REALIZING LEVELS OF THE HYPERARITHMETIC HIERARCHY AS DEGREE SPECTRA OF RELATIONS ON COMPUTABLE STRUCTURES. 1. Introduction

Similar documents
DEGREES OF CATEGORICITY AND THE HYPERARITHMETIC HIERARCHY

DEGREE SPECTRA OF RELATIONS ON COMPUTABLE STRUCTURES

Computable Structures: Presentations Matter

An uncountably categorical theory whose only computably presentable model is saturated

SPECTRA OF ATOMIC THEORIES

Degree Spectra and Computable Dimensions in Algebraic Structures

COMPUTABLY ENUMERABLE PARTIAL ORDERS

A computably stable structure with no Scott family of finitary formulas

CUTS OF LINEAR ORDERS

Π 0 1-presentations of algebras

THERE IS NO ORDERING ON THE CLASSES IN THE GENERALIZED HIGH/LOW HIERARCHIES.

SUBSPACES OF COMPUTABLE VECTOR SPACES

. Final submission March 21, 2010 compiled: March 21, 2010 ON THE n-back-and-forth TYPES OF BOOLEAN ALGEBRAS

Every set has a least jump enumeration

May 31, 2007 ON THE TRIPLE JUMP OF THE SET OF ATOMS OF A BOOLEAN ALGEBRA.

Main Goals. The Computably Enumerable Sets. The Computably Enumerable Sets, Creative Sets

Computably Enumerable Algebras, Their Expansions, and Isomorphisms

Representing Scott Sets in Algebraic Settings

ON A QUESTION OF SIERPIŃSKI

The Arithmetical Hierarchy in the Setting of ω 1 - Computability

(9-5) Def Turing machine, Turing computable functions. (9-7) Def Primitive recursive functions, Primitive recursive implies Turing computable.

Algebras with finite descriptions

Representing Scott Sets in Algebraic Settings

On the Effectiveness of Symmetry Breaking

ON THE ROLE OF THE COLLECTION PRINCIPLE FOR Σ 0 2-FORMULAS IN SECOND-ORDER REVERSE MATHEMATICS

DEFINABLE ENCODINGS IN THE COMPUTABLY ENUMERABLE SETS

Computability Theoretic Properties of Injection Structures

Complete sets of Π c n relations.

The Theory of Fields is Complete for Isomorphisms

THE STRENGTH OF SOME COMBINATORIAL PRINCIPLES RELATED TO RAMSEY S THEOREM FOR PAIRS

Scott Sentences in Uncountable Structures

Unary Automatic Graphs: An Algorithmic Perspective 1

October 12, Complexity and Absoluteness in L ω1,ω. John T. Baldwin. Measuring complexity. Complexity of. concepts. to first order.

COMPUTING AND DOMINATING THE RYLL-NARDZEWSKI FUNCTION

Tree-Automatic Well-Founded Trees

Degree Spectra of Relations on Ordinals

1 Introduction. Σ 0 1 and Π 0 1 equivalence structures

α-recursion Theory and Ordinal Computability

Cone Avoidance of Some Turing Degrees

June 7, 2007 THE ISOMORPHISM PROBLEM FOR TORSION-FREE ABELIAN GROUPS IS ANALYTIC COMPLETE.

AMS regional meeting Bloomington, IN April 1, 2017

INDUCTION, BOUNDING, WEAK COMBINATORIAL PRINCIPLES, AND THE HOMOGENEOUS MODEL THEOREM

EMBEDDING DISTRIBUTIVE LATTICES IN THE Σ 0 2 ENUMERATION DEGREES

COUNTABLY COMPLEMENTABLE LINEAR ORDERINGS

Bounding Prime Models

CCR 2013 Buenos Aires

Definability in the Enumeration Degrees

Löwenheim-Skolem Theorems, Countable Approximations, and L ω. David W. Kueker (Lecture Notes, Fall 2007)

A generalization of modal definability

Ordinal Analysis and the Infinite Ramsey Theorem

PETER A. CHOLAK, PETER GERDES, AND KAREN LANGE

SUBSPACES OF COMPUTABLE VECTOR SPACES

The complexity of recursive constraint satisfaction problems.

