is that of a single decision maker. This defines δ(1,1) = p SD. This also fully determines the value functions of both voters in that case. Let p w(p) denote the value function of voter 2, where p is Voter 1 s probability of being a winner is p, and v SD is the value function of a single decision maker, which is also voter 1 s value function in this case. More generally suppose that at time 0, p 1 0 p2 0. It follows from Proposition 1 that p 1 t p 2 t for all t preceding the first arrival of a lump-sum. In particular, this implies that 1 has full control of the collective decision (under unanimity) over that period. Therefore, he chooses a policy θ that solves [ σ ( u t = supe e r(τ t) dπθ 1 τ (τ) + e r(σ t) qw(p 2 σ + ) + (1 q)v(p 1 σ + )) ], θ t where, letting σ i denote the (possibly infinite) time at which i receives his first lump sum, σ = min{σ 1,σ 2 } and q = Prob[σ 1 < σ 2 ]. This is a standard control problem, whose solution is known to be Markov. Voter 1 is indifferent between R and S at probability level p, if p solves the equation pg + λp[w(αp 2 ) s/r] + λp 2 [v SD (αp) s/r] = s. (1) The left-hand side is increasing in p, equal to 0 for p = 0 and greater than g > s if p = 1. Therefore, it has a unique root δ(p 2,α). This shows that C(p 1,p 2,α) = R if and only if p 1 > δ(p 2,α). The case p 1 > p 2 obtains by symmetry. Theorem 2 states that a voter s incentive to experiment increases both with the other voter s probability of being a winner and with voters type correlation. Intuitively, if types are more positively correlated, the risk of winner frustration decreases. The risk of winner frustration is also lower for a given voter if the other voter is more likely to be a winner. In the extreme case in which, say, Voter 2 is a sure winner (i.e., p 2 = 1), Voter 1 has full control over collective decisions, and can behave in effect as a single-decision maker. In addition, positive correlation increases 4

1 0.9 0.8 0.7 0.6 Experimentation p 2 0.5 0.4 alpha = 1 0.3 0.2 0.1 Status quo alpha = 3 0.1 0.2 0.3 0.4 0.5 0.6 0.7 0.8 0.9 1 p 1 Figure 1: Experimentation Boundary δ as a function of α. r = 1, λ = 1, s = 1, g = 2. the speed of learning, which reduces the time cost of experimentation. In the extreme case of perfect type correlation, the setting is equivalent to one with a single decision maker with twice the initial learning intensity. Figure 1 shows numerical computations of the experimentation boundary for several values of the correlation measure α. Theorem 2 δ is decreasing in both components. Proof. The left-hand side of (1), is increasing in p, p 2 and α. Therefore, keeping α fixed, the root δ(p 2,α) must be decreasing in p 2, and similarly keeping p 2 fixed, δ(p 2,α) must be decreasing in α. 5

References Strulovici, B. (2010) Learning While Voting: Determinants of Collective Experimentation, forthcoming in Econometrica. 6