Topos Theory. Lectures 21 and 22: Classifying toposes. Olivia Caramello. Topos Theory. Olivia Caramello. The notion of classifying topos

Similar documents
Olivia Caramello. University of Insubria - Como. Deductive systems and. Grothendieck topologies. Olivia Caramello. Introduction.

via Topos Theory Olivia Caramello University of Cambridge The unification of Mathematics via Topos Theory Olivia Caramello

Morita-equivalences for MV-algebras

Topos Theory. Lectures 17-20: The interpretation of logic in categories. Olivia Caramello. Topos Theory. Olivia Caramello.

University of Oxford, Michaelis November 16, Categorical Semantics and Topos Theory Homotopy type theor

The Morita-equivalence between MV-algebras and abelian l-groups with strong unit

Topos-theoretic background

arxiv: v2 [math.ag] 15 May 2016

five years later Olivia Caramello TACL 2015, 25 June 2015 Université Paris 7 The theory of topos-theoretic bridges, five years later Olivia Caramello

The Morita-equivalence between MV-algebras and abelian l-groups with strong unit

Lattice-ordered abelian groups and perfect MV-algebras: a topos-theoretic perspective

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

A Grothendieck site is a small category C equipped with a Grothendieck topology T. A Grothendieck topology T consists of a collection of subfunctors

ACLT: Algebra, Categories, Logic in Topology - Grothendieck's generalized topological spaces (toposes)

Boolean Algebra and Propositional Logic

On the characterization of geometric logic

Grothendieck toposes as unifying bridges in Mathematics

Some glances at topos theory. Francis Borceux

SJÄLVSTÄNDIGA ARBETEN I MATEMATIK

Canonical extension of coherent categories

Boolean Algebras, Boolean Rings and Stone s Representation Theorem

Lecture 9: Sheaves. February 11, 2018

Lecture 2: Syntax. January 24, 2018

Adjunctions! Everywhere!

PART I. Abstract algebraic categories

ESSENTIALLY ALGEBRAIC THEORIES AND LOCALIZATIONS IN TOPOSES AND ABELIAN CATEGORIES

Category Theory. Travis Dirle. December 12, 2017

CATEGORY THEORY. Cats have been around for 70 years. Eilenberg + Mac Lane =. Cats are about building bridges between different parts of maths.

ALGEBRAIC GEOMETRY COURSE NOTES, LECTURE 9: SCHEMES AND THEIR MODULES.

MODELS OF HORN THEORIES

Elementary (ha-ha) Aspects of Topos Theory

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 8 Jul 2015

MISHA GAVRILOVICH, ALEXANDER LUZGAREV, AND VLADIMIR SOSNILO PRELIMINARY DRAFT

Categories of imaginaries for additive structures

Unbounded quantifiers via 2-categorical logic

Compactness in Toposes

3. Categories and Functors We recall the definition of a category: Definition 3.1. A category C is the data of two collections. The first collection

Categories and functors

Direct Limits. Mathematics 683, Fall 2013

PART II.1. IND-COHERENT SHEAVES ON SCHEMES

ELEMENTARY EQUIVALENCES AND ACCESSIBLE FUNCTORS INTRODUCTION

COMMUTATIVE ALGEBRA LECTURE 1: SOME CATEGORY THEORY

Category theory and set theory: algebraic set theory as an example of their interaction

Homology and Cohomology of Stacks (Lecture 7)

Category Theory (UMV/TK/07)

0.1 Spec of a monoid

CATEGORICAL GROTHENDIECK RINGS AND PICARD GROUPS. Contents. 1. The ring K(R) and the group Pic(R)

An introduction to Yoneda structures

IndCoh Seminar: Ind-coherent sheaves I

arxiv: v1 [math.ct] 28 Dec 2018

Notes about Filters. Samuel Mimram. December 6, 2012

Syntactic Characterisations in Model Theory

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Categories and Modules

1 Categories, Functors, and Natural Transformations. Discrete categories. A category is discrete when every arrow is an identity.