Ordered structures and computability. By Jennifer Chubb. M.S. in Applied Mathematics, George Mason University, 2003

Boolean Algebras, Tarski Invariants, and Index Sets

Disjoint n-amalgamation

THE POLARIZED RAMSEY S THEOREM

FINITE MODEL THEORY (MATH 285D, UCLA, WINTER 2017) LECTURE NOTES IN PROGRESS

Computability of Heyting algebras and. Distributive Lattices

Incomplete version for students of easllc2012 only. 6.6 The Model Existence Game 99

Some new natural definable degrees. Rod Downey Victoria University Wellington New Zealand

Finite Automata and Isomorphism Types

ON THE ROLE OF THE COLLECTION PRINCIPLE FOR Σ 0 2-FORMULAS IN SECOND-ORDER REVERSE MATHEMATICS

Jónsson posets and unary Jónsson algebras

Halting and Equivalence of Program Schemes in Models of Arbitrary Theories

Uniquely Universal Sets

Local de nitions in degree structures: the Turing jump, hyperdegrees and beyond

ON THE COMPUTABILITY OF PERFECT SUBSETS OF SETS WITH POSITIVE MEASURE

The model theory of generic cuts

The Absoluteness of Constructibility

Isomorphisms of Non-Standard Fields and Ash s Conjecture

The jump of a structure.

EFFECTIVELY EXISTENTIALLY-ATOMIC STRUCTURES

Computability theory and uncountable structures

PETER A. CHOLAK, PETER GERDES, AND KAREN LANGE

Elementary Equivalence, Partial Isomorphisms, and. Scott-Karp analysis

STRUCTURES WITH MINIMAL TURING DEGREES AND GAMES, A RESEARCH PROPOSAL

A ROBUSTER SCOTT RANK

Algebraic Fields and Computable Categoricity

Prime Models of Computably Enumerable Degree

Recursive Ordinals and Ordinal Notations

The Metamathematics of Randomness

Incomplete version for students of easllc2012 only. 94 First-Order Logic. Incomplete version for students of easllc2012 only. 6.5 The Semantic Game 93

Model Theoretic Complexity of Automatic Structures (Extended Abstract)

The Scott Isomorphism Theorem

Overview of Topics. Finite Model Theory. Finite Model Theory. Connections to Database Theory. Qing Wang

AN INTRODUCTION TO COMPUTABILITY THEORY

Aspects of the Turing Jump

FIRST ORDER SENTENCES ON G(n, p), ZERO-ONE LAWS, ALMOST SURE AND COMPLETE THEORIES ON SPARSE RANDOM GRAPHS

STABILITY AND POSETS

Part II. Logic and Set Theory. Year

GENERICS FOR COMPUTABLE MATHIAS FORCING

arxiv: v1 [math.lo] 22 Mar 2008

COMPUTABLE FUNCTORS AND EFFECTIVE INTERPRETABILITY

About the relationship between formal logic and complexity classes

Degree Spectra J.Kepler Universitaet Linz NOCAS - RISC. Faculty of Mathematics and Computer Science Sofia University

Lecture 11: Minimal types

2.2 Lowenheim-Skolem-Tarski theorems

Transcription:

RELIZING LEVELS OF THE HYPERRITHMETIC HIERRCHY S DEGREE SPECTR OF RELTIONS ON COMPUTBLE STRUCTURES DENIS R. HIRSCHFELDT ND WLKER M. WHITE bstract. We construct a class of relations on computable structures whose degree spectra form natural classes of degrees. Given any computable ordinal α and reducibility r stronger than or equal to m-reducibility, we show how to construct a structure with an intrinsically Σ α invariant relation whose degree spectrum consists of all nontrivial Σ α r-degrees. We extend this construction to show that Σ α can be replaced by either Π α or α. 1. Introduction Since the pioneering work of sh and Nerode [10], the study of additional relations on computable structures has been one of the central topics in computable model theory. Not only is it often possible to understand the differences between the various computable copies of a structure M by examining the images in these copies of a particular relation on the domain of M, but concepts and techniques developed for this purpose have also been instrumental in resolving several other types of questions about computable structures. (For more on this theme, see for instance [15], [18], or [21].) Before we proceed, let us recall the basic definitions we will need below. 1.1. Definition. structure is computable if both its domain and the atomic diagram of, a a are computable. n isomorphism from a structure M to a computable structure is called a computable presentation of M. (We often abuse terminology and refer to the image of a computable presentation as a computable presentation.) If M has a computable presentation, then it is computably presentable. sh and Nerode were concerned with relations that maintain some degree of effectiveness in different computable presentations of a structure. 1.2. Definition. Let U be a relation on the domain of a computable structure M and let C be a class of relations. U is intrinsically C on M if the image of U in any computable presentation of M is in C. nother approach to the study of relations on computable structures, which began with the work of Harizanov [12], is to fix a reducibility (most often Turing reducibility) and look at the collection of degrees of the images of a relation in different computable presentations of a structure. Date: January 27, 2003. The results in this paper are part of the authors doctoral dissertations, both written at Cornell University under the supervision of Richard. Shore. The authors thank Professor Shore for many useful comments and suggestions. The authors also thank Julia Knight and the anonymous referee for pointing out related papers in the literature. Hirschfeldt was partially supported by an lfred P. Sloan Doctoral Dissertation Fellowship. White was partially supported by a National Science Foundation Graduate Research Fellowship. 1

