Brit. J. Phil. Sci ), 809±813 REVIEW PHIL DOWE. Physical Causation

Similar documents
Scientific Explanation- Causation and Unification

CAUSATION CAUSATION. Chapter 10. Non-Humean Reductionism

A Crucial Mistake in the Free Will Debate

Tools for causal analysis and philosophical theories of causation. Isabelle Drouet (IHPST)

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Introduction to the Philosophy of Science

Incompatibility Paradoxes

UCLA Department of Statistics Papers

Measurement Independence, Parameter Independence and Non-locality

Commentary on Guarini

Breaking de Morgan s law in counterfactual antecedents

Confounding Causality Principles: comment on Rédei and san Pedro s Distinguishing Causality Principles

ON THE NOTION OF PRIMITIVE ONTOLOGY. Andrea Oldofredi Université de Lausanne MCMP (LMU) 29 Oct. 2014

As you scroll through this review, you move your hand; this causes the

Lewis Counterfactual Theory of Causation

Why Care About Counterfactual Support? The Cognitive Uses of Causal Order Lecture 2

The impact of science on metaphysics and its limits

Euler s Galilean Philosophy of Science

Quidditism vs causal essentialism

Précis of Modality and Explanatory Reasoning

CAUSATION. Chapter 14. Causation and the Direction of Time Preliminary Considerations in Support of a Causal Analysis of Temporal Concepts

Marc Lange -- IRIS. European Journal of Philosophy and Public Debate

Conceivability and Modal Knowledge

Delayed Choice Paradox

SIMILARITY IS A BAD GUIDE TO COUNTERFACTUAL TRUTH. The Lewis-Stalnaker logic systems [2] account for a wide range of intuitions about

In Newcomb s problem, an agent is faced with a choice between acts that

Tooley on backward causation

EASTERN DIVISION OF THE AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL ASSOCIATION 2009 GROUP MEETING: THE PHILOSOPHY OF TIME SOCIETY

Appendix A Lewis s Counterfactuals

Desire-as-belief revisited

Comments on The Role of Large Scale Assessments in Research on Educational Effectiveness and School Development by Eckhard Klieme, Ph.D.

Response to Kadri Vihvelin s counterfactuals and dispositions

Accuracy, conditionalization, and probabilism

Ontology on Shaky Grounds

A proof of Bell s inequality in quantum mechanics using causal interactions

7.1 Significance of question: are there laws in S.S.? (Why care?) Possible answers:

3 The Semantics of the Propositional Calculus

In defence of classical physics

Microeconometrics. Bernd Süssmuth. IEW Institute for Empirical Research in Economics. University of Leipzig. April 4, 2011

Sklar s Maneuver. Bradford Skow ABSTRACT

Causality and Chance in Relativistic Quantum Field Theories Richard A. Healey

Lecture 12: Arguments for the absolutist and relationist views of space

WHAT IS LIFE? / MIND AND MATTER BY ERWIN SCHRODINGER DOWNLOAD EBOOK : WHAT IS LIFE? / MIND AND MATTER BY ERWIN SCHRODINGER PDF

Some Thoughts on Computation and Simulation in Cognitive Science

The identi cation of synergism in the su cient-component cause framework

Hedging Your Ifs and Vice Versa

Favoring, Likelihoodism, and Bayesianism

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 3: Analysis, Analytically Basic Concepts, Direct Acquaintance, and Theoretical Terms. Part 2: Theoretical Terms

Physical Causation by Phil Dowe is both a very good book and further proof that philosophy can benefit from the contributions of contempo-

(January 6, 2006) Paul Garrett garrett/

Popper s Measure of Corroboration and P h b

For Philosophy and Phenomenolgical Research

Contrastive Causation

Essay Review: Cause and Chance: Causation in an Indeterministic World, Phil Dowe and Paul Noordhof, eds., Routledge, 2004

Ian Jarvie, Karl Milford and David Miller (eds.): Karl Popper - A Centenary Assessment. Volume III: Science. Ashgate Pub., Aldershot 2006,

In a series of recent works, William Lane Craig attempts to provide a

1. Characterization and uniqueness of products

MUST DISPOSITIONS HAVE A BASIS? Joshua Hoffman

Counterfactuals and comparative similarity

Replay argument. Abstract. Tanasije Gjorgoski Posted on on 03 April 2006

Manual of Logical Style

Cartwright: Do the Laws of Physics State the Facts?

