Lecture 2: Period Three Implies Chaos

Similar documents
Lecture 1: Period Three Implies Chaos

Lecture 14: The Rank-Nullity Theorem

Lecture 3: Latin Squares and Groups

Lecture 6: Finite Fields

Lecture 8: A Crash Course in Linear Algebra

Lecture 2: Mutually Orthogonal Latin Squares and Finite Fields

Lecture 5: Latin Squares and Magic

The definition, and some continuity laws. Types of discontinuities. The Squeeze Theorem. Two special limits. The IVT and EVT.

Lecture 2: Vector Spaces, Metric Spaces

Adam Blank Spring 2017 CSE 311. Foundations of Computing I. * All slides are a combined effort between previous instructors of the course

Lecture 4: Constructing the Integers, Rationals and Reals

Recitation 9: Probability Matrices and Real Symmetric Matrices. 3 Probability Matrices: Definitions and Examples

Lecture 9: Taylor Series

Lecture 3: Sizes of Infinity

Math Lecture 18 Notes

Lecture 6: Lies, Inner Product Spaces, and Symmetric Matrices

Inference and Proofs (1.6 & 1.7)

Lecture 19: The Determinant

ADVANCE TOPICS IN ANALYSIS - REAL. 8 September September 2011

SPECIAL POINTS AND LINES OF ALGEBRAIC SURFACES

/633 Introduction to Algorithms Lecturer: Michael Dinitz Topic: Matroids and Greedy Algorithms Date: 10/31/16

Math 3361-Modern Algebra Lecture 08 9/26/ Cardinality

Lecture 4: Applications of Orthogonality: QR Decompositions

NOTES WEEK 13 DAY 2 SCOT ADAMS

T i t l e o f t h e w o r k : L a M a r e a Y o k o h a m a. A r t i s t : M a r i a n o P e n s o t t i ( P l a y w r i g h t, D i r e c t o r )

Proof Techniques (Review of Math 271)

MA 1125 Lecture 15 - The Standard Normal Distribution. Friday, October 6, Objectives: Introduce the standard normal distribution and table.

Exercise 2. Prove that [ 1, 1] is the set of all the limit points of ( 1, 1] = {x R : 1 <

Lecture 10: Powers of Matrices, Difference Equations

Functions. Ex. f : R 0 Ñ R 0 defined by x fiñ x 2.

Basics of Proofs. 1 The Basics. 2 Proof Strategies. 2.1 Understand What s Going On

Lecture 2: Eigenvalues and their Uses

One-to-one functions and onto functions

MTH 505: Number Theory Spring 2017

TheFourierTransformAndItsApplications-Lecture28

Exam 2 Solutions. In class questions

c 1 v 1 + c 2 v 2 = 0 c 1 λ 1 v 1 + c 2 λ 1 v 2 = 0

Lecture 2: Change of Basis

Linear Independence Reading: Lay 1.7

Proof by contrapositive, contradiction

( )( b + c) = ab + ac, but it can also be ( )( a) = ba + ca. Let s use the distributive property on a couple of

- a value calculated or derived from the data.

NOTES WEEK 14 DAY 2 SCOT ADAMS

Hypothesis testing I. - In particular, we are talking about statistical hypotheses. [get everyone s finger length!] n =

The group (Z/nZ) February 17, In these notes we figure out the structure of the unit group (Z/nZ) where n > 1 is an integer.

Minilecture 2: Sorting Algorithms

We have been going places in the car of calculus for years, but this analysis course is about how the car actually works.

6.080 / Great Ideas in Theoretical Computer Science Spring 2008

On the other hand, if we measured the potential difference between A and C we would get 0 V.