2 DENIS R. HIRSCHFELDT ND WLKER M. WHITE 1.3. Definition. Let r be a reducibility, such as many-one reducibility (m-reducibility) or Turing reducibility. Let U be a relation on the domain of a computable structure M. The r-degree spectrum of U on M, DgSp r M(U), is the set of r-degrees of the images of U in all computable presentations of M. For simplicity in the statement of results below, we will call an r-degree nontrivial if it contains an infinite and coinfinite set. Note that if r and s are reducibilities such that r is stronger than s, and U is a relation on a computable structure M, then DgSp s M(U) is equal to the set of s-degrees that contain at least one r-degree in DgSp r M(U). There has been a large amount of research on degree spectra of relations, both in the general case and with certain restrictions imposed on the structure or the relation. Much of this work has been devoted to exploring syntactic conditions on a relation that guarantee that its degree spectrum has certain properties. nother rich vein has been the study of pathological examples, such as degree spectra that are finite but not singletons, with work focused both on constructing such examples and on giving conditions that imply that they cannot occur. Less work has been devoted to giving examples of relations whose degree spectra form natural classes of degrees. Despite the fact that there are no known nontrivial restrictions on which sets of degrees can be realized as degree spectra of relations, such examples are still important to our understanding of degree spectra of relations, particularly if they are in some sense natural. The purpose of this paper is to present a family of relations on computable structures whose degree spectra (with respect to any reducibility stronger than or equal to m-reducibility) coincide with levels of the hyperarithmetic hierarchy. Of course, naturalness is very much in the eye of the beholder, but we believe the examples in this paper qualify because they are built up from trees that explicitly code the alternations of quantifiers that define the levels of the hyperarithmetic hierarchy. Furthermore, by the results of [17], our results automatically imply that such examples also exist within well-known classes of algebraic structures, such as integral domains and 2-step nilpotent groups. There are two further reasons for our interest in the family of examples constructed in this paper. First, the trees that form their basic building blocks are useful in establishing a wide range of results in the classification of the complexity of index sets of computable structures with given model-theoretic properties (see [25] for details). Second, realizing levels of the hyperarithmetic hierarchy as degree spectra of relations gives an illustration of the difference between the general case, in which we are trying to realize certain sets of degrees as degree spectra of relations on computable structures with no additional restrictions, and cases in which we impose extra conditions on one or more aspects of this realization. This is due to the following result, proved independently by sh, Cholak, and Knight [2] and Harizanov [14]. 1.4. Theorem (sh, Cholak, and Knight; Harizanov). Let U be a relation on the domain of a computable structure. Suppose that for each 3 set C there is an isomorphism f from to a computable structure B such that f T C T f(u). Then for each set C there is an isomorphism f from to a computable structure B such that f T C T f(u). In particular, DgSp T (U) contains every degree. We should stress that, although our result and the specific trees used to prove it appear to be new, our approach is hardly novel. Indeed, when analyzing hyperarithmetic structures

DEGREE SPECTR OF RELTIONS ON COMPUTBLE STRUCTURES 3 and relations, it is quite natural to consider structures similar to our trees, and to analyze their complexity in terms of recursively defined infinitary formulae as we do. Examples of this approach to various questions in computable model theory are the following papers of sh and Knight [1, 3, 5, 6, 7, 8, 19]; see also their book [4]. ( general abstract framework for these kinds of results would be useful; Soskov and Baleva [23, 24] have introduced such a framework, but from a quite different perspective.) In [13], Harizanov gave a syntactical condition on a computable structure and a relation U on which, with certain additional effectiveness conditions, is equivalent to U being intrinsically c.e. with degree spectrum consisting of all c.e. Turing degrees. reasonable extension of this condition from Σ 1 to Σ α would of course imply our result (at least for Turing degrees), but in [7] it is shown that such an extension is unlikely to exist. Indeed, it appears that the natural classes of degrees captured by such syntactical conditions are not the Σ α degrees but the Σ α degrees possessing an α-table (see [7] for a definition), or the Σ α degrees over 0 α, as in [8]. In [3], conditions on a pair of computable structures and B and a computable ordinal α are given which ensure that for any Σ α set S there is a uniformly computable family of structures C 0, C 1,... such that C n = if n S and Cn = B if n / S. We could use these conditions in proving Proposition 3.2 below, but the direct proof we give is simpler. Indeed, because we are just producing an example, rather than giving general conditions as in the papers mentioned above, our analysis is a particularly simple example of this line of research, so we prefer to give direct proofs rather than attempt to employ some of the abstract theorems available in the literature. In the next section, we define relevant concepts relating to the hyperarithmetic hierarchy and ordinal notations. In Section 3, we define our basic building blocks, the back-and-forth trees. Finally, in Section 4, we define our relations and structures and establish their relevant properties. 2. The Hyperarithmetic Hierarchy and Ordinal Notations Throughout this paper, we will use the standard notions of the arithmetic and analytic hierarchies for predicates R(f, n) on ω ω ω, as in Sacks [20]. However, our definition of the hyperarithmetic hierarchy will follow the less standard terminology of sh and Knight [9], since this is more in line with several important concepts from model theory. 2.1. Definition. system of notations for ordinals consists of a set O ω and a function O taking each element of O to an ordinal. The function O defines a natural partial ordering on O given by a O b a O b O Our notations will follow certain standard conventions. (1) 1 O is the notation for 0. That is, 1 O = 0. (2) If a O is a notation for α, then 2 a O is a notation for α + 1. (3) Suppose that the e th partial computable function {e} determines a fundamental sequence for a limit ordinal. In other words, {e} is total, {e}(n) O {e}(n + 1) for all n, and is the least upper bound for the ordinals {e}(n) O. Then 3 5 e O is a notation for. s there are only countably many notations, not every ordinal will have a notation. However, these standard conventions ensure that every computable ordinal does have a notation. The