The equivalence axiom and univalent models of type theory.

arxiv: v1 [math.ct] 21 Oct 2010

Review of category theory

Postulated colimits and left exactness of Kan-extensions

PART II.2. THE!-PULLBACK AND BASE CHANGE

Category Theory. Categories. Definition.

Representation of monoids in the category of monoid acts. 1. Introduction and preliminaries

Fuzzy sets and presheaves

Geometric aspects of MV-algebras. Luca Spada Università di Salerno

The interplay between Grothendieck topoi and logic

Amalgamable diagram shapes

Algebraic Geometry

An adjoint construction for topological models of intuitionistic modal logic Extended abstract

Models of Intuitionistic Set Theory in Subtoposes of Nested Realizability Toposes

1 Replete topoi. X = Shv proét (X) X is locally weakly contractible (next lecture) X is replete. D(X ) is left complete. K D(X ) we have R lim

A Fibrational View of Geometric Morphisms

C2.7: CATEGORY THEORY

CONTINUOUS COHESION OVER SETS

of algebraic geometry the base topos S may be usefully taken as the Galois topos of Barr-atomic sheaves on finite extensions of the ground field. What

Derived Algebraic Geometry IX: Closed Immersions

arxiv: v2 [math.ct] 27 Dec 2014

Lecture 1: Overview. January 24, 2018

Model Theory and Modules, Granada

Some remarks on Frobenius and Lefschetz in étale cohomology

MATH 101B: ALGEBRA II PART A: HOMOLOGICAL ALGEBRA

Relativizing Tarskian Variables

Category theory for computer science. Overall idea

A Note on Extensional PERs

U-Sets as a probabilistic set theory

1 Notations and Statement of the Main Results

arxiv: v1 [math.ct] 28 Oct 2017

Formal power series rings, inverse limits, and I-adic completions of rings

Representable presheaves

Derived categories, perverse sheaves and intermediate extension functor

Lecture 2 Sheaves and Functors

OPERAD BIMODULE CHARACTERIZATION OF ENRICHMENT. V2

Constructive algebra. Thierry Coquand. May 2018

INTRODUCTION TO PART V: CATEGORIES OF CORRESPONDENCES

Congruence Boolean Lifting Property

3. The Sheaf of Regular Functions

Representations and Linear Actions

William J. CookLogic via Topoi NCSU William J. CookLogic via Topoi. Logic via Topoi. CSC591Z: Computational Applied Logic Final Presentation

IND-COHERENT SHEAVES AND SERRE DUALITY II. 1. Introduction

Descent on the étale site Wouter Zomervrucht, October 14, 2014

LOCALIZATIONS, COLOCALIZATIONS AND NON ADDITIVE -OBJECTS

Transcription:

Lectures 21 and 22: toposes of

2 / 30 Toposes as mathematical universes of Recall that every Grothendieck topos E is an elementary topos. Thus, given the fact that arbitrary colimits exist in E, we can consider models of any kind of first-order (even infinitary) theory in E. In particular, we can consider models of geometric in E. Inverse image functors of geometric morphisms of toposes preserve finite limits (by definition) and arbitrary colimits (having a right adjoint); in particular, they are geometric functors and hence they preserve the interpretation of (arbitrary) geometric formulae. In general, they are not Heyting functors, which explains why the next definition only makes sense for geometric.

Definition Let T be a geometric theory over a given signature. A classifying topos of T is a Grothendieck topos Set[T] such that for any Grothendieck topos E we have an equivalence of natural in E. Geom(E,Set[T]) T-mod(E ) Naturality means that for any geometric morphism f : E F, we have a commutative square of Geom(F,Set[T]) f Geom(E,Set[T]) T-mod(F ) T-mod(f ) T-mod(E ) Theorem Every geometric theory (over a given signature) has a classifying topos. 3 / 30

4 / 30 Representability of the T-model functor of Remark The of a geometric theory T can be seen as a representing object for the (pseudo-)functor which assigns T-mod : BTop op Cat to a topos E the category T-mod(E ) of models of T in E and to a geometric morphism f : E F the functor T-mod(f ) : T-mod(F ) T-mod(E ) sending a model M T-mod(F ) to its image f (M) under the functor f. In particular, es are unique up to categorical equivalence.