David Lewis. Void and Object

Counterfactuals and the Past Hypothesis

Of Miracles and Interventions

Comparative Bayesian Confirmation and the Quine Duhem Problem: A Rejoinder to Strevens Branden Fitelson and Andrew Waterman

Chapter 2 Empirical Foundations

Rerum Cognoscere Causas The Problem of Causality in Economics

HSSP Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics 08/07/11 Lecture Notes

c 2007 Je rey A. Miron

Identity in Physics and Elsewhere

Philosophy of Mathematics Structuralism

Reviewed by Martin Smith, University of Glasgow

3. Nomic vs causal vs dispositional essentialism. 1. If quidditism is true, then properties could have swapped their nomic roles.

Section 1.2: Propositional Logic

Social Science Counterfactuals. Julian Reiss, Durham University

Basics of Proofs. 1 The Basics. 2 Proof Strategies. 2.1 Understand What s Going On

Max Planck, Nobel Prize in Physics and inventor of Quantum Mechanics said:

COPENHAGEN INTERPRETATION:

I. Induction, Probability and Confirmation: Introduction

Classical Menu of Pronouns

Reductio, Coherence, and the Myth of Epistemic Circularity. Tomoji Shogenji

The Inductive Proof Template

A. Incorrect! This inequality is a disjunction and has a solution set shaded outside the boundary points.

Philosophy 148 Announcements & Such

Indicative conditionals

DISCUSSION CENSORED VISION. Bruce Le Catt

It is convenient to introduce some notation for this type of problems. I will write this as. max u (x 1 ; x 2 ) subj. to. p 1 x 1 + p 2 x 2 m ;

Math 1280 Notes 4 Last section revised, 1/31, 9:30 pm.

Mathematics: applications and interpretation SL

CHAPTER 6 - THINKING ABOUT AND PRACTICING PROPOSITIONAL LOGIC

Handout 8: Bennett, Chapter 10

Section 0.6: Factoring from Precalculus Prerequisites a.k.a. Chapter 0 by Carl Stitz, PhD, and Jeff Zeager, PhD, is available under a Creative

Philosophiekolloquium FB Philosophie KGW

Locality and the Hardy theorem

arxiv: v1 [quant-ph] 15 Mar 2016

Causal Reasoning. Note. Being g is necessary for being f iff being f is sufficient for being g

Minimal models with three-valued logic: The case of counterfactual conditionals

KRIPKE S THEORY OF TRUTH 1. INTRODUCTION

Dynamical Embodiments of Computation in Cognitive Processes James P. Crutcheld Physics Department, University of California, Berkeley, CA a

Baker. 1. Classical physics. 2. Determinism

Transcription:

Brit. J. Phil. Sci. 52 2001), 809±813 REVIEW PHIL DOWE Physical Causation Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000, 35 hardback) ISBN 0±521±78049±7 Jonathan Scha er Department of Philosophy University of MassachusettsÐAmherst Phil Dowe, in Physical Causation, addresses such questions as `What are causal processes and interactions?', `What is the connection between causes and e ects?', and `What distinguishes a cause from its e ect?' Dowe not only provides explicit and original answers to these questions, but, en route, provides important critiques of alternative answers as well as sophisticated discussions of negative causation, the fork asymmetry, and quantum mechanics. Those familiar with Dowe's previous publications on causation will nd the most detailed statements of his various views to date, along with several new ideas, all now interwoven into a uni ed approach. In virtue of its original, sophisticated, and uni ed discussion, Physical Causation should play a major role in subsequent discussions of causation. Dowe adopts a somewhat unusual methodology, seeking to discover only the contingent facts about how causation works at the actual world, relegating conceptual analysis to a distinct, complementary, but unpursued role. Dowe's contingent accounts of causal processes, the causal connection, and the causal order are, then, as follows: Causal Processes: CQ1) A causal process is a world line of an object that possesses a conserved quantity, and CQ2) A causal interaction is an intersection of world lines that involves exchange of a conserved quantity p. 90). Causal Connection: The states-of-a airs Fa and Gb are causally connected i there is a set of causal processes and interactions between Fa and Gb such that CC1) any change of object from a to b and any change of conserved quantity from F to G occur at causal interactions involving the following changes: DFa, DFb, DGa, DGb; and CC2) for any exchange in CC1) involving more than one conserved quantity, the changes in quantities are governed by a single law of nature pp. 171±2). Causal Order: Fa is causally prior to Gb i CO1) Fa and Gb are on a causal process containing at least one conjunctive fork open towards Gb and none & British Society for the Philosophy of Science 2001