4 DENIS R. HIRSCHFELDT ND WLKER M. WHITE computable ordinals are an initial sequence of all ordinals bounded above by ω ck 1, the first noncomputable ordinal. It is clear from the final convention that ordinal notations need not be unique, since any limit ordinal may have multiple fundamental sequences. In this paper we will restrict ourselves to a subset O 1 O of unique notations so that every limit ordinal has a unique fundamental sequence. For any limit ordinal, we define n = {e}(n) O where {e} determines our fixed fundamental sequence for. Furthermore, we require that this fixed fundamental sequence contain only successor ordinals and that 0 = 1. We do this simply as a matter of convenience; none of the results in this paper depend on our choice of fundamental sequences. Given these notations for ordinals, we define the hyperarithmetic hierarchy in terms of computable infinitary formulae. 2.2. Definition. Σ 0 (Π 0 ) index for a computable predicate R(f, n) is a triple Σ, 0, e ( Π, 0, e ) where e is an index for the predicate R. For any computable ordinal α, a Σ α (Π α ) index for a predicate R(f, n) is a triple Σ, a, e ( Π, a, e ), where a is a notation for α and e is an index for a c.e. set of Π βk (Σ βk ) indices for predicates Q k (f, n, x), such that β k < α for all k ω and R(f, n) ( x Q k (f, n, x) R(f, n) ) x Q k (f, n, x) k ω k ω We say that a predicate is Σ α (Π α ) if it has a Σ α (Π α ) index. We say that a predicate is α if it is both Σ α and Π α. It is straightforward to check that this definition of the hyperarithmetic hierarchy is equivalent to other common definitions, with one important exception. In the case of infinite ordinals, the levels of our hierarchy may be indexed by the appropriate successor ordinal in other definitions of the hierarchy. For example, in Soare [22, p. 259], a predicate is Σ ω+1 if it is Σ ω 1. In our definition above, these are exactly the Σ ω predicates. We choose this definition because it gives a more natural correspondence between computable ordinals and infinitary formulae. Furthermore, this choice does not omit any interesting levels of complexity in the hyperarithmetic hierarchy. 3. Back-and-Forth Trees Our starting point is the following very simple but highly suggestive example. Let C 0 be the directed graph consisting of a single node and no edges, and let C 1 be the directed graph consisting of two nodes x and y with an edge from x to y. Consider the directed graph G = G, E that is the disjoint union of infinitely many copies of each of C 0 and C 1. Let U be the unary relation on the domain of G that holds of x if and only if there is a y such that E(x, y). Since U is defined by an existential formula in the language of directed graphs, U is intrinsically c.e. Furthermore, it is not hard to check that DgSp m G (U) contains all nontrivial c.e. m-degrees. For any n ω, it is possible to modify this example in a natural way to realize the set of all n-c.e. degrees as the degree spectrum of an intrinsically n-c.e. relation on the domain of a computable structure. In fact, this is true even with n replaced by any computable ordinal α (for the definition of α-c.e. sets and degrees, see [11]). We will not do this here since a stronger result appears in [16]. Instead, we generalize the above example in a different direction. We begin by defining building blocks that generalize the graphs C 0 and C 1 above.