Math 121 (Lesieutre); 9.1: Polar coordinates; November 22, 2017

Series with positive and negative terms

Guide to Proofs on Sets

CSE 331 Winter 2018 Reasoning About Code I

Lecture 7: Differential Equations

NOTES WEEK 11 DAY 2 SCOT ADAMS

ASTRO 114 Lecture Okay. We re gonna continue our discussion today on galaxies and quasars, and

Real Analysis on Metric Spaces

a. Introduction to metatheory

Quadratic Equations Part I

Descriptive Statistics (And a little bit on rounding and significant digits)

Modern Algebra Prof. Manindra Agrawal Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur

Chapter 1. Linear Equations

Quick Sort Notes , Spring 2010

MATH 360 Final Exam Thursday, December 14, a n 2. a n 1 1

Math 115 Spring 11 Written Homework 10 Solutions

FILE NAME: PYTHAGOREAN_TRIPLES_012-( WED).DOCX AUTHOR: DOUG JONES

Lecture 5. 1 Review (Pairwise Independence and Derandomization)

Writing proofs for MATH 51H Section 2: Set theory, proofs of existential statements, proofs of uniqueness statements, proof by cases

SUBGROUPS OF CYCLIC GROUPS. 1. Introduction In a group G, we denote the (cyclic) group of powers of some g G by

Hyperreal Numbers: An Elementary Inquiry-Based Introduction. Handouts for a course from Canada/USA Mathcamp Don Laackman

Mathematics-I Prof. S.K. Ray Department of Mathematics and Statistics Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur. Lecture 1 Real Numbers

A Harvard Sampler. Evan Chen. February 23, I crashed a few math classes at Harvard on February 21, Here are notes from the classes.

CSC165. Larry Zhang, October 7, 2014

Z Algorithmic Superpower Randomization October 15th, Lecture 12

Proof by Contradiction

c i r i i=1 r 1 = [1, 2] r 2 = [0, 1] r 3 = [3, 4].

MAT137 - Term 2, Week 5

MATH 308 COURSE SUMMARY

P (E) = P (A 1 )P (A 2 )... P (A n ).

Section 3.1 Quadratic Functions

Some Review Problems for Exam 1: Solutions

ETIKA V PROFESII PSYCHOLÓGA

Connectedness. Proposition 2.2. The following are equivalent for a topological space (X, T ).

P-adic numbers. Rich Schwartz. October 24, 2014

1. Draw a picture or a graph of what you think the growth of the Jactus might look like.

V. Graph Sketching and Max-Min Problems

Recitation 8: Graphs and Adjacency Matrices

Introducing Proof 1. hsn.uk.net. Contents

University of California Berkeley CS170: Efficient Algorithms and Intractable Problems November 19, 2001 Professor Luca Trevisan. Midterm 2 Solutions

Take the Anxiety Out of Word Problems

Vectors. Vector Practice Problems: Odd-numbered problems from

SOLUTIONS Math B4900 Homework 9 4/18/2018

Lecture 6: Sequential Dynamical Systems

TAYLOR POLYNOMIALS DARYL DEFORD

Partial Fractions. June 27, In this section, we will learn to integrate another class of functions: the rational functions.

x 1 + x 2 2 x 1 x 2 1 x 2 2 min 3x 1 + 2x 2

e π i 1 = 0 Proofs and Mathematical Induction Carlos Moreno uwaterloo.ca EIT-4103 e x2 log k a+b a + b

REAL ANALYSIS II TAKE HOME EXAM. T. Tao s Lecture Notes Set 5

Lecture 2. When we studied dimensional analysis in the last lecture, I defined speed. The average speed for a traveling object is quite simply

Dr. Marques Sophie Algebra 1 Spring Semester 2017 Problem Set 9

Transcription:

Dynamical Systems Instructor: Padraic Bartlett Lecture 2: Period Three Implies Chaos Week 3 Mathcamp 2014 We ended our last class by proving the following result (whose name I found while doing some research last night): Theorem. (The Itinerary Lemma.) Let fpxq be a continuous function on the interval ra, bs, and I 0,... I n 1 denote a collection of closed intervals that are each contained within ra, bs. Assume that 1. fpi k q Ě I k`1, for every k 0... n 2, and 2. fpi n 1 q Ě I 0, where by fpi k q we mean the set given by applying f to all of the points in the interval I k. (In other words, applying f to any one interval I k gives you a set that contains the next interval I k`1 ) Then there is some point x 0 P I 0 such that 1. f n px 0 q x 0, and 2. f k px 0 q P I k, for every k 0,... n 1. Today, we re going to talk about how to use this result! 1 Why We Care: Chaos Consider the following problem: Problem. Suppose we have a fluid filled with particles in some reasonably-close-to-onedimensional object, which we can model as an interval ra, bs. Furthermore, suppose that we know how this fluid is mixing: i.e. that we have some function f : ra, bs Ñ ra, bs, such that fpxq tells you where a particle at location x will wind up after one step forward in time. Where do your particles go? Do they settle down? Do they all clump together at one end? In other words: what does f n look like as n grows very large? Something you might hope for is that your fluid particles settle down: that they either converge to various states, or at least that they all settle into some small set of predictable periodic orbits. In the worst case scenario, however, you might have something like the following: Definition. A function f is called chaotic if for any n, it has a particle of period n. So! The punchline for this class, and the reason we proved the Itinerary Lemma, is the following theorem of Li and Yorke: 1

