Dual Space of L 1. C = {E P(I) : one of E or I \ E is countable}.

Similar documents
THEOREMS, ETC., FOR MATH 515

6. Duals of L p spaces

MATHS 730 FC Lecture Notes March 5, Introduction

Signed Measures and Complex Measures

Riesz Representation Theorems

Integration on Measure Spaces

MATH41011/MATH61011: FOURIER SERIES AND LEBESGUE INTEGRATION. Extra Reading Material for Level 4 and Level 6

The Lebesgue Integral

CHAPTER I THE RIESZ REPRESENTATION THEOREM

Chapter 5. Measurable Functions

ABSTRACT INTEGRATION CHAPTER ONE

Chapter 6. Integration. 1. Integrals of Nonnegative Functions. a j µ(e j ) (ca j )µ(e j ) = c X. and ψ =

Real Analysis Chapter 1 Solutions Jonathan Conder

2 (Bonus). Let A X consist of points (x, y) such that either x or y is a rational number. Is A measurable? What is its Lebesgue measure?

Class Notes for Math 921/922: Real Analysis, Instructor Mikil Foss

Chapter 4. Measure Theory. 1. Measure Spaces

+ 2x sin x. f(b i ) f(a i ) < ɛ. i=1. i=1

Measure Theory on Topological Spaces. Course: Prof. Tony Dorlas 2010 Typset: Cathal Ormond

(U) =, if 0 U, 1 U, (U) = X, if 0 U, and 1 U. (U) = E, if 0 U, but 1 U. (U) = X \ E if 0 U, but 1 U. n=1 A n, then A M.

5 Measure theory II. (or. lim. Prove the proposition. 5. For fixed F A and φ M define the restriction of φ on F by writing.

Measure Theory & Integration

Recall that if X is a compact metric space, C(X), the space of continuous (real-valued) functions on X, is a Banach space with the norm

II - REAL ANALYSIS. This property gives us a way to extend the notion of content to finite unions of rectangles: we define

Real Analysis Notes. Thomas Goller

Folland: Real Analysis, Chapter 7 Sébastien Picard

Analysis Comprehensive Exam Questions Fall 2008

2 Lebesgue integration

L p Spaces and Convexity

2 Measure Theory. 2.1 Measures

MA359 Measure Theory

Measure and integration

3 (Due ). Let A X consist of points (x, y) such that either x or y is a rational number. Is A measurable? What is its Lebesgue measure?

Chapter 8. General Countably Additive Set Functions. 8.1 Hahn Decomposition Theorem

Disintegration into conditional measures: Rokhlin s theorem

CHAPTER 6. Differentiation

INTRODUCTION TO MEASURE THEORY AND LEBESGUE INTEGRATION

3 Measurable Functions

i. v = 0 if and only if v 0. iii. v + w v + w. (This is the Triangle Inequality.)

Measures and Measure Spaces

A List of Problems in Real Analysis

Contents. Index... 15

Math 5051 Measure Theory and Functional Analysis I Homework Assignment 2

Differentiation of Measures and Functions

l(y j ) = 0 for all y j (1)

FUNDAMENTALS OF REAL ANALYSIS by. IV.1. Differentiation of Monotonic Functions

212a1214Daniell s integration theory.

Lebesgue Measure. Dung Le 1

Measurable functions are approximately nice, even if look terrible.

Signed Measures. Chapter Basic Properties of Signed Measures. 4.2 Jordan and Hahn Decompositions

Exercise 1. Show that the Radon-Nikodym theorem for a finite measure implies the theorem for a σ-finite measure.

(1) Consider the space S consisting of all continuous real-valued functions on the closed interval [0, 1]. For f, g S, define

Problem Set. Problem Set #1. Math 5322, Fall March 4, 2002 ANSWERS

n [ F (b j ) F (a j ) ], n j=1(a j, b j ] E (4.1)

6.2 Fubini s Theorem. (µ ν)(c) = f C (x) dµ(x). (6.2) Proof. Note that (X Y, A B, µ ν) must be σ-finite as well, so that.

Measure and Integration: Concepts, Examples and Exercises. INDER K. RANA Indian Institute of Technology Bombay India

MATH 650. THE RADON-NIKODYM THEOREM

Math 5051 Measure Theory and Functional Analysis I Homework Assignment 3

MATH MEASURE THEORY AND FOURIER ANALYSIS. Contents

Real Analysis Chapter 3 Solutions Jonathan Conder. ν(f n ) = lim

3. (a) What is a simple function? What is an integrable function? How is f dµ defined? Define it first

Three hours THE UNIVERSITY OF MANCHESTER. 24th January

LECTURE NOTES FOR , FALL Contents. Introduction. 1. Continuous functions

Overview of normed linear spaces

Product measures, Tonelli s and Fubini s theorems For use in MAT4410, autumn 2017 Nadia S. Larsen. 17 November 2017.