810 Review open towards Fa, or CO2) if CO1) fails, then Fa and Gb can be located in a global net of causal connections containing at least one conjunctive fork open in the direction of Gb, and none open in the direction of Fa pp. 194±206). The reader interested in further explication of these de nitions is invited, of course, to refer to Physical Causation. Any book of such clarity and originality is bound to provoke critique, and I will brie y mention a few more problematic aspects of Dowe's views. Methodology: Dowe's methodological focus on contingent speci cation may leave the reader feeling unsatis ed. Dowe describes his explication of causal processes in terms of conserved quantities as `a plausible conjecture' p. 94), but the line between plausible conjecture and lucky guess seems faint. The reader may well wonder, for instance, what it is about our concept of process that makes conserved quantities appropriate for their actual speci cation. Such a reader, however, may well nd Dowe's plausible conjectures to be a useful guide in attempting a general understanding of the concepts involved. For instance, one might think that, because conservation laws govern the nomic evolution of closed systems, the concept of process is connected to the concept of lawful sequence.) Processes: Dowe's contingent speci cation of what processes are is problematic on at least two points. First, the account presupposes a primitive notion of object identity-through-time in order to trace world lines correctly. If one thinks of identity-through-time as involving a causal interrelation between stages of the object, then one will fear circularity Dowe discusses this concern, pp. 101±9). In any case, this presupposition raises the question of why Dowe doesn't just take causation as primitive, especially since his point that scientists succeed in tracking objects p. 108) applies equally to causal relations. The Humean, for instance, has a principled way of ruling out certain primitives no necessary connections); but it is not clear to me what, if any, principled view of primitives is at work here. Second, Dowe's account invokes the notion of a conserved quantity, which is `any quantity that is governed by a conservation law' p. 91). But a conservation law, as Dowe is aware p. 95), is standardly glossed as a law which holds in a closed system, and what is a closed system other than a causally isolated one? To this Dowe replies that `Instead we need to explicate the notion of a closed system in terms only of the quantities concerned. For example, energy is conserved in chemical reactions, on the assumption that there is no net ow of energy into or out of the system' p. 95). I do not see what alternative explication of a closed system Dowe is o ering, and his assumption of no net energy ow looks to invoke the very notion of ` ow' that the process account is supposed to analyze.

The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 811 Causal connection: Dowe's contingent speci cation of causal connections in terms of process-linkage is problematic in excluding causation by disconnection. Suppose, for example, that Kim lops o Vic's head C), causing Vic to die E). One's brain is normally kept alive by an in ux of oxygenated blood, and the way in which lopping of the head causes death is by disconnecting this oxygenation process, thereby starving the brain cells. Thus the basis for the causation between C and E is not any process-linkage from C to E, but rather the way C shields E by disrupting some other process the oxygenation of Vic's brain) that would otherwise have prevented E. Intuitively, such disconnections seem clearly causal. This intuition can be buttressed by the following considerations. Statistically, head-loppings in such circumstances will be universally followed by deaths. Counterfactually, had Kim not lopped o Vic's head then Vic would not have died then). The explanation for why Vic died will surely include Kim's actions. Knowing that Kim lopped o Vic's head will license an inference to Vic's death. Headloppings in such circumstances are an e ective means for murderous agents. Kim will be held morally responsible for Vic's death. In summary, all of the connotations of causation are in full force. Now Dowe has a chapter-length response to the problem of disconnections, which is to o er an ersatzist account of negative causation as `causation*', based on counterfactuals about causation. So he would say, in the example above, that 1) C causes* *D where D is the oxygenation of your brain), and 2) that *D causes* E. But this response is problematic in two main ways. a) Dowe's account of causation* is unsuited to Dowe's own account of causation, as the former requires an account of how causation works beyond the actual world. Dowe describes his account of causation* as a `cross-platform solution' in that virtually any account of causation can be plugged in. But Dowe's can't. Since Dowe has only o ered a contingent speci cation of how causation operates in the actual world, he has yet to say how causation operates in those nonactual worlds that his counterfactuals take us to here a conceptual analysis is needed). Nor is there any hope in thinking that these nonactual worlds are close enough so that Dowe's contingent speci cation should still apply. For on the standard way of evaluating counterfactual suppositions, we delete or insert the antecedent conditions with minimal modi cation to the rest of history, in which case the conservation laws that Dowe's account relies on will almost certainly turn out to be false. Elsewhere Dowe is quite willing to take worlds whose laws are just like ours, but with nonsymmetric spacetimes, as not covered by his account, since `Symmetries and conservation laws that hold in the actual world break down' [p. 98].) Worse, b) Dowe's account of causation* is semantically unstable. Dowe has o ered us two relations, one that of process-linkage) which he labels