Theorem. Suppose that f is a continuous function on ra, bs with range contained in ra, bs. Then if f has a 3-periodic point, it is chaotic. Before we start this proof, we introduce some useful notation: Notation. Given a function f and intervals I 0, I 1, we write I 0 Ñ I 1 if fpi 0 q Ě I 1. In particular, if fpi 0 q Ą I i, we will write I 0 ý to denote that f of this interval contains itself. Proof. We first note that because our function is a continuous map on ra, bs that contains ra, bs in its range, we get a point of period 1 by the intermediate value theorem, as mentioned on day 1. The case for k 2 is similarly trivial; we leave this for the HW! So it suffices to search for points of period k, for k ě 2. Take a triple x 0 ă x 1 ă x 2 of points that form a 3-periodic orbit. Either fpx 1 q x 2 or fpx 1 q x 0 ; assume that fpx 1 q x 0 without loss of generality, as the proof will proceed identically in the other case. Then we have fpfpx 1 qq fpx 0 q x 2. Let I 0 rx 0, x 1 s and I 1 rx 1, x 2 s. Note that because fpx 0 q x 2, fpx 1 q x 0, fpx 2 q x 1, by the intermediate value theorem, we have I 1 Ô I 0 ý. So: let I 0... I n 2 I 0, and I n 1 I 1. Apply our theorem from before that was designed to find periodic points: this gives us a point y such that y, fpyq,... f n 2 pyq P I 0, f n 1 pyq P I 1, and f n pyq y. I claim that this point is a n-periodic point. We already have that f n pyq y; we just need to prove that f k pyq y, for any k 1,... n 1. To see this, proceed by contradiction. Suppose that f k pyq y, for some k ă n 1. Then f n 1 pyq is equal to an earlier term f n 1 k pyq, because applying f k times is the same thing as doing nothing. But this means that on one hand, f n 1 pyq P I 1, and on the other hand, f n 1 pyq f n 1 k pyq P I n 1 k I 0. Therefore this point is in both sets. But the only point in both I 0 rx 0, x 1 s and I 1 rx 1, x 2 s is x 1 ; so f n 1 pyq x 1. But then f n pyq y x 0, and thus fpyq fpx 0 q x 2 R I 1 rx 0.x 1 s. So we have a contradiction to our assumption that x 0 was not a point with period n. This is... weird. All we used in the above statement was that there was a point with period 3 i.e. some point such that fpfpfpxqqq x, while fpxq, fpfpxq x. And out of nowhere we got points of every period: chaos! Surprisingly, this result is not even the strangest thing we re proving in this talk. Consider the following ordering on the natural numbers: Definition. The Sharkovsky ordering on the natural numbers is the following ordering: 2 0 3 Ÿ 2 0 5 Ÿ 2 0 7 Ÿ 2 0 9 Ÿ... Ÿ 2 1 3 Ÿ 2 1 5 Ÿ 2 1 7 Ÿ 2 1 9 Ÿ...... Ÿ 2 2 3 Ÿ 2 2 5 Ÿ 2 2 7 Ÿ 2 2 9 Ÿ... Ÿ 2 3 3 Ÿ 2 3 5 Ÿ 2 3 7 Ÿ 2 3 9 Ÿ......... Ÿ 2 5 Ÿ 2 4 Ÿ 2 3 Ÿ 2 2 Ÿ 2 1 Ÿ 1. 2