Existence of a Limit on a Dense Set, and. Construction of Continuous Functions on Special Sets

MATH5011 Real Analysis I. Exercise 1 Suggested Solution

Real Analysis, 2nd Edition, G.B.Folland Signed Measures and Differentiation

MAT 570 REAL ANALYSIS LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 1. Sets Functions Countability Axiom of choice Equivalence relations 9

MTH 404: Measure and Integration

REAL AND COMPLEX ANALYSIS

Measure Theory. John K. Hunter. Department of Mathematics, University of California at Davis

6 Classical dualities and reflexivity

CHAPTER V DUAL SPACES

THEOREMS, ETC., FOR MATH 516

Final Exam Practice Problems Math 428, Spring 2017

Notes on the Lebesgue Integral by Francis J. Narcowich Septemmber, 2014

02. Measure and integral. 1. Borel-measurable functions and pointwise limits

1/12/05: sec 3.1 and my article: How good is the Lebesgue measure?, Math. Intelligencer 11(2) (1989),

1.1. MEASURES AND INTEGRALS

DRAFT MAA6616 COURSE NOTES FALL 2015

Math 4121 Spring 2012 Weaver. Measure Theory. 1. σ-algebras

Examples of Dual Spaces from Measure Theory

Section Signed Measures: The Hahn and Jordan Decompositions

1.4 Outer measures 10 CHAPTER 1. MEASURE

Part V. Lebesgue Integration Theory

Chapter 1. Measure Spaces. 1.1 Algebras and σ algebras of sets Notation and preliminaries

Measures. Chapter Some prerequisites. 1.2 Introduction

(2) E M = E C = X\E M

A note on some approximation theorems in measure theory

Stat 451: Solutions to Assignment #1

MAT 571 REAL ANALYSIS II LECTURE NOTES. Contents. 2. Product measures Iterated integrals Complete products Differentiation 17

Section Integration of Nonnegative Measurable Functions

Lecture 5 - Hausdorff and Gromov-Hausdorff Distance

MEASURE AND INTEGRATION. Dietmar A. Salamon ETH Zürich

An introduction to Geometric Measure Theory Part 2: Hausdorff measure

Section 2: Classes of Sets

AN INTRODUCTION TO GEOMETRIC MEASURE THEORY AND AN APPLICATION TO MINIMAL SURFACES ( DRAFT DOCUMENT) Academic Year 2016/17 Francesco Serra Cassano

for all x,y [a,b]. The Lipschitz constant of f is the infimum of constants C with this property.

CONTENTS. 4 Hausdorff Measure Introduction The Cantor Set Rectifiable Curves Cantor Set-Like Objects...

Part V. 17 Introduction: What are measures and why measurable sets. Lebesgue Integration Theory

Transcription:

Dual Space of L 1 Note. The main theorem of this note is on page 5. The secondary theorem, describing the dual of L (µ) is on page 8. Let (X, M, µ) be a measure space. We consider the subsets of X which are µ-locally in M as follows M µ = {E X : E F M for any F M with µ(f ) < }. Remarks. (i) It is easy to show that M µ is a σ-algebra, containg M. (ii) If µ is σ-finite, then M µ = M. [Easy exercise.] Example: Let I be an uncountable set C = {E P(I) : one of E or I \ E is countable}. Let γ : C [0, ] denote the counting measure. Since finite sets with respect to γ are exactly the finite sets, we see that C γ = P(I). Further, let N in M µ be called locally µ-null if µ(n F ) = 0 whenever F M with µ(f ) <. It is obvious that a countable union of locally µ-null sets is itself locally µ-null. Definition. A function f in M(X, M µ ) is (µ-)locally essentially bounded if there is α > 0 so {x X : f(x) > α} is locally µ-null. Let f = inf { M > 0 : {x X : f(x) > M} is locally µ-null }. We let f l.µ g if and only if f = g locally µ-a.e. Let L (µ) = {f M(X, M µ ) : f is locally essentially bounded}/ l.µ. Notice that f l.µ 0 if and only if f = 0, so is well defined on L (µ). Recall that if M is σ-finite, M µ = M and locally µ-null sets are µ-null. 1