DEGREE SPECTR OF RELTIONS ON COMPUTBLE STRUCTURES 5 3.1. Definition. We define the back-and-forth trees by induction on α. 1 consists of a single node. E 1 consists of a root node, to which are attached infinitely many nodes with no children. This tree is illustrated in Figure 3.1. Figure 3.1. The base back-and-forth trees For any successor ordinal α+1, α+2 consists of a root node, with infinitely many copies of E α+1 attached to this root. This tree is illustrated in Figure 3.2. For any successor ordinal α+1, E α+2 consists of a root node, with infinitely many copies of α+1 and infinitely many copies of E α+1 attached to this root. This tree is also illustrated in Figure 3.2. Let be a limit ordinal with fundamental sequence { k } k ω. For any k, L k consists of a root node with exactly one copy of n attached to this root for each n k, and exactly one copy of E n attached to this root for each n > k. This tree is well-defined, since our fundamental sequences consist only of successor ordinals. It is illustrated in Figure 3.3. For any limit ordinal, L consists of a root node with exactly one copy of n attached to this root for each n ω. This tree is also illustrated in Figure 3.3. For any limit ordinal, +1 consists of a root node with infinitely many copies of L n attached to this root for each n ω. This tree is illustrated in Figure 3.4. For any limit ordinal, E +1 consists of a root node with infinitely many copies of L n attached to this root for each n ω { }. This tree is also illustrated in Figure 3.4. We say that the back-and-forth trees L n for n ω { } have rank, while the back-and-forth trees E α and α each have rank α. Note that all of these trees are computably presentable, by effective transfinite recursion on the computable ordinals. In the case of infinite ordinals, the isomorphism structure of these α+2 E α+2 E α+1 E α+1 E α+1 E α+1 E α+1 E α+1 α+1 α+1 α+1 Figure 3.2. The successor back-and-forth trees

6 DENIS R. HIRSCHFELDT ND WLKER M. WHITE L L k 1 2 3 4 1 2 k E k+1 E k+2 Figure 3.3. The limit back-and-forth trees +1 E +1 L 0 L 0 L 1 L 1 L 2 L 2 L L L 0 L 0 L 1 L 1 Figure 3.4. The transition back-and-forth trees trees does depend on our choice of fundamental sequences for the limit ordinals. However, the following basic properties of back-and-forth trees are independent of our choice of fundamental sequences. 3.2. Proposition. Let P(n) be a Σ α predicate. (1) If α is a successor ordinal, there is sequence of trees T n, uniformly computable from a Σ α index for P, such that for all n, E T n α if P(n) = otherwise α (2) If α is a limit ordinal, there is sequence of trees T n, uniformly computable from a Σ α index for P, such that for all n, L T n α if P(n) = for some k otherwise Proof. We proceed by effective transfinite recursion. L α k Case α = 1: Since we can code disjunction over a c.e. set of indices as an existential quantifier, it follows from Definition 2.2 that P(n) = x Q(x, n) for some computable predicate Q. We enumerate a root element into T n. So long as no witness appears for Q(x, n), we do not add any children. Once a witness appears, we add infinitely many children to T n. We can do this while keeping T n computable by ensuring that the children are all elements greater than our witness for Q(x, n).

DEGREE SPECTR OF RELTIONS ON COMPUTBLE STRUCTURES 7 Case α = β+1, with β a successor ordinal: gain P(n) = x Q(x, n) for some Π β predicate Q(x, n). Since we can go uniformly from a Σ α index for P to a Σ β index for Q, we apply our induction hypothesis. s β is a successor ordinal, we have a computable sequence of trees U x,n satisfying 1. For each n, let T n be a tree whose root has infinitely many copies of U x,n for each x ω, and infinitely many copies of E β. s each U x,n is either E β or β, T n is either E α or α. Furthermore, T n is E α only when at least one of the U x,n is β, or equivalently, when x Q(x, n). Case α is a limit ordinal: By padding, we can assume without loss of generality that P(n) is a computable disjunction of Q k (n) Σ αk with { α k } k ω the fundamental sequence for α. Furthermore, we can go uniformly from a Σ α index for P to Σ αk indices for the Q k. By induction, we have a computable sequence U m,n satisfying 1 for the predicate C(m, n) = def Q k (n) Let T n be the tree whose root has exactly one copy of U m,n for each m ω. Then T n is L α n for some n ω { }. Moreover, T n is L α exactly when P(n) fails. So the trees T n satisfy 2. Case α = β + 1, with β a limit ordinal: gain we write P(n) = x Q(x, n) for some Π β predicate Q(x, n). By induction, there is a computable sequence of trees S x,n satisfying 2 for Q. Let T n be a tree whose root has infinitely many copies of L α m for each m ω, and infinitely many copies of S x,n for each x ω. These trees satisfy 1. By appropriately padding the indices of our computable structures, this result allows us several 1-reductions from predicates to our collection of back-and-forth trees. Each back-and-forth tree has a natural level of complexity such that we can go from predicates of that complexity to the corresponding back-and-forth tree. The following results show that we can also go in the reverse direction, from computable presentations of back-and-forth trees to hyperarithmetic predicates. 3.3. Definition. Let T be a tree with edge relation E. tree S is a limb of T if S T and k m x S y T (E(x, y) y S) If a T is the parent of the root of S, we say that S is a limb attached to a in T. For convenience, we often say that S is a limb attached to a if it is isomorphic to a limb attached to a. 3.4. Lemma. Let T be any tree. For each computable ordinal α, there is an infinitary formula χ α (x) L ω1,ω such that for any back-and-forth limb S of T with root a T, (1) T χ α (a) rank(s) = α Furthermore, T χ α (a) is a Π α condition for computable structures T. Proof. We proceed by transfinite induction on the complexity on α. Case α = 1: We define the formula χ 1 (x) = def y, z ( E(x, y) E(y, z) ) This formula is universal, and so T χ 1 (a) is Π 1 for computable structures T. Note that T χ 1 (a) if and only if every element of S has depth at most 1. back-and-forth tree, this can only be the case when S is either E 1 or 1. Since S is a