812 Review `causation', and the other that of counterfactuals involving the rst) which he labels `causation*'. For the sake of neutrality I will relabel these relations `R1' and `R2' respectively, and I will assume that we have some general analysis of R1 perhaps guided by Dowe's contingent speci cation) that applies across worlds. Now we can ask the semantic question as to whether R1 or R2 is really more deserving of the title `causation'. Here I think that it is R2 which is the knock-down winnerðr2 covers cases of causation by disconnection such as dying because one's head is lopped-o ) and thereby squares with the statistical, counterfactual, explanatory, evidential, decisiontheoretical, and moral connotations of causation. Indeed Dowe grants that it is R2 that plays the role of `causation' in evidence, explanation, and agency p. 145). So if one adopts anything like the Ramsey-Carnap-Lewis account of theoretical terms, it will thereby turn out that R2 is a far better satis er of the `causation' role than R1. For those of us who insist that the causation by disconnection is genuine causation, this point actually suggests a way of recalibrating Dowe's account, on which we adopt some generalized notion of process for R1, and then analyze genuine) causation in terms of counterfactuals about process-linkage as per R2. If so, then Dowe has provided the theoretical underpinnings for understanding causation by disconnection, albeit in di erent terms than he proposes. Causal Order: Dowe's account of the causal order seems con icted. Dowe dismisses the temporal account of the causal order on the grounds that `backwards causation may one day nd a place in physical theory' p. 188), for which his primary example is the backwards causation model of the Bell phenomena in quantum mechanics. But Dowe's own positive account in terms of the fork asymmetry is not well-suited to the backwards causation model of the Bell phenomena. The Bell phenomena, after all, do not involve any known past-open forks containing the measurement made at t1 and the entangled state at t0ðthere is no second tine at t0. The reason for adopting the backward causation model is thus not the identi cation of any past-open fork, but rather to provide a causal explanation for a statistical correlation that resists explanation in forward-causal terms. Now Dowe recognizes this con ict, and claims that it furnishes an empirical test for his theory: we should be able to nd some further correlated event to serve as the missing tine at t0 Dowe playfully suggests an itch felt by the experimenter during the set-up [p. 206]). I think Dowe is making the most of a di cult situation. It seems that he has two very di erent conceptions of the causal order the o cial fork asymmetry story, and the uno cial story implicit in the backwards causation model of the Bell phenomena), and no reason at all to suppose that they even contingently coincide. Perhaps Dowe has a better way to go here. His o cial account of the causal order is a weighted disjunction of the local and global direction of

The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 813 open forks. If we understand the motivation for the backwards causation model of the Bell phenomena in terms of statistical correlations that resist explanation by causal hypotheses from one direction, and see such consideration as taking priority over the direction of open forks, then we can consider expanding Dowe's weighted disjunction by giving primary weight to providing causal explanations for statistical correlations, secondary weight to the local direction of open forks, and tertiary weight to the global direction of open forks. In summary, Physical Causation is a very good book. It is original, provocative, and insightful. It advances the discussion at several places. While I have expressed a few doubts as to the speci c recommendations Dowe makes, there should be no doubt as to the overall importance of his work.