Proposition. (i) is a norm on L (µ). (ii) L (µ) is complete with respect to µ. Proof. (i) It is already observed that f = 0 only if f = 0, i.e. f l.µ 0. If f, g L (µ) then for any ε > 0 we have {x X : f(x) + g(x) > f + g + ε} {x X : f(x) > f + ε 2 } {x X : g(x) > g + ε 2 } where the latter set is locally µ-null, so, using definition of essential supremeum, and taking ε to 0 we have f + g f + g. Likewise if α C ith α 0 we have {x X : αf(x) > α f + ε} = {x X : f(x) > f + ε α } form which it follows that αf = α f. (ii) Let us suppose (f n ) in L (µ) satisfies f n <. Given ε > 0 we have { } x X : f n (x) > f n + ε {x X : f n (x) > f n + ε where the latter set is locally µ-null, so f(x) = f n(x) is absolutely converging, hence makes sense for locally µ-a.e. x. Then { } x X : f n (x) > f n + ε {x X : f n (x) > f n + ε is locally µ-null for any ε > 0, from which it follows that f n < f n <. 2 n } 2 n } The following was observed, in the proof of the L p -L q duality. Lemma. If f L 1 (µ), then there is a σ-finite (with respect to µ) subset E in M for which f = fχ E. 2

Proof. We allow the usual abuse of notation, identifying f with a representative function. Let E n = {x X : f(x) > 1 n }. Then µ(e n) = χ En n f = n f 1 <, and E = {x X : f(x) > 0} = E n is hence σ-finite. Remark. If we define µ : M µ [0, ] by { µ(e) if E M µ(e) = if E M µ \ M it is easy to verify that µ is a measure, called the saturation of µ. Any σ-finite set in M µ is in M. Hence, the above lemma tells us that L 1 (X, M µ, µ) = L 1 (X, M, µ). Proposition. Let g L (µ). Then the functional Φ g : L 1 (µ) C given by Φ g (f) = fg dµ is bounded with Φ g = g. Proof. We shall use the usual abuse of notation and conflate equivalence classes of functions with functions themselves. Let f L 1 (µ). Since f admits a σ-finite supporting set E in M, for which f = fχ E we have that fg f g µ-a.e. Hence fg is integrable and Φ g (f) fg g f = g f 1. Hence Φ g is bounded with Φ g g. Given ε > 0, let A ε = {x X : g(x) > g ε} which is in M µ Hence by definition of g there is F in M with µ(f ) < for which µ(a ε F ) > 0. Let 1 f = µ(a ε F ) sgng χ A ε F. Then we see that f 1 = 1 so Φ g Φ g (f) = 3 X A ε F g g ε.

It follows that Φ g g. We shall still require some approximation by finite sets to gain a duality result. The following definition very mildly generalizes that of Exercise 15 on p. 92 of Real Analysis by Folland; compare our condition (d) to his. Definition. We say that µ is decomposable on (X, M) if there is a family {F i } i I M for which (a) each µ(f i ) <, (b) F i F j = if i j and i I F i = X, (c) if E in M has µ(e) <, then µ(e) = { } µ(e F i ) := sup µ(e F i ) : J I is finite, and i I i J (d) if E X satisfies E F i M for each i, then E M µ. We shall refer to {F i } i I, above, as a decomposition for µ. Remarks. (i) Obviously σ-finite implies decomposable (with countable decomposition). (ii) Decomposable does not imply semifinite. (See question on A6.) (iii) It is known that semifinite does not imply decomposable, but examples are too obscure to discuss. (iv) If µ is decomposable with decomposition {F i } i I, then N M µ is locally µ-null if and only if µ(n F i ) = 0 for each i. Sufficiency follows from property (c) above, whereas necessity is obvious. The definition of L (µ), comprising of M µ -measurable functions, allows for the next result to hold very generally. 4