of Universal models Definition Let T be a geometric theory. A universal model of a geometric theory T is a model U T of T in a Grothendieck topos G such that for any T-model M in a Grothendieck topos F there exists a unique (up to isomorphism) geometric morphism f M : F G such that f M (U T) = M. Remark By the (2-dimensional) Yoneda Lemma, if a topos G contains a universal model of a geometric theory T then G satisfies the universal property of the of T. Conversely, if a topos E classifies a geometric theory T then E contains a universal model of T. In particular es, and hence universal models, are unique up to equivalence. In fact, if M and N are universal models of a geometric theory T lying respectively in toposes F and G then there exists a unique (up to isomorphism) geometric equivalence between F and G such that its inverse image functors send M and N to each other (up to isomorphism). 5 / 30

6 / 30 of The Morleyization of a first-order theory It is a matter of fact that most of the important in Mathematics have a geometric axiomatization. Anyway, if a finitary first-order theory T is not geometric, we can canonically construct a coherent theory over a larger signature, called the Morleyization of T whose models in Set (more generally, in any Boolean coherent category) can be identified with those of T. Definition A homomorphism of Set-models of a first-order theory T is an elementary embedding if it preserves the interpretation of all first-order formulae in the signature of T. The category of T-models in Set and elementary embeddings between them will be denoted by T-mod e (Set). Theorem Let T be a first-order theory over a signature Σ. Then there is a signature Σ containing Σ, and a coherent theory T over Σ, called the Morleyization of T, such that we have T-mod e (Set) T -mod(set)

7 / 30 I of Definition Let T be a geometric theory over a signature Σ. The syntactic category C T of T has as objects the renaming -equivalence classes of geometric formulae-in-context { x. φ} over Σ and as arrows { x. φ} { y. ψ} (where the contexts x and y are disjoint) the T-provable-equivalence classes [θ] of geometric formulae θ( x, y) which are T-provably functional i.e. such that the sequents are provable in T. (φ x ( y)θ), (θ x, y φ ψ), and ((θ θ[ z/ y]) x, y, z ( y = z))

of II The composite of two arrows { x. φ} [θ] { y. ψ} [γ] { z. χ} is defined as the T-provable-equivalence class of the formula ( y)θ γ. The identity arrow on an object { x. φ} is the arrow { x. φ} [φ x = x] { x. φ[ x / x]} For a regular (resp. coherent, first-order) theory T one can define the regular (resp. coherent, first-order) syntactic category C reg T (resp. CT coh, C T fo ) of T by replacing the word geometric with regular (resp. coherent, first-order ) in the definition above. If T is a Horn theory then one can construct the cartesian syntactic category CT cart by allowing as objects and arrows of the category those formulae which can be built from atomic formulae by binary conjunction, truth and unique-existential quantifications (relative to T). 8 / 30

9 / 30 of Theorem Properties of syntactic (i) For any Horn theory T, CT cart is a cartesian category. (ii) For any regular theory T, C reg T is a regular category. (iii) For any coherent theory T, CT coh is a coherent category. (iv) For any first-order theory T, C fo T is a Heyting category. (v) For any geometric theory T, C T is a geometric category. Conversely, any regular (resp. coherent, geometric) category is, up to categorical equivalence, the regular (resp. coherent, geometric) syntactic category of some regular (resp. coherent, geometric) theory. Lemma Any subobject of { x. φ} in C T is isomorphic to one of the form { x. ψ[ x / x]} [ψ x = x] { x. φ} where ψ is a formula such that the sequent ψ x φ is provable in T. We will denote this subobject simply by [ψ]. Moreover, for two such subobjects [ψ] and [χ], we have [ψ] [χ] in Sub CT ({ x. φ}) if and only if the sequent ψ x χ is provable in T.