8 DENIS R. HIRSCHFELDT ND WLKER M. WHITE Case α = β + 1: We define the formula χ α (x) = def y E(x, y) z ( E(x, z) χ β (z) ) Since β 1, T χ α (a) is Π α for computable structures T. Because S is a back-and-forth tree, all of the limbs attached to the root of S are also back-andforth trees. s limbs of S are also limbs of T, T χ α (a) if and only if all of the limbs attached to a have rank β and there is at least one attached limb with rank β. It follows from Definition 3.1 that this is true exactly when S has rank α. Case α is a limit ordinal: Let { α k } k ω be the fundamental sequence for α. We define the formula χ α (x) = def n y E(x, y) n ω z ( E(x, z) k ω χ αk (z) ) u, v (( E(x, u) E(x, v) χ αn (u) χ αn (v) ) u = v ) n ω Since α ω, T χ α (a) is Π α for computable structures T. Because S is a back-and-forth tree, T χ α (a) if and only S has exactly one limb of rank α k for each k ω. It follows from Definition 3.1 that this is true exactly when S has rank α. 3.5. Lemma. Let T be a tree and let B be any back-and-forth tree. Then there is an infinitary formula φ B (x) L ω1,ω such that for any back-and-forth limb S of T which has root a T and is of the same rank as B, φ B (a) if S = B (2) T φ B (a) otherwise Furthermore, for computable T, the complexity of T φ B (a) is the natural complexity of B. Proof. We proceed by transfinite induction on the complexity of B. Case B = 1 : We define the formula φ 1 (x) = def y E(x, y) This formula is universal, and so T φ 1 (a) is Π 1 for computable structures T. Note that T φ 1 (a) if and only if a has no children in T. Since any child of a in T is also a child of the root in S, this is the case exactly when S = 1. Case B = E 1 : We define the formula φ E1 (x) = def y E(x, y) This formula is existential, and so T φ E1 (a) is Σ 1 for computable structures T. Since S is a back-and-forth tree of the same rank as B, it is isomorphic to either E 1 or 1. T φ E1 (a) if and only if a has a child in T, and hence in S. This is the case exactly when S = E 1. Case B = α+1, α a successor ordinal: We define the formula φ α+1 (x) = def y E(x, y) z ( E(x, z) φ Eα (z) )

DEGREE SPECTR OF RELTIONS ON COMPUTBLE STRUCTURES 9 Since α 1, T φ α+1 (a) is Π α for computable structures T. Note that T φ α+1 (a) if and only if all of the limbs attached to the root of S are isomorphic to E α. Since S has rank α + 1, this is the case exactly when S = α+1. Case B = E α+1, α a successor ordinal: We define the formula φ Eα+1 (x) = def y ( E(x, y) φ α (y) ) The argument that φ Eα+1 works is as before. Case B = L : Let { k } k ω be the fundamental sequence for α. We define the formula ( φ L (x) = def z E(x, z) ) φ n (z) n ω Note that φ L (x) L ω1,ω, since it involves a countable disjunction of formulae. Furthermore, T φ L (a) is Π for computable structures T. Since S is a back-and-forth tree of the same rank as B, S = L k for some k ω { }. By induction, T φ L (a) if and only if, for each n ω, any limb of rank α n is isomorphic to n. This is the case exactly when S = L. Case B = L n, n ω: We define the formula ( ) φ L n (x) = def y, z E(x, y) E(x, z) χ n (y) φ n (y) χ n+1 (z) φ En+1 (z) This is a formula of L ω1,ω, and T φ L n (a) is Σ for computable structures T. gain, S = L k for some k ω { }. By Lemma 3.4, T φ L (a) if and only if S has a limb n of rank n isomorphic to n and another of rank n+1 isomorphic to E n+1. By Definition 3.1, this is true exactly when S = L n. Case B = +1, a limit ordinal: φ +1 (x) = def y We define the formula ( E(x, y) k ω φ L k (y) ) The argument that φ +1 works is as before. Case B = E +1, a limit ordinal: We define the formula φ E+1 (x) = def y ( E(x, y) φ L (y) ) The argument that φ E+1 works is as before. 4. Main Results We are now ready to use the trees defined in the previous section to obtain new examples of possible degree spectra of relations. relation on the domain of a structure is invariant if it is mapped to itself by every automorphism of the structure. 4.1. Theorem. Let α be a computable ordinal and let s be any reducibility stronger than or equal to m-reducibility. There exists an intrinsically Σ α invariant relation U on a computably presentable structure M such that DgSp s M(U) consists of all nontrivial Σ α s-degrees.