In words: take the natural numbers, and break them into the following groups: S 0 : All odd numbers greater than 1. S 1 : All numbers of the form 2 1 pan odd number greater than 1q. S 2 : All numbers of the form 2 2 pan odd number greater than 1q.... S 8 : All powers of two. For each i P N, order via the Sharkovsky ordering Ÿ each S i using the normal ordering on the natural numbers: i.e 3 Ÿ 5 Ÿ 7... Order the set S 8 using the opposite ordering from the normal ordering on the natural numbers: i.e.... Ÿ 16 Ÿ 8 Ÿ 4 Ÿ 2 Ÿ 1. Finally, to compare any two elements s i, s j from different sets S i, S j, simply say that s i Ÿ s j whenever i ă j in the normal ordering on N Y t8u. The reason we care about this is the following theorem: Theorem. Suppose that I is a closed interval and f is any continuous function from I to itself. Then, if f has a n-periodic point, it has a m-periodic point for any n Ÿ m (under the Sharkovsky ordering.) In other words, it s not simply true that period 3 implies every possible period! We have many other strange consequences, like the following: Period 5 implies every period except for possibly 3. Period 7 implies every period except for possibly 3 and 5. Period 6 implies all of the even periods. Any function with finitely many periodic points must only have points with periods equal to powers of 2. How would we prove such a thing? Well: given that we already have a functioning proof that period 3 implies chaos, perhaps we can adapt it to prove this stronger claim! If you break down our proof from earlier, it effectively has three main parts: First, we recognized that any triple x 0 ă x 1 ă x 2 corresponding to a point of period 3 has one of two orbits x 1 Ñ x 0 Ñ x 2 or x 1 Ñ x 2 Ñ x 0. Then, we translated these orbits into intervals rx 0, x 1 s, rx 1, x 2 s, rx 0, x 2 s, and noted that we have either rx 0, x 1 s Ô rx 1, x 2 s ý or rx 1, x 2 s Ô rx 0, x 1 s ý. Finally, we came up with a clever way to apply the Itinerary Lemma to secuences made out of these two intervals, that let us create points with any period. 3

Therefore, if we want to modify this proof, we should start by examining the first of these parts! We do this here: Lemma. Suppose that f is a continuous function on some interval I with the following two properties: There is some n such that f has a point, x 0, of period 2n ` 1. For all 1 ď m ă n, f has no points of period 2m ` 1. Then the orbit of x 0 must look like one of the following: x 6 x 4 x 2 x 0 x 1 x 3 x 5 x 7 x 6 x 4 x 2 x 0 x 1 x 3 x 5 x 7 In other words: if we define x i f i px 0 q, we have either x 2n ă x 2n 2 ă... ă x 4 ă x 2 ăx 0 ă x 1 ă x 3 ă... ă x 2n 1, or x 2n 1 ă x 2n 3 ă... ă x 3 ă x 1 ăx 0 ă x 2 ă x 4 ă... ă x 2n. Before we start our proof, let s try to understand what we re even attempting to do here. First: to make our notation easier, reorder the 2n ` 1 points in the orbit of x 0 as the sequence z 1 ă z 2 ă... ă z 2n ă z 2n`1. Now: let s look at what we re trying to prove. In both of the pictures that we re trying to prove must hold, we have this sort of spiraling-out relation, where an initially small interval rx 0, x 1 s becomes after one application of f the slightly larger interval rx 2, x 1 s, which after another application of f becomes the larger interval rx 2, x 4 s, which after yet another application of f becomes the larger interval rx 3, x 4 s, 4

... which at our last stage becomes our entire collection of points! Furthermore, this spiraling-out relation looks like pretty much enforces the structure we re claiming must exist: if there is some seed interval rz m, z m`1 s such that Repeatedly applying f to this interval expands it by precisely one z i at each application, and the side this z i shows up on alternates from left to right, we ve got the structure that we want! (Sketch out anything satisfying the two properties above to see why this is sufficient.) This suggests that if we want to prove our claim, we should attempt to look for this sort of interval structure in our z i s. In tomorrow s lecture, we ll do precisely this! 5