Theorem. Suppose µ is decomposable on (X, M). If Φ : L 1 (µ) C is a bounded linear functional, then Φ = Φ g for some g in L (µ). Hence there is an isometric identification L 1 (µ) = L (µ). Proof. As with the proof of duality for 1 < p <, we shall break this into parts. (I) Suppose that µ is finite. As in the case 1 < p <, we have that if E = E i, E i M and E i E j = if i j, then χ E = χ E i = lim n n χ E i in L 1 (µ). Then ν : M C given by ν(e) = Φ(χ E ) satisfies ν(n) = 0 if N M, µ(n) = 0 in particular ν( ) = 0 and ν(e) = ν(e i) for E as above. (Details are exactly as in the case 1 < p <.) Thus ν is a measure, ν << µ so ν = g µ, where g L 1 (µ). Notice that since each element ϕ of S = S(X, M) are bounded, ϕg L 1 (µ). Further, it is easily checked that Φ(ϕ) = ϕg dµ. Hence { } M 1 (g) = sup ϕg dµ : ϕ S, ϕ 1 1 Φ For α > 0, if A α = {x X : g(x) > α} satisfies µ(a α ) > 0. Then f = 1 µ(a α ) sgng χ A α satisfies f 1 = 1 and hence α fg = 1 g = µ(a α ) A α fg M (g). Using the definition of g in this finite measure setting, we may take α up to g, we see that g M (g) <. Now if f L 1 (µ), there is a sequence (ϕ n ) S for which ϕ n f and lim n ϕ n = f. Then ϕ n f 2 f L 1 (µ), and LDCT tells us that lim n ϕ n f 1 = 0. Also ϕ n g fg L 1 (µ) and lim n ϕ n g = fg 5

µ-a.e. (Notice that M µ = M in this finite measure setting.) Thus continuity of Φ, and LDCT tells us that Φ(f) = lim Φ(ϕ n ) = lim ϕ n g dµ = fgdµ n so Φ = Φ g. (II) Now suppose µ is decomposable. Let {F i } i I be a decomposition of µ. For each i let L q (F i ) = {f L q (µ) : fχ Fi = f in L q (µ)} (q = 1, ). Let g i L (F i ) be so Φ L 1 (F i ) = Φ gi. Then let g = i I g i, pointwise locally µ-a.e., i.e. g(x) = g i (x) for µ-a.e. x in F i. We observe that g 1( (α, ) ) = ( ) g 1 i (α, ) i I so g M(X, M µ )/ l.µ, by part (d) of the definition of decomposability. Also the part (iv) of the last remark shows g = sup g i = sup Φ L 1 (F i ) Φ <. i I i I Recall that each f in L 1 (µ) has a σ-finite support set E. Write E = E n where each E n M with µ(e n ) <. For each E n, the set I n,k = {i I : µ(e n F i ) > 1 k } is finite, hence I n = {i I : µ(e n F i ) > 0} is contable. Thus I E = {i I : µ(e F i ) > 0} = I n is countable; write I E = {i k } N k=1 where N is either finite or N =. Thus Φ(f) = i I E Φ(fχ Fi ) = i I E fg i = N k=1 fg ik. If N is finite the sum above is fg. If N = then observe n k=1 fgik fg g f for each n. Hence by LDCT we have k=1 fg ik = lim n n k=1 Hence Φ = Φ g and we are done. fg ik = lim n n fg ik = Example. (i) Let (I, C, γ) be as in the example above where γ is counting measure. Recall that C γ = P(I) and L 1 (I, C, γ) = L 1 (I, C γ, γ). 6 k=1 fg.

Notice that { {i} } forms a decomposition for γ. i I The theorem above gives that L 1 (γ) = L (γ). (ii) Here is a non-semifinite, non-decomposable example. Let X = {f, i}, and consider µ : P(X) [0, ] be the unique measure satisfying µ({f}) = 1 and µ({i}) =. Notice that {i} is locally null. Indeed, {i} = = {f} {i}, so if µ(f ) <, then µ(f {i}) = 0. Thus with our definition, L (µ) = spanχ {f}. It is easily checked that L 1 (µ) = spanχ {f}, and, furthermore, that L 1 (µ) = L (µ). Notice that the existence of the infinite atom {i} means we cannot partition X into subsets of finite measure. Hence this example sits outside of the assumptions of the theorem, above. We remark that if we insisted to take the usual definition of L (µ), i.e. that f L (µ) if and only if µ({x X : f(x) > α}) = 0 for some α > 0, then we would have that L (µ) = span{χ {f}, χ {i} } while still L 1 (µ) = spanχ {f}. Hence the duality would fail: L 1 (µ) L (µ). This is further motivation for the definition for L (µ) as we have it, above, as opposed to the one in the present paragraph. Let me close this section by remarking that any example of a connected locally compact metric space is known to be σ-compact. (Conduct an internet search on this question for yourself.) Hence Radon measure on such spaces are σ-finite, thus decomposable. I cannot come up with an example of a locally compact metric space which is not a union of open σ-compact sets. [E.g. my examples are of the form disjoint union of manifolds, or a locally compact group.] I might suggest that in all interesting cases, decomposability of Radon measures holds. Thus the theorem above is as close to global as one could conceivably need. 7