10 / 30 of The universal model in C T Definition Let T be a geometric theory over a signature Σ. The universal model of T in C T is defined as the structure M T which assigns to a sort A the object {x A. } where x A is a variable of sort A, to a function symbol f : A 1 A n B the morphism {x A 1 An 1,...,xn. } [f (x A 1 1,...,xAn n )=yb ] and to a relation symbol R A 1 A n the subobject {x A 1 An 1,...,x Theorem n. R(x A 1 1,...,x An n )} [R(x A 1 1,...,xAn {y B. } n )] {x A 1 1,...,x An n. } For any geometric formula-in-context { x. φ} over Σ, the interpretation [[ x. φ]] MT in M T is the subobject [φ] : { x. φ} { x. }. A geometric sequent φ x ψ is satisfied in M T if and only if it is provable in T.

11 / 30 of Logical topologies I In a regular category, every arrow f : a b factors uniquely through its image Im(f ) b as the composite a Im(f ) b of Im(f ) b with an arrow c(f ) : a Im(f ); arrows of the form c(f ) for some f are called covers. In fact, every arrow in a regular category can be factored uniquely as a cover followed by a monomorphism, and covers are precisely the arrows g such that Im(g) = id cod(g). In a coherent (resp. geometric) category, a finite (resp. small) covering family is a family of arrows such that the union of their images is the maximal subobject. Definition For a regular theory T, the regular topology is the Grothendieck topology J reg reg T on CT whose covering sieves are those which contain a cover. For a coherent theory T, the coherent topology is the Grothendieck topology JT coh on CT coh whose covering sieves are those which contain finite covering families. For a geometric theory T, the geometric topology is the Grothendieck topology J T on C T whose covering sieves are those which contain small covering families.

12 / 30 Logical topologies II of Notation: we denote by Reg(C reg T,D) (resp. Coh(C coh T,D), Geom(C T,D)) the of regular (resp. coherent, geometric) functors from C reg T (resp. CT coh, C T) to a regular (resp. coherent, geometric) category D. Fact A cartesian functor C reg T D (resp. C coh T D, C T D) is regular (resp. coherent, geometric) if and only it sends J reg T -covering (resp. JT coh-covering, J T-covering) sieves to covering families.

13 / 30 of Theorem Models as functors (i) For any Horn theory T and cartesian category D, we have an equivalence of Cart(CT cart,d) T-mod(D) natural in D. (ii) For any regular theory T and regular category D, we have an equivalence of Reg(C reg T,D) T-mod(D) natural in D. (iii) For any coherent theory T and coherent category D, we have an equivalence of Coh(CT coh,d) T-mod(D) natural in D. (iv) For any geometric theory T and geometric category D, we have an equivalence of Geom(C T,D) T-mod(D) natural in D. Sketch of proof. One half of the equivalence sends a model M T-mod(E ) to the functor F M : C T E assigning to a formula { x. φ} (the domain of) its interpretation [[φ( x)]] M in M. The other half of the equivalence sends a functor F : C T D to the image F (M T ) of the universal model M T under F.

14 / 30 of Corollary For any Horn theory T, the topos [(CT cart)op,set] classifies T. For any regular theory T, the topos Sh(C reg T,Jreg T ) classifies T. For any coherent theory T, the topos Sh(CT coh,jcoh T ) classifies T. For any geometric theory T, the topos Sh(C T,J T ) classifies T.

15 / 30 I of Definition Let T be a geometric theory over a signature Σ. A quotient of T is a geometric theory T over Σ such that every axiom of T is provable in T. Let T and T be geometric over a signature Σ. We say that T and T are syntactically equivalent, and we write T s T, if for every geometric sequent σ over Σ, σ is provable in T if and only if σ is provable in T. Theorem Let T be a geometric theory over a signature Σ. Then the assignment sending a quotient of T to its defines a bijection between the s -equivalence classes of quotients of T and the subtoposes of the Set[T] of T.