10 DENIS R. HIRSCHFELDT ND WLKER M. WHITE Proof. Let M be a copy of E α+1, and let r be the root of M. Case α is a successor ordinal: Let U be the unary relation consisting of the children of r that are the roots of E α limbs. Every limb attached to r is a copy of either α or E α, and hence all such limbs are of the same rank. By Lemma 3.5, (3) a U M E(r, a) φ Eα (a) Therefore, U is intrinsically Σ α. The parameter r in (3) is first-order definable by the formula y E(y, x). Therefore, U is definable by a parameter-free formula of L ω1,ω. Thus U is invariant. Given an infinite and coinfinite Σ α relation P(n) in Σ α, let T n be the computable sequence from part 1 of Proposition 3.2. It is straightforward to define a computable presentation M of M consisting of a copy of E α with root node 0, n for each n ω, a copy of α with root node 1, n for each n ω, and a copy of T n with root node 2, n for each n ω. Now x U if and only if either x = 0, n for some n ω or x = 2, n for some n such that P(n). Thus U M m P. Case α is a limit ordinal: Let U be the unary relation consisting of the children of r that are the roots of copies of L α k for k ω. By Lemma 3.5, a U M E(r, a) k ω φ L α k (a) This is a computable disjunction of Σ α predicates, and so U is intrinsically Σ α. Furthermore, U is invariant since r is first-order definable. Given an infinite and coinfinite relation P(n) in Σ α, let T n be the computable sequence from part 2 of Proposition 3.2. It is straightforward to define a computable presentation M of M consisting of a copy of L α k with root node 0, k, n for each n, k ω, a copy of Lα with root node 1, n for each n ω, and a copy of T n with root node 2, n for each n ω. Now x U if and only if either x = 0, k, n for some n, k ω or x = 2, n for some n such that P(n). Thus U M m P. By replacing U with its complement, we can replace Σ α with Π α in the statement of Theorem 4.1. The next result shows that we can also replace Σ α with α. 4.2. Theorem. Let α be a computable ordinal and let s be any reducibility stronger than or equal to m-reducibility. There exists an intrinsically α invariant relation V on a computably presentable structure N such that DgSp s N(V ) consists of all nontrivial α s-degrees. Proof. Let M and U be as in the proof of Theorem 4.1, and let M 0 and M 1 be copies of M. Let S i be the set of children of the root of M i, let U i be the copy of U in M i, and let Ûi = S i U i. Note that U i is intrinsically Σ α and Ûi is intrinsically Π α. Let a i 0, a i 1,... and b i 0, b i 1,... be the elements of U i and Ûi, respectively. In addition to the edge relation, the language of N has two unary relations D 0 and D 1 and a binary relation F. To define N, we begin with M 0 and M 1, add new elements c 0, c 1,... and d 0, d 1,..., and let F N (x, y) (x = c k (y = a 0 k y = b 1 k)) (x = d k (y = b 0 k y = a 1 k))