On the Dual Space of L Again, let (X, M, µ) be a measure space. Define M µ and L (µ), as above. Proofs here will be more terse, since this material is beyond the curriculum for this class. Lemma. The space S = S(X, M µ ) of M µ -measurable simple functions (modulo equivalence locally µ-a.e.) is dense in L (µ). Proof. Given f in L (µ) and ε > 0, partition {z C : z f } = n B i into Borel subsets, each of diameter diam(b i ) < ε. Let A i = f 1 (B i ) M µ. Then for any choice of points b i B i, i = 1,..., n we have f n b iχ Ai < ε. We now consider the space A(M µ, µ) of functions m : M µ C for which m(n) = 0 if N is locally µ-null in particular m( ) = 0; and ( n ) n m E i = m(e i ), if E i E j = for i j. These are called additive set functions on M µ, which are absolutely continuous with respect to µ. One may also wish to call these finitely additive measures (absolutely continuous with respect to µ) in obvious analogy to the definition of a complex measure. On should be warned, these do not act much like measures, though. For example, continuity from below may fail, an egregious violation of one of the key features we exploited in our integration theory. See the example at the end of this section. Theorem. Each bounded linear functional Φ : L (µ) C determines a unique element of A(M µ, µ). Likewise, each element m of A(M µ, µ) determines a bounded linear functional Φ : L (µ) C by Φ(f) = lim n Φ(ϕ n ) where (ϕ n ) S(X, M µ )/ l.µ, L - lim n ϕ n = f and for each ϕ = n α iχ Ei in S(X, M µ ) (standard form), we have n Φ(ϕ) = α i m(e i ). ( ) 8

Proof. The lemma above shows that and bounded linear functional Φ : L (µ) C is determined on S = S(X, M µ )/ l.µ. But m(e) = Φ(χ E ) then gives an element of A(M µ, µ). It is clear that m is uniquely determined by Φ. It is easy to show that given m in A(M µ, µ), ( ) determines a functional Φ 0 on S with { n } Φ 0 = sup m(e i ) : E 1,..., E 1 is an M µ -measurable partition of X. (Compare with A4 Q4.) Hence if lim n ϕ n = f = lim n ψ n for sequence form in S, then lim n Φ 0 (ϕ n ) = lim n Φ 0 (ψ n ), and this defines a unique value Φ(f). This, in turn defines a bounded linear functional on L (µ). There is an obvious embedding L 1 (µ) A(M µ, µ). what this obvious embedding is?] [Can you determine Example. Let us exhibit an element of L (µ) which is not in the range of the embedding of L 1 (µ) implied above whenever M is infinite and decomposable. A set F M µ is called a µ-filter if for any E, F in F, E F is not locally µ-null, and if F F, F E, E M µ, then E F too. As an example, fix E in M µ non-locally-null and let F E = {F M : E F }. A µ-ultrafilter is a µ-filter U for which if U F for another µ-filter F, then U = F. Notice that if E M µ, then either E U or X \ E U. ( ) Indeed, if E F is non-locally-null for each F in U then {E} U is also a filter, containing U, whence {E} U = U, i.e. E U; otherwise E F is locally µ-null for some F in U, whence F (X \ E) (F E) and thus 9

for every other element F of U, (X \ E) F (F F ) \ (F E) is not locally-null. If M is infinite and decomposable then there exists an M-partition E 1, E 2,... of X into non-locally µ-null sets [why?], and we consider the µ-filter { } F = F M : E n F for each n in N. k=n Any chain Γ of µ-filters containing F has that E G,G Γ E is also a filter. Hence by Zorn s lemma, a maximal µ-filter U containing F exists. It is evident that U is a µ-ultrafilter. Let δ U : M µ C be given by δ U (E) = { 1 if E U 0 if X \ E U. An application of ( ) shows that δ U A(M µ, µ). However, δ U is not countable additive. Indeed, consider the sets E 1, E 2,..., above. No E n U, while X = E i U [why?]. Hence Note further that 1 = δ U (X) 0 = δ U (E n ). ( n ) ( ) 0 = δ U E i < 1 = δ U (X) = δ U E n so continuity from below fails. It is known that axiom of choice (or at least an axiom strong enough to allow construction of ultrafilters) is required to construct elements of L (µ) which are not from the embedding of L 1 (µ) into A(M µ, µ), above. Written by Nico Spronk, for use by students of PMath 451/651 at University of Waterloo. 10