16 / 30 II of If i J : Sh(C T,J) Sh(C T,J T ) is the subtopos of Sh(C T,J T ) corresponding to a quotient T of T via the duality, we have a commutative (up to natural isomorphism) diagram in Cat (where i is the obvious inclusion) T -mod(e ) T-mod(E ) naturally in E BTop. i Geom(E,Sh(C T,J)) i J Geom(E,Sh(C T,J T ))

17 / 30 A simple example of Suppose to have a duality between two geometric T and S. Question: If T is a quotient of T, is there a quotient S of S such that the given duality restricts to a duality between T and S? gives a straight positive answer to this question. In fact, both quotients of T and quotients of S correspond bijectively with subtoposes of the Set[T] = Set[S]. Note the role of the as a bridge between the two!

18 / 30 A simple example of Suppose to have a duality between two geometric T and S. Question: If T is a quotient of T, is there a quotient S of S such that the given duality restricts to a duality between T and S? gives a straight positive answer to this question. In fact, both quotients of T and quotients of S correspond bijectively with subtoposes of the Set[T] = Set[S]. Note the role of the as a bridge between the two!

19 / 30 I of Definition A theory is a geometric theory over a signature Σ which has no sorts. A localic topos is any topos of the form Sh(L) for a locale L. Theorem Localic toposes are precisely the es of.

20 / 30 of II Specifically, given a locale L, we can consider the theory P L of completely prime filters in L, defined as follows. We take one atomic proposition F a (to be thought of as the assertion that a is in the filter) for each a L; the axioms are all the sequents of the form ( F 1 ), (F a F b F a b ), for any a,b L, and all the sequents of the form whenever i I a i = a in L. F a i I F ai In fact, for any locale L, the topos Sh(L) classifies P L.

21 / 30 I of Definition Let T be a Horn theory over a signature Σ. We say that a T-model M in Set is finitely presented by a Horn formula φ( x), where A 1 A n is the string of sorts associated to x, if there exists a string of elements (ξ 1,...,ξ n ) MA 1... MA n, called the generators of M, such that for any T-model N in Set and string of elements b = (b 1,...,b n ) MA 1... MA n such that (b 1,...,b n ) [[φ]] N, there exists a unique arrow f b : M N in T-mod(Set) such that (f b A1... f b An )((ξ 1,...,ξ n )) = (b 1,...,b n ). We denote by f.p.t-mod(set) the full subcategory of T-mod(Set) on the finitely presented models.

22 / 30 II of Theorem For any Horn theory T, we have an equivalence of f.p.t-mod(set) (CT cart )op In particular, T is classified by the topos [f.p.t-mod(set), Set]. Examples The theory of Boolean algebras is classified by the topos [Bool fin,set], where Bool fin is the category of finite Boolean algebras. The theory of commutative rings with unit is classified by the topos [Rng f.g.,set], where Rng f.g. is the category of finitely generated rings.

23 / 30 I of Definition A geometric theory T over a signature Σ is said to be of if it is classified by a. A model M of a theory of T in the category Set is said to be finitely presentable if the functor Hom T-mod(Set) (M, ) : T-mod(Set) Set preserves filtered colimits. Examples Any Horn theory The theory of decidable objects The theory of linear orders

24 / 30 II of Theorem Let T be a theory of over a signature Σ. Then (i) Any finitely presentable T-model in Set is presented by a T-irreducible geometric formula φ( x) over Σ; (ii) Conversely, any T-irreducible geometric formula φ( x) over Σ presents a finitely presentable T-model. In particular, the category f.p.t-mod(set) op is equivalent to the full subcategory of C geom T on the T-irreducible formulae. Fact For any theory T of, T is classified by the topos [f.p.t-mod(set), Set].