DEGREE SPECTR OF RELTIONS ON COMPUTBLE STRUCTURES 11 and D N i (x) x M i This completes the definition of N. Let V = { c 0, c 1,... }. Since V can be defined both as { x N y U 0 (F (x, y)) } and as { } x N y (F (x, y) y Û1) V is intrinsically α. Given an infinite and coinfinite relation P(n) in α, we can use the construction in the proof of Theorem 4.1 to build computable presentations M 0 and M 1 of M satisfying the following conditions. (1) M 0 M 1 =. (2) M 0 M 1 is coinfinite. (3) For some computable list y 0 0, y 0 1,... of the elements of S 0, U M0 (y 0 k ) P(k). (4) For some computable list y 1 0, y 1 1,... of the elements of S 1, U M1 (y 1 k ) P(k). Now build a computable presentation N of N as follows. Begin with M 0 and M 1. Let x 0 < x 1 < be the elements of ω ( M 0 M 1 ). Let Di N = M i, and let F N = { (xk, yk i ) i < 1, k ω }. It is easy to check that N is a computable presentation of N. Furthermore, if x / { x 0, x 1,... } then V N (x), while V N (x k ) U0 N (yk 0) P(k), and hence V N m P. References [1] C. J. sh, Generalizations of enumeration reducibility using recursive infinitary propositional sentences, nn. Pure ppl. Logic 58 (1992) 173 184. [2] C. J. sh, P. Cholak, and J. F. Knight, Permitting, forcing, and copying of a given recursive relation, nn. Pure ppl. Logic 86 (1997) 219 236. [3] C. J. sh and J. F. Knight, Pairs of recursive structures, nn. Pure ppl. Logic 46 (1990) 211 234. [4] C. J. sh and J. F. Knight, Relatively recursive expansions I, Fund. Math. 140 (1992) 137 155. [5] C. J. sh and J. F. Knight, completeness theorem for certain classes of recursive infinitary formulas, Math. Logic Quart. 40 (1994) 173 181. [6] C. J. sh and J. F. Knight, Ramified systems, nn. Pure ppl. Logic 70 (1994) 205 221. [7] C. J. sh and J. F. Knight, Possible degrees in recursive copies, nn. Pure ppl. Logic 75 (1995) 215 221. [8] C. J. sh and J. F. Knight, Possible degrees in recursive copies II, nn. Pure ppl. Logic 87 (1997) 151 165. [9] C. J. sh and J. F. Knight, Computable Structures and the Hyperarithmetical Hierarchy, vol. 144 of Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics (Elsevier, msterdam, 2000). [10] C. J. sh and. Nerode, Intrinsically recursive relations, in J. N. Crossley (ed.), spects of Effective lgebra (Clayton, 1979) (Upside Down Book Co., Yarra Glen, ustralia, 1981) 26 41. [11] R. L. Epstein, R. Haas, and R. L. Kramer, Hierarchies of sets and degrees below 0, in M. Lerman, J. H. Schmerl, and R. I. Soare (eds.), Logic Year 1979 80 (Proc. Seminars and Conf. Math. Logic, Univ. Connecticut, Storrs, Conn., 1979/80), vol. 859 of Lecture Notes in Mathematics (Springer Verlag, Heidelberg, 1981) 32 48. [12] V. S. Harizanov, Degree spectrum of a recursive relation on a recursive structure, PhD Thesis, University of Wisconsin, Madison, WI (1987). [13] V. S. Harizanov, Some effects of sh-nerode and other decidability conditions on degree spectra, nn. Pure ppl. Logic 55 (1991) 51 65. [14] V. S. Harizanov, Turing degrees of certain isomorphic images of computable relations, nn. Pure ppl. Logic 93 (1998) 103 113.

12 DENIS R. HIRSCHFELDT ND WLKER M. WHITE [15] D. R. Hirschfeldt, Degree spectra of relations on computable structures, Bull. Symbolic Logic 6 (2000) 197 212. [16] D. R. Hirschfeldt, Degree spectra of relations on computable structures in the presence of 0 2 isomorphisms, J. Symbolic Logic 67 (2002) 697 720. [17] D. R. Hirschfeldt, B. Khoussainov, R.. Shore, and. M. Slinko, Degree spectra and computable dimension in algebraic structures, nn. Pure ppl. Logic 115 (2002) 71 113. [18] B. Khoussainov and R.. Shore, Effective model theory: the number of models and their complexity, in S. B. Cooper and J. K. Truss (eds.), Models and Computability, vol. 259 of London Mathematical Society Lecture Note Series (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1999) 193 239. [19] J. F. Knight, Coding a family of sets, nn. Pure ppl. Logic 94 (1998) 127 142. [20] G. E. Sacks, Higher Recursion Theory (Springer Verlag, Berlin-Heidelberg, 1990). [21] R.. Shore, Computable structures: Presentations matter, to appear in Proceedings of the Intl. Cong. LMPS, ugust, 1999, Krakow, Poland. [22] R. I. Soare, Recursively Enumerable Sets and Degrees, Perspect. Math. Logic (Springer Verlag, Heidelberg, 1987). [23] I. N. Soskov and V. Baleva, sh s theorem for abstract structures, preprint, October, 2001. [24] I. N. Soskov and V. Baleva, Regular enumerations, to appear in J. Symbolic Logic. [25] W. M. White, Characterizations for Computable Structures, PhD Thesis, Cornell University, Ithaca, NY (2000). Department of Mathematics, University of Chicago E-mail address: drh@math.uchicago.edu Department of Mathematics, University of Dallas E-mail address: wmwhite@udallas.edu