25 / 30 a theory of I of Suppose that T is a theory of and T is a quotient of T obtained from T by adding axioms σ of the form φ x i I ( y i )θ i, where, for any i I, [θ i ] : { y i. ψ} { x. φ} is an arrow in C T and φ( x), ψ( y i ) are formulae presenting respectively T-models M φ and M ψi. For each such axiom φ x i I ( y i )θ i, consider the cosieve S σ on M φ in f.p.t-mod(set) defined as follows. For each i I, [[θ i ]] Mψi is the graph of a morphism [[ y i. ψ i ]] Mψi [[ x. φ]] Mψi ; then the image of the generators of M ψi via this morphism is an element of [[ x. φ]] Mψi and this in turn determines, by definition of M φ, a unique arrow s i : M φ M ψi in T-mod(Set). We define S σ as the sieve in f.p.t-mod(set) op on M φ generated by the arrows s i as i varies in I. We define the associated T-topology of T as the Grothendieck topology generated by the sieves S σ, where σ varies among the axioms of T, as above.

26 / 30 a theory of II Theorem Let T be a theory of and T be a quotient of T as above with associated T-topology J on f.p.t-mod(set) op. Then the subtopos Sh(f.p.T-mod(Set) op,j) [f.p.t-mod(set),set] corresponds to the quotient T via the duality. In particular, T is classified by the topos Sh(f.p.T-mod(Set) op,j). of

27 / 30 of a theory of III The following result provides a link between geometrical properties of J and syntactic properties of T. We say that a site (C,J) is locally connected if every J-covering sieve is connected i.e. for any R J(c), R is connected as a full subcategory of C /c. Theorem Let T be a theory of over a signature Σ, T be a quotient of T with associated T-topology J on f.p.t-mod(set) op and φ( x) be a geometric formula over Σ which presents a T-model M. Then (i) If the site (f.p.t-mod(set) op,j) is locally connected (for example when f.p.t-mod(set) op satisfies the right Ore condition and every J-covering sieve is non-empty) then φ( x) is T -indecomposable. (ii) If f.p.t-mod(set) op satisfies the right Ore condition and J is the atomic topology on (f.p.t-mod(set) op then φ( x) is T -complete. (iii) If every J-covering sieve on M contains a J-covering sieve generated by a finite family of arrows then φ( x) is T -compact.

28 / 30 of The Zariski topos Let Σ be the one-sorted signature for the theory T of commutative rings with unit i.e. the signature consisting of two binary function symbols + and, one unary function symbol and two constants 0 and 1. The coherent theory of local rings is obtained from T by adding the sequents ((0 = 1) [] ) and (( z)((x + y) z = 1) x,y (( z)(x z = 1) ( z)(y z = 1))), Definition The Zariski topos is the topos Sh(Rng op f.g.,j) of sheaves on the opposite of the category Rng f.g. of finitely generated rings with respect to the topology J on Rng op f.g. defined by: given a cosieve S in Rng f.g. on an object A, S J(A) if and only if S contains a finite family {ξ i : A A[s 1 i ] 1 i n} of canonical inclusions ξ i : A A[s 1 i ] in Rng f.g. where {s 1,...,s n } is any set of elements of A which is not contained in any proper ideal of A. Fact The (coherent) theory of local rings is classified by the Zariski topos.

29 / 30 of The for integral domains The theory of integral domains is the theory obtained from the theory of commutative rings with unit by adding the axioms ((0 = 1) [] ) ((x y = 0) x,y ((x = 0) (y = 0))). Fact The theory of integral domains is classified by the topos Sh(Rng op f.g.,j) of sheaves on the opposite of the category Rng f.g. of finitely generated rings with respect to the topology J on Rng op f.g. defined by: given a cosieve S in Rng f.g. on an object A, S J 2 (A) if and only if either A is the zero ring and S is the empty sieve on it or S contains a non-empty finite family {π ai : A A/(a i ) 1 i n} of canonical projections π ai : A A/(a i ) in Rng f.g. where {a 1,...,a n } is any set of elements of A such that a 1... a n = 0.

30 / 30 of O. Caramello. between Grothendieck toposes and geometric, Ph.D. thesis University of Cambridge, 2009 P. T. Johnstone. Sketches of an Elephant: a topos theory compendium. Vols. 1-2, vols. 43-44 of Oxford Logic Guides Oxford University Press, 2002. S. Mac Lane and I. Moerdijk. Sheaves in geometry and logic: a first introduction to topos theory Springer-Verlag, 1992.